phiorg.comphiorg.com/.../03/...error-theoretical-account-of-color-concepts.docx  · web viewphd...

23

Click here to load reader

Upload: lenhi

Post on 25-Apr-2019

213 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: phiorg.comphiorg.com/.../03/...Error-Theoretical-Account-of-Color-Concepts.docx  · Web viewPhD Student, University of South Florida Fink 15 For Wilfrid Sellars, there are two ways

AN INCOHERENCE IN SELLARS’ ERROR THEORETICAL ACCOUNT OF COLOR CONCEPTS

KEVIN FINKPHD STUDENT, UNIVERSITY OF SOUTH FLORIDA

For Wilfrid Sellars, there are two ways to give an account of the ontological status of color: on the

order of being (ordo essendi) and on the order of knowing (ordo cognoscendi). Moreover, there is an important

sense in which the former account is justified and supported by conclusions arrived at in investigation of the

latter1. Ultimately, Sellars concludes his intricate mythological story of our evolving knowledge of color with

the claim that, in the final analysis, colors exist only at the level of sensations: we falsely project them from the

mind as properties of physical objects, but physical objects possess no such properties. When we properly

understand the circumstances of this projection, we may come to appreciate it as false and it at least seems

(Sellars is not so clear about this) that we could (potentially) refrain from such unwarranted projections.

However, after sketching Sellars’ story of color on the order of knowing, I will argue that Sellars’ claim that we

have an intelligible concept of sense impressions of color even after we have eliminated the concept of color as

a property of physical objects is incoherent.

The Story of Color on the Order of Knowing: (1) the pre-pre-Socratics

Sellars takes our original notion of color to be that of a stuff and he attributes this conception to those

whom he calls the ‘pre-pre-Socratics’. In his Notre Dame Lectures, he says:

I want you to think of the objects around you as three-dimensional solid conglomerations of color, they are made of color, I want you think of color as the very stuff of which they are made…. The nice thing about this pink ice cube is that if you take the example seriously you begin to think of pink as a stuff.

1 A large part of the reason these two accounts come apart the way they do has to do with Sellars’ rejection of the Myth of the Given. For instance, he says: “even if these philosophers are right in thinking that what the child is directly aware of is, from the standpoint of an ideal theory of perceptual consciousness, a state of sensing redly, nevertheless the child forms a concept which has quite a different grammar. To reject the Myth of the Given is to reject the idea that the categorial structure of the world -- if it has a categorial structure -- imposes itself on the mind as a seal imposes an image on melted wax.” (FMPP I, #45) Despite the rejection of the Myth of the Given, Sellars still remains committed to a Peircean ideal of a finished or complete science. Embodied in this ideal is the ‘real’ order of things – the order of being. On the other hand, the actual progression of our knowledge of the world and of our conceptual frameworks are captured in the order of knowing. For instance, Sellars says in BLM (1980), “Compare the primacy 'in the order of knowing' of the concept of a middle sized perceptible physical object with the primacy 'in the order of being' of concepts of micro-physical entities.” This is particularly relevant to the discussion later in this paper of the manifest image as primary in the order of knowing and the scientific image as primary in the order of being. Sellars attributes the original distinction between the order of knowing and the order of being to Aristotle. He further explains in his March 9, 1964 correspondence with J. J. C. Smart, when he says, “These predicates would be still mere derivative in the dimension of concept formation from the sense-quality predicates of the manifest image which apply to physical things. They would, however, have a priority in the dimension of explanation by virtue of which they would describe "what really is." That by methodologically derivative predicates we grasp the ontologically prior, is a modern version of Aristotle's distinction between "priority in the order of knowing" and "priority in the order of being".”

Page 2: phiorg.comphiorg.com/.../03/...Error-Theoretical-Account-of-Color-Concepts.docx  · Web viewPhD Student, University of South Florida Fink 15 For Wilfrid Sellars, there are two ways

Fink 2

It’s a cubicle chunk, if you will, of pink…. So that if we look now for our object of perception proper, it looks as though a paradigm case is going to be a cubical chunk of pink, and let it be so.2

Typically, Sellars favors the example of the pink ice cube as a means of illustrating the non-intentional

component of perceptual experience – the way in which something is present in our perceptions of physical

objects other than as believed in. The pink ice cube illustrates this because we do not merely think of it as being

colored through and through; we do not merely think of it as being pink on the opposite side; rather its pinkness

and cubicity are (somehow) actually present in our perception. However, although the emblematic naïveté of the

pre-pre-Socratics consists in their not yet having any notion of phenomenal experience or of sense impressions,

by ‘object of perception proper’ Sellars intends, in this passage, a phenomenal object.3

Although the pre-pre-Socratics lack any notion of phenomenal experience or sense impressions, they do

have the concepts of pinkness and of cubicity – which are concepts that pertain to the ‘objects of perception

proper’, but as categorized by them in a particular way, namely, as physical objects. The story Sellars tells,

then, is one that begins with such objects of perception – i.e., with what is ‘strictly speaking’ perceived4 – and

tracks the evolution of the concepts we use to categorize them. Essentially, the story Sellars tells about color is

put forward as a story of conceptual change.

