ludwig wittgenstein, logical behaviorism and the meaning of sensation-language

Upload: reedisamonk

Post on 02-Jun-2018

225 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/11/2019 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Logical Behaviorism and the Meaning of Sensation-Language

    1/72

    Ludwig Wittgenstein, Logical Behaviorism and the Meaning of Sensation-Language

    A Thesis

    Presented to

    The Division of Philosophy, Religion, Psychology, and Linguistics

    Reed College

    In Partial Fulfillment

    of the Requirements for the Degree

    Bachelor of Arts

    Reed S. Arroyo

    December 2013

  • 8/11/2019 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Logical Behaviorism and the Meaning of Sensation-Language

    2/72

  • 8/11/2019 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Logical Behaviorism and the Meaning of Sensation-Language

    3/72

    Approved for the Division

    (Philosophy)

    Mark Hinchliff

  • 8/11/2019 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Logical Behaviorism and the Meaning of Sensation-Language

    4/72

  • 8/11/2019 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Logical Behaviorism and the Meaning of Sensation-Language

    5/72

    Acknowledgments

    First of all, I must thank Mark Hinchliff for providing constant help throughout

    which strengthened my thesis. I would like to thank Ricardo and Dree for supporting me

    and showing me the love that has inspired my passion for learning and intellectual

    culture. Also, I would like to thank Professor Robert Paul for introducing me to the

    writings of Ludwig Wittgenstein, and Trig Johnson for providing enlightening

    conversations. And finally, I am indebted to my girlfriend Serena for providing moral

    support and all-around encouragement.

  • 8/11/2019 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Logical Behaviorism and the Meaning of Sensation-Language

    6/72

  • 8/11/2019 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Logical Behaviorism and the Meaning of Sensation-Language

    7/72

    Table of Contents

    Introduction: The Meaning of What We Say ................................................................. 7

    Chapter 1: BehaviorismSpecifically, of the Logical Variety ................................... 11

    Logical Behaviorism ..................................................................................................... 15

    The Verificationist Backbone of Logical Behaviorism ................................................ 19

    Some Objections ........................................................................................................... 23

    Chapter 1 Conclusion .................................................................................................... 24

    Chapter 2: Wittgenstein's Proof of the Irrelevancy of Private Mental-States to

    Meaning ........................................................................................................................... 27

    More Counter-examples to the Classical View ............................................................ 33

    Wittgenstein's Theory of Observable Meaning ............................................................ 36

    Chapter 2 Conclusion .................................................................................................... 48

    Chapter 3: Wittgenstein as a Type of Behaviorist ....................................................... 51

    The Similarities ............................................................................................................. 51

    The Differences ............................................................................................................. 54

    Objections ..................................................................................................................... 56

    Conclusion ....................................................................................................................... 65

    Bibliography .................................................................................................................... 67

  • 8/11/2019 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Logical Behaviorism and the Meaning of Sensation-Language

    8/72

  • 8/11/2019 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Logical Behaviorism and the Meaning of Sensation-Language

    9/72

  • 8/11/2019 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Logical Behaviorism and the Meaning of Sensation-Language

    10/72

  • 8/11/2019 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Logical Behaviorism and the Meaning of Sensation-Language

    11/72

    Introduction: The Meaning of What We Say

    358. But isn't it our meaning it that gives sense to the sentence? (Andhere, of course, belongs the fact that one cannot mean a senseless

    series of words.) And 'meaning it' is something in the sphere of the

    mind. But it is also something private! It is the intangible something;

    only comparable to consciousness itself. How could this seem

    ludicrous? It is, as it were, a dream of our language.1

    A younger version of myself used to think, It is strange that each person lives a

    private life, and yet people use language to bridge the gaps between each other. When I

    say something about my private experience, only I know the meaning of what I am

    saying, and it is only an unexplainable happy fortune of ours that we sometimes

    understand each other. It is a very lucky and strange chance event, when somehow

    someone is correct in thinking they understand the meaning of my words. That is to say,

    I believed that it was only by some unexplainable miracle that my school counselor

    understood what I meant when I said something like, The sadness I feel from my going

    to a new school. The counselor would say something, and I would think either Yes!

    That's exactly what I'm thinking or No, she failed to understand what I was actually

    saying. Perhaps, I thought, they understand that I am saying something and what I am

    saying, but not why I am saying it. Or something along those lines; but what I know for

    1Ludwig Wittgenstein,Philosophical Investigations, trans. and ed. G. E. M. Anscombe,

    P. M. S. Hacker and Joachim Schulte, 4thed. (Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell, 2009), 120.

  • 8/11/2019 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Logical Behaviorism and the Meaning of Sensation-Language

    12/72

    8

    certain, is that I thought that behind every thing I said, there was always some remainder

    of meaning that other people could not gather from what I was saying. In this sense, the

    true meaning of my words, I thought, was exclusively available to me.

    Like many people often do, I did not think about how the failure on part of other

    people to understand my mind, depended not on there being something which only I

    understood and that no one else knew, but on the failure of the utterances I had chosen to

    express myself in order to produce in other people the reaction I desired. In other words, I

    was so sure that the words I was using meant exactly and only what I wanted them to

    mean, and not something irrespective of what I wanted them to mean. As a consequence,

    I thought of the problem as irresolvable, and that I was doomed never to meet another

    person for whom my words meant the same thing as what they meant for me. Not until

    much later, did I start to think that what I chose to say as a means to express myself,

    meant something irrespective of my personal caprice. Not until later, did I realize that

    language was like a set of tools available to all, and that I just had to learn how to use the

    right tools in the right circumstances. Before, it was like I was using a saw when I needed

    to use a hammer; and yet since I felt so sure that the saw I was using was actually the

    hammer I needed, I thought that other people must somehow be fundamentally

    disconnected from the dreams and desires of my mind; or, I thought not that the tool was

    the same one in the same toolbox everyone had, but that it was my tool fashioned

    exclusively for my purposes. In reality though, as I now realize, the meaning of what I

    convey to others consists in the specific tools I use, but which everyone has access to.

    Therefore, it is not a question of an irresolvable gap between people's minds, but of the

    choice of tools we use in particular circumstances. If what I want is for a person to

  • 8/11/2019 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Logical Behaviorism and the Meaning of Sensation-Language

    13/72

    9

    understand me as meaning X, well then naturally I have to choose the tool which

    effectively means Xand that there is such a tool will be an observable fact of our

    language. If I fail to use the right tool, then naturally I will feel misunderstood.

    When many people encounter Behaviorism for the first time, they immediately

    and violently rejected it because they think it is absolutely misguided. People like this

    tend to believe there are two relevant facts: people's private lives and the language people

    use to mediate between their private lives. People accuse Behaviorism of completely

    forgetting about the essential private side of individual existence, which some think make

    interactions through language necessary in the first place. I, myself, used to have such a

    reaction to Behaviorism also.

    It was not until I encountered Wittgenstein, that I began to see how Behaviorism

    seemed more sensible. I realized that, it was not that we had to deny certain entities, since

    we had already defined those entities as unobservable and therefore not in need of any

    sort of observable disproof. Rather, it was that we should see the meaningfulness of what

    we talk about in terms of what we canobserve. This much more subtle point, seemed

    irrefutable to me. I no longer was even concerned with hypothetical private mental-states,

    since such things were now clearly excluded from the realm of meaningful things to talk

    about. Whereas I had once believed that the private aspect of my experience entered

    meaningfully into the things I said, I now thought that no such thing occurs, and so I was

    freed to abandon the pretense that my private experience somehow constituted the

    meaning of the things I said. The nonsense, which had me under its spell, was no longer

    disguised, and so it no longer seemed to threaten my understanding.

