yerpal sequences; a generative approach · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no...

199
Mireia LLINÀS I GRAU YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH Tesi Doctoral dirigida pel Dr. Josep Maria Brucart ( Ponent: Dr. Joaquín Domínguez ) Departament de Filolgia Anglesa i Germanistica Facultat de Lletres Universitat Autònoma de Barcelona Any 1990

Upload: others

Post on 19-Oct-2020

7 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

Mireia LLINÀS I GRAU

YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH

Tesi Doctoral dirigida pel Dr. Josep Maria Brucart

( Ponent: Dr. Joaquín Domínguez )

Departament de Filolgia Anglesa i Germanistica

Facultat de Lletres

Universitat Autònoma de Barcelona

Any 1990

Page 2: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

2.3-2 M-A sequences

2.3.2.O Introduction

I will consider M-A sequences to be those basically including a modal

or aspectual verb and an infinitive. The syntax of these sequences in

Romance has been the issue of much debate essentially because the two

adjacent verbs display a syntactic behaviour which indicates that the

structure in which they occur is "anomalous" - as will become clear in what

follows, French differs from other Romance languages in important

respects; i.e. in not allowing clitic climbing in these constructions - ; it

differs from the structure in which non-modal/aspectual verbs plus and

infinitive occur. A crucial characteristic of M-A sequences is that the

subject of the infinitive - obviously, if it is granted a clausal status - must

coincide with the subject of the M-A verb - a clear difference with the C-

sequence -:

(239)a. £tsyupiespoden JJençar eJs diners

(2 40)a. *E11yupiespoden Jes seves dones JJençsr eJs diners

b. les dones deis yupies poden JJençar eJs diners

The structure is one of Control, and thus, the possibility of analyzing

it as such is reasonable - cf. Section 2.2 - . The structure, though, displays

characteristics that indicate that it is not a normal Control structure. The

difference lies in the processes which are permitted to elements occuring in

the same clause- as will be shown in the sections to follow-: clitics may

climb to the modal/aspectual43, in impersonal si/se constructions in Italian

and -in some dialects of - Spanish objects may be preposed triggering

Page 3: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

agreement with the modal44, whenever aspect may be expressed by

different auxiliaries there is a change of auxiliary - in Italian -, etc. This

curious syntactic behaviour was analyzed by Rizzi (19Ô2a) as being the

result of a specific rule of r$stnict.iirw£ that did away with a part of the

structure which would otherwise make the processes impossible - as in

other Control sequences -. As observed by all the proposals under review,

Rizzi's account is not tenable in the present model, although his insights

remain and have been reformulated into mechanisms which satisfy the

principles assumed in the present model. It is of uttermost importance that

none of the tests indicative of restructuring are found in English: it has no

clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subject clitics - sf/s& -

either , therefore no object preposing constructions, and aspect is only

expressed by Itave, so there is no a&£r&-jess&r$ equivalent. Restructuring

is, therefore, not a process to be considered in English.

The verbs that belong to the modal class in both English and Romance

are restricted to a small set. The sets are different and only clear-cut in

English; the set of modals in Romance is not definite and even considered

non-existent as a different category by some linguists : "... a les llengües

romàniques, és impossible delimitar formalment una categoria de verbs

modals." ( Ferrater (19Ô1) p. 11). Statements of this sort are based on the

fact that the characteristic morphological properties of English modals - and

some of their syntactic characterists - do not apply to verbs that have a

similar or equivalent meaning in Romance. For English most authors

coincide in considering (241) as an accurate list; in Catalan, (242) is only

approximative:

(241) Will/would, shall/should, can/could, may/might, must,

ought to; dare, need; is to; had better; used to

(242) poder, deure, haver de; voler, gosar

Page 4: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

Modals in English are assumed to have the properties of other

auxiliary verbs - ci. section 2.1 - , plus other characteristic ones:

morphologically, they do not take the -s 3psg , nor have infinitive nor

gerund forms. Syntactically, they cannot co-occur, nor be preceded by other

auxiliaries.45

With respect to the morphological characteristics, Romance modals

differ: they do show inflection for person and number, as well as infinitival

and gerund morphology:

(2 43)a. * Thepresident cans change the constitution

b. Tu potscanviarla constitució

(2 44)a. * To can dance flamenco JsJn fashion

b. Poder ballar flamenco està de moda

(2 45)a. * Canning to speaA- English you can get a job

b. Podent, parlar l'anglès pots aconseguir un lloc de treball

The syntactic properties of modal verbs are not shared by modal

verbs in Catalan either - nor in Romance in general - :they can co-occur or

be adjacent (246)a., and they may be preceded by auxiliaries C247)a.:

(246)a. La Maria Jïosa deu poder deixaria feina

b. *&farla £osa may can leave her fob

(247)a. la Isabel ha pogut anar a Anglaterra

b. * lsabel has canned go to England

Nevertheless, certain relevant observations in terms of these

syntactic characteristics are made in section 2.3.2.3 - cf. Picallo (1965) and

(1990) -, where it is shown that the clearcut distinction between English

Page 5: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

and Catalan modals is not precise in that not all types of modals display the

differences. The crucial factor involves the distinction epistemic/root

reading.

The distinction root / epistemic in the use of modals is found both in

English and Romance.^ An epistemic reading implies judging a proposition

possible or necessary; a root reading implies either ability, volition,

permission, or obligation of the subject. The following exemplify the

difference:

(1) EPISTEMIC:

a. The end of the world may i>e approaching

The end of the world must be approaching

b. la fi del mon espof. estar apropant

La fi del mon es deu estar apropant

(2)ROOr*7

a. The governments must put an end to injustice

The governments can put an end to in/ustice

b. Ets governs han de posar fi a la injusticia

Eisgovernspoden posarfi a la m/usticia

It is obvious by the use of the same lexical item in the second

example of (Da. and the first example in (2)a for English , and the first

example in ( l)b. and the second example in (2)b. for Catalan, that the same

lexical items may have different readings. This is not true for all modals as

instantiated by the verb deure in Catalan which has only an epistemic

reading (l)bv as opposed to the Spanish "equivalent" deberlo-.

(24ô)a. m fin delmundo debe (de)lestar cerca (EPISTEMIC)

Page 6: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

b. los gobiernos dejben poner fin a Ja injusticia (ROOT)

- See section 2.3-2.3 for relevant conclusions regarding this fact-.

With regards to aspectual verbs in Romance and English, they may

add a certain temporal aspect to the complex predicate they are part of -i.e.

when they are followed by an infinitival verb^9. For this reason, they are

often considered modifiers of the predicate phrase, not imposing

restrictions on the subject of the clause . They have been analyzed as

having an adverbial function - cf. Picallo (19Ô5), Zubizarreta (19Ô2) -. Note

the possible paraphrases of the following examples:

(249)a. Es militars nan tomata amenaçar Ja democracia

b. Es militars nan amenaçat la democràcia una altra vegada

(250)a. Es politics solen dir mitges veritats

b. Es polítics molt, sovint diuen mitges veritats

(2 51 )a. Tne armvAeeps threatening democracy

b. Tne army threatened democracy once again

Aspectual verbs are usually kept apart from aspectual

auxiliaries - A? Ft?. l>e cf. Section 2.2.2 -. In this sense it is worthwhile

noting that they have non-aspectual interpretation, as in the following

examples, where thay may be interpreted as motion verbs 50,51.-

(252)a. Ha tomata dir-lique no podia viure sense ella

b. Ha vuelto a decirle que no puede vivir sin ella

(253)a. Ha vingut a dir-me que no considerava l'article prou Joo per la

seva revista

Page 7: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

b. Ha venido a decirme que no considera mi articulo io

suficientemente Mtenopara su revista

The semantics of English aspectual verbs is, thus, equivalent to

Romance aspectual verbs, but there are, once again, no tests that would

point to a possible application of restructuring.

Note that the use of an aspectual verb does not change the relations

between the predicate and its internal/external arguments:

(254)a. Israei MisPaiestinians

b. Israeinasnot ceased toMf Palestinians

c. Israel keeps ¿iiiing Palestinians

(255)a. E/spaïsosrics s'oMden dei Tercer Mon

b. Eis països rics tornen a oMdar-se del Tercer Mon

c. Eis països rics seien oMdar~se dei Tercer Mon

As is suggested by the preceding observations, the kind of syntactic

variation in M-A sequences is more fundamental than the contrasts

observed in C- sequences - cf. 2.3.1 - : it not only involves a different order

of constituents but there may be reasons -cf. especially 2.3.2.3 - to posit a

distinct category for some modals - a "traditional" consideration for English

modals. As already observed in section 2.2.2, modals are assumed to be

generated in INFL - cf. especially Chomsky ( 19Ô1) p. 140 fn. 26* -. Therefore

sequences of modals and infinitives in English are not considered in this

brief introduction to the proposals considered in this section, as they do not

constitute complex predicates.

Page 8: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

The relevant factor oí M-A sequences - as with C-sequences - is that

they consitute an instance oí V+V:

(256)a. Lady Macbeth va voter convencer ai seu marit.

b. Lady Macbeth qwso convencer a su marido

c. Lady Macbeth¿a voliitio convincere ii suo sposo

in the sections that loiiow, the authors focus on the explanation oí

the processes - if any - that relate the two verbs and allow them to

function as a unit with respect to certain syntactic phenomena -

alternatively, the process erases the clausal boundary between the two

verbs -. The validity of the processes will ultimately depend on whether

they satisfy the principles in the grammar, and whether they are,

independently required, since the structure gives way to no changes - cf.

C-sequences and the non-standard word order -. In (256) the postulation of

a process is PF vacuous, in (2575, cliticization of the embedded object is

seen as a consequence and, therefore a signal, of the application of the

process - cf. Section 2.3.2.1, 2.3-2.2 -:

(257)a. Lady Macbeth eJ va voter convencer

b. Lady Macbeth Jo quiso convencer

c. Lady Macbeth J' ha voiutto convincere

Note that French does not allow the same structure. A fact which is

not explained in the proposals in this section. Several of the proposals

summarized attempt explanations to this fact -especially section 2.4 -:

(256)a. Lady Macbeth a voulu convaincre son mari

b. Lady Macbeth a voulu Je convaincre

Page 9: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

c. * Lady Mscbotn J 'avoulu convaincre

The proposals reviewed are representative of different alternative

analyses of M-A sequences. The authors who postulate a biclausal status for

the structures - Rizzi (1902a) and Burzio (19Ô6) - sustain arguments for a

clausal subcategorization and subsequent processes of deletion - Rizzi - or

movement - Burzio -. Deletion is a much too powerful mechanism , barred

in the present framework as pointed out in several of the following

sections.

Those authors defending a monosentential analysis need not recur to

movement or deletion but must account for the non-existence of a subject

position in the infinitive complement. 52

Page 10: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

2.3-2-1 A Restructuring Rule ( Rizzi 1902a)

In his well-known article "A restructuring riûe" Rizzi examines the

status and structure of certain verbs taking infinitival complements , and

puts forward a rule -restructuring - which these verbs optionally trigger.

His analysis is set within a pre-GB model; i.e. he makes use of some

mechanisms which have since been abandoned or reformulated. One of

these is the Specified Subject Condition (SSC) - cf. 2.3.1 -. As observed in

other sections, within the new framework, the effects of such a condition

follow from other principles of the grammar - for instance, binding . In the

model in which Rizzi develops his proposal the transformational component

had not yet been reduced to its limit so he makes use of specific

transformational rules for specific structures. One of such rules, which has

been explained above, is Clitic Placement - cf. Kayne(1975). In spite of this

background, Rizzi does not actually give a complete characterization -

Structurai Description and Structurai Change - in transformational terms

of the rule that he posits -moreover, he gives the final format in a footnote

( cf. p.47, fn. 42 ). The fact that the transformational component contained

a series of different rules favoured the reference to extrinsic ordering to

account for phenomena which could not be explained otherwise - Rizzi,

though, argues against conceivable alternative explanations of his data

through the use of this strategy. It is obvious that in the present model

Rizzi "s proposal needs reformulation, which is the case of some of the

analyses sketched in the following sections.

Rizzi" s main goal is to characterise a set of main verbs in Italian

which show a distinctive behaviour with respect to certain - previously

unrelated - syntactic processes. The set of verbs includes modais.

sspectuais and motion verbs. The syntactic processes the explanation of

Page 11: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

which he unifies are basically cliticization, object preposing in impersonal

"si" sentences, optionality in auxiliary selection. Considering the structure

which makes these syntactic processes possible, he postulates a

derivational account of the data; i.e. the output structure is different from

the structure at the outset of the derivation. This last remark is essential in

his explanation and in order to prove that a specific structure is involved,

he tries these processes by making use of constituency tests; certain

syntactic operations only apply to whole contituents so the structure

resulting from the application of restructuring will either prevent or allow

these processes to operate. The processes involved are: wn-movement {Piecf

Piping), cleft sentence formation. Pignt Node Raising (RNP¿ zxiâCompJex

NP-Süift Briefly, if restructuring applies, elements which were part of

different constituents - two verbs - become united into one constituent, "a

verbal complex"; and elements which were in the same constituent - an

embedded clause - become members of different constituents. The

processes mentioned are correctly predicted to apply only when

restructuring has not applied. The only way to verify the fact that

restructuring has applied is by alluding to the set of syntactic processes

that are particular to verbs which trigger this rule, thus, "constituency

tests" will only be possible if clitics have not moved, objects in impersonal

"si" constructions have not preposed, and there has been no auxiliary

change in a structure which would otherwise allow it. These predictions are

briefly reviewed below.

Restructuring, as Rizzi puts it: "optionally transformis] an underlying

bisentential structure into a simple sentence, creating a unique verbal

complex consisting of the main verb and the embedded verb." (p.2) In

other words, sequences such as the ones in (259) have two possible

structures: a bisentential one - if the rule does not apply -, which implies

the presence of a clausal node intervening between the two verbs; and a

Page 12: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

monosentential structure - ií the rule applies -, which results in the loss of

the clausal node between the two verbs:

(259) a. voter faro/poter fare/dover fare

b. continuare a faro / fJnJscere di fare / starperfare

c. venire a faro /andaré a faro

The following structure is given by Rizzi to illustrate the process:

(260)

ojanm fvi1eve presentare! Ja a Francesco

(16)

The first verb is a modal and for this reason, it triggers the

application of the rule and the two verbs are reanalyzed as a verbal

complex with no clausal boundary nor subject position intervening.53

The first of the syntactic processes that Rizzi deems possible because

of the application of restructuring is cliticization. In (260) the fact that the

two verbs are reanalyzed as one verbal complex allows the clitic to take a

Page 13: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

"long step" and cliticize to the first verb of the complex instead of cliticizing

to the infinitive:

(2 61 ) a. Gianni Is dove presentare a Francesco (17)

b. Gianni dove presentarla_a Francesco ( 1 ô)

The rule involved is Clitic Placement (CP), which has the following

format ( p.3 in Rizzi( 1902a)) - cf also 2.1 -:

(262) vbl - V - vbl - PRO - vbl

1 2 3 4 • 5 - ^

1 4+2 3 / 5

The crucial condition concerning Rizzi's proposal is that terms 2 and 4

must be clausemates; the PRO - here: clitic pronoun- and the verb to which

it clicizes cannot be separated by a clausal boundary. Therefore, if (259)

did not imply an erasure of the clausal boundary dominating the second

verb, CP would be predicted impossible, contrary to fact. Within the model

then used, such a condition followed from the SSC: a specified subject is

present in the embedded clause (PRO) which prevents the application of

any rule. If CP applies, the application of restructuring is indispensable and

compulsory. Nevertheless, if CP does not apply, the application of

restructuring is, in principle, optional since it applies vacuously.54

Nevertheless, Rizzi assumes that restructuring does not apply if the clitic

does not take the "long step". This is precisely what his "constituency tests"

suggest, as will be illustrated below.

Another syntactic process indicative of the application of

restructuring is object preposing in impersonal "si" sentences - cf. also

section 2.1 - . I will not review the analyses of this construction but simply

Page 14: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

point out the aspects relevant to Rizzi"s proposal. A sentence like (263)

contains a subject clitic "si", which does not - at least at this stage of the

derivation - occupy the subject position but has cliticized to the verb

adjacent to it.

(263) Si dorme troppopoco (50)

if the verb is transitive, Italian has a special construction which

allows the preoposing of the object to preverbal position:

(264) a. Si contruisce treppe casein quests città

b. Troppe case si contriuscono in quests città (57)

As (264)b. illustrates, this movement triggers agreement with the

verb; the preposed object functions as the subject. If there are two verbs in

a sentence, this transformation is only possible with the set of verbs

relevant for restructuring:

(2 65) a. *Le nuove casepopoiari si sono promesse di construire

entro un anno (59b.)

b. Jprobiemi principan si continuano a dimenticare (63b.)

The explanation for this is also given by the fact that restructuring

allows an apparent violation of the SSC by the rule of object preposing; the

clausal boundary - and, thus, the subject - is erased only if the matrix verb

is a member of the class of triggering verbs.55

Page 15: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

The last basic piece of evidence which Rizzi brings to bear upon the

application of restructuring is a particular behaviour of the class of

"triggering" verbs with respect to the choice of auxiliary . In Italian, there

are two auxiliary verbs required by different lexical verbs: essere.. and

avere:

(266)a. fiero J¡a/*& volute cuesto libro (71)

b. Piero *hs/è venuto con noi (72a.)

As (266)a. illustrates, modals functioning as main verbs take avere.

Nevertheless, in constructions where modals take an infinitival complement

which requires essore, they no longer impose this requirement:

(267)a. Pioro lia/e voluto/potiito/dovuto venire con noi (72b.)

b. Piero M^—À. promesse di venire con noi (77)

Such examples show that a process of auxiliary change (avere—

essere) is only possible with verbs which allow restructuring. It illustrates

the fact that modals in a structure like (267) - as opposed to (266)a. -

function as auxiliary verbs ; they are part of a verbal complex in which it is

the embedded verb that imposes its lexical requirements.

Another important issue in Rizzi "s proposal are his "constituency

tests" which, as mentioned above, are referred to as evidence for the fact

that restructuring turns constituent-mates into members of different

constituents. Namely, that presentaré a Francesco in (2 6 Da. is not a

constituent but that presentarla a Francesco in (26l)b. is a constituent;

that dimendicare i problem! in (265)b. is not a constituent, but that the

same structure without agreement -si continua a [dimendicare i problem!I-

is a constituent; and that venire con noi in (267) a. is a constituent only if

Page 16: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

the ayer* occurs as an auxiliary. What is crucially at stake is that the

application of restructuring precludes any rule whose application hinges on

the fact that the infinitival complement is a clause; it is only a clause if it

has not been restructured

The following are some examples of the different processes which

indicate that restructuring has applied, having undergone one of the

"constituency tests" mentioned; their grammatical counterparts show that if

restructuring does not apply, the structure meets the structural description

of these "constituency tests": - cf. Chomsky (1972), Ross (1967), Postal

(1974), among others, for a description of these transformations -:5&

Clitic Placement:

-Wh-movement:

(26ô)a. Questl argomentl. a parlarti del quail verre s/p/u presto....

b* Çuesùargomentl, a par Jare del quail ti verre al plu preste...

(10)

- Cleft S Formation:

(2 bQ)a.I"propplo arlpertagJJ 1 seldl die ste andando, stal tranquille/

i>.*F'propplo arlpertare 1 seldl che glî ste andando....

(30)

- Right Node Raising:

(270) a. Mario sinceramente vorrebbe - ma a mloparère nonpotrà

mal - pagargJi Meramente 11 suo debite

b* Mario sinceramente gil vorrebbe - ma a mlo parère non

potra mal -pagare Intoramente 11 suo debite

(37)

Page 17: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

-Complex NP Shift:

(2 71 ) a. Fra quaJcne giorno, verrò a Firenze adesporti Ja mía idea

b. *Fra quaJcne giorno, ti verrò a Firenze ad esporre Ja mía idea

(41)

Before closing this brief review on Rizzi's restructuring proposal, I

will give the actual format of the rule :

(272) vbl Vx y ] (COMPL) V vbl ~>vbl Vx(COMP) V v- ] vbl

(where Vx is a V member of the "triggering" class of verbs)

(p.47fn.42)

Rizzi grants the node dominating the verbal complex a V status on

the basis of examples like (273) which, if we assumed the node had an X-0

status, would " deprive the notion of lexical category of its content" (p.3Ô),

allowing other lexical items to intrude between the parts of an X-0

category.

(273)a. Lo verre subito a scrivere

b. GJi stessd error/ si continuano stupidamente a commetere

c. Maria è dovuta immediatamente tornare a casa

(144)

Note that all of these examples are examples of restructured

structures. The basic argument to posit such a projection dominating two

verbal elements comes from the observation that it is independently

Page 18: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

needed in Italian for sequences of auxiliary-verb, which may, furthermore,

be interrupted by other lexical items :

(274) a.j%> subite scrJíte aJfraacesw

b. Man's ê Jmm&diatamente ternata a casa

(145)

The analysis sketched above inevitably gave rise to many proposals

and counterproposals. In the following sections I will summarize some of

the most salient related analyses within more recent models than that

within which Rizzi ( 1962a) was posited. Here though I want to mention the

article Hernanz & Rigau (164) who assumed Rizzi"s analysis, applying it to

Catalan and Spanish; i.e. they noted that the same type of verbal complexes

are found in both languages - cf. 2.1.2 for a comment on the nature of the

verbs which are assumed to undergo this process -. They put forth more

arguments and show that M-A verbs differ not only from proper main

verbs but also from auxiliaries; they are "double natured". Following Rizzi,

they claim that a rule like restructuring would explain their characteristic

behaviour. Nevertheless, they note that Rizzi's rule must be reformulated in

terms of the present theory because, as it stands - as presented in this

section -, it does not conform to the principles of the theory. One of these

principles is the Projection Principle which ensures that lexical properties

of items are kept throughout the derivation - cf. section 1.2.1 -. Notice that

a rule which erases or destroys structure stands in sharp violation of such a

principle. Much of the subsequent work on "restructuring" verbs attempted

to avoid this.

Page 19: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

2.3-2.2 Restructuring as VP-movement (Burzio 1966)

Burzio "s analysis of restructuring constructions shares many of the

insights of Rizzi (19ô2a). He considers that restructuring constructions are

instances of "complex predicates" as evidenced by the constructions that

Rizzi accounts for; namely, Clitic Climbing (CL CL), Long Object preposing

(Long OP.) in sz/S*? impersonal constructions, and Change of Auxiliary (CA)

- avère— ess&re where both auxiliaries may realize aspect - . As shown in

the preceding section, these phenomena occur with the same class of verbs

- "restructuring" verbs -; they share structural characteristics - cf. the

constituency tests in Rizzi (19ô2a) -; and they interact - i.e. if one occurs,

the others do, too. What these constructions are a reflex of is the fact that

the resulting structure is a "complex predicate": there is " a closer than

usual relation between the main V and the infinitive" (p.32Ô). In the

framework in which Burzio makes his proposals, the "structural anomaly"

of these constructions would imply an exceptional non-violation of the

Binding Principle A - in the previous section it was shown that in Rizzi "s

framework, the relevant principle is the SSC.