The first major conceptual change in the story is brought on through recognition, on the part of the pre-

pre-Socratics, of the fact that construing colors as having the categorial status of stuffs does not advance our

goals and capacities for explanation and prediction and so does not help us get along in the world.5 The result is

a revision – not a replacement – of our concept of color such that its categorial status is transposed from that of a

substance to that of a property or mode: colors are no longer stuffs that are proper parts of physical objects –

they are properties or dispositions of such objects. That is the first major evolution of the concept of color on

the order of knowing.

The Story of Color on the Order of Knowing: (2) Genius Jones’ Theory of Sense Impressions

2 Notre Dame Lectures, (bootleg version) http://www.pitt.edu/~brandom/phil-2245/downloads/Sellars.The.Notre.Dame.Lectures.March.1.pdf pp. 299-300.3 Ibid, p. 300.4 Ibid.5 As deVries says, “Red things are not always good to eat, nor blue things bad; some red things rot, others do not” (deVries, 2005, p. 204).

Page 3: phiorg.comphiorg.com/.../03/...Error-Theoretical-Account-of-Color-Concepts.docx  · Web viewPhD Student, University of South Florida Fink 15 For Wilfrid Sellars, there are two ways

Fink 3

The second major evolution of the concept of color on the order of knowing is the introduction of sense

impressions. (This is done by Genius Jones in EPM.) Genius Jones’ introduction of sense impressions is not

the introduction of a language to describe occurrences of which we were already somehow consciously aware

(i.e., aware of as such). That it is part of a theory means, in part, that sense impressions are newly

conceptualized states of perceivers introduced to play an explanatory role. They make possible a distinction,

previously unavailable in the language, between, say, seeing a red triangle6 and its merely looking to one that

there is a red triangle. This distinction, then, allows us to explain perceptual errors.7

How are we to understand these (epistemologically) new states of perceivers? Sellars introduces them

through the use of a model:

[T]he model is the idea of a domain of ‘inner replicas’ which, when brought about in standard conditions, share the perceptible characteristics of their physical source….[T]he model for an impression of a red triangle is a red and triangular replica....8

These replicas, however, cannot be said to have the very same perceptible qualities as physical objects. ‘Red’

and ‘triangular’ are properties of physical objects that are the properties they are, at least in part, because of the

way they are causally related to other physical properties. So, although sense impressions cannot be, strictly

speaking, red and triangular, they are so in an analogical sense. As Sellars says,

The essential feature of the analogy is that visual impressions stand to one another in a system of ways of resembling and differing which is structurally similar to the ways in which the colours and shapes of visible objects resemble and differ.9

In SK, Sellars elaborates on the analogy thus:

[T]he manners of sensing are analogous to the common and proper sensibles in that they have a common conceptual structure. Thus, the color manners of sensing form a family of incompatibles, where the incompatibles involved are to be understood in terms of the incompatibilities involved in the family of ordinary physical color attributes. And, correspondingly, the shape manners of sensing would exhibit, as do physical shapes, the abstract structures of a pure geometrical system.10

6 Sellars almost always uses ‘seeing’ as an achievement term.7 The role of sense impressions is actually a bit more complex than this. Sellars says, “I regard sense impressions as necessary elements in a theory adequate to explain not just ‘human behavior,’ but also ‘perceptual propositional attitudes’” (SSIS, p. 400). So, on the one hand, sense impressions simply function to explain the occurrence of thoughts, but, on the other hand, by examining their causes (e.g., whether they arise in normal perceivers in standard conditions) sense impressions serve to explain both abnormal behavior and non-veridical perceptual takings.8 EPM, p. 191.9 EPM, p. 193.10 SK, I, #64.