  • 8/11/2019 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Logical Behaviorism and the Meaning of Sensation-Language

    14/72

    10

    The reason, I think, an encounter with Wittgenstein is conducive to a new

    understanding of language about mental-states and sensations, is simply that he presents

    the argument in a way which somehow manages to escape most immediate rejections on

    the part of popular biases. When one first reads his discussion of sensation and

    knowledge of sensation, one entertains his scenarios until, almost unwittingly, one begins

    to see how easily his argument convinces. The argument is successful because it makes

    clear the exact sense of 'private mental-state thatis being denied as a necessary condition

    for meaningful talk of sensations. My claim is that when a person has been thoroughly

    convinced that Wittgenstein's theory is correct, she implicitly becomes a type of

    Behaviorist. This is because I see in the argument of Wittgenstein that has convinced me,

    essentially the same argument as a certain type of Behaviorism that had previously not

    convinced me. Perhaps my understanding of the original Wittgensteinian position is

    wrong, and therefore my understanding of the Behaviorism that I take to be similar to

    Wittgenstein is also ill founded. I plan to show this is not the case, by first giving an

    overview of Behaviorism in Chapter One, and then giving an explanation of the

    interpretation of Wittgenstein that I endorse and which I claim is similar to Behaviorism

    in Chapter Two. In Chapter 3, after I have presented both Wittgenstein and Behaviorism

    separately, I will argue for their affinity. I will argue that both Wittgenstein and Logical

    Behaviorism reject any theory that claims private mental-states necessarily enter into the

    meaningfulness of language about sensation; and finally I will propose a preliminary

    point of departure for future research into the subject.

  • 8/11/2019 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Logical Behaviorism and the Meaning of Sensation-Language

    15/72

    Chapter 1: BehaviorismSpecifically, of the

    Logical Variety

    In this chapter, we will give a general overview of Behaviorism, and specifically

    focus on Logical Behaviorism. The latter, will serve to give us a rigorous and logical

    perspective on certain issues concerning the nature of language. Although, arguably,

    there are many affects and poetic experiences that can deepen our awareness of

    language's formal complexity, such things do not have any definitive thesis and therefore

    cannot yield certain knowledge in a regular way. If our goal is a systematic explanation

    of language, we require something more tractable; and apart from the research projects of

    linguistics, there are questions which warrant a more philosophical and general approach.

    Logical Behaviorism is potentially one coherent and systematic approach to certain

    aspects of language, in that it has well-formulated and fundamental axioms meant for the

    parceling out of linguistic meaning. Between three emblematic versions, or camps, of

    behaviorism--logical, methodological and psychological--it is only logical behaviorism

    that directly addresses questions of language and meaning. Directly, in the sense of it

    tackling our most ordinary and typical use of language; and as opposed to 'indirectly' in

    the sense of only concerning a theoretical discourse and not plain and ordinary language.

    Unlike the other versions of behaviorism, the implications stemming from logical

    behaviorism strike at the heart of meaning in its most general form, the language we use

  • 8/11/2019 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Logical Behaviorism and the Meaning of Sensation-Language

    16/72

    12

    every day. It is primarily the semantic theory at the heart of logical behaviorism that

    concerns us.

    There is much more to be said specifically about logical behaviorism, but first, we

    should understand what is meant by behaviorism more generally. One concise definition

    that can serve our purposes is put this way:

    Behaviorism is any psychology that sees its mission as the explanation

    of behavior and accepts stimuli (more generally, situations) and

    responses as its basic data...Science aims at understanding publicly

    observable happenings in the world, and the only such eventsavailable to psychology are responses and the situations in which they

    occur.2

    In other words, behaviorism is the theory that says animal behavior (of course, this

    includes human verbal behavior) can and should be explained without any reference to

    unobservable mental states that an individual might or might not possess, simply by

    reference to the observable forms of behavior within given environmental circumstances.

    This theory therefore restricts psychological data to include only observable stimuli-

    response patterns, and not any hypothetical mental states. Even more broadly put,

    behaviorism chooses a 'stimuli-response' model of psychology as opposed to a 'stimuli-

    mental state-response' model.3The reason for this choice is that any supposed intervening

    mental state is in principle unobservable, and is therefore not at all appropriate for the

    determination of behavioral theories and experiments. This is not at all yet to say that

    behaviorism necessarily denies the being of private subjective experiences, only that it

    does not deem them relevant to an explanation of behavior, since it views the sources of

    2Gregory A. Kimble, Behaviorism and Unity in Psychology, Current Directions in

    Psychological Science 9, no. 6 (2000): 208.3Kimble, Behaviorism and Unity in Psychology, 209.

  • 8/11/2019 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Logical Behaviorism and the Meaning of Sensation-Language

    17/72

    13

    behavior to exist essentially onlyin observableenvironmental and physiological

    conditions:

    According to this principle, the observation sentences needed to

    provide the basis for an empirical science of psychology cannot beintrospective protocols describing the private experiences of a singleindividual. What are needed in order to put psychology on a proper

    scientific footing are objective records of publicly observable

    behavioral events--supplemented where appropriate by objectiverecords of the associated physiological events occurring beneath the

    skin.4

    It is not the case in behaviorism that mental states are necessary explanans of behavior,

    and behavioral principles alone are sufficient for the task of explanation. The question, of

    whether behaviorism denies mental states in totois not important for our immediate

    purposes, since what is important is that behaviorism certainly does not say such states

    are relevant to a psychological explanation of human behavior.

    To be clear, and in order to not be accused of misrepresenting behaviorism in all

    its vastness, there are strands of behaviorism that allow for inferences that use theoretical

    concepts such as that of the 'intervening variable'. In other words, there are behaviorisms

    which have practically 'S-I-R' models whereI issome intervening variable like a mental-

    state.2But, nevertheless, these are still types of behaviorisminsofar as the intervening

    variables are acknowledged as 'abstractions without material existence' 3unlike the

    observable environmental stimuli and behavioral responses which are essential. These

    abstractions, apparently, are used as explanatory ornaments even though they are, strictly

    speaking, irrelevant to behaviorism's practice.

    4U. T. Place, A Radical Behaviorist Methodology for the Empirical Investigation of

    Private Events,Behavior and Philosophy20, no. 2 (1993): 30.

  • 8/11/2019 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Logical Behaviorism and the Meaning of Sensation-Language

    18/72

    14

    There are several major types of behaviorism, one of which ismethodological

    behaviorism. This version of behaviorism is most basic, in that it is simply a normative

    view concerning the way psychologyshouldbe done:

    Methodological behaviorism involves a widely accepted professionalorientation towards how one should conduct psychological research

    in general.5

    According to this theory, psychologists shouldn't use concepts which are in principle

    supposed to reference unobservable mental-states, since they add nothing to explaining

    human behavior, and at worst they only add confusion:

    According to methodological behaviorism, reference to mental states,

    such as an animal's beliefs or desires, adds nothing to what psychologycan and should understand about the sources of behavior. Mentalstates are private entities which, given the necessary publicity of

    science, do not form proper objects of empirical study.6

    As a consequence of this view, behavioral science is seen as absolutely and exclusively

    concerned with observable things like animal behavior and environmental circumstances,

    and not with things that subsist only in and through conjecture. By extension, this

    program is also a way to regulate what sort of language is acceptable in psychological

    explanation.

    Another major type of behaviorism ispsychological behaviorism. The

    distinguishing characteristic of this theory is that it claims that the sources of human

    behavior can be exhaustively explained without reference to mental states. This theory is

    5Willard Day, On the Difference between Radical and Methodological Behaviorism,

    Behaviorism11, no. 1 (1983): 91.6George Graham, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy,s.v. Behaviorism, ed.

    Edward N. Zalta, accessed December 4, 2013,

    http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2010/entries/behaviorism.

  • 8/11/2019 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Logical Behaviorism and the Meaning of Sensation-Language

    19/72

    15

    similar to methodological behaviorism, but it is construed on positive grounds as a claim

    about what behaviorism cando unlike methodological behaviorism's focus on what

    behavioral scienceshould notdo.