In line with Rizzi's proposal, the special cohesion of the verbs is

assumed to be the result of a syntactic derivation, as opposed a base-

generated complex predicate; nevertheless, the type of derivation is not a

reanalysis of the structure - with the consequent subject deletion -, but

rather movement of the embedded clause VP. Burzio also diverges from

Rizzi in the assumption that causative sequences and restructuring

sequences may be accounted for in a parallel fashion and that the

difference follows from the different structures to which the rule of VP-

movement applies.

Page 20: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

The similarity of restructured and non-restructured structures with

respect to selectional restrictions is a crucial fact for positing a syntactic

derivation versus base-generation. Within Burzio's classification of verbs,

those which undergo restructuring belong to three different types:

(275) ERGATIVE: andaré, venire

RAISING: dovere, potere, cominciare, continuare, sater (per),

sembrare

CONTROL: volere, sapere, cominciare, continuare (ô)

The following show the three types of input and output structures to

restructuring as VP -movement:

(276)a. Giovannij va t][PRO] a prendere]]iibro/

b. Giovanni] va [a prenderen iibro It] [PRO] —/

(277)a. Giovannij dovrebbe [ i] prendere ii iibro I

b. Giovannis dovrebbe [prendere ii iibro! [ t] — /

(27ô)a. Giovanni] vorebbe [PRO] prendere ü iibro I

b. Giovanni] vorrebbe [prendere ii iibro ¡[PRO] —/ (9)

Note that they crucially involve configurations with coindexed

subjects. Many differences with causative constructions will follow from

this; i.e. the fact that the two subjects are coindexed only in restructured

constructions - cf. (296) -(296).

In a structure like (277), the matrix subject is subject to the

selectional restrictions of the embedded verb, as clearly illustrated by

(279) . This is a typical argument for Raising, and it differs for Control

structures, where there is a "double" dependence - i.e. the matrix subject

Page 21: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

must obey selectional restrictions of both, the embedded verb and the main

verb, as (2Ô0), (2Ô1) and (262) illustrate:

(279) a. IIlibro dovrobbo essore portato da Giovanni

b. L 'acqua dovrebbe scorrere

c. Dovrebbe plovere

d. Dovrebbe risultare che Giovanni non c'era ( 1 ô)

(2ô0)a. * Il libro viene ad essore pórtate da Giovanni

b. *L acqua viene a scorrere

c. * Viene apiovere

d. * Viene a risultare che Giovanni non c'era ( 19)

(2 Ô1 )a. *lllivro vuole essorepórtate da Giovanni

b. *L 'acqua vuole scorrere

c. * Vuole piovere

d. * Vuolerisultare che Giovaninon c'era (20)

(2 62 )a. * Giovanni viene ad essore lotto da Mario

b. * Giovanni vuole piovere (21)

The relevant data for identifying restructured and non-restructured

complex predicates is exemplified by the following sentences, in which clitic

climbingi CL CD indicates that restructuring has applied, and selectional

restrictions apply in parallel to non-restructured complexes:

(2ô3)a. Il libro glidovrebbe essore portato

b. L 'acqua vi dovrebbe scorrere

c. Cf dovrebbe piovere dentro (22)

Page 22: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

200

Burzio invalidates three possible alternatives to a syntactic

derivation of these complex predicates: that restructuring verbs are like

English modals; that restructuring constructions involve base-generated

VP-complements; and that restructuring complexes are base-generated

complex verbs. He notes that although these would all account for CL CL

and Long OP. correctly - i.e. Binding Principle A would not block any of

these processes-, they would fail to account for the similarity in terms of

selectional restrictions; i.e. the main verb failing to impose restrictions

would not be explained if it were taken as the head of the verbal complex,

and thus a primary predicate - as in (2Ô3).

Burzio "s specific proposal of VP-movement is founded on, basically,

evidence from the restructuring ergative verbs anâare and vemre . He

claims that the effect of restructuring on these verbs provides sufficient

motivation for a VP-movement formulation which changes the linear order

without implying an elimination of the embedded subject position. As has

already been mentioned - cf. the introduction to this section - the deletion

of the subject position is not in line with the present framework. Burzio

notes two basic facts that point towards the existence of a subject position

in the restructured complexes: one is their interpretation - the selectional

restriction observations made above -, and the other one is the fact that the

existence of a trace in subject position - which is not properly bound, and

thus, violates the ECP - accounts for the ungrammatically of (2Ô4) ,

otherwise unexplained. Note that votere is nota Raising verb and, thus, the

trace cannot be properly governed even if there is no restructuring, but if

restructuring deleted the trace, the ungrammatically would not be

predicted.

(2 64) *Inostn atfetij sf vorrebtero [ vlnœrelitj — / (43)

Page 23: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

The interaction of restructuring ergative verbs and a fare -

construction involving a VP-complement with CL CL of the subject of the

ergative gives evidence for the fact that the object position - the original

position of the subject of the ergative - has not been deleted, but rather

that the VP of the embedded clause has been moved. The dativi2ation

process, mentioned in Section 2.3-1-2 in relation to the causative

constructions, applies in this context: the NP II libro becomes an object of

the ergative verb, and of the causative verb as well - all the boundaries

that separate fare and the NP are VPs . The ec of the clitic becomes a

second object of fare and the context for dativization arises, accounting for

the occurrence of git and not lo:

(2Ô5) GUj faro fyp andaré [yp a prendere il libro / ft e /

ÍSPWj — / (36)

The following change in structure is what accounts for dativization;

NP2 induces dativization of NP i:

(266)a. IvPlVi NPiIsPROÍVP2V2 NP2 111

t>. IVPl Vl [ V2 NP2 1 NPl Is PRO ---]]] (37)

The lack of S SC effects in sentences like the following is another

argument for VP-movement; it follows from the movement of VP out of the

clause, out of the domain of the "specified subject":

(2Ô7)a. Marioloj vuoleleggere fiel (la.)

b. Questilibrij si volevanopropio leggere tj (2a.)

Page 24: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

The fact that the subject of clauses embedded under restructuring

verbs is always null is assumed to be a consequence of the fact that there is

no way for it to acquire Case: verbs like voters are not S'-deletion verbs, so

there is no government ,(2ôÔ)a.; and verbs like potere. sembrare trigger S'-

deletion but do not assign Case, (2ôÔ)b.:

(2ÔÔ) a. * Maris vuoie fme participare I

b. *ie/puo/sembra i me partecipare / (47)

This observation carries over to restructured constructions where the

main verb still fails to govern and/or assign Case to the embedded subject:

(2Ô9) a. * Maria vuoie [yp partecipare /is me — /

b. * ie/ puó/sembra fyp partecipare/is me — / (46)

The lack of dativization of the subject of the embedded verb - as

opposed to causative structures - is accounted by the failure of application

of the dativization process. This process only applies if both objects are

governed by the main verb or assigned Case by it; the non-S'-deletion

accounts for (290)a. and the lack of Case assignment accounts for (290)b:

(290)a. * Maria vuoie [yp ieggere ii iibro /is a Giovanni — /

b. * i e/ puó/sembra fyp ieggere ii iibro / is a Giovanni — /

The lack of phonetically realized subjects follows from Case

requirements, and the assumption of the presence of a syntactic subject at

all levels is not undermined by this fact. Therefore, restructured and non-

restructured structures are alike in D-structure; there is no deletion of the

subject position. This also follows form the Projection Principle and the fact

Page 25: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

tnat semantic interpretation is derived from S-structure. The existence of

the subject at all levels, moreover, is necessary to ensure the correct

distribution of Raising and Control.

Some similarities and some differences between

restructuring and causatives

In Burzio's analysis, the similarities observed between restructuring

complexes and causative constructions support the VP-movement analysis

in that they are both derived structures; the differences also corroborate it

indirectly in that they can be attributed to the distinct properties of each of

the D-structures to which VP-movement applies; namely, coreference

between main and embedded subject in restructuring.

Two of the similarities that Burzio observes are the distribution CL CL

and past participle agreement. Clitics in this construction are assumed to be

base-generated in the embedded verb and moved to the main verb after or

in conjunction with VP-movementBinding Principle A is, thus, not violated:

(2 9 Da. Lij ho fatii [yp JoggereQej] fs a Mario — /

b. Lij ho voiuti ÍVP teggere fi # JffPRO — / (56)

(291) also exemplifies past participle agreement, which takes place

between the past participle causative or restructuring verb and an

argument of the embedded verb. These arguments have, thus, been

reanalyzed as dependents of the matrix verb as well.

Clitic climbing exemplifies one of the two possible relations that may

hold between an element in the matrix clause and an element in the

embedded clause - cf. (293). Past participle agreement is one of the two

phenomena that are triggered when this relation holds - cf. (292); the other

Page 26: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

204

phenomenon is ¿äaare - assignment (E-assignment). These two phenomena

directly bear upon one of the differences between causatives and

restructuring constructions: the fact that restructuring with ergative verbs

is possible - recall that VP-movement analysis of causatives does not allow

ergative causative constructions because an NP-trace relation must be met

at all levels ; these are analyzed as FP constructions -.

Past participle agreement and E-assignment are defined by Burzio as

in (292); (293) are the possible relations and the rule that they trigger:

(292) a. Auxiliary E is assigned when there is a relation of a certain

type between the subject and either a clitic or a direct object

b. A pp will agree with an element holding a relation of a

certain type with its direct object

(69)

(293) a. NP cl V . . . E only

b. . . . cl V NP . . . pp agreement only

c. NP V NP . . . Both E and pp agreement (70)

In restructuring constructions, pp agreement is triggered as in (291)

above and (294), which shows that the embedded object does not cease to

be an object of the embedded verb even if it also becomes an object of the

main verb:

(2 94) Lij vorreiÍVP avergia tetti fj<? / / is PRO — / (74)

*

The fact that restructuring verbs can occur with ergative verbs is due

to the fact that the trace of the object of the ergative is properly bound at

S-structure, after VP-movement, as a result of the basic coindexation - i.e.

tiie Control relation - of the matrix subject and the embedded subject; the

Page 27: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

trace in object position is also coindexed with the matrix subject and, thus,

properly bound - i.e. it has a c-commanding antecedent at S-structure -:

(295) a. fj&fsij sarebbe volute { PKOj andaré tj/

b. fje/sij sarebbe voiuti {yp andaré tj/fPffij — / (76)

This process is what Burzio calls Subject Substitution, which is only

possible when the two subjects are coindexed. The distribution of E -

assignment and pp agreement is predicted by this process: this is one of the

possible relations which will trigger these phenomena-(293)c. E-assignment

applies when there is restructuring - a fact observed by Rizzi, but explained

by Burzio:

(296) a. Nolj avremmo voiutols PROj andaré tj /

b. Noij saremmo voluti [yp andaré tiffs PRO] — / (60)

And the difference with the causative construction follows in that in

causatives, there is no relation which can trigger pp agreement (297) nor E

-assignment (2 95):

(297) fjefsij sarebbe fatto/ *fatti [yp andaré Giovanni I (79)

(2 9ò)J]/oj avremmo fatto/ *saremmo fatti [yp andaré Giovanni / (Ô1 )

The differences are thus predicted: in causative constructions only

certain complements may be embedded under fare ( Fl) - i.e. those not

involving an NP-trace relationdhip - (299)a vs. (299)b. -; in restructuring

constructions there is no bifurcation since they all involve a relationship

between the two subjects - either Raising or Control - and, thus, allow

Subject Substitution, (300). Recall that (200)a. is possible because

Page 28: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

reconstruction licenses the relation between the lexical anaphor and its

antecedent - cf. section 2.3-1-2:

(299) a. Giovanni ne/ farà {yp invitare una [j e I dascunoj I

ÍS ai suoi amidj — /

b* Maria gJij farà [yp esserepreséntate tj fief/

ÍS (à) Giovanni/ — / (95)

(300)a. / suoi amid se vorebbero /potrebbero /andrebbero ad

invitare una dascuno

b. Giovannigli vorrebbe /potrebbe /andrebbe ad

essere presenta to

The different properties of each of the two constructions, thus, follow

from their different initial structures, but there is a common formulation

that can be assumed for both, a fact not considered by Rizzi. Burzio puts

forth the proposal that VP-complementation is a marked option - which he

assumes for FP construction (cf. Section 2.3-1-2 ), and that restructuring and

causative structures only exist in a language if they are "minimally

productive" ; i.e. they may occur with transitive, intransitive and ergative

verbs. Since Subject Substitution is only possible with restructuring verbs,

in order to allow ergatives, causative constructions may take VP-

compiements to satisfy the "minimal productivity" requirement. Another

difference that follows from general principles is the fact that the causative

nile is obligatory and the restructuring rule is not obligatory: only the

former is needed for Case-assignment to the embedded subject.

Page 29: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

2.3-2-3 Monosentential analyses of restructuring complexes

Picallo (1965)

The analysis Picallo (1965) provides of modal and aspectual verbs is

related to her proposal for redefining the notion of Governing Category,

which captures the special properties of subjunctive clauses with respect to

the coreference possibilities of their null pronominal subjects; i.e. pro

cannot corefer with an element in the matrix clause. This implies that

Binding Principle B applies on the more inclusive domain; the Governing

Category of the pronominal in the subject position of the embedded clause

is not its S - cf. (301)- (303) -. Picallo redefines Governing Category in

terms of Tense chains in multisentential structures where the verbal head

of the embedded clause is "tense-dependent" - the subjunctive -. Elements

subject to the Binding Conditions must be linked to an accessible Subject

within a Tense chain. Structures containing modal verbs in subjunctive

clauses behave differently as regards opacity - cf. (304) -(306). They allow

the subject pronominal to corefer with the matrix subject. Picallo refers to

this as the "opacity-inducing" property of modals ; (epistemic) modals seem

to delimit a binding domain:

(301) *[la seva/ esperança que fproi partes amb eil //

anava disminuint

(302 ) * proi sentien que ípny produissin una faisà impressió/

(303) * Tj 'agradava que fproj ei consideressis amic /

(304) [La sevai esperança que [proi pogués parlar amb eii //

anava disminuint

(305) proj sentien que fproi deguessin produir una falsa impressió/

Page 30: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

(306) Tj 'agradava que (proi poguessis considerar-lo amic I

(D-(6)

The explanation to this exceptional behaviour of only epistemic

modal verbs is contingent on their analysis as INFL elements. It is assumed

that no Tense chain is formed linking the modal with the tense in the

matrix clause because the modal in INFL, its head, cannot be anaphorically

related to the head of the upper clause. This behaviour is opposed to root

modals and aspectuals (30?) - (309); the coreference possibilities of their

null pronominal subjects are as in (30D-Í303):

(307) * La Isabel] esperava que {proj hi volgués anar I

(30ô) * [La seva/ Insistència que [proi la comencessin a demolir II

* era dubtosa

(309) * En Joan] desitjava que [proi tornes a venir I

(9),(6),(7)

Since Picallo's reformulation of the binding domain does not bear

directly on this thesis I will not review it further, but will proceed to

summarize her analysis of modals and aspectual verbs.

The basic insight in the proposal under review is that complexes of

restructuring verbs and infinitivals are not bisentential at any level of the

grammar; they are monosentential base-generated verbal complexes.

Nevertheless, the basic contrast in terms of epistemic vs. root

interpretations is accounted for by the possibility of modals of occurring in

different positions in phrase structure. This carries over to aspectual verbs,

which are analyzed as occupying the same structural position as root

Page 31: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

modals verbs. The phrase-structure contains the following positions for

modals and aspectuals:

(310)5? INFL"

NP INFI/

[Tense,AGR] INFLÛ Vf

Modal

Aux Vi'

' v°j \ Modal V°i

(53)

As the subscripts and bar-projections indicate: infinitives in

restructuring complexes are the heads of the verbal projection ( Vi ) ; root

modals (Vj) are adjoined to a verbal projection; and epistemic modals

(INFL0) are the heads of INFL. Therefore, modal verbs do not head a verbal

projection.

As seen in the preceding sections, the main arguments against a

derived analysis for restructuring complexes are based on observations on

selectional restrictions. In contrast with Burzio (19Ô6) - who uses these

observations precisely to distinguish between Raising and Control - in

Picallo (19Ô5), the Raising / Control distinction is seen as irrelevant for

restructuring complexes . Firstly, the distribution of GO/HM cliticization

shows that if the structures were analyzed as instances of Control, a

violation of the Projection Principle would arise. Secondly, Rizzi (1966)

locality condition on the formation of chains shows that modals are not

/ \

Page 32: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

relevant for the determination of the presence of a derived subject - i.e. of

a Raising predicate, as will be seen below.

Selectional restrictions show a distinction between modal verbs: voler

assigns an external theta-role, but poder does not. Voler is, thus, analyzed

as a Control verb, whereas poder is a raising predicate - cf. section 2.3.2.2,

Burzio (1956) -. (311) and (312) illustrate this. Nevertheless, poder has

another reading in which it contributes to the selectional restrictions that

must be satisfied by the nominative NP, (313) has a double interpretation.

This fact would require a double subcategorization frame for modal verbs.

Picallo, instead, argues in favour of a double-position in the phrase-

structure, and against a raising or Control analysis:

(311) * Les pedres ni* volen caure [el1 (24)

(312) Les pedres ni J poden caure Íe/J (25)

(313) Ei lladre pogué entrar per la finestra (2 Ô)

The distribution oí en/ne cliticization shows that in a restructuring

complex, the infinitive is the dominant head in terms of thematic structure;

therefore, a Control analysis of the modal V is undesirable as the " formal

manifestations of the thematic structure" of the modal verb would change -

being invalidated by the infinitive - leading to a violation of the Projection

Principle. The relevant properties of en/ne cliticization are the folowing: it

stands for the head of an N' constituent of a quantified NP which is an

internal argument - either a direct object (315) or the nominative subject

of an ergative verb (314)-:

(314)a. Han sortit algunes persones

b. Nnan sortit, algunes

c. * Han sortit algunes (29)

Page 33: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

(315)a. Sempre compra molts llibres el Guillem

b. Sempre en compra molts el Guillem

It is obligatory if there is wh-movement of the specifier of the

internal argument:

(316) a. Quants n han sortit

b. * Quants han sortit (30)

it is disaiiowed when the quantified NP is in preverbal position

independently of the status of the NP - internal / external -:

(317)a. * Algunes n'han sortit (31)b.

b. * Alguns n'han dormit (32 )b.

It is disallowed when the postverbal quantified NP is not an internal

argument, but a postposed external argument:

(31ô)a. Parlaven molts nois

X>.* En parlaven molts (33)a.,b.

(319)a. Volien llibres alguns amics teus

b. *£n volien llibres alguns (34)a.,b

The distribution of this phenomenon depends on the external theta-

role assigning properties of the verb: it is only allowed if the postverbal NP

is not an external argument. The distribution of en/he cliticization in

restructuring verbal complexes is incorrectly predicted if the modal verbs

are assumed to be verbal heads imposing their selectional restrictions on

the arguments of the verbal complex - i.e. Control predicates -; the facts

Page 34: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

212

bear out Picallo's analysis of modal verbs as non-heads and infinitive

"complements" as the heads of the verbal complex, en /ne cliticization is

allowed only if the infinitive is an ergative - independently of the nature of

the restructuring verb as an ergative, Raising or Control predicate -:

(32 0)a. * Quants te ¿n 'arribaren a escriure cartes fe ¡J

b. Quants tJ ' arribaren a escriure cartes fe/J (40)

(321 )a. *HJ1 tornaven a créijser moltes fe fJ

b. N'hiJ tornaven a crëïsermoltes fe fJ (41 )

(32 2 )a. *Quants te ¿ n comencen a escriiwe cartes fe fJ

b. Quants et J comencen a escrJure cartes fe/J (42)

(32 3)a. N'hi1pogueren entrar s/s fe P

b. * Hi1 pogueren entrar sis fe I1 (44)

(324)a. Quants n ni * vollen arribar [el1

b. * Quants ni i volien arribar fe f¿ (45)

Cliticization is only allowed of internal arguments, so if the only

argument of a verb is en/ne cliticized, the verb must be ergative.

Neverthelss, Control verbs like voJer require en/ne cliticization as in

(324). The contradiction is that in restructuring constructions, Control verbs

behave semantically like Control verbs , but syntactically like Raising

predicates. As was pointed out above, this is interpreted as a violation of

the Projection Principle. Picallo follows Zubizarreta (1962) in attributing to

these modal verbs the function of secondary or adjunct predicates, although

she diverges from this proposal in not granting modals a double

simultaneous structure - cf. section 2.3.1.3 for the equivalent proposal for

causatives -.

Page 35: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

Before considering the adjunct-predicate status of root modals, I will

briefly mention how Picallo invalidates a raising analysis of some modals

by referring to Rizzi (19Ô6) locality condition on chain formation.

Configuration (325) is ungrammatical by condition (326), which disallows

interruption of a chain by coindexed elements:

(325) *NPj... dj... [e//... fe¡i (57)

(326) C = (@i, ...@n ) is a chain iff 1 i n

@ i is the local binder of @ i+n

(i) @ is a binder of ß iff, for @, ß = any category,

@ and ß are coindexed and @ c-commands ß.

(ii) @ is the local binder of ß iff @ is a binder of ß,

and there is no ¥ such that ¥ is a binder of ß, and

¥ is not a binder of @. (66)

It accounts for ungrammatical structures with anaphoric clitics and

NP movement - i.e. in configurations with derived subjects -, such as (327)

and (32 ô):

(32 7) * Eis nostres amies/ esj foren presentats fe /j fe // (56)

(32 ô) * Ei Joanj es/ sembla [ e Ij intelJlgent fefj (62)

(329) shows that analyses of modal verbs as raising predicates are

not consistent with the locality condition on chains; contrary to predictions

of these analyses, an anaphoric clitic in a restructuring construction is

allowed:

(329) En Joan es deu afaitar

(230) En Pere i en Gerard es leiten considerar inteiiigents (67)

Page 36: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

The condition on chains is not violated if epistemic verbs are

generated in INFL - as in (310) above - and not considered raising

predicates. As with en/ne cliticization, the infinitive is shown to be the

head which determines the argument structure of the complex. Anaphoric

clitics are not allowed in structures with a modal and a non-external theta-

role assigning predicate:

(331) * En foam esj devia semblar fe ¿ intelJigent fe ¿ (71)

(332 ) *Els teus amksj sjñavien de ser presentats fe Jj fe ¿ (72 )

(333) * En Joan] esj podía semblar fe // un geni fe ¡i (73)

The parallel behaviour of aspectuals implies that these are not

raising predicates either:

(334) Enjeani esi començava a afaitar íe u

(335) Enjoani esi solia afaitar fe ¡i (74)

(336) * Els meus arnicsj esj començaven a ser presentats fe Jj fe ¿

(337) * En Joanj esj solia semblar fe ¡i inteüigent fefj (75)

On the basis of the fact that they do impose restrictions on the

nominative subject (33ôb. vs. 339b), but that they are within the VP when

they have a root interpretation ( 340a.), root modals are granted an

internal VP position as in (310) above. Note that the fact that they are

within VP is argued on the basis of the distribution of aspectual markers

with modals. Modals only have a root reading if they are preceded by

aspect markers (340a), if they are followed by aspect markers, then they

may only have an epistemic reading (340b):

Page 37: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

(336) a. Et quadre em va impressionar

b. *E1quadre em va voler impressionar (149)

(339)a. En Joan em va impressionar

b. En Joan em va voler impressionar ( 150)

(340)a. En Joan na pogut anar al cinema

b. En Joan pot Haver anat al cinema (57)

Since perfect aspectual markers preceding modals bar their epistemic

reading, the selectional restrictions of modals in such configurations must

be kept - Note that, as adjunct predicates, they do impose them. (33Ô)b.

and (341) below show that the selectional restrictions on the nominative NP

imposed by modal and infinitive must coincide:

(341) * Havia pogut ploure tot el dia (91)

Aspectual verbs have a parallel status as root modals although they

do not impose selectional restrictions on the nominative subject. They

nevertheless modify the infinitive they occur with; they have an adverbial

function. Note the ambiguity of (342)-(345): the aspectual verbs may either

have a motion verb interpretation - as main verbs -, or stand for a non-

predicative, adverb-like expression - future marker, iteration of action, etc.