Page 4: phiorg.comphiorg.com/.../03/...Error-Theoretical-Account-of-Color-Concepts.docx  · Web viewPhD Student, University of South Florida Fink 15 For Wilfrid Sellars, there are two ways

Fink 4

The analogy, then, as deVries says, “is principally a matter of the relational structure of the two property

fields”11. DeVries worries that since the analogy only concerns extrinsic properties (i.e., ‘relational structures of

property fields’) it may fail to ensure an intrinsic characterization of sense impressions. But, when combined

with the ‘model’ of inner replicas, the intrinsic characterization is supposed to be secured. DeVries himself

argues that Sellars’ description of the model in EPM is misstated: the inner replicas are what the theory posits,

not the model for them.12 The model is the perceptible objects themselves and, for these, there is no conceptual

difficulty securing an intrinsic characterization. So, given that we grasp the relevant intrinsic properties of

physical objects, our ability to grasp the intrinsic properties of sense impressions depends on the precise nature

of the analogy. But, what Sellars says is that:

The pinkness of a pink sensation is 'analogous' to the pinkness of a manifest pink ice cube, not by being a different quality which is in some respect analogous to pinkness (as the quality a Martian experiences in certain magnetic fields might be analogous to pink with respect to its place in a quality space), but by being the same 'content' in a different categorical 'form'13.

This is a puzzling use of the term ‘content’ here, but it seems that Sellars must intend to highlight here some sort

of similarity or sameness of a purely phenomenal or non-conceptual sort. (Perhaps deVries’ concerns have to do

with this. It should at least be clear that Sellars himself doesn’t think there should be any difficulty grasping

such intrinsic properties of sense impressions.) Indeed, I suspect that Sellars thinks the pinkness in the two

cases is the same ‘content’ insofar as it is the same ‘object of perception proper’ – it’s just that that object is

categorized differently in each case.

The Story of Color on the Order of Knowing: (3) Relocation

The next major development in the story of color on the order of knowing involves a revision to our

concept of color that results from a clash of the manifest and scientific images. Although sense impressions are,

in the first instance, postulated by Jones as part of a theory, Jones’ fellows and pupils are successfully trained in

making a reporting use of the language of sense impressions. Indeed, Jones’ pupils and descendants come to

have direct and privileged access to their own sense impressions. For these reasons, we can take sense

11 DeVries, 2005, p. 209.12 DeVries, 2005, p 207 fn. 8. See also Sellars, SSIS, p. 408. 13 FMPP, III, #47.

Page 5: phiorg.comphiorg.com/.../03/...Error-Theoretical-Account-of-Color-Concepts.docx  · Web viewPhD Student, University of South Florida Fink 15 For Wilfrid Sellars, there are two ways

Fink 5

impressions to be part of the manifest image – our common sense image of the world developed through

observational and correlational techniques. Jones’ level of scientific theorizing does not disqualify sense

impressions from the manifest image, since they do not involve the postulation of unobservables.

The property of colored objects of the manifest image that poses a problem for stereoscopically fusing

the two images is their ‘ultimate homogeneity’ – by which Sellars means not that colored objects are always the

same color throughout, but that “colour expanses in the manifest world consist of regions which are themselves

colour expanses, and these consist in their turn of regions which are colour expanses, and so on…”14

The trouble comes when we attempt to reconcile this feature of the manifest image with a scientific

image which postulates not only proportionally vast regions of unfilled (and hence uncolored) space within

manifest objects, but describes the fundamental spatial occupants only in terms of their mechanistic properties.

Two problems present themselves at this stage: (1) color properties are not reducible to the non-colored,

mechanical objects and properties (and vast empty spaces between them) the scientific image takes as basic, and

(2) since they cannot be reduced, color properties seem to be causally inert – all the behavioral features of

material objects being fully explainable in terms of their mechanical properties. (Sellars’ account of the first

problem has been appropriately dubbed ‘the grain argument’.15) Sellars is committed to the idea that a

successful stereoscopic image would ultimately reduce manifest image objects, properties and events to those

more basic ones of the scientific image.16 The key principle guiding such a reduction is the following:

If an object is in a strict sense a system of objects, then every property of the object must consist in the fact that its constituents have such and such qualities and stand in such and such relations or, roughly,

every property of a system of objects consists of properties of, and relations between, its constituents.17

It is this ultimate irreducibility of color as a property of physical objects to systems of non-colored objects that

prompts Sellars to ‘relocate’ colors to the mind. The story is often referred to as the ‘relocation story’18 because

14 PSIM, p. 3515 DeVries claims that there are either two ‘grain arguments’, or one argument with two stages. The first argument (or first stage) is that, “colours (and odours, etc.) are not really properties of physical objects per se” (deVries, 2005, p. 227). The second argument (or second stage) is that, “the proper sensibles also cannot be modifications of the brain qua system of micro-particles” (ibid.). 16 What, exactly, is required for a successful stereoscoping of the images is a controversial matter. The only point I wish to insist upon in this context is that Sellars himself believed it called for ‘relocating’ color to the mind. See, SSIS p. 409 and the discussion of the relocation story below. 17 PSIM, p. 27.18 On the use of this description, see SSIS p. 409, Rosenthal 1999 and forthcoming, O’Shea 2011.