    Logical Behaviorism

    The last, and most pertinent for our purposes, version of behaviorism is logical

    behaviorism. Logical behaviorism is a thesis about the meanings of mental terms and thus

    of sentences in which mental terms occur. Logical behaviorists claim that the meaning of

    mental-state sentences can be reduced to the meaning of equivalent sentences that only

    mention observable behavioral phenomena. For example, according to logical

    behaviorism, any sentence in which a mental term occurs such as Wittgenstein believes

    that going out into the cold is bad can be accurately translated into a sentence like It is

    the case that Wittgenstein rarely or never goes outside when it is cold and when he does

    so, he reacts negatively. In other words, logical behaviorism is a theory about the

    meaningandsemantics of mental term containing expressions, in that it claims that such

    expressions can be reduced to expressions equivalent in meaning, and that this can

    happen without any loss of semantic information. The theory therefore claims that this

    translational work can be done correctly without sacrificing anything which is not

    capturable by the newly translated sentence; the two expressions (the one with mental-

    predicates and the other without) are semantically identical such that they are

    interchangeable without any significant difference in what they actually express; and, an

  • 8/11/2019 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Logical Behaviorism and the Meaning of Sensation-Language

    20/72

    16

    analytical reconstruction of the two sentences would yield the same meaning. Similarly,

    although the sentences are different, they express the same proposition since they are

    both true in the same exact circumstances. Put very simply, for any expression or

    sentence X that contains mental terms, there is an equivalent sentence Y that does not use

    those terms yet means exactly (if translated correctly, of course) what the original

    sentence meant:

    According to this standard interpretation...statements containing

    mental terms can be translated, without loss of meaning, intosubjunctive conditionals about what the individual will do in various

    circumstances. So Ryle (on this account) is to be construed as offering

    a dispositional analysis of mental statements into behavioral ones.7

    Logical behaviorism does not simply claim that it is possible to give such an equivalent

    translation, rather it claims that since one version of the expression contains only explicit

    behavioral terminology, the other version must be seen as expressing this meaning and

    not the other way around; and so, although there is a type of equivalency between the

    two, the direction of the reduction is always from 'with mental-terms' to 'without mental-

    terms'. This is to say that, even though the two expressions can be used interchangeably,

    it is the one that is behavioral which is primary, and the other is seen as alternately

    expressing the same thing as the behavioral expression; the expression withmental-

    predicates is a shorthand way of saying thesameas the expression withoutthe mental-

    predicates:

    It says that the very idea of a mental state or condition is the idea ofa behavioral disposition or family of behavioral tendencies, evident in

    how a person behaves in one situation rather than another. When we

    attribute a belief, for example, to someone, we are not saying that he

    7Julia Tanney, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, s.v. Ryle, Gilbert, ed.

    Edward N. Zalta, accessed December 4, 2013,

    http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2009/entries/ryle/.

  • 8/11/2019 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Logical Behaviorism and the Meaning of Sensation-Language

    21/72

    17

    or she is in a particular internal state or condition. Instead, we are

    characterizing the person in terms of what he or she might do in

    particular situations or environmental interactions.8

    What must be extremely precise in order to be clear is the point that the mental-term

    version of a proposition does not represent a unique type of 'mental' proposition and it

    does not indicate the existence of any unobservable mental entity, rather, it expresses

    exactly what is meant by the version containing only behavioral principles. Whatever else

    we might think these expressions mean, according to logical behaviorism, they must

    actually mean what is paraphrasable in only observable behavioral principles.

    Although behaviorism as a whole is admirable as one framework among others, it

    is in logical behaviorism that we find the most controversial claims, if only because it is

    logical behaviorism which makes not only a normative claim, but a theoretical claim

    about the actualmeaning of mental-term sentences:

    [T]he meaning of a psychological statement consists solely in thefunction of abbreviating the description of certain modes of physical

    response characteristic of the bodies of men and animals.9

    What this means, put more directly, is that logical behaviorism claims that, in essence,

    mental-term language expresses nothing else than what the very same equivalent

    sentences in behavioral language express; and being that behavioral language obviously

    only references observable behavior, it follows that mental-term language only indexes

    8George Graham, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy,s.v. Behaviorism, ed.

    Edward N. Zalta, accessed December 4, 2013,http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2010/entries/behaviorism.9Carl Hempel, The Logical Analysis of Psychology, inReadings in Philosophy of

    Psychology, ed. Ned Joel Block (Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press, 1980-

    1981), 19.

  • 8/11/2019 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Logical Behaviorism and the Meaning of Sensation-Language

    22/72

    18

    that very same behavior and not another type of phenomena. In this way, logical

    behaviorism is first, a theory about the actual or real meaning of mental-term language:

    In its simplest form, logical behaviorism holds that terms in

    psychology can't be taken to refer to mental phenomena per se becausethe mental phenomena aren't directly, publicly observable.Consequently, they can't be measured using the instruments of physics

    for purposes of verification. Therefore, logical behaviorism advocates

    the semantic thesis that psychological terms must be taken to refer toeither (a) publicly observable behavior, (b) physiological states

    correlated with publicly observable behavior, or (c) dispositions to

    engage in publicly observable behavior...10

    And secondly, an implicit philosophical critique of the scientific illegitimacy of assuming

    the existence of immaterial, or private, mental entities based solely off the superficial

    form of mental-term language.

    Practically, the way one would proceed to think correctly in light of logical

    behaviorism, is rather straight forward. For example, with reference to the sentence 'Jones

    is vain', we can understand its meaning by thinking of it as expressing a proposition about

    Jones' habits of behavior which we can perceive, like his tendency to behave arrogantly

    or boast in front of others. In essence, such a sentence makes an indicative statement

    about his behavior up until the point of the utterance, and it implies that he has a

    disposition to act this way again. It does not express anything about a hidden cause of his

    behavior:

    The utterance, 'Jones is vain,' to laymen, is no contradictory invitationto an invisible cartesian peep-show, but the formulation of a law-like

    statement about one of Jone's tendencies, which has been inductivelyarrived at by observing Jones and can be tested for its truth or falsity

    by further observations...Jone's vanity is his actual or possible

    10Jay Moore, On Psychological Terms that Appeal to the Mental, Behavior and

    Philosophy29 (2001): 167.

  • 8/11/2019 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Logical Behaviorism and the Meaning of Sensation-Language

    23/72

    19

    boasting, encouraging conversations about himself, etc., and not the

    epistemically sealed cause of them.11

    The Verificationist Backbone of Logical Behaviorism

    At some point, any analysis of logical behaviorism will lead one down a path

    towards verificationism. The doctrine of Verificationism is closely influential on the

    motivating factors and underlying strategies apparent in Logical Behaviorism. For

    example, it is through a type of appeal to verificationism that logical behaviorism

    concludes the real meaning of mental-term language:

    In psychology, verificationism underpins or grounds analytical

    behaviorism, namely, the claim that mental concepts refer tobehavioral tendencies and so must be translated into behavioral

    terms.12

    Put succinctly, Verificationism is the idea that a non-analytic sentence is only genuinely

    meaningful if there is an empirical way to verify its truth or falsity. In other words, a

    statement only has determinate meaning (as opposed to associative significance[The

    sentence expressing it may be emotionally significant...but it is not literally significant"13])

    insofar as there is a relative circumstance or observation that would affirm or negate the

    11Morris Weitz, Professor Ryle's Logical Behaviorism,The Journal of Philosophy48,

    no. 9 (1951): 298.12George Graham, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy,s.v. Behaviorism, ed.Edward N. Zalta, accessed December 4, 2013,

    http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2010/entries/behaviorism.13A. J. Ayer,Language, Truth, and Logic (Harmondsworth, Middlesex, England:

    Penguin, 1991), 16.

  • 8/11/2019 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Logical Behaviorism and the Meaning of Sensation-Language

    24/72

    20

    truth of the statement. Therefore, according to verificationism, a sentence such as 'God is

    both nothing and everything',is without literal meaning since it is not clear what relevant

    observation there could possibly be for the confirmation of the sentence's validity:

    The central idea behind verificationism is linking some sort of

    meaningfulness with (in principle) confirmation.14

    To be clear, the relevant observation might not be actually possible for any given reason,

    so long as it is theoretically possible. So, for example, the sentence There is a cat in the

    center of the moon might as of yet have no actually observable relevant circumstance,

    yet we can at least know what experience wouldconfirm or disconfirm its truth; going to

    the moon's center would definitively affirm or negate the truth of the sentence. This is all

    to say that, the condition that there be a relevant observation or experience does not

    require that such an observation be practically realizable in the present moment, only that

    it be theoretically observable under the appropriate circumstances. Therefore, the

    difference between 'There is a cat in the center of the moon' and 'God is both nothing and

    everything' is that the latter is not even verifiable in principle, while the former is, given

    the possible relevant observation. Such observations and possible experiences, when

    relevant to any given indicative statement, serve as, or function like, necessary

    coordinates for the proper parceling of meaningful content. Within philosophy, there are

    many things that could be called versions of verificationism, which vary in the degree to

    which their interpretation of 'verifiability' and 'verification' are either more strict or less

    strict, more lenient or less lenient etc. What unites all of these types of verificationism is

    14Richard Creath, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, s.v. Logical Empiricism,

    ed. Edward N. Zalta, accessed December 4, 2013,

    http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/logical-empiricism/.