In the latter sense they specify certain aspects of the predicate which

auxiliaries do not, and thus they are modifiers of the head.

(342) Anava a dir-te el que vapassar

(343) Be tomata felicitar-la

(344) Va venir a dir-me que no li interessava

(345) Ha arribat a molestar-la

Page 38: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

The interaction of aspectual verbs - VP elements - and modals, like

aspect markers, indicates that root modals are VP elements. When

aspectual verbs precede a modal, the latter may only have a root reading

(346). An aspectual preceding douro - which may only have an epistemic

reading - is not possible (347). The reverse order is possible (346):

(346) Tornava a poder tocar oipiano (97)

(347) * Tornava a douro focar oi piano (99)

(34Ô) Bovia tornar a tocar oi piano ( 100)

Several other predictions follow from the analysis just sketched. One

of these is the fact that only the first modal in a sequence of modals may

have an epistemic reading. - Note that this is a difference between English

and Romance, as a sequence of modals is impossible in English-:

(349) La Núria doupodor tocar oi piano (101)

(350) En Jordi pot havor do soiucionar aquost assumpte moit aviat.

(109)

This is what is predicted if epistemic modals are analyzed as INFL

elements; there is only one slot in the structure for it. Note that (347) is

also explained by this: douro is an epistemic (only) verb, consequently

occupying the only INFL position in the structure; no other modal may

precede it because there simply is no position for it. If douro is followed by

a modal, the latter must be interpreted as a root modal. (351) is ruled out

because the selectional restrictions of podor are not met; in other words,

the selectional restrictions of the infinitive and the modal do not coincide.

Page 39: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

(350 * Deu podar pJoiira

The fact that epistemic verbs in Catalan do not have infinitive or

gerund morphology, whereas root verbs do is another phenomenon

explained by this analysis, together with the asumption that the licensing

condition on epistemic modals is that they must be linked to morphological

tense. This is assumed to be true of all epistemic notions as possibility or

necessity, which must be relative to a given time. Licensing may take place

either under the relation predicate-argument ( "the modal constituting a

property of the time-frame expressed in the sentence"), or operator-

variable (" the value of the variable being determined by the features [ +/-

PAST ]").. The following illustrate the fact that if they have infinitival or

gerund morphology, modals may only have a root reading, in other words,

that epistemic modals must bear tense:

(352 ) Ignoràvem con? [PROpoder a&prassar-JJ aJ qua sant/am / ( 110)

(353) fPEO podant dadJcar-ta ajscJusivamant a also ¡no antaño

parqué no ño fas

(111)

This observation does not hold for English, a fact which may follow

from morphological constraints given the fact that English modals lack

infinitival and participial morphology.

Strozer (1961) *

Strozer proposes an alternative to the restructuring rule in Rizzi

(1902a) which implies a base solution. She argues that a base solution is

preferable and that, apart from theoretical problems that the restructuring

Page 40: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

rule poses, there are also empirical inadequacies. The fact that there are

verbs that show a double subcategorization is taken as an argument in

favour of a possible VP-complementation; the assumption that, most

infinitives are clauses is not affected by the fact that a very limited set of

verbs take VP-complements. The following examples show that there is a

difference in meaning , and thus a plausible double subcategorization,

which in turn counts as evidence for a VP-subcategorization. The Italian

example does not display a difference in meaning and, thus, is assumed to

be a simple sentence:

(354) a. Ana volvió a f yp empezar a copiaria I

b. Ana volvió (allí) a is MP empezar a copiaria / (ô)(9)

(355)a. Siani eleve is presentarla a Francesco /

b. Gianni { y la óeve presentare fa Francesco

Strozer claims that there is no strong evidence to posit a bisentential

analysis for sentences like (355); that there are other reasons that may

account for the ungrammaticalities observed by Rizzi - cf. 2.3.2.1 -, which

he interprets as being evidence for constituency. An example:

(35b)a. çuesti argomentJ, a partarti del quaii verró ai più presto,

mi sem&rano moito interessant/'

b. *Çi?esti argomenti, apariare dei quale ti verro aipiüpresto....

The ungrammatically of this sentence could be due to the fact that

the trace of the clitic is not properly bound. (357) seems to be

ungrammatical due to restrictions on the breaking up of constituents by a

Page 41: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

locative PP, a restriction which could also be at work in ungrammatical

sentences where Rizzi claims restructuring has applied (356):

(357) *Lo no a Firense messo ai carrante delia nostra dedsione (2 0)

(35Ô) a. Fra qualque giorno. verrò ad esport/Ja m/a ide a Firense

b. Fra qualque giorno, ti verrò ad esporre la mia idea a Firense

c. *Fra qualque giorno, tí verrò a Firenze ad esporre la mia idea

Thus, the tests used by Rizzi fail to provide evidence for

restructuring if other reasons are found that could explain the

ungrammatical examples.

What the VP-hypothesis shares with restructuring is that it also

applies to a small class of verbs , assumed not to be subcategorized for

clauses. The basic difference is that phrase-structure rules directly

generate the simple sentences in which restructuring complexes occur.

According to Strozer, the greatest shortcoming to restructuring is that the

cyclic transformation posited by Rizzi is too powerful in that it changes

structure throughout the derivation. The advantage of a base-generation

account is that no other extra device is needed.

Page 42: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

220

2.4 An alternative theory: Guéron and Hoekstra (19ÔÔ )

Guéron and Hoekstra (19ÔÔ) (G&H) addresses the problem of verbal

complementation. They redefine the concepts of Jessica/ and auxiliary

verb and establish sets of verbal elements all characterized by their ability

or inability to mark their complements with a specific feature (a T-index ),

or assign them certain properties (a theta-role, or a T-role). Their

characterization of verbal elements makes crucial use of the notion of LF

and the fact that complements must be either, arguments or (parts of)

predicates. In their framework, complements are construed in LF as

nominal or verbal - i.e. as arguments or as (parts of) complex predicates. By

doing this, they formalize and extensively argue for the idea that auxiliary

verbs have verbal complements - VP - whereas lexical verbs have nominal

complements - NP, CP -.. The selection of a verbal complement is not

problematic; they draw upon the notion of sisterhood in Chomsky (19ô6b) -

cf section 1.2.2 - , where functional nodes do not count, and thus a V will

lexically select a VP eventhough functional nodes intervene. Proceeding in

this fashion, though, they come up with sets that differ substantially from

previous classifications - basically, they classify causative verbs as

auxiliaries, and modal verbs as having this option in certain languages -.

Their characterization is achieved by the introduction of formal

mechanisms ( T-marking, T-chain, T-role 58 )f which basically define the

circumstances under which a V may select a VP. The grouping of verbal

items as different types of verbs with very specific properties - some of

which may be subject to language variation - leads to a very constrained,

and compact theory on the complementation of verbal items.

Page 43: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

G&H consider that the verbal or nominal nature of a projection is not

to be determined solely by the categorial nature of its head, but that

syntactic context plays a crucial role. An XP may be nominal or verbal

depending on the categories that dominate it .They propose the following

LF construal for complements:

(359) FimotionaJDetermination of Categories (FBC)

a. External

An XP is construed as a nominal projection iff it is casemarked

An XP is construed as a verbal projection iff it is T-marked

b. Internal

The subject of a nominal projection receives a Case which is

determined internal to XP; the subject of a verbal projection

receives Case ( if any ) determined by an external governor

(1)

Nominal projections are, thus, casemarked; their independence

follows from the fact that their subject is internally licensed - this includes

Genitive in NP and also Nominative in CP, as will be seen below - . Verbal

projections are not independent, they are part of complex predicates; they

are licensed by T-marking - Tense-marking - , which is a property of

auxiliary verbs only. This property is the formal instantiation of the fact

that auxiliary verbs, unlike lexical verbs, never denote an event, they

modify the event denoted by a VP. This event is situated in time by Tense,

and this is referred to by G&H as T-marking; the assignment of a T-index.

Lexical verbs may be T-marked in two ways: a) by Infi if it contains tense -

it is assumed that every CP introduces a new T-index ; and b) by an

auxiliary, if there is one. Auxiliaries may alternatively pass on the T-index

Page 44: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

222

assigned by a higher auxiliary or by Infi. Lexical verbs absorb the Tense

value assigned to them and this becomes part oí the reference of the VP

which they head - and are the semantic head of -. Hence, the first basic

distinction between lexical and auxiliary verbs is that lexical verbs absorb

a T-index, and auxiliaries assjgn it. Note that it follows from the FDC above

that auxiliary verbs will always govern a verbal projection, and that lexical

verbs will not because they are not T-markers. Moreover, VP projections

that are not T-marked will not be licensed, and, therefore, will give rise to

an ungrammatical configuration. Although G&H do not explicitly make the

parallel, VPs are subject to a T-marking" Filter as NPs are subject to a Case

Filter. Only T-marking of a VP will identify it as a verbal projection at LF.59

Examples (36O) and (361) are not possibly identified as such because the

lexical verb croire cannot T-mark them. Examples (362) and (363) are

identified as verbal projections because an auxiliary verb governs them-

avolr in (362), laisser in (363):

(360) */e croyais Marie partir

(361 ) * Je croyais Marie aimée par Georges ( 17)f .,d.

(362) J'ai vu Pierre

(363) Eile laisse les enfants partir ( 19)

The following example instantiates how an XP may be interpreted as

nominal or verbal depending on the context:

(364) Eu lamento íjp os depiitedos terem trabalhado pouco]

(365) Eu lamento ÍXP1 teremj

ÎXP2 os deputados tj trabalhado pouco /

(7)a.,b.

Page 45: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

The verb lamentar in Portuguese is assumed to optionally assign

case to its complement. From the FDC, if it assigns case then its complement

villi be interpreted as nominal; if it does not, as verbal. In (364), lamentar

assigns case to XP so it is nominal. As such, its subject must receive case

determined within the SP. This is the function of the inflected INFL in

Portuguese : it assigns Nominative case to the subject via subject-Infl

agreement. The structure of (365) is the result expected if we assume that

lamentar does not assign case and thus the XP must be interpreted as

verbal. This is assumed to follow from the fact that there is no Spec position

to the left of the head of the complement. If there is, the structure is as in

(364). As a verbal projection, the XP in (365) needs to be T-marked, but

since lamentar, a lexical verb cannot T-mark it, terem moves to Comp - or

alternatively adjoins to VP in LF - and identifies the complement as a

verbal projection. XP 1 and XP2 are analyzed as two segments of the same

projection because they share a head, terem - cf .Chomsky 1966b -. The LF

of (365) is :

(365*) £1? lamento Iypj terem 1ÍVP2 *>$ esputados ¿j/vpj

trabalnado peuco ¡jj (9)b.

where VP1= CP , VP2=IP and VP3=VP in the syntax; in LF they are

all interpreted as part of the same projection. The subject of the embedded

clause is assigned case under government by the raised auxiliary. The

identification of the subject is, thus, external - cf. (359), FDC - and not

internal by subject -Infi agreement as in (364). This is basically G&H's

account of Aux-to-Comp (Rizzi 1962c). The same factors apply to the

sequences that Rizzi considers in Italian:

Page 46: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

(366) Suppongo [ ypj non esserj í yp2 Jui tj in grado di

affrontare Ja sititaztone / / / (14)

The lack of structures equivalent to (364) in Italian is assumed to be

the consequence of a difference in the infinitival morphology of the two

languages: Italian lacks a T-morpheme capable of assigning nominative

case. The lack of both of these structures in French follows if it is assumed

that French infinitival morphology also lacks this possibility, plus the fact

that the infinitival affix is too weak to assign nominative case to its own

subject by government, as is the case in (365") and (366). (367) contrasts

with (364), and (36Ô) with (365') and (366):

(367)* IJ regrette Jes députas avoir travaiJJepeu

(36o)* Je crois avoir Jes deputes travaiJJepeu ( 15)b.,c.

Several other basic assumptions are crucial in the framework of G&H.

Proper government is subsumed by antecedent government - proper

government is a function of chains (Chomsky 1966b) - and, thus, a link in

a chain will properly govern the link following it if there are no barriers

intervening. T-marking can void an XP of barrierhood (T-marking in G&H is

equivalent to L-marking in Chomsky (1906b)), so T-marking of a VP will

imply that the VP is not a barrier for an empty category in need of proper

government inside the VP - unless other factors hold, such as minimality,

as will be seen below . Note that certain consequences follow from this:

movement out of a VP is allowed - T-marking of VPs is a requirement -,

not out of a CP - a CP is never T-marked and case-marking is not identified

Page 47: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

with L-marking. This is of crucial importance in their account of modal

structures and clitic climbing possibilities, as will be explained below.

The process of T-marking forms a T-chain : ( where k= the T-index

assigned by Tense )

(369) T* - [ aux* ] - [ vPk V* 1 (121)

The concept of T-chain provides a formalization of a specific

syntactic domain where the formation of a path provides a way for

feature percolation. Assuming that the external theta-role originates in the

V and is assigned to the external NP via INFL by subject-agr agreement,

the following example shows how theta-role percolates from the VP

through an auxiliary which is a link in the T-chain. This auxiliary is

assumed to have specific properties, as will be explained below. The

external theta-role reaches the NP-subject via I:

(3?0) John hasseen Mary

John {I fyp has Í yp laughed///

theta-1 (35)

There - structures and unaccusatives are instances of percolation of

Nominative case:

(371) There Js a problem

There fT-k fbe-k Í a problem ///

NOM (125)

Page 48: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

Nominative case percolates through the T-chain and is assigned to

the postverbal NP ( it bears Nominative case because it determines the

form of the verbal inflection ).

(372) No sono arrivais molti

T&no i sono & / o j arrivaü'& ÍNPl n2oJtJ o/J

NOM (129)

As (372) shows, clitics climb within the T-chain, in the domain in

which features percolate. G&H show that clitic climbing and NP-raising are

possible within a T-chain because of the government and barrierhood

voiding properties of chains. A crucial fact about chains is that they may be

extended by Spec-Head agreement. G&H's account of passive relies on this:

(373) m I+tef ÍVPJ Vj ÍVP2 V2 i J//

John was killed

where i=j by SHAG (Specifier-Head Agreement) (74)

In such a structure, the trace of the raised NP is properly governed

by antecedent government. The verbal elements all share the same T-index

by virtue of the T-chain formed by T-marking. The chain is extended

because of SHAG which results in the proper government of the trace since

the other links in the chain share its same index^0 . Note that if V2 would

have another index by subject-head agreement within the VP, then

minimality would block the proper government of the trace - cf. (375) -.

The same process allows clitic climbing in structures where extended

chains are created:

Page 49: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

(374) 11 lai est fidèle 11 j luij +1& [ yp-k est& ÍAP ti fidèle ej H (Ô3)a.

Note that the AP must be interpreted as a verbal projection - a

predicate -since it is T-marked by the verb., and as mentioned above, it

follows that movement out of verbal projections is allowed. The trace in

object position is antecedent governed by the adjective because it bears the

same index as its antecedent, and is, thus, a link in the same T-chain . SHAG

ensures the identity of k=i, and the adjective bears index i by subject-head

agreement internal to the AP. Note that the fact that the clitic attaches to I

ensures that the clitic and I share the same index - cf. also Chapter 3 and

Baker "s indexation convention on the X* dominating incorporated elements

-. As G&H point out, proper government of a clitic trace may be blocked by

minimality as in the following example:

(375) *U Jui/ croit [ Jean fidèle ej / (Ô3)c

Minimality blocks proper government of the clitic trace: the

adjective minimally governs it, but it is not coindexed with its antecedent

because it shares index with the subject of the AP.There is no raising of the

NP-subject of AP, so SHAG does not apply as a way to extend a chain,

contrary to what happens in (374) above. Moreover, the lack of T-marking

makes the complement an independent unit out of which extraction is not

possible - cf. the SSC -.

The fact that SCs may be IPs in the syntax and contain an INFL node

- i.e. the assumption that functional nodes are relevant in the syntax - ,

allows for the explanation of certain processes. As mentioned above, the

Page 50: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

22Ô

external theta-role is assumed to be assigned by the VP via INFL. If INFL

absorbs the case assigned by the selecting lexical verb ,by visibility, it will

be allowed to "keep" the external theta-role, and to function as a

pronominal inflection. Causative structures in French exemplify this

phenomenon. G&H provide evidence to show that the complement of a

causative verb is , in fact, a VP, and thus the causative verb must be an

auxiliary ( cf. below):

(376)/<?/t?/a/ [jpl iyp lire ces livres // V-to-I

TH-1 TH-2

Je feral [ jp lirej [yp tj ces livres //

fifVPl ferai ÍVP2 llr#i ÍVPJ tl ces livres/ff IS

TH-1 TH-2 (17Ô)-(179)

Linked with the fact that lexical verbs are the only verbal elements

that may have nominal complements is the fact that they are the only ones

that may assign theta-roles. An XP is nominal only if it is assigned a theta-

role. Auxiliaries do not assign theta-roles, but they may assign Tense-roles

(T-roles)D 1 to their complements. Auxiliaries which assign T-roles select a

VP with an independent tense. This creates a bifurcation of auxiliaries into

two different types: T-auxiliaries ( those that assign T-roles) and neutral

auxiliaries ( those that do not assign T-roles). T- auxiliaries govern a VP

with an independent Tense-morpheme. Neutral auxiliaries combine with

the Tense-morpheme of their complement to form a complex tense and

define the tense of S. BE is assumed to be a T-auxiliary; HAVE a neutral

auxiliary. T- auxiliaries and Neutral auxiliaries show systematic properties

that justify their classification into two distinct classes. One of such

properties is that only neutral auxiliaries allow the percolation of the

Page 51: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

229

external theta-role assigned by the VP to the subject. T-auxiliaries do not.

T-auxiliaries, thus, involve Raising or Control whereas neutral auxiliaries

involve VP complemements with no subject position and direct percolation

of theta-role to matrix subject position. (12) above illustrates percolation

over a neutral auxiliary, Mve. A passive structure like (15) illustrates no

external theta-role percolation over the auxiliary: the external theta-role is

assumed to be assigned to the verbal affix of the participle. The causative

structure (18) also illustrates a T-auxiliary structure where all theta-roles

are assigned within the complement of the auxiliary - via the pronominal

Infi.

The observed correlations between T- role assigning properties of

auxiliaries and thematic relationships, make G&H unify them under a

specific notion, Complete Thematic Constituent:

(377) An XP which is assigned a T-role is a Complete Thematic

Constituent (CTC): all theta-roles associated with X, the head of XP,

are assigned internal to XP (34)

This also captures the idea that tense is an operator on a theta-

domain. The identity of both domains is illustrated by a number of

syntactic processes. Note that precisely the examples mentioned to

illustrate theta-role percolation/ non-percolation illustrate the concept of

CTC: the complement of a passive (373) is a CTC: all its theta-roles are

assigned internally- A? is a T-auxiliary and assigns a T-role - ; the

complement of a causative (376) is a CTC: all its theta-roles are assigned

internally- faire is a T-auxiliary and assigns a T-role-. The complement of

the auxiliary A?r<? (370) is not a CTC: it is a neutral auxiliary ; the external

theta-role is percolated onto the matrix subject position, and the resulting

Page 52: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

tense is complex - a complex past- as a result of the combination of both

Tense-morphemes.

The grouping of auxiliaries into two different classes and the

postulation of constraints based on their properties, accounts for a problem

essentially left unexplained in previous analyses: the fixed order of

auxiliaries as well as their distribution - cf. section 2.1, and 2.2.2. G&H

postulate the following two constraints:

(37Ô)a. A T- chain may not contain two auxiliaries of the same class

b. Neutral auxiliaries precede T-auxiliaries (40)

If auxiliaries are assumed to have a function in terms of assigning a T-

role - only T-auxiliaries -, then a. follows from the assumption that there

should only be one auxiliary with a specific function in a T-chain. - in other

words, that auxiliaries with the same syntactic function are in

complementary distribution -. If theta-role percolation is only allowed by

neutral auxiliaries then b. follows because the opposite order is impossible:

a T-auxiliary would block the external theta-role percolated through a

neutral auxiliary on its way to the matrix subject position. The following

examples illustrate violations of (37Ô)a. and (37ô)b. :

(3?9) * ft fais avoir travaillé Marie b.

T-aux/neutral (25)b.

(36" 0) * John wast nave seen b.

T-aux/neutral (41 )a.

(3Ô1) * Mary made John have played with the baby b.

T-aux/neutral (41)b.

Page 53: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

(3ô2) * MarJoJoavrebbe doruto aver finite a.

netural/ neutral (2l6)b.

(3Ô3) * M est été vu a.

T-aux/T-aux (27)a.

(3Ô4) * fíe is been seen a.

T-aux/T-aux (27)b.

The characterisation of auxiliaries is subject to language variation, as

will become clear in the summary of G&H' s account of modal complement

structures. This characterisation, though, is also subject to variation within

the same language; the same lexical item may be a neutral or a T-auxiliary

depending on the context, as is the case with have in English:

(3Ô5) John has burned his house Neutral aux

(366) fthn had his house burned T-aux

Causative and modal verbs:

G&H classify Italian, French and English causative verbs as auxiliaries on

the basis of three basic facts: they can intervene between a raised object

and an extraction site (367) and (3ÔÔ) - only auxiliaries "continue" a T-

chain, and, thus make the proper government of the trace possible - ; they

can bear the value of tense required for VP anaphora (3Ô9), which is

assumed to be a property of auxiliaries ^2 - cf. section 2.1, no. 6 -; and they

take bare infinitives (32), which are assumed to be VPs as opposed to "to-

infinitives" -:

Page 54: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

(3Ô7) ft l'ai fait voir

(3ôÔ) llihrifurono fattileggere ( 173)a.,b.

(3Ô9) Jean a acheté du pain ce matin et Pierre le fera ce soir ( 174)b.

(390) They let John leave (175)a.

English make /let, and French faire are structural case assigners so

they may case-mark the subject of the VP complement. Note that by being

T-auxiliaries, they assign a T-role to their complement and give it the

status of a CTC, whose external theta-role is assigned within its VP-

projection. :

(391) We made/let ¡the warden hang the prisoners /

(392 ) Nous avons laisse {le gardien prendre les prisoniers I

(176)b.,c.

For French faire, as explained for (376), case is absorbed by INFL

and the external theta-role is assigned to it. As (393) shows, clitic climbing

is possible in causatives in French, as follows from the assumption that they

are auxiliaries, they take a VP, and that extraction is only possible out of a

(T-marked) VP:

(393) ft T& les/ ferai* [lire-*' ej/ (163)

Modal verbs are assumed to be always auxiliaries only in English -

not in French, nor Italian -. Root modals can function as both, auxiliaries

and lexical verbs in Italian and French. In French they raise to INFL in

infinitival structures like auxiliaries and unlike lexical verbs - cf. Pollock

Page 55: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

(19Ô7), and Chapter 4, sections 4.2,and 4.3 -. The following contrast seems

to imply that they are T-markers:

(394) a. ? Il pensait ne pouvoir] f yp pas tj dormiria'/

b* 11 pensait ne croirej [yp pas tj auxnistoiresdefantomesj

(191)d.,f.