Page 6: phiorg.comphiorg.com/.../03/...Error-Theoretical-Account-of-Color-Concepts.docx  · Web viewPhD Student, University of South Florida Fink 15 For Wilfrid Sellars, there are two ways

Fink 6

despite the fact that at this stage of the overall story of color on the order of knowing there is already a sense in

which sense impressions are both colored and ‘in the mind’, we have seen that this is so in a derivative sense –

for up to this point Sellars holds that the fundamental context for ascriptions of color is as properties of physical

objects.

The relocation is the final major revision of our color concepts19. We are now at a point where we can

appreciate that, since color cannot possibly be a property of physical objects (since science, for Sellars, is the

measure of all things and colors are not reducible to the fundamental objects of the scientific image) color must

have all along been a state of perceivers that was categorially confused or taken for a property of physical

objects. Rosenberg explains the point this way:

What colors, within the Manifest Image, then are, in the final analysis, are conscious states of perceivers – states which, however, are systematically taken by those perceivers to be "independent existences," color quanta that are constituent ingredients of causally interactive spatio-temporal physical objects. 20

Sellars has much more to say by way of working out the details of the relocation (e.g., dealing with the second

stage of the grain argument), but these details need not concern us since my objection is to the coherence of the

relocation itself.

Re-evaluating Sense Impressions: What Really Makes Them Intelligible Concepts?

As Sellars presents the story, it is tempting to think that Genius Jones’ new sense impression predicates

become intelligible concepts solely on the basis of our grasping the model of inner replicas and our grasping the

analogy with the relational structure of the family of color concepts (where these latter are taken as properties of

physical objects). This would be a mistake.

A kernel of evidence for the insufficiency just mentioned can be found in PSIM when Sellars contrasts

Jones’ theory of thoughts with Jones’ theory of sense impressions. In an oft quoted, but less often fully

appreciated passage, he says:

Whereas both thoughts and sensations are conceived by analogy with publicly observable items, in the former case the analogy concerns the role and hence leaves open the possibility that thoughts are

19 At least, it is the final major revision that I discuss. Sellars does see further revisions as necessary for dealing with the second stage of the grain argument. It’s not obvious, however, that these revisions affect the manifest image concept of color, which is my primary focus here. 20 Rosenberg, 1982, pp. 325-6.

Page 7: phiorg.comphiorg.com/.../03/...Error-Theoretical-Account-of-Color-Concepts.docx  · Web viewPhD Student, University of South Florida Fink 15 For Wilfrid Sellars, there are two ways

Fink 7

radically different in their intrinsic character from the verbal behaviour by analogy with which they are conceived. But in the case of sensations, the analogy concerns the quality itself.21

Most commentators focus on the positive feature of the sense impression analogy – i.e., that the analogy

concerns the intrinsic character. While this is clearly crucial in understanding the difference between Jones’ two

theories, it is essential not to overlook the negative aspect of the sense impression analogy. Unlike the case of

Jones’ theory of thoughts, the analogy employed in Jones’ theory of sense impressions is, by itself, insufficient

for mastery of concepts of the newly introduced entities. Since Sellars holds that concepts are defined by their

functional or inferential roles22, it is the theory of thoughts and not the theory of sense impressions that makes

immediately intelligible the concepts of the entities it introduces (since, in the former case, the analogy

concerns, precisely, the conceptual role).

Although Sellars intends the overall story of color to be one of conceptual change, Jones’ theory of

sense impressions is not, taken by itself, a story of conceptual change. That is, it is not, primarily, about a

change in Jones’ color concepts, but about the introduction of an entirely separate concept – that of sense

impressions of color.23 We understand the conceptual role of ordinary color concepts (i.e. color as a property of

physical objects), but we cannot assume that an analogous conceptual role holds of sense impressions of color.

Sellars makes it abundantly clear that the analogy employed in introducing the concept of sense impressions of

color is only taken to concern the qualitative nature of color.

What would be required to spell out the conceptual role of the newly introduced concept of sense

impressions – as is required in spelling out the conceptual role of any concept – would be to spell out their

contribution to the system of language-entry, language-exit, and intra-linguistic uniformities – i.e., to spell out

the normative functional role they have in licensing reports, inferences and behaviors. For Sellars, spelling out a

conceptual role in such a way is at the same time spelling out both part of a system of semantical rules of

criticism and part of a system of laws of nature24.

21 PSIM, p. 35.22 See, e.g. MFC.23 Of course, Jones theorizes sense impressions of many things besides color. I am here simply drawing attention to the fact that, with Jones’ theory, we now have two distinct items: colors and sense impressions of colors. 24 On the relation in Sellars between ‘laws of nature’ and ‘semantical rules of criticism’ see Jay Rosenberg, Chpt. 7, p. 52. In what follows, I will focus specifically on the connection between concepts and laws.