  • 8/11/2019 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Logical Behaviorism and the Meaning of Sensation-Language

    25/72

    21

    that they all assert the fundamental necessity of there being observable circumstances

    that inform the meaning of any truth-bearing sentence; and such that if these criterial

    circumstances are absent, the sentence is meaningless even if it has the form of a genuine

    proposition:

    We say that a sentence is factually significant to any given person, if,

    and only if, he knows how to verify the proposition it purports toexpressthat is, he knows what observations would lead him, under

    certain conditions, to accept the proposition as being true or reject it

    as being false...15

    As for the set of sentences considered 'meaningful' and the other set of those considered

    'meaningless', there is a clear distinction operative. The criterion of verifiability can be

    stipulated in a very inclusive way, so that even fantastical sentences are allowed;

    something like There is a Pink Unicorn in a cave under Lake Michigan is completely

    fine, since it is obvious what sort of experience would provide verification. On the other

    hand, a sentence like There is a completely undetectable and ancient entityin the room

    is not fine; this example in particular is very pertinent, since it shows how at first glance

    it looks like the sentence represents a verifiable statement to the effect of 'There exists a

    thing X', but because the thing in the sentence is described as 'completely undetectable',

    the sentence precludes having determinate meaning. This point is very subtle, in part

    because the type of meaningfulness verificationism concerns itself with is itself very

    particular, but according to verificationism, any sentence that asserts the existence of

    something-- which is also at the same time claimed to be something in principle

    unobservable-- is meaningless. Hopefully, these examples make the verificationist

    delineation between sense and nonsense more apparent.

    15A. J. Ayer,Language, Truth, and Logic, 16.

  • 8/11/2019 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Logical Behaviorism and the Meaning of Sensation-Language

    26/72

    22

    It should be clear by now how exactly verificationism plays a role within logical

    behaviorism. We have shown earlier that logical behaviorism concludes that mental-term

    language must actually be nothing other than talk about simple and complex behavior,

    since any genuine proposition must be verifiable in terms of relevant observations; and

    anything that we can observe, and that is also relevant to propositions which entail

    mental-ascriptions, is a type of behavior, not some unobservable hypothetical

    circumstance:

    For mental conditions, like all others, get the meaning they have from

    the circumstances in which we can know it is correct to apply

    them...Mental descriptions, like all descriptions, claim that theconditions criterial for their application obtain; hence they do not, andcannot, refer to private events but to tendencies for there to be public

    and physical events. To suggest otherwise is incoherent, for on the

    alternative which construes mental descriptions as analogous to bodilyones, there will be no criterial conditions for the mental words, so they

    will have no meaning at all.16

    While we see that Verificationism adapts verifiability as a criterion for meaningfulness,

    Logical Behaviorism shows that when faced with a proposition involving some sort of

    mental-ascription, it is sufficient to talk only about behavior if we wish to determine the

    sentence's meaning. The message of Logical Behaviorism is that indexing or representing

    unobservable objects or relations is notnecessary for determining the meaning of mental-

    term propositions; and by essentially asking the same question that is posed by

    Verificationism, it determines that only behavior is included in the set of relevant

    circumstances for mental-ascriptions:

    We cannot conclude, because mental terms are not dispensable, thatthey describe something spiritual beyond the body and its

    behavior...Behaviorism rejects the idea that the mind is a spiritual

    16Keith Campbell,Mind and Body, (Notre Dame, Indiana: University of Notre Dame,

    1984), 68.

  • 8/11/2019 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Logical Behaviorism and the Meaning of Sensation-Language

    27/72

    23

    thing, and rejects it principally because there can never be the public

    human experience of spirits upon which alone the idea and knowledge

    of such things could be founded. Behaviorist theory has no place for

    [hypothetical] mental objects.17

    Some Objections

    There are two popular counter-examples often used to refute behaviorism.18They

    each represent an extreme, and I will call one the Zombie scenario and the other the

    Intelligent Rock scenario. In the first scenario, you are supposed to imagine a body of

    some sort, moving and acting as humans do, but which does not have any mental life. In

    the second scenario, you are supposed to imagine an inanimate object, like a rock, that

    nevertheless has a vibrant mental life. Both scenarios are meant to show the implicit

    disconnection between observable behavior and unobservable private mental-experience.

    It is obvious why both scenarios fail though, in that they are not even clearly sensical. For

    example, if I imagine the Zombie is observably identicalto the person I call my mother,

    then I have no reason to think it has any less of a mental-state than my mother. Or, if the

    intelligent rock has never spoken to me, or moved, or made any other observable

    difference in its surroundings, then I am clearly not justified in thinking that it is any

    different from a normal rock. For either counter-example to succeed, we are implictly

    supposed to think that the Zombie does differ from a human in some observable way, or

    17Keith Campbell,Mind and Body,61.18Alex Byrne, Behaviourism, inA Companion to the Philosophy of Mind, ed. Samuel

    Guttenplan (Oxford: Blackwell, 1994), 132-140.

  • 8/11/2019 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Logical Behaviorism and the Meaning of Sensation-Language

    28/72

    24

    that the Intelligent Rock doessomehow behave differently than a normal rock. But this is

    no refutation of behaviorism. No, rather, it only proves the point that we require

    behavioral criteria to differentiate between categories of mental and non-mental.

    Chapter 1 Conclusion

    The facet of Logical Behaviorism that concerns us can be summarized by saying

    it is a behaviorist view which provides a semantic theory for the meaning of expressions

    which involve ascriptions of mental-predicates. Unlike other types of behaviorism,

    Logical or Analytical Behaviorism offers a theory of what mental terms actually mean, as

    opposed to just stating how we should view them in light of a certain scientific pursuit.

    Other types of behaviorism might only offer a normative positionhow things should be

    doneor they might attempt to exclude certain terms from their practice completely, but

    Logical Behaviorism does not attempt to exclude or regulate any terms so much as it sets

    out to describe them in their unperturbed actuality. In fact, Logical Behaviorism describes

    these terms by appealing to their conditions of assertability and/or truth, and to their

    usage; and in doing so, ventures to describe their real nature. Closely tied to the method

    of verification and the notions of truth and assertability conditions, is the concept of

    'usage' most often associated with the philosopher Ludwig Wittgenstein. As we will see

    later in Chapter 3, Wittgenstein's theory of the meaning of so-called mental-terms or,

    'sensation-language', is very similar to Logical Behaviorism's theory. We will see how

    they can be compared in light of their similar conclusions, and how they can be

  • 8/11/2019 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Logical Behaviorism and the Meaning of Sensation-Language

    29/72

    25

    contrasted in light of their different methods for reaching the conclusions. But first,

    before we speak about the theoretical affinities between Wittgenstein's theory and

    Logical Behaviorism, we will proceed in Chapter 2 to give a description of Wittgenstein's

    theory of sensation-language.

  • 8/11/2019 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Logical Behaviorism and the Meaning of Sensation-Language

    30/72

  • 8/11/2019 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Logical Behaviorism and the Meaning of Sensation-Language

    31/72

    Chapter 2: Wittgenstein's Proof of the Irrelevancy

    of Private Mental-States to Meaning

    This chapter will focus exclusively on the Wittgenstein of thePhilosophical

    Investigations. Specifically, the questions that we will set out to answer include: what

    was Wittgenstein's theory of the meaning of terms and expressions that involve mental-

    state ascriptions? How does he construct his argument? What opposing view did he

    respond to? Was he right? And ultimately, does our interpretation of Wittgenstein imply

    that he had views that were similar to Logical Behaviorism?

    The classical view regarding the meaning of sensation-language to which

    Wittgenstein responded, was the view that expressions like I have a pain or Serena has

    an ache refer to mental-states or sensations which are the private experience of the

    subject of the attributed property; it is not the mere claim that the experience is a token

    example of a generic type, rather it claims that the experience is itself essentially private

    and only available to a single observer. Put another way, the classical view took the terms

    'pain' and 'ache' to refer to private sensations, or private experiences of mental qualities.

    So, under the classical view, 'pain' would refer to a thing which we all might experience

    individually, but which we only ever experience in isolation from others. Therefore, I can

    speak of knowing that another person is in pain, but not of knowing the pain itself which

    only she is privy to. Or, if we think of each person's body as a box, and the pain as a

    thing, we can say that only the person who has the box can experience the thing inside;

  • 8/11/2019 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Logical Behaviorism and the Meaning of Sensation-Language

    32/72

    28

    and, by extension under the classical view, when a person expresses that she has a

    sensation, the meaning of her utterance is determined by the thing inside of the box which

    only she can observe.