Their ability to allow VP anaphora is also evidence for their auxiliary

status:

(395) a. Pierre voudrait accorderJe piano maisilne peutsYeut/doit

pas

b* Pierre voudrait accorderJe piano maisilne décide/croit pas

(192)

In Italian, there are also two possibilities. Nevertheless, as Italian

allows clitic climbing in modal complement structures, the different

function of the modal verbal element may be contrasted with respect to

this structure, which is not possible in French. When modal verbs are

lexical, they assign case to their complement identified as a nominal

projection. The subject position is, thus, not case assigned from the outside,

and the external theta-role of the embedded verb is taken up by PRO in

Spec-IP position. It is a Control structure:

(396) Mario vuolel' ¡p PRO / / • [ypleggere il libro III

TH-1 TH-1 (193)t>.

If the modal functions as an auxiliary, the case that it assigns is

absorbed by AGR in INFL, which then may bear the external theta-role of

the embedded verb. The pronominal argument inflection is subject to

Page 56: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

Control from the matrix subject. The auxiliary assigns a T-role to its

complement and the CTC requirement is satisfied:

(397) Mario vuote [ yp logg&rej iyp tj iiiibroi]

TH-1 TH-1 (194)b.

Clitic climbing is only allowed in a structure like (397) because the

trace of the clitic is a link, in the unique T-chain which includes all the

verbal elements in the sequence. The embedded verb properly antecedent

governs the trace, as was exemplified above in the French causative

structure (376):

C39Ô) Mario Joj + vuoio & {leggerek oj] (196)b.

Clitic climbing is not possible in a structure like (396) because there

are two T-chains in the structure; the lexical modal verb does not T-mark

its complement, so each of the subjects is the subject of a distinct T-chain.

This invalidates a structure like the following:^

(399) Mario 1* Jo/ + vuoJo ¿' [PRO //•* [Joggoro ¿ o/ J/J ( 195)b.

G&H explain the fact that French modal complement structures

equivalent to the Italian structures do not allow clitic climbing by making

reference - following Kayne (1967) - to the properties of AGR in INFL: only

the AGR of pro-drop languages may function as a syntactically active

pronominal argument. Note that the fact that it functions as a pronominal

inflection is not only a characteristic of pro-drop languages - cf. French

causative structures (376) -, what is is the fact that it is a pronominal

Page 57: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

argument subject to syntactic processes such as Control, which is assumed

to be the case in (397), as implied by the fact that the infinitival and the

matrix subject have the same theta-role. This process is assumed to be

what defines INFL as an A-position; French needs the Spec-IP position. The

lack of such a possibility explains the lack of structures like (397) and

(39Ô) in French.

This account is problematic for English , which is not a pro-drop

language and its modals take a VP complement. G&H attribute this to the

fact that there is a strong verbal affix in modals, which may function as the

external argument of the VP it governs. In (400), the modal assigns its

external theta-role to the matrix subject, while it takes the external theta -

role of the embedded VP - its verbal affix having inherent case -:

(400) Johßj {must iyp examine hispatients/

TH-1 TH-li TH-2 (203)

Epistemic modals in English are also auxiliaries , in French they are

lexical verbs, and in Italian they may be both. The contrast between (401)

and (402) shows that they are different in French and Italian:

(401) * Jeaniliaj devrait*[ P&Oj JP voir? tj (206)b.

(402 ) Giannij iioj deve J [ agr vedere J' ej/ (2 05)b.

The French modal assigns case to its complement; it is interpreted as

a nominal projection with an internal subject. Raising would be blocked by

minimality, as in the Italian structure (399). In the Italian example, (402),

AGR in INFL absorbs the case assigned by the modal and functions as an

expletive pronoun. Proper government of the trace is not blocked because

Page 58: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

vedere, the nearest link in the chain shares indices with the antecedent of

the trace by virtue of the fact that the matrix auxiliary, which bears the

clitic, T-marksit.

The avere -» essere rule

The non-rigidity oí the properties oí verbal items - i.e. their ability to

have them or not - is basic in G&H' s account oí the avere— essere rule

which, as has been shown in section 2.3.2.1 , applies in clitic climbing

structures after restructuring:

(403) a. Maria Jfa volute venird

b. Maria d è yoJuta venire ( 169)

It is assumed that Italian essere as opposed to French être has the

possibility of refraining from assigning a T-role , but still preventing theta-

role percolation. There is, thus, a neutral essere in Italian. This property of

essere is illustrated in several processes some of which draw upon the

theory internal restrictions on the order of auxiliaries. Neutral essere may

precede a T-auxiliary, as opposed to French être:

(404) a. Mar/a éstata invitata

b. Marie a été invitée * (I65)a.

(405) a. Jlibrifuroso fattiieggere

b. * Leslivresfurent / ont été fait, lire ( 165)c.

Italian stare is a T-auxiliary which may be preceded, not followed,

by essere.

Page 59: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

(406) Fssendo Mario state tortiirato .... ( 166)b. (407) * Mario stava essendo bastonato ( 167)

The account of the rule of avore — essore draws upon the

assumption that modals are T-auxiliaries in clitic climbing structures, and

the fact that essere may be a neutral auxiliary- and thus precede a T-

auxiliary - while not allowing the percolation of the external theta-role

assigned by the VP. The complement of the modal is a CTC, and all theta-

roles are assigned internally. It is a raising structure:

(406) Mariai fvpj ci/ è[yp2 e/ voiuta / ypj venire ej/fe//

(170)b.

In non-clitic climbing structures, the choice is avere, which allows

the percolation of the external theta-role when the modal is a lexical verb.

The complement of the modal is a nominal projection. It is a Control

structure:

(409)Mariay/vp/ A? /VP2 volute lo> PSOj venird e/ ///(170)a.

In French, there is no auxiliary change although there is a marginal

structure where clitic climbing is permitted ( Kayne 1967):

(410) ? Jean y a voulu aller

(411) *Jean y est voulu aJJer (172)

Page 60: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

This follows from the difference between £¿rt? and AÏS*?/*? ; the

French auxiliary is always a T-auxiliary, thus, the only auxiliary which may

precede other auxiliaries in French is avcdr.

Page 61: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

2.5 A few remarks

The inevitable changes in the model have led to the invalidation of

some of the mechanisms used in the sketched proposals. In other words,

pre-GB proposals are often invalidated because they imply a violation of GB

principles. This is the case, as already observed, with the first attempt to

explain the peculiar nature of "half-blooded" verbs by restructuring , which

was deemed no longer tenable as it led to a violation of the Projection

Principle, modifying the lexical properties of the verbs throughout the

derivation. The same can be observed for the first attempt to explain the

behaviour of causative predicates; i.e. Kayne (1975) - as noted in section

2.3.I.O -. Burzio (1966) discusses the proposal - cf. 2.3.1.2 - and rephrases

aspects of it. Quoting Burzio: " This is an obvious weakness, given Kayne's

extensive and convincing discussion of the similarities between passives

and FP. This weakness arises from the inability of the ST framework to

separate the three properties of passives, as is rather clear from Kayne "s

own discussion " (p. 256) (italics mine).

Nevertheless, Burzio (19ô6)'s VP movement analyses are also

dubious. Although they are independently motivated for certain

constructions - cf. 2.1. and preposing structures -, there seems to be no

direct motivation to posit such a mechanism in either C- or M-A sequences.

The basic proposal in this work necessitates several ad hoc mechanisms

such as " Subject Substitution " - cf. section 2.3.2.2 -; does not provide a

trigger for VP movement; nor does it establish and license the exact landing

site for the moved VP. See Chapter 3 - section 3.3.2 - for another VP

movement analysis - at LF - by Baker (190*0) and - section 3.4 - for some

criticisms of this proposal.

Page 62: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

240

VP complementation íor complex predicates must confront strong

arguments in favour of a clausal status of tue node dominating the verbal

complement - cf. especially section 2.2.1 -. It will be explained in section

3.4 - see also 2.4 - how the alternative theory proposed by Guéron and

Hoekstra (19ÔÔ) allows for a preservation of clausal complementation of

most instances of Vis in complex predicate structures in the syntax,

while it construes them as VPs in LF. In this fashion, it reconciles

VP complementation proposals and the strong syntactic clausal

complementation arguments.

The simultaneity of two parallel structures must face the assumption

that principles hold at different levels but both structures are present at all

levels. Principles requiring a monosentential structure - such as Binding -

will obviously be violated by the other, bisentential, yet simultaneous

structure. If mechanisms are found that avoid this - inevitably undesirable

- consequence, I believe they should be assumed.

Adjunctions to V proposed for adjunct predicates- as in Picallo

(1985) - are not independently motivated, and shown inviable in Chomsky

(1966b) - cf. i.2.2 -: adjunctions are only allowed to Xo or XP, not to X'.

Although, as noted in section 2.3.2.3, Picallo (1990) adjoins root modals to

VP, and not to V. The proposal for root modals differs from the hypothesis

for epistemic modals, for which a VP complementation seems to hold, and

for which I will tentatively argue for in Chapter 3.

Other mechanisms such as thematic rewriting rules and reanalysis

may be accounted for in the light of the present theory in ways not

exclusively needed for these processes. Such ways include chain formation,

- which may apply to verbs in a sequence as shown by G&H -, and head

movement. Together with these, one might explore the importance of LF as

a way to explain the peculiar behaviour of some verbs in a sequence - in

Page 63: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

241

line with G&H, as mentioned -. The possibility of consecutive VPs - cf.

section 3.3.I.2- is, at present, not necessarily problematic to the principles

of grammar.

Explanatory adequacy - and, thus, independent motivation for the

chosen mechanism - will be the guiding lines to the approach adopted in

Chapter 3.

Before bringing in the main hypothesis in the thesis, though, I would

like to point out some other ( apparently ) problematic facts which arise in

view of the proposals sketched for complex predicates. These are not

theoretical but empirical facts from Catalan and Spanish. There are verbs

which are not traditionally classified under M-A nor C-predicates and

which, nevertheless, allow clitic climbing. The folllowing illustrate this

phenomenon:

(412 )a. Ho semblava entendre tot

b. L "na aconseguit seduir

c. L "ña decidit trucar

(413)a. La intento convencer

b. Lo deseaba ver

c. Lo pretendió ridiculizar

It must be noted that not all speakers find these fully grammatical,

but the fact that most speakers do, indicates that whichever mechanism is

found valid for the formation of complex predicates should apply to these

verbs as well. 6 4

Page 64: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

Notes to Chapter 2

242

(1) I am deliberately leaving aside important studies on the matter which

do not follow a generativist view. This has been done in order to keep a

coherent presentation of the issue. Moreover, the aim of this thesis is not to

compare or contrast frameworks but to put forward an attempt of

explanation within one specific framework, as the title implies.

Observations made by non-generativist authors such as Palmer ,

Huddleston, Quirk, etc. have, at certain points, been included.

(2) Môdàîb in English M ve been traditionally assumed to be a distinct

category M and, therefore, generated under a different node Aux or INFL.

This issue will be touched upon in several sections in what follows .

(3) In the sections where a specific proposal is summarized, the number

next to the example indicates the number in the source.

(4) There are other instances in the language of this same phenomenon

with other verbs: soy, estoy.

(5) Although Zagona (19ÔÔ) proposes a framework where auxiliaries

assign specific theta-roles, temporal roles - cf. section 2.2.2 -.

(6) See Chapter 4, section 4.1, Abney (1966), Fukui & Speas (19ÔÔ) for the

use of this argument to grant elements a functional status. A question which

arises within the present framework" and which is briefly touched upon in

Chapter 4 is whether auxiliaries may be generated in funtional nodes.

Page 65: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

(7) In languages with other choices for the head parameter, this order may

be reversed; e.g. Basque: Maiteak Jon ikusd du ; where ikusi is a non-

finite form of the main verb (to see) and du is the auxiliary ( 3sgS - 3sg0).

(Ô) See sections 2.4 and IA for an attempt to explain the ordering and the

distribution restrictions of auxiliaries within the present framework..

(9) The Affix Hopping Rule is valid for English sequences of auxiliaries.

Modals in Romance languages differ from modals in English and, as will

become clear in later sections, they are not traditionally considered

auxiliaries. Even in recent proposals which do consider them auxiliaries - cf.

2.4 -, they are only so considered in certain configurations. See section 2.3.2

for the debate on modals in Romance. In 2.1.2, modals and aspectuals are

regarded as having a double nature, the fact which all sections summarized

which deal with M-A sequences try to account for.

(10) Note, though, that British English savo allows for constructions of the

type: (i) savo you asy eslieron?. Here, HAVE cannot be considered an

auxiliary. See Pollock (19Ô7) for an explanation in the present framework for

this special behaviour of British English HAVE.

( 11) It must be noted that in the present framework, the concept of adjusct-

prodlcate has been posited - cf. Zubizarreta (19Ô2), Picallo (1985X0 990)

among others -, which would allow a verb imposing a specific type of

selectional restriction not to be a main verb - cf. section 2.3-2.3 -.

(12) I will use the term clitic climbing as a general term , bearing in mind

that the phenomenon is far from being established. The original work

referred to in this section relied on a movement account of clitic placement

Page 66: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

because me model tnen used couia account ror its distribution on me basis

of the Specified Subject Condition (SSC), a condition on transformations

which disallowed movement if there was a subject intervening between the

extracting site and the landing site - cf. also section 2.3.2 -. An alternative

account is to consider clitics as base-generated on me verb (or INFL) and

licensing an empty category in their thematic position. - cf. Borer (1964),

Burzio C1956), Rosselló ( 1966), among others.

(13) There are important restrictions with respect to different types of

adverbs -cf. especially jackendoff (1972) -, a type of evidence which I have

not considered in this thesis as adverb typology is not, to my mind, directly

related to its main proposal.

(14) See Hernanz&Rigau (19Ô4), Belletti(19ô2) among others, for discussion

on this issue.

(15) Examples like (i) and (ii) show mat not all main verbs disallow clitic

climbing in either Spanish and Catalan. See section 2.5 for some

observations on mis fact.

(i) Ho va iieJjsar veure ajs seus antics

(ii) la Mentó ver

See also note (64)

(16) Note that the examples in (g) correspond to an aspectual verb and a

modal verb. H&R obviously refer to me contrast shown by auxiliaries as in

test 6, which disallow anaphora - cf. Chapter 3 for an explanation of mis

constrast and main proposal of mis thesis.

Page 67: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

(17) Note also that most main verbs do not allow Null Complement

Anaphora, as pointed out by ]M Brucart -p.c.-: (i) *Lius entró finalmente a

Ja fiesta, pero ne deseaba. The fact that the Spanish and Catalan examples

in test 6 which are used to illustrate that main verbs do allow VP anaphora,

include a clitic; a fact which is obviously not to be disregarded in any

explanation oí VP anaphora - which is beyond the aim of this study.

(10) Note that there are other structures where two verbs are also

consecutive : En Eamon es dutjsava cantant / Corría cantando / He left

laughing at us .These are accounted for in the literature by positing either

a secondary predication or a small clause (cf. Chomsky (19Ô1), Stowell

(19Ô3), Williams (19Ô0) among others). Note that these structures often do

not imply a sequence of two consecutive verbs: fíe left the room laughing

at us/ En Eamon esdutsava cada dia cantant /Pepe corria los maratones

cantando. Thus, I will not take these sequences into consideration.

(19) These are not the only possible control structures. I will not consider

those which do not involve a sequence of verbs, for instance, interrogative

infinitives as: / wonder who PEO to ask to the party or cases of non-

obligatory Control: PEO to leave the city during the Olympics would be a

verygoodldea.

(20) In using the distinction suntactle / lexical passive, I follow Wasow

(1977). By syntactic passive I refer to the fact that the NP which has been

raised to subject position is not related to the main verb in the lexicon; i.e.

it is not one of its arguments. In a lexical passive construction, the NP

which has been raised is the argument of the matrix verb, as in : She lost

the key / The £ey was lost. In the Catalan and Spanish examples, the

impossibility of syntactic passive implies the raising of a non-argument of

Page 68: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

tne matrix vert) - creure /creer-; i.e it is tne tue external argument or the

embedded verb which is raised.

(21) Nevertheless, there are alternative approaches within the present

model ; approaches which postulate a base-generated VP node for some

infinitival structures. Some of these will be discussed below - section 2.3.-.

There is an important alternative within the framework: Guéron and

Hoekstra (19ÔÔ), who grant some infinitival structures a VP status at LF -

cf. section 2.3.3.

(22) As already noted in Chapter 1, in the summary of Control Theory, the

status of PRO has been the issue of much debate. The so-called PRO

Theorem has been argued to follow from other subtheories, thus, the effect

of Control to be reducible to other modules. See Manzini (1963a), Borer

(1969X Bouchard (19Ô4) among others.

(23) Note that for- deletion is not allowed after N or A, only after V: * It is

silly you not to call Mm / * Tne desire you to finish your thesis.

(24) Nevertheless, in the present framework, INFL may be granted certain

properties which allow it to function as a pronominal - cf. Guéron &

Hoekstra (19ÔÔ) -, or verbs may be linked in other ways - cf. Picallo (19Ô5)

, Zubizarreta (1965)- The arguments alluded to in this section, thus, lose

strength.

(25) But see section 2.3.2.3 for some'monosentential analyses of complex

predicate structures within the present framework.

Page 69: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

247

(26) Zubizarreta (19Ô5) uses the term complex verb for a sequence of

causative plus main verb; a sequence for which I use the label complex

predicate.

(27) I include modals in the examples for completeness, but as has been

observed - cf. Chapter 1 section 1.1 -, they are assumed to be generated in

a different node from other auxiliaries- cf. also Chapters 3 and 4 -.

(20) The reason why a full verbal sequence ( 5 verbal elements ) is not

grammatical in Catalan nor in Spanish as in (i) and (ii) respectively, calls for

an explanation:

(i) *? Els caramels que no trobem poden haver estat essent menjats per les

criatures

(ii)*? Los caramelos que no encontramos pueden haber estado siendo

comidos por los niños

This thesis deals with 2 verb sequences, so the account of this restriction is

beyond its scope. Note that the English examples are not fully acceptable

either.

The fact that the modals in the sequences in the examples in the text are

interpreted as epistemic will gain importance in Chapter 3 - cf. also 2.3.2.3-

(29) As noted in the introduction, in this thesis Í will concentrate in the a.

sequences - leaving progressive and passive for further research.

(30) Functional nodes have been briefly introduced in Chapter 1, and will

not be further taken into account until Chapter 4. In this section the issue is

to consider the structure of complex verbs bearing in mind that all verbal

elements are members of the V category, but disregarding - for the sake of

Page 70: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

simplicity - tüe important matter oí whether they should be granted a

distinct, functional, node - an issue to be touched upon in section 4.3 .

(31) I am leaving aside comment on other studies referring to ASW's

proposal which are not within the present model. Note the article by

Gazdar, Pullum, and Sag (19Ô2).

(32) I will not make crucial use of Zagona*s framework in the rest of the

thesis. More precisely, I not consider part of her framework, although I will

refer to it in several occasions ; i.e. the licensing of VPs . I will assume her

structural conclusions. The licensing of empty and full VPs is, obviously, a

very important matter, but beyond the scope of this thesis. It must be

noted that - to my knowledge - there are two important proposals on this

subject in the field: one is Zagona (198Ô), the other is Guéron&Hoekstra

(i960). The latter will be considered in 2.4 and in Chapter 3 as it touches

upon not only auxiliary constructions, but also complex predicates. Zagona

(1956), nevertheless, provides the structure necessary to postulate V-0

movement in Chapter 3-

(33) I will not consider this important matter, again because it lies outside

the scope of this thesis. Nevertheless, section 2.4 refers to Guéron &

Hoekstra (I960)' s framework who, using Tense as an unanalysed primitive

provide a basis for an account of the distribution of auxiliaries which seems

to me not at all implausible. G&H also directly avoid some of the theoretical

problems observed below as a consequence of the subcategorization

licensing condition on VPs.

Page 71: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

(345 An important explanation of this fact is provided by Pollock (19Ô7)

relying on the parameterization of inflectional nodes - cf. Chapter 4, section

4.2-.

(35) Zagona does not refer to Baker's framework of incorporation , although

V-to-V is also seen as an instance of head-movement as in Barriers.

Zagona's claim of participle incorporation is related to the main hypothesis

in this thesis, as will be posited in Chapter 3, although it crucially differs

from it because I do not consider temporal-role marking.

(36) The status of X is left undetermined here, as this is the matter of

debate among the scholars in the literature sketched in the following

sections . Nevertheless, as has been made clear in section 2.2.1, there are

many reasons to consider X a clausal node.

(37) The capitalized English verbs are used to refer to causatives in general.

When a distinction is needed between English and a Romance language, it is

made by using the corresponding lexical items. This also appiles to other

sections.

(30) The term reanaJysis is defined differently in Manzini (1903t»), section

2.3.1.4.

(39) Brucart (1984) assumes a process of restructuring proposed by

Bordelois (1974), which I do not consider in the review of proposals.

(40) See Chapter 4, section 4.3 for a different account of Past participle

agreement in the present framework; cf. Kayne ( 19Ô7)

Page 72: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

(41) Note that structure such as (215) in the text implies allowing for a VP-

internal subject. Nevertheless, Manzinii 19o3*>) does not refer to the present

debate on an original internal position for the subject - and subsequent

movement to the specifier of a functional projection - because it was

posited in later works - cf. Chapter 1 ( p. 11) for references.

(42) The fact that structures like J'allait une table exist, imply that faire

may also assign Case. This according to Manzini must, be captured in the

lexical entry by an implication: if the verb assigns a theta-role to a small

clause, then it must be a reanalyser.

(43) It must be noted that clitic climbing is allowed in some control

structures, verbal sequences composed of a main verb not characterized as

a modal plus an infitive, both in Catalan and in Spanish. This is briefly

touched upon in section 2.5, where some examples are given. See also note

( 15) and last note to this Chapter.

(44) In Catalan there is always agreement with the modal verb, regardless

of the position of the object:

(i) Està segur que espoden aturar fes situations injustes

(ii) Fstà segur que ies situacions injustes es poden aturar

(iii) *£sta' segur que espot aturaries situacions injustes

(45) Note that not all the verbal elements in (241) conform to all of these

properties: dare/need are also non-modals, is to has all the finite forms.

The characteristics of modals in English are not considered in depth as they

do not bear directly upon the subject of this thesis.

Page 73: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

(46) It must be noted that this distinction - due to Hof mann (197o) -

disregards other classifications of modality into more different types as in

Palmer (1979). Palmer makes a difference between epistemic modality -

" making a judgement about the truth of a proposition" ; deontic modality -

influencing the action as by giving permission, or imposing an obligation,

and dynamic modality - which refers to ability or volition of the subject. I

will not consider this classification - nor others - but follow the general use

in generative studies which unify deontic and dynamic into "root" . The

subject of modality types is beyond the scope of this thesis.