Page 8: phiorg.comphiorg.com/.../03/...Error-Theoretical-Account-of-Color-Concepts.docx  · Web viewPhD Student, University of South Florida Fink 15 For Wilfrid Sellars, there are two ways

Fink 8

Although the existence of such laws is absolutely crucial to the intelligibility of the new sense

impression predicates, that fact is not something that Sellars draws attention to in connection with the theory of

sense impressions. Nonetheless, Sellars makes the general point in an early article entitled “Concepts as

Involving Laws and Inconceivable without Them”25 and it is a feature of concepts that remains at the core of his

thinking.26 In that piece and others on the topic, Sellars defends at least two claims about the minimal conditions

for being a concept that are relevant here: (1) concepts are defined by laws27, and (2) these laws must include

what Sellars calls ‘material invariancies’ of the concept – i.e., laws that go beyond what would be deducible

from purely logical principles defining the concept or the family to which it belongs via relations to other

concepts or families of concepts28. For, Sellars detects a circularity in resting at this general level (i.e., not

appealing to the ‘material invariancies’). He expresses this in CIL by saying:

Now it might seem that the fact that universals fall into this pattern of determinables and determinates provides us with at least a partial answer to the question, "In virtue of what are two universals different?" If two most determinate universals, Φ and Ψ, fall under different determinables, of course they must be different! Yet a moment's reflection shows that we cannot rest here. How are we to understand the difference of two determinables? How are we to understand the fact that a most determinate universal is a specification of one determinable rather than another? Redness isn't red; nor is Color a case of Color; Φ doesn't exemplify Φ. We thus find it difficult to put our finger on any distinctive contents for Φ and Ψ other than their relational properties with respect to the determinate-determinable structure. We seem, therefore, to be confronted by the following paradox: Each universal belongs where it does in the determinable-determinate structure, by virtue of being the universal it is;

25 "Concepts as Involving Laws and Inconceivable without Them," Philosophy of Science 15 (1948): 287-315. Reprinted in PPPW.26 While this feature of concepts does remain at the core of his thinking, the connection with ‘laws’ softens somewhat. See IM, CDCM, and Brandom’s use of the expression ‘material proprieties of inference’ to replace Sellars’ more rigid term ‘material invariancies’ (Brandom, 2014, p. 191; 1994, p. 247, p. 267). Nothing in my argument depends on which expression of the relation is correct.27 In CIL he says: “universals and laws are correlative, same universals, same laws, different universals, different laws.” (p. 296).28 In CIL, Sellars thinks of the ‘material invariancies’ in terms of possible worlds (which he calls ‘histories’). A family of possible histories is determined by a shared set of universals exemplified in each history of the family. Material invariancies are non-compossible exemplifications that are not logically contradictory, and as such: “these invariancies restrict the family to less than what we referred to as the ‘logically possible arrays of exemplifications of the universals’ – and are therefore not the invariancies which are exhibited in the formulae of logic…” (p. 301). So, for example, given that ‘cube’ and ‘banana’ are universals in our family of possible histories, it is a law of nature (not logic) that they are not compossible of a given object. This law and many others like it serve to provide the content of the concepts ‘cube’ and ‘banana’. If I (fully) grasp the concept ‘banana’, I know that: if x is a banana, x cannot be cubical. To the reader who thinks appeal to such material invariancies just rules out by fiat certain perfectly (i.e., logically) coherent and conceivable possibilities (as cubical bananas), Sellars responds by saying that all conceivable possibilities are part of some family of possible histories or other, but certainly not all such families. In other words, although our concepts ‘cube’ and ‘banana’ are not compossible, some closely related concepts of other families are. The important thing, of course, is mastery of the material invariancies of concepts of our family of possible histories. For, the obvious upshot is that, for Sellars, conceptual content is determined by physical, not logical, possibility.

Page 9: phiorg.comphiorg.com/.../03/...Error-Theoretical-Account-of-Color-Concepts.docx  · Web viewPhD Student, University of South Florida Fink 15 For Wilfrid Sellars, there are two ways

Fink 9

yet each universal is the universal it is by virtue of belonging where it does in the determinable-determinate structure.29

But a similar objection clearly applies to Sellars sense impression analogy. The point is that just as, in the

argument quoted, the merely “relational properties with respect to the determinate-determinable structure” are

insufficient to allow us to “put our finger on any distinctive contents” for any given (universal) concepts of that

structure, likewise the merely relational properties of color concepts that Sellars is trying to use to analogically

give content to sense impression concepts are equally insufficient for this task. Recall the quote from SK above:

[T]he manners of sensing are analogous to the common and proper sensibles in that they have a common conceptual structure. Thus, the color manners of sensing form a family of incompatibles, where the incompatibles involved are to be understood in terms of the incompatibilities involved in the family of ordinary physical color attributes.