    To sum up the Wittgensteinian position, which this chapter explores, and that

    refutes the classical view, we can say that it is the position which denies that such things

    in the private domain of individual experiences have any causal or logical connection to

    the meaningof mental-terms. In other words, the meaningof expressions that we might

    wrongly take to be dependent on private mental-states, is actually never determined by or

    dependent on any sort of private mental-entity. We will show that this position really has

    nothing to do with the denial of any set of entities in toto, but rather with the denial of

    any causal or logical connection between a particular hypothetical set of things and the

    meaning of certain terms and expressions. We can call the set of terms and expressions,

    the set of sensation-languagewhich is to say the set of all terms and expressions we

    take to be relevant to propositions about 'mental-properties'; and, we can call the set of

    hypothetical private entities, the set ofprivatemental states. The theory which this paper

    endorses, as a Wittgensteinian theory of sensation-language, denies that there is any

    logical or causal connection between the elements of the two separate sets described

    above; specifically, it denies that there is a connection between the meaning of the

    elements in the first set and the being of the objects in the second set.

    Before we set out to describe the theory we endorse in more detail, let us quickly

    and preemptively clarify some possible misunderstandings. The first question one might

    have is, why do we choose to deny both a causal andlogical connection? Of course, these

    are different types of connection, and therefore cannot just be explained by the same

  • 8/11/2019 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Logical Behaviorism and the Meaning of Sensation-Language

    33/72

    29

    reasoning: a causal connection is one such that it expresses an empirical relation between

    an antecedent event and a consequent event; and a logical connection is a conceptual

    relation, such that one concept figures into the definition of another. What we mean to

    say in including both types, is that first, there is no function that the private mental state

    fulfills in the logical determination of the sentences' meaning; and second, the private

    mental state does notact as a cause of the meaning such that, the meaning of the

    expression alters according to whether or not the private mental state is actual. One

    might, under some influence from the classical view, still argue that the private

    experience occasions the utterance of the expression, and so acts as a cause of the

    utterance-event. But our question is not what causes you to say 'apple' over 'orange', but

    how is it that either 'apple' or 'orange' can mean anything effectively in the first place.

    We are not concerned with some hypothetical entity that causes the subject to utter an

    expression; we are concerned with the meaning of the utterance and the observable facts

    about the world that determine our understanding of the meaning.

    Another foreseeable objection to the view we just expounded, is that people

    obviously do experience things as individuals first and foremost; for example, it is true

    that we each have our own sense-organs, which operate for and within a particular

    human bodyand some would argue that there are events which only that body

    experiences. But the key point is altogether different; to the extent to which it is truly a

    private experience, we cannot speak about it. If we can speak about it, it is not a

    categorically private experience. The difference hinges on the distinction between a

    privateexperience which is in principle only applicable to oneperson, and numerically

    distinct applicationsof a certain mental description to particular persons. Two objects

  • 8/11/2019 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Logical Behaviorism and the Meaning of Sensation-Language

    34/72

    30

    can be qualitatively identical if they are of the same type (i.e 'This rock and that rock; this

    tree and that tree.'), and they can be numerically non-identical if they are separate

    instantiations of the same object-type. The theory we offer as the right one claims that

    anypossible experience we cantalk about is, in principle, one that could have

    qualitatively identicalbut numerically distinctinstantiations, and hence not be private in

    the sense which the classical view supposes.

    For example, one might say something like 'We all agree that we're looking at a

    rock, but how can we tell our experiences of the space within the outer-limit that defines

    the rock, are not different? What if, for me, there is a slight impression of blurriness

    within my experience of the rock, which you do not have?' And we could respond: 'Well,

    perhaps the thing which we agree is definitely a rock looks different to youbut different

    in what sense? In whatever sense you explain the difference,I still understand the sense

    in which they are different:

    294. If you say he sees a private picture before him, which he is

    describing, you have still made an assumption about what he hasbefore him. And that means that you can describe it or do describe it

    more closely. If you admit that you haven't any notion what kind of

    thing it might be that he has before himthen what leads you into

    saying, in spite of that, that he has something before him? Is it not asif I were to say of someone: "He has something. But I do not know

    whether it is money, or debts, or an empty till."19

    And so, the experience you have described is in no way representative of something

    'private'; rather, it shows only the degree to which and way in which your experience is

    different. And it does not prove that you are talking about a private phenomenon, so

    much as it proves you are talking about a public phenomenon that you in particular

    19Ludwig Wittgenstein,Philosophical Investigations, trans. and ed. G. E. M. Anscombe,

    P. M. S. Hacker and Joachim Schulte, 4thed. (Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell, 2009), 107.

  • 8/11/2019 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Logical Behaviorism and the Meaning of Sensation-Language

    35/72

    31

    happen to be experiencing in the present moment. If there was some feature of your

    experience that was wholly private, then we could not talk about it; because, if we could

    truly talk about it, then we would be talking about things that in principle do not depend

    on some categorically private experience. We now see how the person who claims that no

    one but he can know his own pain, mistakes a simple convention of our language such

    that what is incorrigible is the use of 'know' instead of 'believe' in reference to one's own

    pain, for some sort of deep incorrigibility about private mental-states:

    303. "I can only believe that someone else is in pain, but I know it if I

    am."Yes: one can make the decision to say "I believe he is in pain"

    instead of "He is in pain". But that is all. What looks like anexplanation here, or like a statement about a mental process, is in truthan exchange of one expression for another which, while we are doing

    philosophy, seems the more appropriate one.20

    Perhaps we should re-state the dilemma: the classical view would think it sensible

    to believe we can talk about experiences that are categorically private. The opposing view

    which we offer, claims that anything categorically private would be impossible to speak

    about ever; and that, no matter the complexity or seeming particularity of an experience,

    it is in principle an experience which anyone who understands the meaning of the words

    in the relevant statements could experience. It might be said, I do not know what it is like

    to be a female, since I do not have the proper biological make-up or I am not embodied in

    the appropriate way. Nevertheless, I know the defining differences in terms of biology,

    and I know what it is to have something, and to be something, or to feel sad and

    discriminated against etc. So, the experience 'typical' of being female is not something

    categorically undisclosed to me, so much as it just is not my experience. The key

    20Ludwig Wittgenstein,Philosophical Investigations, 108.

  • 8/11/2019 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Logical Behaviorism and the Meaning of Sensation-Language

    36/72

    32

    distinction here, perhaps, is that since I know the meaning of the words comprising the

    description, does not imply that the description applies to me; by the same token, given

    my understanding of the words describing the experience, I understand what the

    experiencewhich is not mineis. This is just like if a person were to tell me that I

    cannot understand his experiencethe experience he describes to me with languagebut

    I obviously can in a sense, since I understand what they are telling me I cannot

    understand. We must be careful not to equivocate the different senses of 'understand'

    which we are using. The fact, which we really mean to reiterate in such circumstances, is

    simply the fact that it is or is not the actual experience of a particular person at a given

    moment in time. This is all to say, whatever a truly and wholly private experience would

    be, it is not something that we can talk about; what we can talk about, is what we can

    agree we are able to simultaneously experience, given the right conditions. The

    precondition for any word having meaning, would be that there be at least one other

    person who has had the same experience and can agree that the word refers to that

    experience; and so, this would already violate the condition that the experience be wholly

    the possession of a single person. Therefore, there is absolutely no such thing as a private

    experience that we can also talk about. The extent to which we talk at all, is the extent to

    which we agree with others over the presence or absence of a thing in the shared

    circumstances; the extent to which we can mean anything, is the extent to which there is

    an experience which we share with someone otherthan ourselves.

  • 8/11/2019 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Logical Behaviorism and the Meaning of Sensation-Language

    37/72

    33

    More Counter-examples to the Classical View

    There are many more obvious counter-examples to the classical view, one is

    evident in this anecdote: A neuroscientist wants to isolate the neurological basis for

    experiencethat is to say, she wants to find the definite part of the brain without which a

    person cannot have experiences. But how will she do this? Perhaps she will selectively

    shut-off different parts of the brain, and then perform certain tests, like asking the patient

    different questions about his condition, or monitor certain physiological data. But what

    will this prove? Perhaps, at any given point in the process of research, she might

    permanently have destroyed the capacity for private experience, but just in such a way

    that all behavioral capacities and operations remain the same. How will the scientist

    become aware that she has crossed that limit? There is no conceivable way through which

    she could. Or, vice versa, she might only disable the behavioral capacity but retain the

    experiential capacityas if she had paralyzed the patient completely; but in general, in

    cases like these, what warrants us to say that 'the lights are still on' so to say, if not for

    behavior anyway? Perhaps certain brain activity we associate with experiencebut we

    only came to associate it after its correlation with other behavior. It seems that the only

    criteria for the supposed difference between experience and non-experience is behavior

    itself (including internal physiological behavior), and yet many of us refuse to admit that

    the meaning of such distinctions isjust a distinction between different forms of behavior.