(47) It must be noted that the second examples allow an epistemic

interpretation: (i) Us governs poden posar fi a la injustícia, però no volen

fer-ho. In the examples I intend a root interpretation; i.e. (ii)The

governments have sufficient power to put an end to injustice".

(4ô) In Spanish the distinction is made by including the preposition de

after deber when intending an epistemic interpretation, as the parentheses

show. I have included the parentheses because this is not followed by all

speakers.

(49) The syntax of aspectual verbs is more complicated than that of other

"restructuring" verbs as they have several other options: they may be

followed by other non-finite forms, and, indeed, there are some aspectual

verbs that must be followed by an -ing form, while others allow both:

(i)a. Continua *fer/fent les mateixes classes

b. la policia comença a desea/regar / ¿descarregant quan rep

ordres

(ii)a. Will Israel ever stop *tc kill /killing Palestinians

b. Will Israel ever cease to kill /killing Palestinians

Page 74: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

Note that the relevant interpretation of (i)b is what makes the second

option ungrammatical, the verb comencarm&y be followed by an -ing form

if interpreted as in (iii):

(iii) Els actors comencen J "obra Interrogant eJpuMc

(50) Catalan and Spanish have ways of disambiguating : the use of a

different preposition or a periphrastic construction :

(i) Ha tornat per CtaJde JdJr-JIque....

iii) Ha vlngutper {taJde)dirque...

(iii) Ha venido para decirme que...

(iv) Ha vuelto para dearie que... )

(51) As pointed out to me by ]M. Brucart, this test is also applicable to

some modal verbs, as in (i) for Spanish and (ii) for Catalan:

(i)a. Luis debe de estar enfermo

b. Luis está probablemente enfermo

(ii) a. En Lluís deu estar malalt

b. En Lluís està probablement malalt

These modals are interpreted as epistemic - as already noted deiwe

may only have an epistemic reading in Catalan, cf. also note (46*).

(52) It must be mentioned that several important analyses have been left

out in this section. I am basically referring to the parallel structure analysis

in Zubizarreta (1962) and the "parallel phrase-marker" analysis in

Manzinii 19ô3b). The former follows the same proposal explained in section

2.3.I.3. Manzini incorporates restructuring into a theory of phrase-markers:

she allows a double phrase-marker for M-A sequences one of which may

be derived from the other.

Page 75: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

(53) The NP subject of the complement clause is PRO, but the fact that there

is a subject position does not, in Rizzi's framework, prevent the rule from

applying . The present framework disallows such a "destruction" of

structure. Linguists who have posited a non-sentential status for the

embedded clause have had to somehow rearrange the dischargement of the

subject role - cf. especially Guéron and Hoekstra (I960) -.

(54) Note that it also applies vacuously if the clitic takes a "long step". The

argument is theory internal; it relies on the assumption that there Is- a

clausal node.

(55) Note that agreement with the verb and postverbal occurrence of

subject ( preposed object ) are possible. This is regarded as a consequence

of the available post-verbal position for subjects in pro-drop languages.

(56) I have only included examples illustrating clitic climbing because

object preposing and auxiliary choice - cf. also 2.1 - are not relevant tests in

Catalan nor Spanish. See Rizzi (1902a) for illustrations on these

constructions for Italian.

(57) It must be noted that in Picallo (1990) the same proposal is made, but

root modal verbs are generated as VP-adjuncts - (9), p. 259 -.

(50) It must be noted, as will become clear in what follows, that G&H*s

concept of T-marking, and of Tense-role, is not equivalent to Zagona's - cf.

section 2.2.2 - notion of temporal-marking. She makes use of distinct

temporal roles - E,R,S -, which are not considered by G&H. Their notion of

T-chain is also distinct from Picallo(19Ô5)'s use of T-chain as a redefinition

of a governing category of an element.

Page 76: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

(59) G&H do not make the parallel of T-marking and theta-marking in the

same way that Zagona(19ÔÔ) does: the assignment of Tense-roles by

auxiliaries - see below - does not lead them to a theory of "argumenthood"

for VP projections, as is clearly expressed by the FDC ,(359) in text. Their

theory avoids interaction problems with NP/CP argumenthood - basically

VP-adjunction -, some of which were noted in sectioon 2.2.2 -. See also note

(50).

(60) The mechanism of chain extension by Spec-head agreement is also

crucially used in Barriers to account for passive in English, and also in

Zagona (19ÔÔ), following the barri&rs explanation.

(61) See note (59).

(62) Note that there is a reversal in the use of this test as compared to its

use in 2.1: VP anaphora was assumed to be a characteristic that only main

verbs could have in Romance languages. By considering causatives as

auxiliaries, G&H generalize the English test to Romance. Obviously, though,

the presence of the clitic cannot be disregarded.

(63) The fact that there exists the possibility of clitic climbing with other

types of verbal sequences has already been pointed out in note (15), and

will be briefly touched upon in section 2.5. See note (64).

(64) I must note, though, that the main proposal in this thesis refers to

complex verbs . Nevertheless, and because of the fact that they are

verbal sequences, a hypothesis will also be posited for complex

predicates in Catalan and Spanish; namely Guéron and Hoekstra (19Ôô)"s

Page 77: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

T-tlieory proposal. Hence, the feature that the verbs in the examples would

acquire would be that of optionally being T-markers - cf. sections 2.4, 3.4,

4.3 - . Further research is obviously required; i.e. the specific restrictions on

which type of verbs allow this optionality. The fact is that not all main

verbs do, as there are clear ungrammatical examples of clitic climbing with

two main verbs in both Catalan and Spanish as in (i) and (ii) ( Í10) in H&R

1954):

(i) * Hi Jamento pensar

(ii) *la Jámente pegar

Page 78: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

CHAPTER THREE: Incorporation

3.1 An outline of Morphology Theory

3.1.1 A note on non-evident single constituents

The observations in this section are intended to show basically that it

may be the case that not all morphologically separate units are also

syntactically separate. This approach is , to my mind., legitimated by the

kind of theory of morphology that will be presented in the next section. 1

Certain verbal sequences of two verbs are not evident single

separate units because they function as one lexical unit - they cannot be

divided under any circumstances, and it is often the case - in certain forms

of the tenses - that the first part of the sequence never bears stress -. I

believe it is worthwhile pursuing the idea that these do constitute a unit,

even though they do not surface as one morphologically complex form. In

other words, we may try to characterize their behaviour by assuming that

they become an Xo by the application of a syntactic process; namely, head-

movement, which allows for further cliticisation of the auxiliary verb onto

its host. In section 3-3-1 I will present the syntactic analysis and in the

next section I will review the theory of morphology assumed in Baker

( 19ÔÔ) - and Ouhalla (I960) among others - which seems to be relevant for

the explanation of the behaviour of such sequences.

Before presenting the theory of morphology which may lead to an

explanation of such a phenomenon, it may be wise to note that several

authors in the literature have pointed out and provided analyses of other

cases of two constituents that function as one single lexical unit in several

Page 79: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

respects -1 will not assess the analyses; I will only point out some of the

data-.

Pronominal cliticization is the most obvious example of such a

phenomenon. Kayne ( 1975) already analyzed these as Xo items. The degree

of cohesion of pronominal clitics and V elements is very strong, but

arguments have been posited in the literature - cf. especially Kayne

Î1975U19Ô7), Aoun (19Ô5), among others- granting an independent theta

position for clitics, and subsequent movement onto the V head - cf. also

sections 2.1, 3.2 -. According to some authors, the unit cl+V is, thus, not

generated as a unit, but becomes a unit by a syntactic phenomenon

because it involves head movement - see section 3.3.1.1 for further

comments on cliticization-.

Another example of the phenomenon of "non-evident single

constituency" are some sequences of V+preposition - as in sequences of

modal verbs ; i.e. V+P+infinitival -, which seem to function as one single

lexical item as well. G&H (I960) already suggest an analysis in terms of

incorporation of the preposition to the verb; head movement- although

they do not refer directly to Baker's incorporation theory - for the sequence

have * to in English. For it, G&H suggest adjunction of to to have and

they propose a structure as in (l)a.,b.. It must be noted that in their

analysis they assume to to head a PP at S-structure (Da , but to be

interpreted as part of a predicate at LF ( DbJ.e. as a VP- cf. section 2.4, and

3-4- G&H (19ÔÔ); 53-54):

(Da. Johnj I ÍVP has* to/ fpp e/fyp ej leave Mary HI

b. Johnj Hyp has * to/ fype/f ypej leave Mary III

That have-f-to form a syntactic constituent is shown by the

ungrammatically of (2). - G&H (1955); 53 -:

Page 80: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

(2 ) *John Ms sot to leave Mary

The same analysis is posited for Italian avere+da , where the

preposition adjoins to the verbal head in the same fashion.

Other verbs requiring a preposition, such as the aspectuals analyzed

in section 2.3.2, are obvious candidates to be considered as non-evident

single consituents: començar * a, tornar + a;empezar + a. volver f a, etc.

Burzio (1986) proposes an analysis for these sequences in Italian - which

he terms prepositional infinitives ( cominciare (a¿ continuare (à), aneare

ía), venire Ca)- in terms of cliticization of each of these prepositions onto

the infinitival verbal head; i.e. the verbal head that follows them. He cites

Rizzi (1982) who gives evidence for such a claim. Evidence such as the

contrast in (3)a. and b., which suggests that the preposition and the

infinitival verb form a syntactic constituent, as they cannot be separated:

(3)a. Alario pensa ene ferse potra partiré

b. * Mario pensa di forse poter partiré

The English sequences of verb plus preposition in phrasal verbs are

also candidates of non-evident single constituents. Stowell (1981) refers to

'Particle Incorporation" and "NP-incorporation" to account for the contrast

in structures like (4)-Stowell (1981); 296- 2, for which he assumed the

structures in (5) - StowelK 1981);301,303- ; where complex X-0 constituents

are created :

(4)a. Kevin turned on the light

b. levin turneé the light on

(5)a. Kevin ÍV'ÍV turned - on 11 the light 111

Page 81: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

b. Kevin (y [y [y turned -theiight / - on //

Radford (19ÔÔ) also analyzes such constructions as instances of

word-level adjunctions. An example as (6) is given the structure (7) -

Radfordí 19ÔÔ); 257-:

(6) The weather may turn out rather frosty

(7) v

/ \

V P turn out

As Radford points out: * ... it is traditionally claimed that the [...]

sequence turn out forms a kind of "complex verb". " (p.257)3

As a final observation to this informal introductory section on the

relationship between morphology and syntax - but without implying, that

the here-mentioned analyses are assumed valid - one could mention Rizzi's

claim that two verbs undergoing restructuring become part of one

syntactic consituent - cf. section 2.3.2 -, although the dominating node is

not given an X-0 status - i.e. it is considered a V -. Also worth noting is

Zubizarreta's claim that a sequence of causative plus infinitival complement

is generated as a complex verb in one of its simultaneous parallel

structures - mainly on the basis of the fact that the first verbal element

does not define a stress domain -, and obviously that it forms a semantic

unit with the second verb. One might also mention analyses dating from

Chomsky (1965) where a sequence of different constituents - generated as

separate morphological elements - were assumed to undergo reanalysis and

assigned an X-0 status; typically idioms such as [ taÁ'e advantage of ].

Page 82: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

To conclude, the difference between morphologically created lexical

items and syntactically created unite is an issue worth considering. I will

focus on the latter - the former not being the subject matter of study of this

thesis -. Baker's theory of incorporation sheds light on phenomena such as

the ones briefly noted above. Again, as the title of the thesis indicates, I

only intend to attempt an explanation on verbal sequences and not on any

other syntactic units which may have been formed by an identical - or

similar process -. Generally, morphologically created units generated as

one lexical item, remain "opaque" - in a sense to be explained below, cf.

section 3-1.2 - to any_ process whatsoever; on the other hand, two

syntactically independent elements may have the option -cf. 3-3.1- of not

undergoing processes that have the effect of creating a unit, therefore

allowing a margin of "non-cohesiveness". This will give a clue to the

explanation of some apparently problematic interruptions of syntactically

created verbal units - cf 3.3.1.1, and 3.3.1.3. -. It must be noted that, in the

present framework, the borderline between morphology and syntax is not

straightforward, and processes of affixation - in other words, the adjunction

of lexical heads to functional nodes containing inflectional affixes, such as

V-to-I (see section 1.1, 1.2.2) -, although syntactically created, remain as

opaque as "proper" morphologically base-generated units.

3.I.2 The approach

"Si una combinación sintáctica se funde en una unidad léxica, esta nueva unidad es tratada por analogía de la palabra simple y se traslada a ella lo que es posible en relación con la palabra"

(Dietrich (1973:38)

Page 83: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

What Dietrich's words express is, to my mind, translated into GB-

barriers terms by Baker in his theory of morphology. In other words, it is

made precise by alluding to concepts like head movement and constraints

that apply to (syntactically created) X-0 elements.

One of the alternative ways in viewing the relationship between

morphology and syntax is the one assumed in Baker(19ôÔ) - basically

following Marantz (1954)- , Ouhalla (19ÔÔ) and others, which regards

morphology as another subtheory in the grammar, on a par with Binding

Theory, Theta Theory, Case Theory, etc. applying to Xo elements at any

level of the grammar, from the lexicon to PF. In this view, Morphology

Theory contains principles that determine the well-formedness of Xo .

Quoting Baker: "As such, "morphology theory" (as we may call it) can be

characterized as the theory of what happens when a complex structure of

the form lz-o X + Y ] is created. In this way, it is parallel to (say) the

binding theory, which is the theory of structures of the form [NPi... NPi' ],

where the subscript is a referential index." (p. 6ô)

Ouhalla (19ÔÔ) claims that, apart from language-specific

morphological principles, there are two universal principles: the Affix

Principle (AP) - (Da.,as in Baker (19Ô5) - and the Head Opacity Condition

(HOC) (l)b.(Ouhalla (19ôô); 15). The Affix Principle is essential as a trigger

for incorporation processes - as will be explained in 3.2 -:

(Ô)a. The morphological subcategorisation frame of affixes

must be satisfied prior to the S-structure level

b. The internal structure of Xo categories is opaque to move-

alpha

Baker (19ÔÔ;73) states (ô)b. as a well-formedness condition on

representations:

Page 84: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

(9) * ÍXO ti ]

As Baker points out this may be linked to the Lexicalist Hypothesis.

Selkirk (1962) proposes the Word Autonomy Hypothesis which disallows

rules (i.e. deletion or movement transformations) applying to S-structure

categories to involve categories of W-structure (word-structure). In this

way she rules out the "manipulation of affixes". The intuition in this

proposal is kept in Baker (1986) but it is given another dimension. Selkirk

uses it to disallow the interference of syntax in the domain of morphology,

in other words, to postulate that all morphological processes take place in

the lexicon . Baker uses it to disallow the breaking up of Xo categories

created anywhere in the grammar. Before the creation of a head, move-

alpha may - and in some cases must, as the result of the Affix Principle-

apply to W-structure categories - namely, affixes, which have been

generated in an independent D-structure position. Baker's principle -(9)

above- implies that traces must be exhaustively dominated by an X-0 level

category in the case of head movement.

X-0 categories created in the lexicon are evidently subject to

the same constraints, as implied by the theory of morphology which

regards it as another subtheory.

What the above considerations suggest is that if a sequence of

head categories become one head category by the application of a

syntactic mechanism, the sequence will become a domain of

application of principles which apply to head categories, i.e.

morphology principles.

In the next section I will present the fundamental reasoning

behind the idea that a part of a word - i.e. an affix - which may end

up morphophonologically amalgamated with another part of a word

Page 85: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

should be generated in an independent D-structure position; the

principle which ensures it is Baker's Uniformity of Theta Assigning

Hypothesis (UTAH).4 - cf. section 3.2 -.

Another important principle of morphology theory that Baker

posits is the Mirror Principle5 (Baker ( I960); 13):

(10) MIRROR PRINCIPLE:

Morphoiogicai derivations must directly reflect

syntactic derivations (and vice versa)

An example that illustrates this principle , and which Baker uses to

argue in favour of a syntactic analysis of passivization is the following, from

Chichewa, which involves interaction between causativization and

passivization:

(11) KaluJu a-ns-menv- ets-#dw-a kwa ssyanHndl

birimsnkhwi)

hare SP-PAST-beat-CAUS-PASS-ASP to baboons

(by chameleon)

'The hare was caused to be beaten by the baboons (by the

chameleon)"

The causative affix is nearer to the verbal root than the passive affix,

a fact which, according to the Mirror Principle, implies the precedence of

causativization over passivization. Note that - as will be explained below -

the fact that causativization is regarded as a syntactic phenomenon leads to

the postulation of passive also being a syntactic phenomenon. 6

Page 86: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

264

3-2 Incorporation (Baker 19ÔÔ)

3.2.O Introduction

Baker(19ôô) posits a mechanism that explains the different

Grammatical Function (GF) changing phenomena found in languages without

the need to postulate different rules for each GF process. He claims that

particular GF changing processes do not exist in language, but that

" "Grammatical function changing" is the side effect of this word movement"

(p.i) ; that is, the consequence of a general mechanism that involves the

combination of two words into one7. By GF changing processes he refers to

constructions where an underlying GF becomes another one at S-st; for

instance, passivization , which involves the change of an object into a

subject - cf. "rule"(14) below -; or causativization, which involves the

introduction of a new subject and the change of a subject into an object - cf.

"rule*'(4) below -. The advantage of such a move is to explain the

relationship between two different sentences with the same meaning

{tà^matíc paraphrases), thus obtaining a unified explanation. Hence he

explains apparently GF changing processes as the incorporation of a V, N or

P into another head category, generally a V - although Note (3D on

passive- ; the consequent structural changes create new government

relationships - with agreement and case consequences - giving rise to what

have been traditionally considered changes in grammatical functions. In GB

GFs are non-primitives , and thus Baker's work is a move towards

eliminating unneccessary notions from the theory.

Page 87: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

Baker focuses basically on highly agglutinative languages - Bantu

languages, Eskimo languages, etc - but, as we will see in the following

sections, his proposal seems to be applicable to Romance languages as well -

I will claim this for Catalan and Spanish -. In section 3.2.1 and 3.2.2,1 will

briefly put forward Baker's main ideas giving examples and evidence from

his basic source (agglutinative languages), and in sections 3.3.2 I will show

how he applies these ideas to other languages.^ Section 3-3-1 is an

application of Baker's mechanism to verbal sequences which he does not

consider ; i.e. complex verbs in Romance, basically Catalan and Spanish.

It is of utmost importance to mention that I will only be referring to

a very specific part of Baker's theory; i.e. V- incorporation, because it

seems to me to give a plausible account for verbal sequences in Catalan and

Spanish, basically 9.1 will not refer to the other types of head movement

that he posits.

3.2.I The notion

Incorporation is the term used by Baker for the adjunction of an X-0

element onto another X-0 element. In this section I will sketch how he

makes use of such a process to account for grammatical function changing

phenomena.

Consider the passive example:

U3)a. Alfonso attacked fordi AGENT PATIENT

b. Jordi was attacked (by Alfonso ) PATIENT AGENT

(13) a. and b. express the same relationship between Jordi and

Alfonso, but the surface forms are different. The theta role that each

element bears is the same in both, but the order and morphological shape

Page 88: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

266

of the verb differs, plus the fact that the AGENT in U3)b. is introduced by

a preposition. The descriptive characterization is given by Baker as follows:

( 14) Passive: subject --J oblique (or null) ; object —> subject

But (14) is a descriptive statement; it adds nothing theoretically

interesting to the grammar.

Consider an instance of causative in Chichewa (Bantu):

( 15) a. Mtsuko u - na -gw - a

waterpot SP-PAST -fall -ASP ( 10)a.p. 10-11

'The waterpot fell"

b. Mtsikana a -na - u -gw - ets - a mtsuko

girl SP-PAST-OP-fall-CAUS-ASP waterpot (lô)b.

"The girl made the waterpot fall"

Note: where OP = object agreement prefix

SP= subject agreement prefix

This is an instance of one of the different possible causativization

processes in languages and its descriptive statement is :

(16) null —> subject; subject-->object

(which accounts for the agreement relationships indicated)

( 15)b. may be paraphrased in Chichewa as in ( 17) ,

(17) Mtsikana ana - chit-its-a kutJ mtsuko u-gw-e

girl AGR - do-MAKE -ASP that waterpot AGR-fall-ASP

Page 89: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

"The girl made the waterpot fall" (2)a. p. 148

Just like (13)a. and b., 05)b. and (17) also express the same

"meaning" relationships between NPs. Baker's way of characterizing the two

corresponding structures is by saying they are thematic paraphrases. This

is a clue to their underlying structure. Namely, Baker,formulates a principle

which will ensure that, thematic paraphrases have the same D-structure,

but, for reasons to be explained, surface differently.

(10) The Uniformity of Theta Assignment Hvpothesis:(UTAH)

Identical thematic relationships between items are

represented by identical structural relationships between

those items at the level of D-structure (30) p.46

The UTAH implies that the passive counterpart of ( 13)a. has the same

D-structure as (13)a... the active form: the thematic relationship between

attacl'ecf and prdi is identical in both, so it must be represented in an

identical structural relationship. For the Chichewa examples, the UTAH

applies to part, of & word. Quoting Baker (p.49) : "Generally, whenever part

of a word shows signs of assigning or receiving a thematic role in the same

way that morphologically independent constituents do, the UTAH will imply

that that part of the word appears in an independent position at D-

structure"

The relevant structures are :

Page 90: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

(lcj)Passive: S 10

A NP VP

A V NP

sttsct prâi

The theta-role PATIENT is assigned canonically. The passive account

in GB is that the NP-obi must move to subiect Dosition in order to get case J J A KJ

since the participle has been devoided of the ability to assign case by the

morphological process deriving the participle - cf, also alternative analyses

such as Jaeggli ( 19ô6) where the participle affix absorbs theta-role -. Baker

explains passive differently: he accounts for it in terms of the incorporation

of the V into I , thus in this sense, claiming that it is a syntactic process,

and not only a morphological one. He accounts for the status of the implicit

argument by claiming that I is an argument and must be assigned a theta-

role . In this way , passive in English is regarded as an instance of

incorporation, although a different sort of incorporation - as it involves a

head movement into a non-lexical head, I - cf. Note (32) on Baker's account

of passive.

Page 91: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

(20) Causative:

NP VP 0TJ / \ ^

V

NP VP

pût

V

fall

As (15b) shows, fall is not in its D-structure position at S-structure,

movement takes place and gw - fall- morphologically combines with its -

mate -. Incorporation, thus, implies movement; it is an instance of move-

alpha. Movement, though, is not triggered by the usual case or by +wh

COMP features. Here, the trigger of movement is the morphological

subcategorization of the elements that appear separated in D-structure:

they are affixes and must be bound - cf. the Affix Filter in 3.1 -. Baker

follows Lieber (I960) and Williams (1961) in saying that affixes are

specified for all the same types of features as independent words, and he

goes a step further in assuming that elements which surface as affixes may

head phrases and assign theta roles just like independent words do, at D-

structure. The difference between words and affixes is, then, "that affixes

must attach to a word - clearly a morphological requirement. If an item is

specified as being an affix, but is generated in an independent position at

D-structure in accordance with the UTAH, that item will have to undergo

/N

Page 92: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

270

X-0 movement to adjoin to some other X-0, failure to do so will result in a

structure which results in the violation of a principle of morphology." (p.72)

3.2.2 The process: V-Incorporation (VI)

As the passage quoted above states, affixes - X-0 categories at D-

structure - must move to adjoin to another X-0 . Move-alpha, thus will not

imply the movement of an XP but rather of a head of a phrase in

incorporation structures.