The sort of incompatibilities that Sellars is referring to here, in attempting analogically to give content to

concepts of colors as sense impressions are precisely the ones he previously deemed insufficient for giving

content to (physical) color concepts (i.e., in the long quote from CIL above). In “Berkeley and Descartes”

Sellars describes sense impressions thus:

[F]or a case of red to have being-for-sense in a state of a perceiver (or of his sensorium) is neither for that state to be red as physical objects are red, nor for it to be red as conceivings that intend a case of red are red. The state in question (let us call it s) is properly characterized…by…s is {a case of red}, or s is a {red item} where to be {a red item} is to be a state that has a character analogous to the physical redness of a facing surface.30

Sellars appends a footnote to “analogous” that reads: “Thus, for example, a state that is a {uniform case of red}

cannot also be {a uniform case of blue}”31. It is clear, then, that the analogy does not extend beyond the merely

relational properties of the ‘family of incompatibles’ and, as such, is insufficient, by Sellars’ own lights, for

giving content to the new concepts.

So, in order that our concepts of sense impressions be intelligible and coherent, we need to spell out

their contribution to the system of language-entry, language-exit, and intra-linguistic uniformities (i.e., to spell

out their conceptual roles) and we need to do so in a robust way – i.e., in a way that not only insists on their

difference from other universals but shows this difference through examining the laws governing their

29 CIL, pp. 297-8.30 BD, p. 287.31 Ibid.

Page 10: phiorg.comphiorg.com/.../03/...Error-Theoretical-Account-of-Color-Concepts.docx  · Web viewPhD Student, University of South Florida Fink 15 For Wilfrid Sellars, there are two ways

Fink 10

application to particulars where these laws emphasize the relevant material invariancies. The sense impression

analogy, alone, does not do this.

When we recall that the motivation for introducing sense impressions in the first place was to explain

why some cognitions are veridical and others are non-veridical, we can appreciate that these laws must properly

connect sense impressions with properties of physical objects. So, qualitatively, sense impressions have

properties analogous to the properties of physical objects. But, this analogy only takes us so far. It only gives

us a handle on the qualitative aspects of sense impressions (provided we have a handle on the qualitative aspects

of the analogous properties) without developing the full-fledged laws necessary for fully intelligible concepts.

That is done by the rest of the theory. Sellars says:

Thus, sensing a pink cube is a manner of sensing which is conceived by analogy (a transcategorial analogy!) with a pink physical cube and which, though normally caused by the presence of a pink and cubical transparent object in front of a normal perceiver’s eyes, can also be brought about in abnormal circumstances by, say, a grey object illuminated by pink light or by a pink rhomboidal object viewed through a distorted medium, or in hallucination by, for example, a probing of a certain region of the brain with an electrode, or by the taking of an hallucinogenic drug after much talk of pink ice cubes. (My emphasis.)32

and in the EPM passage already quoted he gives the theoretical assumptions as:

[T]he model is the idea of a domain of ‘inner replicas’ which, when brought about in standard conditions, share the perceptible characteristics of their physical source.

The key, then, to understanding the theoretical laws that give content to our concepts of sense impressions is not

just the analogy with properties of physical objects. It is the causal laws connecting them with such objects.

Let redp be a property of physical objects and let reds be a property of sense impressions. Then the primary such

law is the following: if one is a normal perceiver in standard conditions perceiving a redp object, then one will

have a reds sense impression. Other important corollaries follow from this, but this causal law is really doing all

of the heavy lifting when it comes to making our concepts of sense impressions intelligible.33

32 SK, II, #4.33 Again, Sellars certainly does not emphasize these laws in relation to the content of concepts of properties of sense impressions. But, he does make opaque references to them in places – such as when he says, “In the Manifest Image, color is not identical with, though it is conceptually tied to, causal properties pertaining to the perceptual states of normal observers in standard conditions” (SSIS, p. 394). Although this claim is ostensibly about color as a property of physical objects, it should be clear that the conceptual tie to perceptual states does much more to define these latter than the former, since sense impressions are the (epistemologically) derivative concept.