    The whole confusion hinges on the neuroscientist thinking that by 'experience', she means

    some sort of unobservable thing, and not some complex of observable phenomena; if this

  • 8/11/2019 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Logical Behaviorism and the Meaning of Sensation-Language

    38/72

  • 8/11/2019 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Logical Behaviorism and the Meaning of Sensation-Language

    39/72

    35

    behavioral terms. To these worries we offer two responses. First, there certainly is a

    difference between things with consciousness and things without it; after all,

    'consciousness' and terms like it have a use in our language, and we do not use them with

    reference to just any object whatsoever. In other words, we do notpropose the thesis that

    sensation-language means nothing. On the contrary, we assume that such aspects of our

    language have a use, and proceed to explain the conditions under which such use is

    effective. Second, we might believe that the things we ascribe mental-states to differ in

    kind and not in degree from those we do not. From the outset though, this is a misleading

    perspective, since it is actually a difference bothin kind and in degree. Certainly the

    sensation/non-sensation distinction issui generis in the sense of us thinking it necessary

    and useful, but we say that insofar as it expresses a difference in kind it is a distinction

    that depends solely on a threshold within a continuum. The continuum we speak of is the

    fact of observable behavior, and the threshold is a point on that continuum past which we

    are warranted to speak of 'consciousness', 'experience', 'sensation', 'mental-state' etc.:

    284. Look at a stone and imagine it having sensations.One says tooneself: How could one so much as get the idea of ascribing a

    sensation to a thing? One might as well ascribe it to a number!And

    now look at a wriggling fly and at once these difficulties vanish andpain seems able to get a foothold here, where before everything was,

    so to speak, too smooth for it. And so, too, a corpse seems to us quite

    inaccessible to pain.Our attitude to what is alive and to what is dead,is not the same. All our reactions are different.If anyone says: "That

    cannot simply come from the fact that a living thing moves about in

    such-and-such a way and a dead one not", then I want to intimate to

    him that this is a case of the transition 'from quantity to quality'.21

    Hopefully, this perspective we now propose as the correct one, makes it obvious why we

    do not say a rock has consciousness, but we are sometimes almost tempted to say so of

    21Ludwig Wittgenstein,Philosophical Investigations, 104.

  • 8/11/2019 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Logical Behaviorism and the Meaning of Sensation-Language

    40/72

    36

    things like dynamic, self-regulating and self-adjusting complex systemssuch as

    computers, social movements and cultural memes.

    Wittgenstein's Theory of Observable Meaning

    What we will now call the Theory of Observable Meaning is not something that

    Wittgenstein explicitly mentioned or endorsed. At our discretion, we propose it as the

    theory implicit in his ruminations on sensation-language inPhilosophical Investigations.

    The most pertinent passage from the investigations that we will now look at is the

    passage containing the 'Beetle in the Box Experiment'. This thought-experiment is the

    best and most direct example of Wittgenstein's conclusive refutation of the classical view.

    In it, he paints a picture which contains so-called private mental-states, but that offers

    them no relevant causal position for what else goes on in the picture. That is to say, he

    entertains the classical views notionof a private mental-entity, only to show how no

    such thing really matters at all. In section 293, Wittgenstein wrote the following:

    Well, everyone tells me that he knows what pain is only from his own

    case!Suppose that everyone had a box with something in it whichwe call a 'beetle'. No one can ever look into anyone else's box, and

    everyone says he knows what a beetle is only by looking at his beetle.

    Here it would be quite possible for everyone to have something

    different in his box. One might even imagine such a thing constantlychanging. But what if these people's word 'beetle' had a use

    nonetheless?If so, it would not be as the name of a thing. The thing

    in the box doesn't belong to the language-game at all; not even as aSomething: for the box might even be empty. No, one can 'divide

    through' by the thing in the box; it cancels out, whatever it is. That is

    to say, if we construe the grammar of the expression of sensation on

  • 8/11/2019 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Logical Behaviorism and the Meaning of Sensation-Language

    41/72

    37

    the model of 'object and name', the object drops out of consideration

    as irrelevant.22

    Let us examine the structure of the argument. First, he asks the audience to entertain the

    idea that a word 'beetle' refers to the thing in the box of each person. Then, he supposes

    that the things in the boxes are all different from each other, or that the things are

    constantly changing in nature. Finally, he supposes that theword 'beetle' still has a use

    despite all of these previous suppositions; and by making this last supposition, he has

    already shown that the word 'beetle', insofar as it has such a use, does not depend on the

    object which we at first thought it referred to. In what sense does it not depend on it? In

    the sense of the hypothetical object within the box being completely irrelevant to the

    actual useof the word 'beetle'; and what is to differentiate the word from the mere

    utterance if not for its conformity with patterns of established convention? There is not

    even an indirect connection in such cases, since the thing in the box doesn't even

    remotely influence the actually possible usages of the word.

    It should be obvious how the Beetle in the Box scenario is illustrative, and

    analogous to the circumstances of all expressions of sensation. Knowing that all the

    expressions contained within the set of sensation-language are not meaningless (they

    have a sufficiently definite use), we have shown that they are meaningful despite any fact

    about the supposed thing in the box. The word 'pain' is just like 'beetle', in that it has a

    use-determined meaning; but if we think of its function as that of referring to a private

    knowledge or experience, we realize its actual use happens to be apparently very

    different. If we still assume it has such a function, and that we are just confused as to the

    22Ludwig Wittgenstein,Philosophical Investigations, 106.

  • 8/11/2019 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Logical Behaviorism and the Meaning of Sensation-Language

    42/72

    38

    facts about its actual usage, then howshouldwe positively think of it? There is no answer

    to such a question, and if we tried to describe the meaning of sensation-language

    according to such a pretense, we would be left describing nothing or being unable to

    describe anything.

    Wittgenstein shows that words such as 'pain', like the word 'beetle' in the thought-

    experiment, do not mean anything about private experience or knowledge. What he

    doesn't do in the experiment though, is say what such words do mean. We can only gloss

    over this question now, but a promising beginning is offered in this supplement to the

    scenario: Suppose a person in the imagined scenario has a thing X in their box, and

    suppose this thing requires water. Obviously, the person cannot just show other people X

    in a way which would directly communicate facts about X. Also, suppose the people in

    the scenario have a card-system, much like language except with cards instead of words

    and combinations of cards instead of sentences. In this card-system, the expression 'I

    would like some water' has a direct translation in terms of an analogous combination of

    different cards. Now finally, imagine that the person with X used card sequence 'Y' to

    express to other people that she would like water. We know that the card-expression has a

    definite use, since in all relevant cases in which it is used the same kind of events almost

    always followi.e another person retrieves water for the person who presented the card-

    sequence. One possible cause of our confusion with sensation-language might be that we

    think, because the hypothetical thing X required water, and the possessor of X eventually

    received water, that there is some causal connection between the two. When, in actuality,

    the relevant causal relation obtains between the water-retrieval and the person, not as the

    possessor of X, but as the utterer of Y. The effect of the water being retrieved has as its

  • 8/11/2019 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Logical Behaviorism and the Meaning of Sensation-Language

    43/72

    39

    cause the presentation of the card-sequence; and the causal power of the card-sequence

    has only as its cause the established fact of its usage being determined by conventions of

    behavior. The supposed fact that object X required water is entirely irrelevant in relation

    to the fact of the card-sequence causing such a possible change in the environment of the

    card-presenter. To be precise, what we are saying is that object X has no necessary role as

    cause in relation to what is caused when a person utters an expression or presents a

    sequence of cards; and, conversely, if we assume that sensation-language does

    something, even if that something is expression, then we can say that it doing so is

    sufficiently explained by observable (non-private) facts about the world. In other words,

    we could understand the meaning of the card-sequence entirely separate from knowing

    anything about X; we could in fact know nothing about X, but still know everything

    about the card-sequence Y. The supposed sensation that is the object of 'thirst', for

    example, is construed through the grammar of the word 'thirst'. We do not confirm that a

    person knows the meaning of Y by confirming anything about X; rather, for example, we

    might observe how the utterer reacts once the water-retrieval has been completedif

    they react a certain way, we say they understand the meaning of what they uttered,

    otherwise we say they do not:

    296. "Yes, but there is something there all the same accompanying mycry of pain. And it is on account of that that I utter it. And this

    something is what is importantand frightful."Only to whom are

    we telling this? And on what occasion? 23

    And,

    298. The very fact that we should so much like to say: "This is the

    important thing"while we point privately to the sensation is

    23Ludwig Wittgenstein,Philosophical Investigations, 107.