This type of movement is not new: Chomsky (19ô6b) - cf. section

1.2.2 - , Koopman (19Ô4), Torrego (1954), Pollock (I960) among many

others have assumed that V is subject to move-alpha under certain

circumstances. As mentioned, Baker applies X-0 movement to V, N and P in

order to account for GF changing phenomena of different types.

Reviewing certain conclusions reached in outlining the barriers

framework - section 1.2.2 -, there are several important facts about X-0

movement. Firstly, a head may only move to another head position and

adjoin to it; it may not move to an XP position, a configuration which would

presumably violate some version of the Structure Preserving Hypothesis

(Emonds 1976) -. By the Projection Principle, an X-0 category must leave a

trace; if lexical properties of items are to be kept throughout the derivation,

an element which assigns a theta-role to a certain position at D-structure

must leave a trace, just like an element which has received a theta-role in a

certain position at D-structure. The structural relationship between the two

positions created by movement must be that of government, a consequence

of the fact that all traces are subject to the ECP - the syntactic aspect of

incorporation -. Since X-0 categories cannot be lexically governed - by

virtue of the fact that theta-marking takes place only between sisters - cf.

Page 93: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

271

section 1.2.2 where theta-marking is shown not to percolate to the head of

a theta-marked Xmax - antecedent government must be satisfied.

It must be noted that Baker somewhat modifies the notion oí

barrierhood in that instead of BC and L-marking, he introduces the notion

of s#JectJoj2 as follows: (p.56-57)

(21) A selects B if and only if:

(i) Á assigns a theta role to B

(ii) A is of a category C and B is its IP

(iii)A is of a category I and B is its VP

(50)

He also accounts for minimality barriers (22) (ii) :

(22) Let D be the smallest maximal projection containing A.

Then C is a BARRIER between A and B if and only if C is a

maximal projection that contains B and excludes A, and

either:

(i) C is not selected, or

(ii) the head of C is distinct from the head of D and

selects some WP equal to or containing B. 1 1

(49)

These modifications together with Baker's indexing system have

the same results - as far as V-incorporation in the cases considered

are concerned -than the assumptions in Chomsky (1906b) : an X-0

trace must be antecedent governed. To summarize Baker's indexing

system, there are three types of indices: identification indexing (the

Page 94: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

result of movement); theta-indexing ( the result of theta-assignment);

and Case-indexing ( the result of Case-assignment).

Baker states the ECP in terms of a requirement of either theta-

indexing or identification indexing. Theta-indexing is never available

to traces left by incorporation because theta-marking can only take

place between sister nodes, as already noted. Hence, by assumption,

the theta-index that the XP dominating the trace of the incorporated

item bears never percolates down to it. Thus, the only possible way

for an X-0 trace to be properly governed is for its antecedent to

govern it. Baker states the ECP as follows for X-0 traces:

(23) An X-0 must govern its trace

Government requires two things: that c-command hold between

the antecedent and the trace, and that there be no barriers between

the two elements. Both are satisfied in proper incorporation structures,

as will be exemplified below.

With the joining of two X-0 level categories , incorporation

creates a syntactic node which does not comform to the X'-schema in

the sense that it is not an X' category - it has no complement position-,

and it is not a proper X-0 category - it contains two different heads.

The special status of this category is expressed by the following

statement as regards its interpretation:

(24) The indices of the parts of an X-0 category count as

the indices of the X-0 category itself

In the structure:

Page 95: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

273

(25) YP

Y* XP

Xi Y ti ZP

Y* c-commands the trace and is a proper governor ior i t because

it bears tüe same identification index, by vir tue of the fact tha t i t

contains the antecedent of the trace.

The definition of barrier is somewhat modified by Baker , as

stated above. In other terms, for Chomsky, the categories tha t can be

barriers between two elements, A and B, are relative to the B element

- cf 1.2.2 -. Baker makes the notion of barrier relative to both, the

governor and the governee:

(26) The maximal projection C is a government barrier between

A and B if and only if C contains B, C does not contain A,

and C is not theta-indexed ( with A ) 1 2

In (25), repeated here with the corresponding theta-indices:

(27) YP

Xi Yj ti ZP

Page 96: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

274

XP is the only potential barrier between X and t; it does not

contain Y* (=A) and it contains t ( = B), but it is not a barrier because it

is theta-indexed with A (=Y*) - Y assigns a theta-role to XP, and thus

shares the same theta-index with it - and by (24) Y* also shares that

same index.

Another condition that must be satisfied by all instances of

movement is Subjacency. Subjacency with regard to incorporation will

always be redundant since the crossing of just one barrier will block

government, resulting in an ECP violation, and, thus, the trace will not

be licensed. If the X-0 moves to a Y-0 that is not theta-indexed with

the XP headed by the X, the XP will be a barrier to government since it

will not satisfy the theta-requirement.

Another propsal by Baker is the Government Transparency

Corollary (GTC):

(2ô) A lexical category which has an item incorporated to it

governs everything which the incorporated item governed

in its original position

This follows from the indexing relations mentioned above , as

illustrated in the following struture:

(29) YP

Xi Yj ti ZPi

Page 97: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

The notion oí transparency implies basically that neither the XP

nor the ZP are barriers to government when the head of the XP is

incorporated. This will have a series of consequences in Grammatical

Changing processes in most of the languages that Baker studies: a

complex verb will govern more elements once it has been incorporated

and, thus, more agreement possibilities arise giving rise to apparently

GF changing process. The GTC has no consequences for the kind of

complex verbs for which I will propose incoporation - cf. 3-3-1 -.

The ECP, thus, is satisfied in a head-to-head movement

structure such as (3D) - the Chichewa causative, to be considered again

below - if the movement of the lower verb follows the Ifeaä

Movement Constraint (3D - cf. also section 1.2.2 -:

V V

fallj mate

Page 98: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

276

(3D HEAD MOVEMENT CONSTRAINT(HMC)

An X-0 may only move into the Y-0 which properly governs

it. (43)

As shown by Baker, the HMC is derived from the ECP since it

implies that traces of x-0 must be properly governed. This is the case

in incorporation structures.

Biclausal structures

There are two possible situations where movement of a head

may take place:

1. if the head is governed by another head in its D-structure

position it may incorporate into the other head following the HMC

straightforwardly

2.if the head is not in a governed position, it must move prior to

incorporation in order to reach a position from which it is governed by

the X-0 category into which it incorporates. This is the case of biclausal

structures, as we will see below.

Consider first Baker's account of the following incorporation

structures:

(32 )a. [yp Xi + Y [ xpti ZP]] (where XP is selected by Y)

b* [ YP Xi + Y [ XP ti ZP ]] (where XP is not selected by Y)

c.*lYPZi + Y[xpX Izpti]]] (40)

(32)b.and c. are both ruled out by Baker's notion of barrierhood:

b. implies an ECP violation because the XP is not selected, and c.

Page 99: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

implies a violation because there is a head, distinct from Y which

selects ZP containing the trace of Z; in other words, SP is a minimality

barrier in c. In a structure such as this, incorporation would only be

allowed if Z would have moved to a position from which Y could

govern it prior to incorporating - X -. Direct movement is not allowed:

it violates the HMC, or, alternatively, the t violates the ECP.

(32a.) is an instance of situation 1.; it is either a simple clausal

structure like (30) above, where S is selected by V, and there are no

other maximal projections intervening, or the movement of the head

of any selected complement - for instance N incorporation to V -.

Now consider the structure assumed for a complex configuration,

in the case of the Chichewa causative:

Page 100: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

(33) IP

NP

gití

Y

VP

V CP

mak& \

C"

IP

NP I

wsterpot.

I VP

V

fan

Direct verb incorporation - henceforth VI- is not possible: there

are two head positions which could create minimality barriers -

namely C and I- and cause an ECP violation. It is relevant to point out

the notion of distinctness that Baker defines - cf. also (22)(ii) - in

order to fit his barrierhood notion with the incorporation structures :

(34) X is distinct from Y only if no part of Y is a member of a

(movement) chain containing X (64)

Page 101: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

279

This notion is relevant because if the head in question contains a

trace of the incorporated element, then the maximal projection

dominating it will no longer be a minimality barrier; its head will not

be distinct from the potential governor (as long as the governor

contains the antecedent): An instance of this :

05? Vt

y* sp

Xi Y X ZP ! I ti Z

In this structure, XP cannot count as a barrier between Y* (a

potential governor) and ZP because XP contains the trace of X; it is not

distinct from Y*.

Considering structure (33) above, the lower verb must.

incorporate into the higher verb, due to its morphological

requirements. There are two ways for the lower verb to be able to

move into the higher verb:

a. from the Spec-CP position (if the whole VP moves)

b. from the C position (if only V moves)

Baker claims that both possibilities are attested, and give rise to

different causative structures. Baker analyzes complex predicate

structures in Romance as instances of a special kind of

incorporporation - abstract mccrpcratJojx which I will summarize in

section 3.3.2 - as instances of the a. possibility. I will, thus, leave the

Page 102: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

b. possibility unsummarized as it is assumed for languages which are

not the subject of this thesis. Nevertheless, direct V-to-V movement

will be claimed for complex verb sequences -cf. section 3.3.1 -.

Note that in structures where a CP node is assumed to intervene

between two verbs to be incorporated, VI involves the incorporation

of a head within a (selected) complement. The embedded internal

movement of the V to reach a position from which to incorporate is

not directly related to the status of the CP, but the next step, proper

VI, is directly related because CP must be selected in order not to

count as a barrier between V* and the trace of the incorporated V.

Page 103: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

3-3 Incorporation and verbal sequences

3-3-0 Introduction

Section 3.3.1 represents an attempt to apply the mechanism of

incorporation to complex verb sequences in Catalan and Spanish. A

fundamental difference regarding the languages that Baker studies in more

depth and the two Romance languages for which I will propose

incorporation is the issue of the trigger of incorporation. As mentioned,

languages like Chichewa- in the constructions where incorporation is

assumed to take place- the incorporated items constitute a single word, a

morphologically complex item that surfaces as a unit. The Affix Principle

(AP) requires that affixes which are generated in independent D-structure

positions move to positions where they may attach to an affix-bearing

element - there may be cases in which they may attract a host to move to

their position -. This morphological justification for movement is obviously

absent in both Catalan and Spanish. The verbal sequences do not form one

word; they surface as two separate morphological units - crucially, that the

first item bear independent inflectional morphology is evidence for this.

The reasons that bring one to postulate incorporation for complex verbs in

Catalan and Spanish when there is no direct morphological evidence stem

basically from the fact that they function as a single lexical unit. Apart from

the tests which will be alluded to in ¿ection 3.3.1.1, an important piece of

evidence is the fact that the first member of the complex verb - &a/ra -

does not define a stress domain, and it has a clitic status - but see also

3-3-1-1- The complex verbs introduced in section 2.2.2 are , thus, analyzed

in 3.3.1 as instances of head movement in the syntax. I must emphasize

that although cliticization is posited as subsequent to head-movement, the

Page 104: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

262

fact that cliticizatíon represents the interface not only between morphology

and syntax but also phonology overreaches by far the scope of this thesis,

so no detailed analysis may be provided here.

Section 3.3.2 presents the type of incorporation that Baker postulates

for Romance complex predicates , abstract mcorporatJon ( or r$anajysjs).

The basic idea is that in the sequences for which this type of incorporation

is assumed the two verbal elements are semantically linked, they constitute

a complex predicate - cf. section 2.3 - but not a complex word; according to

Baker, their "amalgamation" must be at a different level: " Fare is not an

incorporator, but a "reanalyzer" ( an LF affix?) and must enter into the

Reanalysis relationship with another verb at LF. This may be a semantic

property of the verb, to the effect that it forms "complex semantic

predicates", since it is generally the same kinds of verbs which have such

properties from language to language" (p. 203). I will refer only to the

essentials of Baker's abstract mcorporatJon proposal, and propose some

arguments against it in section 3-4 , suggesting that G&HÎ19ÔÔ)' s proposai

gives the theory sufficient scope to account for complex predicate

behaviour without having to postulate LF-movement.

Note that there is another way of characterising the verbal sequences

in question - sections 3.3.1 and 3.3.2; namely, as verbal clusters or verbal

chains - cf. Bordelois & Evers (1990) - . This would lead to say that those

sequences in 3.3.1 - complex verbs - are verbal clusters, although the fact

that they are analyzed as head-movement implies that they are also part of

a chain, which includes empty Xo categories subject to the ECP; and that

those sequences in 3.3.2 - complex predicates - imply non-movement

chains - in line with G&H (19ôÔ)'s proposal; cf. 2.4 and 3.4 -. *3

Page 105: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

3.3-1 Incorporation and complex verbs

3 3 1-1 Complex verbs as x£ units

Reconsider some or the tests presented in section 2.1 as tests for

auxiliaries versus main verbs:

Catalan;

1.- Interruption by lexical items (adverbs and parentheticals)

(Test 10)

(36)a. He vlst la Teresa al bar fa una estona

b* He, fa una estona. vlstla Teresa al bar

c* He casualment vist Ja Teresa al bar

(37)a. Be veritat hem cregut que t'agradarla

b* Hem, de veritat, cregut que tagradarla

c* Hem sincerament cregut que t'agradaria

(3ô)a. Va veure la Teresa al bar

b * Va.ahir al vespre, veure la Teresa al bar

c* Va casualment veure la Teresa al bar *

(39)a. Vam saber que tenia molts diners

b. * Vam sempre saber que tenia molts diners

2. Placement of the negative particle (or Tensed negative VP)

( Test 3 )

Page 106: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

(40)a. La Maria no va venir

b. *LaMaria va no venir

(4 l)a. En Terendnona entrevistat en Lfiu's

b. * £0 Terendli3j20£nïz£EM2Len Liais

\ VQ movement ( or Tensed verb preceding subject):

( Test 4 )

(42) a. Ha trucat en Joan?

b. * Ha en Joan trucat?

(43) a. Va veure el partit el Llius?

b. * Ya en Lluís veure el partit?

4. Preposing and postposing

( Test 11)

(44)(FromH&R 19Ô4)

a. Va parlar de le seves velles amistatsparisenques durant l'estiu

b. * Va durant l'estiu parlar de les seves velles amistats

parisenques

(45)a. Ban dit que farien els deures i els nan fet

b * Han dit que farien els deures i fet elsnan

(46)a. Creia que veuria l'eclipsi i el va veure

b. * Creia que veuria l'eclipsi i veure'l va

The examples above show a basic characteristic of Catalan verbal

sequences : the sequences made up of "haver"+ participle and "va"+

infinitive - i.e the sequences which I have called complex verbs - may not

Page 107: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

be interrupted by other constituents nor may be subject to move-alpha.

The verbal sequences labelled complex verbs form an indivisible unit.

Spanish:

The following examples seem to indicate that Spanish has the same

restrictions as Catalan as regards the interruption and breaking up of

verbal sequences which constitute complex verbs.14

1. Interruption bv lexical items ( adverbs and parentheticals ):

(Test 10)

(47)a. He visto a Teresa en eJharnace un rato/casualmente

b. * J&_. ¿tace un raie, visto a Teresa ex eJ A?/-

casualmente

(4ô)a. De verdad /sinceramente nemes creido que te gustaría

b. * Hernes, de verdad, creído que te gustar/a

sinceramente

2. Placement of the negative particle ( or Tensed negative VP)

(Test 3)

(49) a. luis ne A? JJamado

b. * Luis nano JJamado

\ V movement ( or Tensed verb preceding subject):

( Test 4 )

(50)a. Ha JJamado ¿uis ?

Page 108: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

b. *Ha Litis llamado ?

(50a. Habrán llegado los invitados ?

b. * fíabrÉR los invitados llegado ?

4. Proposing and postposing:

(Test 11)

(52) a. Lilis dijo quo vendría y ha venido

b. * Luis dijo quo vendría y venido ha

(53)a. Los alumnos dijeron que estudiarían vhan estudiado

b. *Los alumnos dijeron que estudiarían y estudiado han

Now, if we consider these non-evident single constituents - (36)-

(53X- and assume they are X-0 constituents- pending a syntactic derivation

in section 3.3.1.3 -, it seems that the HOC - as defined in section 3-1 - may

be made responsible for their behaviour: the V movement - i.e Vo

movement and preposing/postposing - examples show that apart of the

sequence cannot be moved, under any circumstances -i.e. that there can be

no V trace of part of the sequence -. Nevertheless, apart from this fact, we

could also appeal to the HOC to account for the impossibility of interruption

of the sequence. One could modify the HOC by making it general enough as

to ban any type of separation of a category once it becomes a proper l9

category, and one could attempt a defintion of "proper" YS> category by

implying morphophonological amalgamation. - in the case of incorporated

sequences complex verb sequences which have undergone head-movement

and subsequent cliticization - see below " A note on cliticization" -

.Generalizing the notion of "opaqueness" to include other ways in which a

Page 109: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

head becomes "frozen/opaque"(Ouhalla (1908,16), the HOC may be

reformulated in the following terms:

(54) Xo categories are opaque

If a set of elements is dominated by an Xo node these elements are

not accessible to movement, plus they may not be interrupted by other

constituents.

A note on cliticization

As mentioned, the facts presented so far obviously lead one to the

issue of ctfttasatfaa Clitic climbing was already alluded to as a test to show

the cohesiveness of complex verbs and complex predicates - cf. 2.1, and 2.3

-, but an important distinction between "clitic climbing" -as in Kayne( 1975),

Burzio(19ô6) among so many others - and "cliticization" m complex verb

sequences must be made as well as some qualifications added to this issue.

It is well-known that clitics are a not easily defined set of elements.

The criteria that work for clitics in one language may fail to work for those

elements considered clitics in a different language - cf. especially Spencer

(forthcoming) for definitions and comparison of clitic systems -. Two

definitions will do to see that capturing the notion of cMtJc is not a simple

matter:

"It is largely agreed that genuine clitics are words which happen to be phonologically dependent on a host. Thus, they are elements which have the syntactic properties of words, but the phonological properties of affixes." (p.7ô) and from the same source: ".. we will see yet more evidence of schizophrenia on the part

Page 110: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

2ÔÔ

of clitics, behaving now as fully-fledged words, now as ¡hound morpnemeS (p. 16)

(Spencer (forthcoming))

"Solem designar amb el terme "clitic" aquests elements morfològics que ocupen l'espai entre el mot i el morfema. En aquest espai aquelles propietats que diferencien el mot del morfema ( caràcter lliure, certa llibertat d'ordre, fenòmens fonologies típics, inexistència d'al·lomorfia ) esbarregen..."

(Mascaró (19Ô5)p-12 3)

(italics mine)

From these definitions one may expect to find difficulties in trying to

account for the behaviour of sequences of elements that contain a clitic, as

is the case with complex verbs. As is pointed out in both definitions, clitics

have some properties of words, and some of affixes. Clitics are not like

words, for instance, in the fact that they do not ususally bear stress, and

their clustering is not hierarchical like that of syntactic constituents. "... we

are actually dealing with an unusual form of free-floating affixation , and

that as far as the syntax is concerned clitics aren't words at all " ( Spencer

(forthcoming) p. 14). But clitics are not affixes either: they may attach to

different types of elements in many languages - for instance, Serbo-Croat -,

and they may move to different positions, a rather word-like property.

In his comparison of different clitic systems - Serbo-Croat,

Macedonian, and Portuguese - Spencer clearly shows that even

characteristics which seem general enough of clitics are not universal. As he

points out, following Klavans (19ô2)'s observation, the fact that clitics do

not bear stress is not a universal characteristic of clitics. Another important

apparently general characteristic of clitics - that of being tightly knit with

their host- is also not universal. These two observations - plus others - will

allow us to explain some otherwise problematic examples in Catalan and

Page 111: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

Spanish; i.e. sequences where other clitics interrupt the sequence of a

complex verb, or sequences where the first element in a complex verb

sequence bears stress.

The formation of the future tense in many Romance languages, is a

consequence of a content word becoming an affix. Catalan and Spanish are

examples of this - see section 3.3.1.3 -. Portuguese seems to have followed

the same development with the only difference that the future suffixes

may be separated from their host verb by a pronominal clitic as in the

following examples from Spencer: ter&fJeyadoi = I shall have raised ) / / Ä?

- Jo - OJ levado (= I shall have raised it ). This is in clear constrast with

Catalan and Spanish where the future suffixes are not separated from their

host not even in the compound tenses. ! 5

Classifications of clitics include not only pronominal clitics but also

auxiliary forms, determiners, conjunctions, and prepositions. As the subject

of this thesis are verbal sequences, I will only refer to the clitic status of

auxiliaries in complex tenses - except for the observations in Chapter 2 on

Clitic Placement/Climbing as a test for cohesion between two verbs -.

Nevertheless, a crucial difference with pronominal clitics and auxiliary

clitics must be noted: due to the argument status of the former, there has

been intense debate *& claiming either movement from a base-generated

original position or base-generation on their host, a debate which has not

taken place for auxiliary clitics.

To conclude this note on clitics - to be further discussed as applied to

complex tenses in Catalan and Spanish in 33-13- - I will point out an

observation by Mascaró (1966) which, I believe may be traslated into

incorporation - plus subsequent cliticization - . I am referring to the

comparison that he makes between compounds and "larger words" - "small

words" plus clitics -: he distinguishes between the lexical character of the

Page 112: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

former-compounds- and the syntactic character of the latter-larger

words"-, paving the way for a syntactic characterization of larger words",

as is the case with complex tenses.

3.3.1.2 The structure of complex verbs

In this section I will put forward the structure that has been

independently posited in many works - cf. especially Zagona (19ôô), among

others - and which will provide the possibility of postulating direct

incorporation of V to V in complex verb sequences. - 3.3.1.3 - 1 7

This section is in a sense the attempt to show that even if the UTAH -

cf. section 3.2 - of Baker is not involved in the structure of complex verbs,

there are still reasons to believe that the two Vs are not generated as a unit

but become a unit in the syntax; each is granted an independent head

position. We will assume for the time being - and reconsider the issue in

Chapter 4 -, that each V heads a VP.

In section 2.2.2 I briefly reviewed a few proposals, some of which

were within earlier frameworks - ASWÜ979), Emonds (1976) -.

Nevertheless, each still granted each "auxiliary" a separate V node - not yet

a "head" in terms of X'-theory. The structures are reapeated here:

Emonds (1976)

V V

lavés

V V A

Page 113: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

ASWC1979)

(5«

(have)

V

Zagona(19ÔÔ) represents one of the reformulations of these proposals

in X"-theory terms : each auxiliary heads a VP with full phrasal structure; it

has all possible projections - as explained in section 2.2.2 -. The structure is

repeated here:

(57) V

spec V (XP)

where XP is a possible position for a modifying adverb, and V" the

complement, of an auxiliary.

Her theory, moreover, puts forward the licensing of Vs

subcategorizing for VP, vritb her specific temporal-role marking proposal.

Furthermore, the parameter she proposes to distinguish English and

Spanish does not rely on a different VP phrasal structure for auxiliaries ,

but rather on different possibilities for temporal assignment.