Page 11: phiorg.comphiorg.com/.../03/...Error-Theoretical-Account-of-Color-Concepts.docx  · Web viewPhD Student, University of South Florida Fink 15 For Wilfrid Sellars, there are two ways

Fink 11

To appreciate this last point, an illustration will help. Suppose that it is a material invariance that the

only color predicate compossible with an object being a banana and being ripe is yellow. If so, then it is a law

that: For all x, if x is a banana and x is ripe, then x is yellow. But, given our theory of sense impressions, just as

there would only be one colorp property compossible with an object being both a banana and ripe, there would

correspondingly be only one colors property of sense impressions compossible with a normal perceiver

perceiving such an object in standard conditions: the one analogous to yellowp: yellows. So, in a very neat way,

the material invariancies that make up the conceptual laws governing sense impressions piggy-back on their

physical property analogues. And, thus these laws give content to the new concepts.

Criticism: The Incoherence of the Relocation Story

Can we make sense of others or of ourselves having sense impressions of color while at the same time

holding that no physical objects are colored? Are our colors concepts sufficiently well-defined to stand on their

own in the absence of their colorp concept analogues? It is crucial to point out that Sellars is not claiming that

physical objects were once colored and ceased being so: they were never colored – but we used to believe that

they were. Now, we can properly understand our previous mistakes, thinks Sellars, as unwitting projections

based on mistaking items belonging to the category of sense impressions as belonging to the category of

properties of physical objects. One gloss, then, on Sellars’ thinking would be the following. Colors were

originally taken (by the pre-pre-Socratics) as spatial contents. Our growing scientific knowledge forced us to

revise that understanding several times to try to fit colors into our understanding of nature, but the

inconsistencies were insurmountable. Our original notion of colors as spatial contents, however, did justice to

the phenomenology, if not the science. Our experience of color far exceeds what is merely thought about or

believed in: colors do indeed present themselves as contents of perceptual or phenomenological space and any

account of them must do justice to the perceptible qualities they present in such experiences. The correct

analysis, then, is that on either ontological interpretation (whether as property of physical objects or as sense

impressions) we have always been talking about the same perceptible qualities – so we are clear on the

‘contents’ that we are attempting to categorize, the problem is just that we have consistently gotten the category

wrong: colors have all along been properties of perceivers, not physical objects.

Page 12: phiorg.comphiorg.com/.../03/...Error-Theoretical-Account-of-Color-Concepts.docx  · Web viewPhD Student, University of South Florida Fink 15 For Wilfrid Sellars, there are two ways

Fink 12

There is a fatal flaw in this account. This is in part due to Sellars’ often idiosyncratic use of the term

‘content’ to refer to a perceptible quality (or ‘object of perception proper’), in a way suggestive of

nonconceptual content. Sellars presents his story of color as if it is a story of conceptual change, but really it is

about our evolving ontological classification of certain basic qualities or ‘contents’ which it is presumed we can

track despite either radical differences in the concepts by which we contemplate them or the absence of

sufficiently articulated concepts. This explains why Sellars never worries that the conceptual role of sense

impression concepts – on the relocation story – is insufficiently defined or developed for these to be coherent

concepts: he is not interested in establishing a generic similarity of normative functional roles of color concepts

identifiable across successive iterations of a manifest image framework; instead he presumes to have in mind (in

a framework independent way) a particular quality, about which his only interest is our ontological classification

of it.34

The glaring problem is that Sellars’ own critique of the Myth of the Given rules out the notion of

intelligible, consciously accessible nonconceptual contents. Further, Sellars’ own considered view on

conceptual change requires the presence of generic similarity of functional roles that are identifiable across

conceptual frameworks or theories. I have already indicated the ways in which both color as a physical property

and color as a sense impression of colored objects are concepts whose inferential roles are well-defined via

robust physical laws including material invariancies. I argue, in line with Sellars’ own philosophy of conceptual

content that in the absence of a grasp of such inferential roles and material invariancies, grasp of any sort of

(non-logical) content is impossible. But, for sense impressions, the defining conceptual laws are those that link

them to their physical property analogues via notions of standard conditions and normal perceivers. And, since

the relocation story removes both of these links (without proposing new laws in their place), it leaves sense

impressions as unintelligible. Finally, even if coherent inferential roles could be specified for sense impressions

on the relocation story, it would still be an open question whether sense impressions should be considered the

final (ontological) home of color. For such a story to succeed – for the new concepts to be concepts of color –

34 See p. 4 above (and quote from FMPP). Consider also SSIS p. 408: “In the Manifest Image the primary concept of red is of red as the content of red physical objects.”

Page 13: phiorg.comphiorg.com/.../03/...Error-Theoretical-Account-of-Color-Concepts.docx  · Web viewPhD Student, University of South Florida Fink 15 For Wilfrid Sellars, there are two ways

Fink 13

the normative functional role of the new concepts would have to bear at least generic similarity to previous

concepts of color.