  • 8/11/2019 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Logical Behaviorism and the Meaning of Sensation-Language

    44/72

    40

    enough to show how much we are inclined to say something which

    gives no information.24

    If a person utters 'I am so thirsty', and we want to know if they understand the meaning of

    their own utterance in the relevant language, we do not search for an unobservable object

    in vain, but actually observe how they behave once they have obtained a beverage; if they

    react in a certain unconventional way, to a sufficient degree, we will be forced to

    conclude they simply do not know the meaning of what they ostensibly uttered as a

    means of expression. One might also object and say that the person is not using the word

    wrongly, he is just using the word to refer to a thing only he can possibly know is being

    referred to. If this is the objection, then it will require Wittgenstein's refutation of private

    language to defend his theory. For our purposes though, it can be simply said that a

    person has no standard of knowing whether she is actually referring to her own private

    experience and not something else, and that the 'private language' required for such a feat

    would be practically impossible. For one reason, simply because proof of a private

    experience would not only require that a person privately claim he has such an

    experience, but also that he confirm that other people do not have it; and this would

    require that he use language to describe his experience, and therefore nullify the assertion

    that he is describing something wholly private. Hopefully it cannot be any clearer that,

    things within the domain of 'private' knowledge like 'object X' have no relation to the

    understanding and explanation of how expressions we actually are ableto use mean

    things in the first place.

    24Ludwig Wittgenstein,Philosophical Investigations, 107.

  • 8/11/2019 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Logical Behaviorism and the Meaning of Sensation-Language

    45/72

    41

    What we have outlined now is the theory, which we call the Theory of Observable

    Meaning, which claims that sensation-language does not involve private mental-states.

    The 'classical view' believes the essence of communication lies in people understanding

    each others' private mental experiences:

    363. But when I imagine something, somethinggoes on, doesn't it?

    Well, something goes on and then I make a noise. What for?Presumably in order to communicate what went on. But how, in

    general, does one communicate something? When does one say that

    something is being communicated? What is the language-game of

    communicating something?

    I'd like to say: you regard it much too much as a matter of course that

    one can communicate anything to anyone. That is to say, we are soaccustomed to communicating in speech, in conversation, that it looks

    to us as if the whole point of communicating lay in this: that someone

    else grasps the sense of my wordswhich is something mentalthat

    he, as it were, takes it into his own mind. If he then does somethingfurther with it as well, that is no part of the immediate purpose of

    language. 25

    We have shown this is not the case since, first, the extent to which we can speak about

    something is the same extent to which it is in principle notprivate; and second, we have

    shown that the power of communication hinges on the grammar of different patterns of

    usage, which in turn hinge on the observable or public features of the world. It is not the

    case that we 'read off the facts' from some private mental object and think of the

    expression which bests represents it; no, rather, the object of the expression is construed

    on the basis of the grammar associated with its usage, including its connection to other

    expressions and contexts:

    371.Essenceis expressed in grammar.26

    25Ludwig Wittgenstein,Philosophical Investigations, 121.26Ludwig Wittgenstein,Philosophical Investigations, 123.

  • 8/11/2019 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Logical Behaviorism and the Meaning of Sensation-Language

    46/72

    42

    And,

    373. Grammar tells what kind of object anything is.27

    Language is not a circuit with a private picture on one end, and an expression which best

    approximates the picture on the other end. The objects which we speak of have their

    character made explicit in a circuit which only involves grammar and facts of the

    observable world. By 'grammar', Wittgenstein meant the shared experience of any given

    language's conventions of usage28i.e. When do we use a word or phrase? What occurs

    before its employment? What follows its employment? Etc. For example, when do we

    use the word 'dead'? In certain contexts only of course, like when an animal no longer

    exhibits certain physiological characteristics. This is what we mean by grammar.

    Wittgenstein resolutely denied the view that sensation-language operates

    according to a split between private mental-states, and their representative expressions.

    He proposed the opposite view, that if we speak of an object, it is an object which has its

    logical origins as a definite thing in the grammar which defines the contours of its

    relations to other objects and relations-between-objects:

    374. The great difficulty here is not to present the matter as if therewere something one couldn't do. As if there really were an object,

    from which I extract a description, which I am not in a position to

    show anyone.And the best that I can propose is that we yield to thetemptation to use this picture, but then investigate what the application

    of the picture looks like.29

    27Ibid.28Anat Biletzki, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, s.v."Ludwig Wittgenstein,"

    ed. Edward N. Zalta, accessed December 4, 2013,

    http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/wittgenstein/.29Ludwig Wittgenstein,Philosophical Investigations, 123.

  • 8/11/2019 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Logical Behaviorism and the Meaning of Sensation-Language

    47/72

    43

    In other words, it's not like a person uses language in an attempt to describe some

    indescribable private object for everyone to understand, but rather it is that the only

    object logically available ever is the one everyone can access on equal-footing by

    understanding the original set of expressions which defined the supposed object's

    particular presenceWhich object? The one with features x,y,z.....

    Another objection to the Theory of Observable Meaning goes like this: what

    about cases where only a single person discovers a new thing, and then reports back to

    others. For example, when an explorer discovers a new geographical location, he might

    go back to his society and describe his experiences to others. One might say he is

    describing something that everyone else can understand, but that he also actually has an

    image before his mind that he cannot put completely into words. In other words, he has

    an image that can be partly put into words, and partly not. In this case though, how can

    we say anything about what he still cannot put into words? It's not even obvious that he

    still hassome such part that he cannot put into words. One might also say that the

    explorer's words mean for him something over and above what anyone else can

    understand from the words; as if everybody else only understood the picture through bits

    and pieces, and the explorer understood the singular thing that the whole description

    applied to:

    280. Someone paints a picture in order to show, for example, how heimages a stage set. And now I say: The picture has a double function:

    it informs others, as pictures or words dobut for the informant it isin addition a representation of another kind: for him it is the picture of

    hisimage, as it can't before anyone else. His private impression of the

    picture tells him what he imagined, in a sense in which the picturecan't do this for others. And what right have I to speak in this

  • 8/11/2019 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Logical Behaviorism and the Meaning of Sensation-Language

    48/72

    44

    second case of a representation or piece of information if these

    words were correctly usedin thefirstcase? 30

    But our question concerns the meaningof the words, and these are not dependent on

    some private image in the explorer's mind. Imagine that it wasn't our explorer 'James'

    who discovered the new island, but some other explorer 'Frank', and that our explorer this

    time was in the position of hearing the words he would of otherwise used were he in the

    same position as before. In this way, we see how the description, as it were, stands alone;

    its meaning not determined by a private picture before the mind of any particular utterer.

    The classical view looks everywhere except where the obvious answer lies. This

    why Wittgenstein says:

    464. My aim is: to teach you to pass from a piece of disguised

    nonsense to something that is patent nonsense. 31

    What generates the classical view is an insistence on keeping the nonsense disguised as a

    real problem. In short, the classical view turns a blind-eye to the relevant facts, and

    focuses instead on some hypothetical and ambiguous process or entity:

    308. How does the philosophical problem about mental processes and

    states and about behaviourism arise?The first step is the one that

    altogether escapes notice. We talk of processes and states and leavetheir nature undecided. Sometime perhaps we shall know more about

    themwe think. But that is just what commits us to a particular way

    of looking at the matter. For we have a definite concept of what it

    means to learn to know a process better. (The decisive movement inthe conjuring trick has been made, and it was the very one that we

    thought quite innocent.)And now the analogy which was to make

    us understand our thoughts falls to pieces. So we have to deny the yet

    uncomprehended process in the yet unexplored medium. And now it

    30Ludwig Wittgenstein,Philosophical Investigations, 103.31Ludwig Wittgenstein,Philosophical Investigations, 141.