The notion of complex predicate in Manzini (19Ô7) also involves

more than one VP: a "verb-to-verb" selection allows for the properties of

Page 114: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

the non-auxiliary head to be "dominant" as far as the selection of the

subject is concerned.

ManzinidÇjô?)1^

(SÄ) VP

/ \ NP VP

/ \ ï v :

V VP

I V

V VP

In G&H (I960)- cf. section 2.4 - it was shown that auxiliaries T-mark

VPs, so subsequent VPs are also permitted and LF licensed by the FDC. An

example (£35);49) of a complex verb in their paper is repeated here - cf.

also 3.4. -:

(59) John íj'Iívp hasfvp laughed///

Another basic source which validates consecutive VPs ; i.e. the

subcategorization of VP by V is Chomsky ( 1956b) 1% where such a proposal

is not argued for or explicitly claimed. Nevertheless, a consecutive VP

structure is given for passive - cf. also 1.2.2 - . The structure of passive

Page 115: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

after V-raising is the following, where @=i=j by Spec-head agreement:

((171;p.76)

(to) Jiaaoj fate -JHyp- tj fyp killed tjI

331-3 Syntactic incorporation

As made explicit in the previous section , the structure assumed for

complex verbs in Catalan and Spanish is:

(61) VP

V

/ \

Vl VP

\ V2 . . .

partidple/infiniiive

In such a configuration, the relevant structural relationships hold of

the two V-elements in question so that move-X0 may take place: V2 moves

to adjoin to Vi and such a process results in the creation of a new V-

category, V*.

Page 116: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

(62) VP

A Vi* VP

A I Vi V2 V2

«once matme v? position is aireaay governea by vi prior io movement.

The HMC is satisfied, and consequently the trace of V2 does not violate the

ECP. As explained in 3-2, the V* counts as an antecedent governor for the

V2 trace; they share indices20 and, thus, antecedent government holds.

Note that V i to V2 incorporation is ruled out:

Vi V2

This is a case of downward movement, where the trace c-commands

its antecedent, and, the ECP is violated, government of the trace by V* is

not possible here as there is an intervening maximal projection which,

although selected, blocks c-command.

Page 117: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

in structure (ôz), once the v-2 nas moved up to v-l, there is nothing

• to prevent a cliticization of the first verbal element onto the second. This

gives the expected results, i.e. the impossibility of separating them, which

parallels with the behaviour of all other clitics in both Spanish and Catalan:

(64)a. sempre Ja veJg

b. Ja veig sempre

c. * Ja sempre veig

{h^)z..sJempre Ja veo

b. Ja ¥$o siempre

c. * Ja siempre veo

Therefore, once incorporation has taken place, cliticization follows,

although, a qualification must be added at this point, which will be taken

up again in the next section. The fact that clitics tend to be monosyllabic

and not bear stress - although, as pointed out in section 3.3.1.1. in "A note

on cliticization", this is not a universal - implies that cliticization will be

ensured when the first verb in the sequence is monosyllabic, but non-

cliticization may give a certain degree of non-cohesiveness in non-

monosyllabic forms - cf. Suñer (19ÔÔ), section 3-3-1-4 -.

If we assume that the process of incorporation followed by

cliticization leads to a "frozen/opaque" constituent for the HOC - cf.3.1 -,

the existence of an element which interrupts the complex verb sequence in

Catalan - jaas - may be due to its own status as a clitic - in these

constructions21 - preceding cliticization of the first verbal element:

(66) Noüepas vist Ja nena

Page 118: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

Note that, as was already observed, it may be expected of a unit that

becomes an Xo constituent in the syntax to be less tightly knit than a

lexical unit created in the lexicon. Although, as implied by Morphology

Theory they are both subject to the same constraints. Moreover, as pointed

out in "A note on cliticization" in section 3.3.1.1, there are even cases - as

in Portuguese future tense - where a pronominal clitic may intervene

between an affix - which has historically developed into one from a

previous content word - and its host verb. Phenomena such as these may

be expected in an area as murky as is cliticization. 2 2

As has been noted in section 3.3.O, the trigger for postulating

incorporation in languages like Chichewa is the Affix Principle. The V, N, or

P elements that undergo incorporation in these languages are generated in

a different D-structure position by virtue of the UTAH - cf. 3-2 -, but they

are affixes. As such they need a host, and to find one, they must move. In

complex verb sequences for which I am proposing incorporation there is no

such morphological justification to allude to; there is no morphological

trigger. The assumption that I will be making here is that verbs that

subcategorize for VPs trigger incorporation of the participle - or infinitive,

in the case of the pt?+infinitive sequence in Catalan - ; i.e. they attract the

main verb onto them. Incorporation in such cases is obligatory - with

possible subsequent cliticization -. 23

Why aren't the two V-elements phonologically amalgamated? The

answer to this question is beyond the scope of this thesis, but one could

attempt an approximative answer by alluding to a language-specific

morphological characteristic of Catalan and Spanish - and all Romance

languages, and also English- : the lack of inflectional prefixes . This might be

the reason why , although HAVER/HABER has lost its lexical (= "possess" )

Page 119: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

meaning in modern Catalan and Spanish, they have still retained a lexical -

V - and non-affixal status.

There is a phenomenon in the history of both Spanish and Catalan

that may shed some light on the behaviour oí complex verbs: the formation

of the Future tense - cf. also section 3.3-1.1. for Portuguese - . The present

day Future tense(b) is the fusion of two forms; an infinitival form and a

form of "haver/haber"(a) :

(67)(a) amar + he = (b) amaré

amar + has amarás

fer + he = (b)faré

fer + has faràs

We could explain the development of these forms by positing a

process of incorporation. The difference with the complex verb sequences is

that one could allude to a possible formation of the future forms by a left

incorporation of V i to V2 , as in (60):

(66) VPi

/ \ Vi VP2

/ \ \ V2 V i V

f&r i¡e J

V2

t

As is usually assumed, adjunction is allowed both to the right and to

the left, but the morphophonological result is different; in the future case,

v

Page 120: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

29Ô

the fact that inflectional suffixes do exist in the language may have paved

the way for the amalgamation. It must be stressed that this process may be

the explanation of a diachronic phenomenon; it is obvious that present-day

future inflection is an affix and not an independent lexical head - as I am

assuming for V1 in complex verb sequences -.

There is another problem that arises if we assume that the complex

verb sequence becomes an I o unit in the syntax: the fact that the first

element bears tense and agreement; i.e. why are the (b) examples not the

result of the union of the two verbal elements?:

(69)a. Has fet

b. *ha fûts

(70)a. has techo

ï>.*MJ3$CÙOS

Here, again we allude to the fact that morphologically created units

and syntactically created units are not completely alike, although they are

both subject to the HOC. There seems to be only one way to account for this

fact: assuming that the syntactic process is a "special" kind of adjunction;

proper adjunction would lead to the T and AGR morphemes to be borne by

V2 -as would be expected of the structure (30) -. but since the participle

has already undergone morphological processes - as postulated in several

recent studies; cf. Belletti(1990), Drijkoningen (19Ô9X among others.- no

more affixes can attach to it. Note that there is an independent ban on

gerunds and participles to bear any person or number affixes. The

following structure includes inflectional nodes and expresses the

subsequent adjunctions that have applied: V2-to-V 1 -to-T-to-AGR24 :

Page 121: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

299

(71) AGRP

V V

V

t

A comparative fact to point out in favour of the clitic status of the

auxiliaries in question, despite their bearing independent inflections is that

Serbo-Croat auxiliary clitics have this same property, they inflect for tense

and for person. - cf. Spencer (forthcoming) -.

3.3.1.4 Remarks on language variation

In this section some observations are made regarding the different

behaviour of equivalent complex verb structures basically in Catalan and

Spanish, but also Italian and a note on English and French is made.

Page 122: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

Spanish

There are certain differences between Catalan and Spanish that call

for an explanation. Suñer (I960) reports a contrast found in Spanish which

does not seem to arise in Catalan. Namely, the contrast between one-

syllable forms of the verb "haber", and longer forms.

Suñer gives the following examples to argue against the "inseparable

unit" hypothesis:

(72 ) Lo hubiera usted oído en Ja mesa (4)a.

(73) ¿ Como se espJJca çue desde entonces ses no naya usted dado

paso aJgiwo? (4)b.

(74) ¿ Como hubieras tu quedado? (4)c.

(75) .... ycuando yo hubiera ya sido mayor... (4)d.

(76) J>;' despues i?ue había mucho corrido, ¿no? (4)e.

(77) Habían eJJospagado ya anticipadamente (5)a.

(76) Platero me habia ya saludado con un rebuzno (5)b.

(79) ße ahí que hubiese, durante meses, visitado Ja casa sin toparse

con Marià (5)c.

(00) ¿çue habrá ef gobernador aprobado Ja semana pasada? (6)a.

(Ô1 ) cí4 quien hubiera el vecino agradecido Ja atención si... ?(b)b.

(Ô 2 ) Se había casi convertido a Ja reJigion de su novia cuando... (6)c.

(03) £sto habría indudabJemente aceJerado eJproceso (6)d. «

The above - also from Sufîer(19Ô7);6ô3 - contrast with:

(04) * ¿Jía Pepe terminado eJJJbro? (Strozer 1976)

(05)* ¿çuéha Juan Jeído? (Zagona 19Ô2 )

Page 123: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

(Ô6) * ¿Çuéha Ja gente organizado? (Torrego 19Ô4)

The examples cited show that there are instances of the verbal

complex "haber + participle** which allow interruption. It must be noted that

the dialects that Suñer considers do not coincide with the dialect of many

Spanish speaking native speakers of the Iberian Peninsula. For many

speakers, examples (72)-(ô3) are not ungrammatical but are not wholly

acceptable either.

Suñer explains the difference by alluding to a cliticization of the

monosyllabic form of the verb "haber*" which needs a host and cannot stand

on its own. Evidence for this comes from the fact that the only monosyllabic

form of the existential "haber" (there-be) ha does not exist as such; its only

form consists of ha+a locative clitic "y" which has not survived in modern

Spanish:

(07) Hay muchagente en este Jugar

(Ôô) Bab/a mucha gente en ese Jugar

(07) and (ÔÔ) illustrate the difference: only the monosyllabic ha

needs the clitic "y", the past form ha&fa does not. Suner, thus explains the

contrast by saying that when one of the monosyllabic forms of the verb

"haber" occurs - lsg he, 2sg has; 3sg ha, 3pl han -, it always cliticizes to the

form that follows it.

Note that - irrespective of the validity of Suñer's analysis - the fact

that monosyllabic forms need a host points towards the possibility of

incorporation applying in this sequence - as the mechanism to license

cliticization -. But, note that, universally, clitics are not always

monosyllabic; as for instance the bisyllabic prepositions of Catalan and

Spanish - cf. also Spencer (forthcoming), Klavans (19Ô2) -.

Page 124: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

Catalan

Consider the Catalan translations to some of the above sentences:

(72') * Si l'haguës vostè sentit a la taula

(74') * Com hauries tu quedat?

(76') * Jöf després çue havies molt corregut.

(77") *Havien ells pagat, ja anticipadament

(79") * I> aquí que hagués, durant mesos, visitat la casa sense topar-se

amb la Maria

(02 ') * S'havia quasi convertit a la religio de la seva promesa quan....

(03') *? Aisâ hauria indubtablement accelerat elprocés

Most of the above examples are ungrammatical. Considering Suñer's

arguments for positing a cliticization rule, it is relevant to allude to the fact

that Catalan existential "haver" does not parallel to Spanish existential

"haber": in Catalan, all the forms of the verb require the locative clitic "hi",

which has survived in modern Catalan.

(09) Hi vaig

(90) Hi ha molta gent

(91 ) Hi havia molta gent

Clearly, then, if we follow Suñer's argument - i.e. the reference to the

(no longer) clitic "y" as evidence for the necessary cliticization of the form

ha in sequences of A?+ past participle -, all the forms of the verb haver in

Catalan must cliticize; in the hi + haver sequences, it is hi which cliticizes

onto the lexical head, haver; in the haver* past participle sequences, it is

Page 125: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

the haysr form which cliticizes onto the participle - independently of the

number of syllables it has .

As has been pointed out in 3.3.1.3, an explanation to the fact that

interruption is not allowed in Catalan under any circumstance, but

marginally accepted in Spanish, may be that although incorporation occurs

in all forms of complex verbs both in Spanish and in Catalan, subsequent

cliticization may fail to apply, allowing for a certain degree of non-

cohesiveness. Nonetheless, even in sequences where cliticization may be

argued to have failed to apply, the acceptability of the sentence is not

complete - cf. (72)-(ô3) • Incorporation, thus, accounts for the marginality

for most speakers of Spanish in the Iberian Peninsula of Suner's examples.

Italian

Belletti (1990) considers the possibility of the following word order

possibilities in Italian of Neg particle-Aux-PParticiple-Weg adverb in Italian

- the examples in (93) clearly contrast with Catalan and Spanish -:

(92 )a. Gianni sos napariatopJù

b. Maria sosêuscitamai

c. (Qu&llavoro )Nos J'no finito ancora ( 1 )

(93) a. Gianni sos na pió pariato

b. MarianosêmaJusata

c. iVu$iJavoro)NosJnoascora finito (2) *

Belletti makes use of a more complex structure where the past

participle and the auxiliary are both dominated by independent non-lexical

(functional) nodes25. There is also a NegP which includes a Spec position,

the position where the negative adverbs are generated. The movement of

Page 126: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

both , the negative particle and the tensed verb to the highest inflectional

node -AGR - would derive the (93) order:

(94) AGRP

AGR NegP

pm Neg"

A Neg TP

\

non

AuxP

Aux

ttò) V

V (10)

Belletti considers but invalidates the derivation of the order in (92)

by a process of incorporation -as the one postulated in section 3-3-1-3 for

Catalan- of the past participle to the auxiliary, and subsequent movement

of both to the highest AGR node. Instead, Belletti proposes that negative

Page 127: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

adverbs may be generated in VP-spec position, and that the participle

moves past the adverb to its AGR position , and the Aux element to its

corresponding AGR node. Adjacency is, thus, obtained without recourse to

Baker"s incorporation. ( Belletti ( 1990);(12))

(95) AGRP

Gianni AGR

AuxP

pres Aux AGRP

avère

AGR'

AGR VP

-to più VP

V

•paria-

Page 128: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

The choice of one proposal over the other is done on empirical

grounds. There seem to be two very different predictions made by

the two analyses:

" ... given a sequence "NP Aux Adv PstPrt" , whatever the nature of the adverb involved, the incorporation hypothesis predicts that the order "NP Aux PstPrt Adv " will always be available as well, no matter which position the adverb fills, provided that it is a position lower than the (highest) AGR head. On the other hand, if no process of "Aux+PstPrf incorporation is assumed to be available, the prediction is that the order "NP Aux PstPrt Adv " can only be obtained if the adverb in question fills the VP initial position; if it fills any position higher than VP, the final order of constituents will always be "NP Aux Adv PstPrt '*. (p.30)

These predictions are borne out in Italian, but not in Catalan nor in

Spanish, as was shown in preceding sections, as there is no possibility of

"NP Aux Adv PstPrt" sequence, equivalent to the Italian (96), where a

sentential adverb is used in order to prove that, the incorporation analysis

fails given the ungrammaticality of (97):

(96) a. Gianni na probabilmente telefónate

b. Maria è evidentemente partita (14)

(97)a. *Gianina telefónateprebabilmente

b. * Maria è partita evidentemente (15)

Page 129: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

A note on Frenen and English

These two languages contrast sharply with Catalan and Spanish in not

allowing adjacency of Aux and Past Participle in certain constructions, for

instance, V movement and Placement of the negative particle, or

Interruption by the negative adverb neverz/amals - this was already seen

in the presentation of the tests in section 2.1 for English- as (96) -(99) and

(100)-( 101) show:

(9Ô)a. Has Peter seen the film?

b. * Has seen the film Peter?

(99)a. Pierre, a-t.-ll vu le film?

b. *A vu Pierre le film?

(lOO)a Peter has sot. seen the film

b. * Peter not has seen the film

( 101 )a. Pierre n a pas vu le film

b. * Pierre n'a vu pas le film

( 102 )a. /have never seen anything as terrible

b. *fhave seen never anything as terrible

( 103)a. Je n al jamais vu une chose aussi atroce

b. *Je n'ai vu/amals une chose aussi atroce

These examples imply the non-application of incorporation in

equivalent complex structures in French and English - cf. Pollock (1967)

for an explanation of such contrasts -. As will become evident in section

3.4, these differences will also lead to the assumption that different kinds

of auxiliaries - N-aux / T-aux in G&H (I960)* s framework - may have

Page 130: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

different properties in different languages. HAVE, for instance - a neutral

auxiliary - cf. section 2.4 - triggers obligatory incorporation in Catalan and

Spanish but not in English, although, as all auxiliaries, it T -marks its VP

complement.

These differences seem to me best captured in terms of the general

loss of '•content" ("possess") lexical status of àaver/üatef in Catalan and

Spanish, as opposed to English and French, -where Jiave/avojr have

retained their "content" lexical status in structures other than complex verb

sequences. This is another argument in favour of the loss of syntactic

autonomy of úaver / Jsaber, and, thus, the triggering of process of

incorporation in these two languages as opposed, again, to French and

English. English and French hav$ /avoir, despite their ability to function as

auxiliaries, do not trigger incorporation,2 6

Page 131: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

3.3-2 Incorporation and complex predicates

3-3-2.0 Introduction

This section presents the analysis that Baker assumes for those

sequences analyzed in section 2.3 as complex predicates; i.e. verbal

sequences that do not behave as lexical units, but which are a semantic

unit, although there are reasons to postulate a biclausal status of the

structure in which they occur; i.e. Control or ECM structures. I here present

Baker"s analysis as objectively as possible, leaving possible dubious aspects

for section 3.4. His mechanism of VP to Spec CP is one of these dubious

aspects, and I will attempt to render it unnecessary by making use of

G&H's analysis - as presented in section 2.4 -.

3.3.2.1 A note on complex predicates

Reconsider some of the tests presented in both section 2.1 for

Catalan and Spanish, which seem to indicate that the two verbs in the

sequence - as opposed to those in the sequences considered in 3.3.1 - are

not lexical units:27

Catalan:

1. Interruption by lexical elements (adverbs and parentheticals):

(Test 10)

(104) a. Sempre feia portar lesmaletes alseu marit

\>{l)Feia sempre portar les maletos al sou marit

( 105) a. Comença a protostar gitan te gana

Page 132: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

b.(?) Comença sempre a protestar quan te gana

(106) a. Molt sovint vol anar a la platja

b.(?) Vol molt sovint anar a la plat/a

(104) a. Podem sortir on barca si voleu

b. Podem, si voleu, sortiren barca

From Espinal (I960). The * marks the positions where the adverb

òbviament" ( obviously) may appear:

( 10Ô). * On Joan * va haver * däbandonar

(109). * la fortalesa *ha estat * essent * observada

(110). *" En Joan *devia * haver vingut

2. Placement oí the negative particle ( or Tensed negative VP):

(Test 3)

From Picallo (I960):

(111 )£n Jordi pot no haver sortit

(112) Començo a no tenir-ne ganes

(113) En Pep voldria no haver-ho de fer

3. V-0 movement (or Tensed verb preceding subject):

( Test 4)

( 114) a. Solia anar a veure el mar la Maria F

b.(?) Solíala Maria anar a veure elmar?

( 115) a. Pot fer el viatge la Pepa?

b.(?) Pot la Pepa fer el viatge ?

(116) a. Començarà a fer les preguntes l'entrevlstadorP

Page 133: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

311

b. (?) Començarà J'entrevistador a fer Jes preguntes?

4. Preposing and postposing:

( Test 11 )

(From Hernanz & Rigau ( iyò4))

(117) a. Solia parlar de Jes seves veJJes amistatsparisenques durant

Jestiu

b. Solia durant Jestiupariar de Jes seves veJJes amistats

parisenques

(From Espinal I960, who does not include ?).

( 11 ô)(?) Crèiem que millorava i empitjorant anava

( 119)(?) Van dir que seria empresonat i empresonat va ser

Spanish

1. Interruption by lexical items (adverbs and parentheticals):

(Test 10)

( 12 0)(?) Hacia siempre JJevar JasmaJetas a su marido

(121)(?) Comienza siempre a protestar cuando tiene Èam&re

(122 )(?) Quiere .cada domingo.Jra JapJaya

( 123)(?) Podemos, si queréis, saiiren barco

2. Placement of the negative particle( or Tensed negative VP):

(Test 3)

(124X?) Carmen deo-eria no Jeer tantas noveJas

Page 134: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

( 125)(?) J&te alumno puede no tener que hacer el eissmen,

si su trabajo está bien hecho

\. yO. movement ( or Tensed verb preceding subject):

( Test 4 )

( i 2 ÓJÍ?) ¿Puede tu amigo venir un momento?

f 12 7)(?) ¿ Quieren sus padres conocer a su novia F

4. Preposing and postposing:

( Test 11 )

(From H&RO 964):

( 12ô) a. Bebí comentar este lamentable Incidente hace mucho tiempo

b. Debí hace mucho tiempo cementar este lamentable Incidente

(129) (?) Sabíamos que volverla a fumar v a fumar volvió

The fact that move-alpha may break the sequence of two abstractly

incorporated or reanalyzed - cf. below for an explanation - items is implied

by Baker in several passages of Baker (19ÔÔ). It is important to mention

that this is noted in cases where non-syntactic incorporation takes place -

cf. below for an explanation, section 3.3.2.2 -, as, according to Baker, in the

cases of complex predicates in Romance. In his analysis oí copular passive -

cf. Note (32) - he assumes that BE is generated in INFL and that the V

incorporates abstractly into it, but if BE is a V subcategorizing for another

VP - cf. section 1.2.2 Chomsky 1966b - "we may assume that first the main

V reanalyzes with the auxiliary, and then the auxiliary overtly

incorporates into INFL (p.477 in9).2°" In another passage of the book, which

Page 135: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

Baker links to the above statement himself, a parallel process is assumed to

take place in the analysis of causatives in Chimwiimni and Chamorro: "First,

the verb reanalyzes (i.e. is coindexed) with the head of its NP object, thus

freeing the object from the need to get Case. The verb tft$n may move to

INFL C, and ultimately to the matrix verb without taking the object NP

along." (p. 279) What these passages imply is that a sequence of two

reanalyzed items may be broken up by move-alpha. In this case, move-

alpha is an instance of a specific type of abstract incorporation, as will be

explained below.

In the examples above we see that the sequence of two verbs may

be broken up either by the interruption of lexical items or by movement (

preposing or postposing , Vo to C ). Even if we take into account the fact

that for some speakers these configurations do not render a wholly

acceptable result, this set of verbal sequences still clearly constrasts with

the complex verbs analyzed in the previous section in that they form a

quasi - indivisible unit, as opposed to an utterly indivisible unit.

Note that although Baker's theory allows for interruption of verbal

sequences - and , thus, makes correct predictions for the examples above

considered - the dubiousness of the mechanism proposed for complex

predicates calls for reconsideration -cf. section 3.4 -.