Page 14: phiorg.comphiorg.com/.../03/...Error-Theoretical-Account-of-Color-Concepts.docx  · Web viewPhD Student, University of South Florida Fink 15 For Wilfrid Sellars, there are two ways

Fink 14

Works Cited

Brandom, R. B. From Empiricism to Expressivism: Brandom Reads Sellars. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, (2014).

Brandom, Robert B. “Pragmatism, Inferentialism, and Modality in Sellars’s Arguments against Empiricism.” Empiricism, Perceptual Knowledge, Normativity, and Realism, Willem A deVries, editor, Oxford: Oxford University Press, (2009).

Brandom, Robert B. Online lectures from his Fall 2009 Seminar on Sellars at the University of Pittsburgh available at www.pitt.edu/~brandom/phil-2245/, (2009).

Brandom, R. B. (1994). Making It Explicit. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, (1994).

De Vries, Willem A. Wilfrid Sellars. Montreal: McGill-Queen's Univ Pr, (2005).

DeVries, Willem A. "Sellars Vs. McDowell On The Structure Of Sensory Consciousness." Diametros: An Online Journal Of Philosophy 27.(2011): 47-63.

O'Shea, J “The Central Importance of Sellars' Theory of Conceptual Change”, (Conference presentation) College de France, Paris, (May 18-19, 2009) found at https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=pJUzKZ41w-E .

Rosenberg, Jay F. Wilfrid Sellars: Fusing The Images. Oxford: Oxford Univ Pr, (2007).

Rosenthal, David M. Sensory quality and the relocation story. Philosophical Topics 26 (1-2) (1999): 321-50.

Rosenthal, David M. “Quality Spaces, Relocation, and Grain,” in the volume from the Sellars Centenary Conference in Dublin, 2012, O’Shea, J. R. (ed.) (forthcoming).

Sellars, Wilfrid. “Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind.” Science, Perception and Reality, Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview Publishing Co., (1991). [Cited above as EPM.]

Sellars, Wilfrid. “Phenomenalism.” Science, Perception and Reality, Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview Publishing Co., (1991). [Cited above as PHM.]

Sellars, Wilfrid. “Philosophy and the Scientific Image of Man.” Science, Perception and Reality, Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview Publishing Co., (1991). [Cited above as PSIM.]

Sellars, Wilfrid. "Foundations for a Metaphysics of Pure Process." (The Carus Lectures) The Monist 64 (1981): 3-90. [Cited above as FMPP.]

Sellars, Wilfrid. "Behaviorism, Language And Meaning." Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 61 (1980): 3-25. [Cited above as BLM.]

Sellars, Wilfrid. “Berkeley and Descartes: Reflections on the ‘New Way of Ideas’”. In Studies in Perception: Interpretations in the History of Philosophy and Science, P. K. Machamer & R. G. Turnbull (eds), 259-311. Columbus, OH: Ohio State University Press. (1977). [Cited above as BD.]

Sellars, Wilfrid. "The Structure of Knowledge”, in Action, Knowledge and Reality: Studies in Honor of Wilfrid Sellars, edited by Hector-Neri Castañeda, Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1975: 295-347. [Cited above as SK.]

Sellars, Wilfrid. "Meaning as Functional Classification." Synthese 27 (1974): 417-37. [Cited above as MFC.]

Sellars, Wilfrid. "Science, Sense Impressions, And Sensa: A Reply To Cornman." Review Of Metaphysics 24.(1971): 391-447. [Cited above as SSIS.]

Sellars, Wilfrid. The Notre Dame Lectures (bootleg version) http://www.pitt.edu/~brandom/phil-2245/downloads/Sellars.The.Notre.Dame.Lectures.March.1.pdf. (1969-1986).

Page 15: phiorg.comphiorg.com/.../03/...Error-Theoretical-Account-of-Color-Concepts.docx  · Web viewPhD Student, University of South Florida Fink 15 For Wilfrid Sellars, there are two ways

Fink 15

Sellars, Wilfrid. "The Identity Approach To The Mind-Body Problem." Review Of Metaphysics 18 (1965): 430-451. [Cited above as IAMB.]

Sellars, W. (1957). “Counterfactuals, Dispositions, and the Causal Modalities.” in Minnesota Studies in The Philosophy of Science, vol. II, Herbert Feigl, Michael Scriven, and Grover Maxwell, eds., University of Minnesota Press: Minneapolis, pp. 225–308.

Sellars, Wilfrid. "Concepts As Involving Laws And Inconceivable Without Them." Philosophy Of Science 15 (1948): 287-315. [Cited above as CIL.]

Stroud, Barry. The Quest for Reality: Subjectivism and the Metaphysics of Colour. New York: Oxford University Press, (2000).