  • 8/11/2019 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Logical Behaviorism and the Meaning of Sensation-Language

    49/72

    45

    looks as if we had denied mental processes. And naturally we do not

    want to deny them. 32

    As Wittgenstein puts it, the classical view from the outset commits itself to

    particular idea that leads nowhere. It insists there is a process or a mental state essential

    to sensation-language, and yet leaves the nature of the supposed key element completely

    unexplained:

    426. A picture is conjured up which seems to fix the sense

    unambiguously. The actual use, compared with that suggested by the

    picture, seems like something muddied. Here again, what is going onis the same as in set theory: the form of expression seems to have been

    tailored for a god, who knows what we cannot know; he sees all of

    those infinite series, and he sees into the consciousness of humanbeings. For us, however, these forms of expression are like vestments,

    which we may put on, but cannot do much with, since we lack the

    effective power that would give them point and purpose.

    In the actual use of these expressions, we, as it were, make

    detours, go by side roads. We see the straight highway before us, but

    of course cannot use it, because it is permanently closed. 33

    In the passage just presented, Wittgenstein is speaking directly to the classical view's

    mistaken view that the actual usage of the expression is somehow derivative of or

    dependent on some other private mental essence. Let us elaborate by using the particular

    example of silent readingthat is, reading, not aloud, but only to oneself. When do we

    say a person can 'read silently'? We do so, for example, when we provide new material to

    a child, observe them for a period, and then ask them questions about the material.

    Assuming they had no prior knowledge of the material, we say, that because they

    obviously did not read aloud, there must have been some otherprocess that accounts for

    their competency in the material. But we cannot leave this mysterious process so vaguely

    32Ludwig Wittgenstein,Philosophical Investigations, 109.33Ludwig Wittgenstein,Philosophical Investigations, 134.

  • 8/11/2019 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Logical Behaviorism and the Meaning of Sensation-Language

    50/72

  • 8/11/2019 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Logical Behaviorism and the Meaning of Sensation-Language

    51/72

    47

    language-game of 'remembering'. And neither is the process of remembering nor the

    thing remembered categorically private.

    We can speak of a word or expression, and the thing to which the word or

    expression refers; the meaningof the word, can be given in terms of the being of the

    thingi.e the meaning of 'dog' can be explained in terms of the objects that are called

    dogs. The connection between the two, inheres within the established usage of the

    linguistic community:

    383. We do not analyse a phenomenon (for example, thinking) but a

    concept (for example, that of thinking), and hence the application of a

    word. 35

    And,

    384. You learned the concept of 'pain' in learning language. 36

    In other words, for example, when speaking of the word 'tree', we can speak of the

    concrete objects trees. But when we speak of pain, we cannot point to an object when we

    supposethat the object is private. So, we canspeak of the concept of pain, but that just

    leads us to speak of the application of the word'pain'. We suppose the cases are not

    analogous, since in one case the word refers to an observable object and in the other to an

    unobservable. But they really areanalogous, since what actually happens is we do use the

    word to refer to observable facts like: verbal reports, crying, cringing etc. If we abandon

    the presumption that 'pain' necessarily refers to an unobservable object, we can see the

    actual properties of the world that are essential to its application just like we can with

    trees! The appropriate circumstances for the use of the word 'tree' involve the observable

    35Ludwig Wittgenstein,Philosophical Investigations, 125.36Ibid.

  • 8/11/2019 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Logical Behaviorism and the Meaning of Sensation-Language

    52/72

    48

    tree-objects, just like the appropriate circumstances for the use of the word 'pain' involve

    the observable pain-objects, like crying, wincing, moaning and reports. It would be

    absurd to say that 'tree' doesn't refer to trees, but to something unobservable that we know

    after observing trees, but which is not a tree. Yet this is exactly what we do with 'pain'.

    We should not, in the case of sensation, want to turn a blind eye to what is actual and

    instead imagine some non-actual circumstance.

    Chapter 2 Conclusion

    For the ending of this chapter, we now move on to some 'deconstructive' passages

    from Wittgenstein, which will serve as excellent diagnostic tools for finalizing our lasting

    abandonment of the prejudices' of the classical view. Also, as we set out to answer at the

    beginning of this chapter, we will intimate some of the similarities between Wittgenstein

    and Logical Behaviorism.

    Notice, in these passages, the similarities between Wittgenstein and what we

    already know about Logical Behaviorism. They both beg the question, of, what are the

    criteria? They both insist on the necessary and sufficient role of observablefacts in

    ascriptions of sensation. Wittgenstein is adamant in showing that the ascription of a

    sensation does not happen in a vacuum, as if we were just spiritual minds telepathically in

    contact with each other and without need of the observable world's mediation:

    391. I can perhaps even imagine (though it is not easy) that each of

    the people whom I see in the street is in frightful pain, but is adroitlyconcealing it. And it is important that I have to imagine adroit

  • 8/11/2019 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Logical Behaviorism and the Meaning of Sensation-Language

    53/72

    49

    concealment here. That I do no simply say to myself: Well, his mind,

    is in pain: but what has that to do with his body? or After all, it need

    not show in his body. And if I imagine thiswhat do I do? Whatdo I say to myself? How do I look at the people? Perhaps I look at one

    and think, It must be difficult to laugh when one is in such pain, and

    much else of the same kind.

    37

    In this passage, first it is proposed we think of people in pain, but not acting typically like

    those in pain usually do, and instead having to conceal their normal reactions. We do not

    therefore conclude, since the typical pain-behavior is absent, that the pain is something

    unobservable to which no observable fact can be related. Rather, we say something about

    their disposition to react to another stimuli, given the fact that they are repressing their

    usual reaction; in other words, we say that their 'adroitly concealed pain' consists in, not

    the regular display of pain, but a modification of it, such that, for example, the person

    would have a hard time laughing and still maintaining their adroit concealment. The

    example of laughing while also trying to conceal pain, is just one way we can identify the

    criteria to which the particular ascription refers to. More simply, we do not just say a

    person is concealing her pain, and then assume that therefore she is essentially acting as if

    there were no pain at allif this were the case, there would be no difference between the

    absence of pain and the pain which is adroitly concealed. There still has to be some

    criteria to ensure the ascription is meaningful; perhaps not the same criteria as regular

    pain, but still something which differentiates the person adroitly concealing his pain from

    the person without any pain. One might still object, 'What if they are just amazing at

    concealing their pain, and they never showed any sign of it, as if it were actually not

    there.' But who told us they are in pain? They did notin fact they act in every way to

    37Ludwig Wittgenstein,Philosophical Investigations, 126.

  • 8/11/2019 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Logical Behaviorism and the Meaning of Sensation-Language

    54/72

  • 8/11/2019 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Logical Behaviorism and the Meaning of Sensation-Language

    55/72

    Chapter 3: Wittgenstein as a Type of Behaviorist

    In this final chapter, using what we already know from the two preceding

    chapters, we will compare and contrast Wittgenstein's theory with Logical Behaviorism.

    First, we will look at the similarities between the two. Then we will look at some

    important differences. Finally, we will engage with some objections to either view, and

    provide some possible answers. The main goal of this paper has been to convince the

    reader that Wittgenstein, when judged according to his thoughts on sensation-language,

    was a type of behaviorist. It has not been our goal, to show that either theory denies

    private mental-states; one is mistaken to draw that conclusion. In actuality, we have only

    shown that both theories categorically deny that private mental-states can be

    meaningfully spoken about. That is to say, we have shown that both theories deny that

    the meaning of sensation-language relies on private mental-states. It is in this sense, that

    Wittgenstein was a behaviorist.

    The Similarities

    Since we have already explained both of the theories separately, we know that

    both Wittgenstein and Logical Behaviorism deny that the meaning of sensation-language

  • 8/11/2019 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Logical Behaviorism and the Meaning of Sensation-Language

    56/72

  • 8/11/2019 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Logical Behaviorism and the Meaning of Sensation-Language

    57/72

    53

    thing, which is that they do not think private mental-states matter when discussing the

    meaning of mental language.

    Some might argue that the connection between Wittgenstein and behaviorism is

    tenuous at most. Admittedly, it seems Wittgenstein evaded answering the question

    altogether:

    307. Aren't you nevertheless a behaviourist in disguise? Aren't you

    nevertheless basically saying that everything except human behaviour

    is a fiction? If I speak of a fiction, then it is of a grammatical fiction.41

    Rather than give a direct answer to the question of whether he is a behaviorist, he

    qualifies the sense in which he believes everything except human behaviour is a

    fictionhe calls it agrammatica