Page 136: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

3.3-2.2 Romance causatives

Baker extends his analysis of causative structures in Chichewa,

Malayalam, etc. to Italian. He posits that the rule of incorporation as

outlined in section 3.2 is not only available in these languages; Italian

seems to have a similar rule. In other words, among all the possible

variation within causative conductions that Baker studies, Italian - and

other Romance languages - group together with Chichewa2 9 and

Malayalam. Note that following the assumptions in section 3.2 the

configurations in both of the following sections are instances of biclausal

structures - they are considered GF-changing processes .

Baker's analysis of Italian causatives is a reformulation of previous

analyses which posited a rule of reanalysis - cf. Section 2.3.1.4, Manzini

(19Ô3)- for such structures. Reanalysis in the actual framework can be

seen as an instance of incorporation at another level of the grammar; i.e LF.

Italian causatives such as ( 1 ) and (2 ):

( 130) Maria fa iavoraro Giovanni ( 121 )a.

(131 )Maria ha fatîo ripararo ia maccftina a Giovanni ( 121 )b.

are analyzed as instances of this type of incorporation. The crucial

fact is that there are basic syntactic properties that these constructions

share with the relevant constructions in the other two languages. If both

may be explained with one general "mechanism for which , according to

Baker, there is independent evidence, the theory will gain explanatory

adequacy. Baker focuses on the characteristics of the NPs following the

causative sequences: the embedded object of a transitive verb, and the

embedded subject of an intransitive verb behave as the object of the main

Page 137: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

verb after causativization, and the embedded subject of a transitive verb

bears an oblique case, namely dative - cf. also sections in 2.3.1 for other

analyses -. The following rule is the descriptive statement of this fact:

(132) Causative Rule 1

GF in embedded clause GF in surface clause

ergative oblique (10)

absolutive direct object (41)

where absolutive= subject of intransitive, object of transitive

ergative= subject of transitive

The relevant tests for Italian are cliticization30, which shows that the

two absolutive NPs may be object clitics of the higher verb (133), and

passivization, which allows again both these NPs as subjects (134)3*

(133)a. Maria Jo faJavoraro

b. Maria Ja fa ripararo a Giovanni ( 12 2 )a. and b

( 134)a. Giovanni è statu fatto Javoraro (moJto)

b. la macdtina fu fatta ripararo a Giovanni ( 12 3) a. and b.

These descriptive observations are predicted by Baker's analysis.

They are, thus, explained if incorporation is accepted as a universal

mechanism. The differences these languages exhibit - " ... one important

difference between the two: from the viewpoint of morphology, the

causative verb and the embedded verb are still two separate words in

Romance." p.201 - seem to be reducible to a parameter; i.e. the level of

application of this rule in the grammar. If incorporation in these

Page 138: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

(reanalysis) constructions is assumed to take place from S-structure to LF -

and not from D-structure to S-structure as posited for Chichewa and

Malayalam - the differences follow. This, as mentioned by Baker, is parallel

to the well-known parametric variation in Chinese where wh-movement

aplies at LF.

The differences alluded to above are facts which will gain

importance in what follows. One obvious difference that (135) and (136)

show if compared to (130) and (131) is that causativization in Chichewa

and Malayalam creates a morphologically complex unit, one word:

(135) AnayanJ a-na-wa-m&ny-$îs-a ana kwa buJuzi

baboons SP-PAST-OP-hit-CAUS-ASP children to lizard

" The baboons made the lizard hit the children"

(Chichewa) (94)a.

(136) Amma kuWy&-kkonta annay& mill-ice-u

mother child-ACC with elephant-ACC pinch-CAUS-PAST

"Mother made the child pinch the elephant"

(Malayalam) (9ô)a.

(135) and (136) also show that, in these two languages, there is only

one inflectional ending in the causative verbal units. This contrasts with

Italian where each verbal element carries a specific inflection. Crucially,

though, it is the first verb in the sequence, the causative verb proper that

carries the tense and agreement inflection, the lower verb is in its

infinitival form.

The result of this process - i.e. LF-incorporation - is that the syntactic

properties of causative constructions in both groups of languages - i.e.

Chichewa and Malayalam on the one hand and Italian on the other - are the

Page 139: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

same, but they allow for the surface structure differences pointed out

above: "... we must give an account of Romance causatives in which they

have exactly the same syntax as (say) Chichewa causatives, but they differ

with respect to morphology " (p. 202) - . The formal characterization of the

contrast between the two groups of languages is as follows. Note, though,

that the relationshiD between the two verbal heads is and must be a.

essentially the same in all of these constructions: the link that the first

verbal element bears with the second one is translated into a government

relation . Coindexing between nodes is interpreted in these constructions as

the coindexing between a part of a complex word and its trace as in the

following. Note that both a. and b. involve a government relationship and,

thus, further incorporation is legitimated - in b. -:

(1375a. IYP. . . (Xi + Yli . . . !XP t i . . .]]

b.Iyp. . .Yi. . .IxpXi . . .]] (124)

If the lower verb is not in a position where it is directly governed, it

moves in order to reach such a position - cf. section 3-2 -. Crucially, the

Romance constructions that Baker analyzes all require movement; i.e

movement previous to the incorporation process, because they all constitue

cases of biclausal structures.

Recall that in section 3.2 the issue of the movement of the embedded

V to a position governed by the matrix V prior to incorporation was already

mentioned. Two possibilities were mentioned without giving specific

examples. Consider the following structures, which instantiate the two

possibilities:

Page 140: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

(13Ô)a. S

NP VP

V CP

1 / \ ai:e VPi IP

ti V NP*

V* NP* NP* r

A I VP

0 ti

(62)a.andb.

These structures show the different movement possibilities of the

verb prior to incorporation of the lower verb to the matrix verb. In

transitive constructions, there are two NPs in each structure which, like all

NPs are subject to the Case Filter. The complex verb resulting after

incorporation, will only be able to assign as many cases as simple verbs in

the language may assign. This is Baker's Case Frame Preservation Principle

(CFPP), which states that " a complex Xo category formed by Incorporation

cannot go beyond the maximum case-assigning properties allowed to a

morphologically simple member of that category in the language" (p.355)

So, if Vs only assign one case, there will be an NP lacking case: in a. the

embedded object, NP*; in b. the embedded subject, NP*. Notice, though, that

Page 141: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

this lack of case is not due to the fact that they are ungoverned: both these

NPs are governed by the incorporated V since there are no minimality

barriers, and all the X-max are selected. What plays a crucial role here is

the CFPP. In the b. structure, crucially the causative verb is assumed to

have the lexical property of Complementizer Deletion, otherwise, CP would

be a minimality barrier, containing a distinct head. For both NPs , thus, a

marked type of case assignment is needed.

Consider the Italian example (131) above, repeated here:

( 131 ) Maria ha fatto riparare Ja macctttea a Giovanni (121 )b.

In Italian the insertion of a preposition allows the NP subjects to pass

the Case Filter - cf. also section 2.3.1, Kayne (1975), Burzio (1966) -. It is

the NP subject, not the object which surfaces as an oblique in these

constructions, so their surface structure follows by assuming that they are

derived via VP-to-Spec-CP movement, as in ( 13Ô)b.

Chichewa and Malayalam have this same option for embedded

subjects. Notice that these surface with an oblique case in (135) and (136):

A'wa jbu/usftto lizard; Chichewa),

kuttye-kkonta (child-ACC with; Malayalam, SOV).

The derivation in 03ô)a., VI, is assumed for languages with verbs

that have the ability to assign two accusative cases. One such language is

another Bantu language, Kinyarwanda. In Kinyarwanda, Vs assign

accusative case to two postverbal NPs, and both of these show direct object

properties. In the derivation of (13Ô)a., where the lower V has

incorporated, V* governs both of the NPs, the subject and the object,- there

Page 142: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

are no "distinct" heads, no minimality barriers-, and since the V has the

capability of assigning two accusative cases, there is no need to have

recourse to a marked type of case assignment. The following example

illustrates this:

(13*9). Umugabo a -r - uuba}: -JJst -a abaantu Jnsu

man SP-PRES-build-CAUS-ASP people house

"The man is making the people build the house." (67)b

(140)

NP

V

VP

CP

V C IP V*

baildj make tj NP* I

VP

ti V NP*

(66)

Going back to Baker's explanation for Italian, Chichewa and

Malayalam causatives (i.e., 130b) it is assumed that only the embedded Vs

of the last two languages undergo movement in the syntax: they surface as

Page 143: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

one morphologically complex form. What Baker posits for Italian is a

process of Abstract Incorporation. Incorporation of the lower V to the

higher V takes place at LF. Before this, the V must move to a position

where it can reanalyze with the higher V : Quoting Baker: " Because of the

presence of the Infi node in the sentential object the verb must undergo

movement internal to the clause in order to get into a position to Reanalyze.

This much happens in the syntax by S-structure. [...] if the lower verb is

transitive, the entire VP must move into sentence initial position, so that

the lower object does not violate the Case Filter. " (p. 203). Thus, it is

assumed that for transitive verbs, the whole VP moves to the Spec of CP (as

in (9)b. - cf. also section 2.3.1.2 for another VP-movement analysis of

causatives, Burzio C1966) -. The object NP is assigned accusative case by the

complex V, and the embedded subject receives case via a preposition

insertion rule.

As implied by the quotation, for intransitive Vs, there is no reason to

assume that the whole VP must move, since the NP-subject in the lower

clause will be governed if the V moves head-to-head. The NP-subject is the

only NP needing case and it can be assigned case directly by the complex

verb.

3.3.2.3 Restructuring constructions

Baker's analysis of restructuring - cf. 2.3.2- constructions in Romance

is parallel to his analysis of causatives . Namely, he proposes that this other

type of complex predicate may also be analyzed as an instance of VI, of

abstract VI. What causatives and restructuring constructions share is that

they are made up of two verbs which function as one, a complex predicate,

and, according to Baker, their D-structure is biclausal; they both have a

lower subject and a lower object, but there are some crucial differences/The

Page 144: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

embedded subject in restructuring constructions, as opposed to causatives,

must be phonologically null, and it must be preferential with the matrix

subject - as noted and explained in section 2.3. -. The structure is , thus,

analyzed as an instance of Control. This construction is a point of interest

for Baker in his analysis of GF changing patterns since it also involves a GF

change as the following rule describes:

( í 4 i ) Initial &F Final OF

embedded object object

embedded subject X

matrix subject subject ( 12 5)p.2 04

This rule is assumed to coexist with a specific causative pattern.

Baker analyzes the differences between these two types of GF changing

processes in the same way, but alluding to a specific property that

causative verbs have that restructuring verbs do not have: the lexical

property of Complementizer Deletion. This allows the government of the

embedded subject by the complex head V-0 containing a causative V and

an incorporated V, but blocks government of the embedded subject by the

complex head V-0 containing a restructuring V and an incorporated V.

Recall that if there is C-deletion, CP will not be a minimality barrier since C

wil not be a distinct head. The result, if C-deletion does not take place, is

that the only element allowed in this subject position is PRO, as the theories

of Binding and Control ensure. The' parallel boils down to the difference

between ECM and Control verbs.

The structure Baker assumes for the causative pattern found in

Italian is ( 13ôb) repeated here:

Page 145: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

U36)b. S

/ \ NP VP

/ \ V CP

/ \ VPi IP

A V NP*

NP* T

/ \ I VP

I ti

As mentioned, in causative structures of transitive verbs the second

NP is case-marked by a special device which assigns it oblique case ; in

restructuring constructions the second NP does not need case, moreover, it

may not be governed because it is PRO. The fact that the second NP could

not get case followed from the Case Frame PreservatJon PrmdpM which

disallows the assignment of more cases by a complex X-0 than are typically

assigned by a non-complex member of the given X category. 32

A

Page 146: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

3.4 Incorporation and T- theory

3.4.0 Introduction

The aim of the next three sections 3.4.1, 3.4.2,and 3.4.3 - is to explore

some of the possible interactions of I(ncorporation)-tlieory (Baker 19ÔÔ)

and T-theory (Guéron & Hoekstra (I960)). Since both, I-theory - the part

of it which is referred to in this thesis, and which constitutes its main

hypothesis - and T-theory are attempts to explain the cohesiveness of

verbs in a sequence ; i.e. of complex predicates and complex verbs, I

believe it worthwhile to attempt a look at the extent of compatibility and

interactions that there are between the twTo.

In section 3-4.1 the basic idea that syntactic incorporation ( as

postulated in 3-3-1- for complex verbs ) - a derivation at S-structure - and

T-theory ( cf. section 2.4) - which crucially involves the FDC, an

interpretation principle of LF - are compatible will be approached.

In section 3-4.2 the two LF mechanisms in each theory - LF-

incorporation and the FDC - are compared. Some dubious aspects of LF -

incorporation and the generality of the FDC seem to malee the former

unnecesssary.

Finally, section 3.4.3 is an attempt to rejoin the idea put forward in

section 3.3.I that V [ VP ] subcategorization requires obligatory

incorporation with the notion of neutral auxiliary (N-aux). The questions

raised are: Do only N-auxiliaries trigger obligatory incorporation of their V

complement ? ; Is it a universal'property of N-auxiliaries or is there

language variation?; May the behaviour of complex predicates be explained

by assuming that the first verb of a complex predicate sequence is an

auxiliary , moreover a T-auxiliary, which does not trigger incorporation?

The special status of epistemic modals is also raised.

Page 147: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

In this introduction I would like to briefly retrace some notions

which were raised in the "digest" - section 2.3 -, some of which may be - if

only - "relatable" to some of the notions proposed by Guéron & Hoekstra

(19ÔÔ) ; notions like T-chain, the concept of auxiliary as a T-marker, and

the proposal that the first verbal element in a complex predicate sequence

may be an auxiliary in certain configurations.

Rouveret & Vergnaud (19Ô0) - section 2.3.1.1 - posit the notion of

superscript , borne by both, [- N] elements and [ + N ] elements. In the

former case, one may see how verbs in a sequence were already seen as

bearing "indices" of some sort. They proposed this for the French causative

faire - a much trodden on verbal element - as in their rule I repeated here:

(142) Rule I

FAIRER [ - N ]P NP * 1 [ - N M 3

1 2 3

CONDITIONS : (i) [ - N ] does not branch

(ii) NP is the Theme of I - N 1

The fact that Burzio (1966) - section 2.3.1.2 - proposes VP

subcategorization for certain - obviously - non-derived causative structures

also relates to G&H's proposal of faire as an auxiliary, although - cf. 2.4 and

below - G&H assume IP in the syntax. In the parallel structure analysis of

Zubizarreta - section 2.3.1.3 -, we find that faire is generated as (part of a)

a complex verb in one of its parallel simultaneous structures; another link

with its auxiliary status in G&H. The fact that Manzini (19Ô3t>) - section

2.3.I.4 - proposes the lexical property of renalyser for a causative like

faire, again indicates its - at obvious different stages of the model -

theoretical bond with G&H's proposal.

Page 148: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

The proposals for restructuring constructions offer no parallel

contrast possibilities , although Riz2i (1952a) " complex verb" formation -

and all the other proposals which obviously posit mechanisms for linking

M-A + infinitive verbal sequences - may be subsumed by G&H's proposal of

classifying certain of these verbs ( in specific constructions ) as auxiliaries ,

which, therefore, T- mark their VP complements. As will be seen in the

next sections, VP-movement is rendered unneccessary by T-marking, when

the verbs have an auxiliary status; otherwise - if they have a lexical verb

status - they Case-mark their complement and it is interpreted as an

argument, not as ( part of ) a predicate.

Note that in G&H's terms, the notion of complex verb and complex

predicate may be unified at LF by their mechanism of FDC - cf. (143)

below-: verbs forming a complex verb sequence are always part of a

predicate, and when complex predicates are formed , verbs in these

sequences are also part of a complex predicate. Evidently, this is so because

their aim is to contrast between argument/predicate ( nominal/verbal )

verbal complementation, which is not the aim of this thesis. It must be

noted that in order to avoid confusion whenever I refer to the notion of

comptez pr&tieate as in G&H09ÔÔ) - as a result of the FDC -, I will use

italics to distinguish it from the notion of complex predicate used in this

thesis - as explained in Chapter 2 -.

Page 149: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

3.4.1. Syntactic Incorporation and T-theory

3.4.1.1 Another look at T- theory 33

The aim of Guéron and Hoekstra to consider the concept of auxiliary

more closely is, to my mind, in the sense of Wass's passage - cf.

introductory quotation to 2.1 - :* Un élément portant le nom d "auxiliaire ne

peut se justifier que s"il permet de révéler des propriétés significatives du

langage ". By giving the notion of auxiliary a firm basis - that of T-marking,

essentially - G&H (I960), to my mind, achieve a simplification of the

grammar in that they allow for VP complementation in cases where

traditional arguments for Control or ECM structures would not allow a VP,

and , thus, explain the exceptional behaviour of complex predicates, and

also, more obviously, the behaviour of complex verbs. This is done by

making intensive use of the level of LF, which is where VP

complementation of otherwise not straightforward VP projections is

caBstru&d Their framework gives a basis - in terms of a construal

principle -, which allows for a specific interpretation of an XP complement

as nominal or verbal - argument or predicate -. The FDC, repeated here:

(14^) Functional Determination of Categories

a. External.

An XP is construed as a nominal projection iff it is

casemarked.

An XP is construed as a verbal projection iff it is T-marked.

b. Internal.

The subject of a nominal projection receives a Case which is

determined internal to XP; the subject of a verbal projection

Page 150: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

receives a Case ( if any ) which is determined by an external

governor.

ensures that the complement of the V in a complex verb structure is

construed as part of a complex predicate. Note that I will only refer to the

external determination of XP complements; i.e. I will focus on the notion of

T-marking. The fact that there is no internal subject to the VP of a complex

verb makes it dependent as a part of a comptes predicate. Quoting G&H :

"Arguments, then, are Case-licensed. Their independence is internally

brought out by the fact that if they have an internal subject, this subject is

licensed independently from the syntactic context in which it appears .[...]

In contrast, if the subject of a complement is licensed from toe outside, the

complement is in that sense not entirely autonomous." (p.36) - see section

3.4.2.2 and 3.4.3 for external licensing of subjects in complex predicate

structures -.

How is the XP complement of a complex verb determined as verbal

by the FDC? Recall - cf. section 2.4 - that either Tense or auxiliary verbs

may T-mark; the latter also have the ability to pass on a T-index assigned

by Tense or another auxiliary. It is assumed that an auxiliary always

governs the tense morpheme of its non-finite VP complement. This is a

basic distinctive feature of auxiliary verbs versus lexical verbs, the latter

do not have the ability of T-marking - or passing on a T-index-. In a

complex verb structure, Tense assigns a T-index to the auxiliary , which

then passes it on to VP of the main verb and the main verb absorbs it. This

is, in essence, the formation of a T-chain in a complex verb structure, as

exemplified in (144)a. (022)b. in G&H))- b. for French and English, where

the question of incorporation does not arise; cf. 3-31-4 and 3.4.3.2 -:34

(144) a. Jean { TA' a/Â' [ vpk ¿iÀ' chanté ¡Il

Page 151: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

t>.JonnfT*nasj¿{yp£ tj¿sungjf/

Note crucially that, despite the application oí incorporation, which I

am assuming is - in complex verb sequences - an S-structure phenomenon,

the verbal projection will nevertheless be construed as verbal because of

T-marking - rather the passing on of the T-index - of the auxiliary in such a

sequence. Hence, in complex verb sequences verb movement of the lexical

verb - i.e. incorporation- is not needed to identify the XP complement as a

VP, as in the following structures, the Catalan and Spanish traslations of

(3)a. and b. -1 have ommitted showing the application of incorporation, cf.

3.4.1.2 , to illustrate this fact - :

(145) a. En Joan (T* í yp^ha* í ypk cantat fII

b. Juan (T& ÍVPÁ'nak í VPA' cantado III

G&H point out that there are constructions where verb movement is

needed - although in such cases it is movement of an auxiliary and not a

lexical verb - as I am assuming for Catalan and Spanish in the structures

for which I posit incorporation - to identify the complement of a verb as

verbal, and, consequently, to license it. In Portuguese tensed infinitival

examples like (146) the equivalent of the "Aux-to-Comp" - cf. Rizzi (1962c)

and, as already explained in 2.4 - phenomenon ensures the identification of

the SP as a VP at LF. In the following example, the verb lamentar is

assumed to have an optional Case to assign, if it does not assign it - as in

(146), the CP complement must be T-marked in order to be licensed - as it

is not assigned Case -, but since lamentar is a lexical verb, auxiliary terem

must raise in order to T-mark the complement and, thus, identify it as a

verbal projection at LF - and, thus, license it -. ( (9)a.,b. G&HU9ÔÔ)):

Page 152: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

(146) a. Fulamente fcp teremjI¡posdiputadostj

[ yp trabalhado pouco JIJ

b. Eu lamente [yp-] teremj fvP-2 os deputados tj

f yp.j traùalhado pouce III

As was explained in section 2.4, the segments in (146)b. are

construed as part of the same VP, following Chomsky (1906b). The

assignment of Case to the subject was also explained in section 2.4 as a

consequence of government by teres? - i.e. an external governor -.

There are several aspects of T-marking and the subsequent creation

of T-chains35 that are closely related to complex verb structure of the type

studied in 3.3.1 - in section 3.4.2. we will see the implications of some of

these aspects for complex predicates -. Recall that T-marking implies the

passing on of a T-index, which percolates to the semantic head of the main

verb VP and becomes part of its reference. Auxiliaries, having no

referential value, cannot integrate a T-index, so they pass it on until there

is a VP headed by a main verb which may integrate it, hence, absorb it.

Another aspect of T-chain formation is that it provides a way for certain

syntactic features to percolate along it. As was illustrated in 2.4, for

instance, theta-role percolation (147), and (148); - (136),(137)in G&H09ÔÔ)

-, which is assumed to be almost identical in simple tenses consisting only

in one verb form, such as ( 147), as in complex tenses, such as (146):

(147) a. John saw Mary

b. John s fagrJ Tlyp saw Mary //

theta-l

( 140) a. John has seen Mary

b. John * fagrJ T[ ypj has [ yp2 seen Mary II

theta-1

Page 153: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

The equivalent examples in Catalan and Spanish presumably imply

the same percolation of features by T-chain formation -although the

Catalan simple past example implies a complex verb sequence (Ô) -:

(149) a. En Joan va veuf'? Ja Maria

b. En Joan J [ agrJ T[ VPJ va ÍVP2 veure Ja María ///

thêta-1

( 150) a. Juan * { agr1 Tíyp vio a María I !

thêta-1

Another of the crucial facts about T-chain formation is that they may

be extended by the application of Spec-head agreement (SHAG) or head-

head agreemeent - i.e. when the two V heads share a T-index . This

explains that NP-raising and clitic climbing are only allowed in

configurations where the complement is interpreted as verbal in LF,

because it is T-marked. As explained in 2.4, NP-raising and clitic climbing

are possible when antecedent government holds - as in the passive account

in Barriers-cf. 1.2.2 - : VP is nota barrier because of Spec-head agreement

(SHAG); I shares index with the governed ec by virtue of raising or

"climbing" - cf. 2.4 -, and the ec is antecedent governed, as in the following

complex verb structure with clitic climbing- (76)a. in G&H09ÔÔ) -:3&

(15D Je J j ailypej vu ejl

It is obvious, thus, that in complex verb structures, clitic climbing

should always be possible, as is indeed borne out by the facts, and

Page 154: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

independently predicted by G&H's framework. - as quoted in section 3.4.2.2,

(23) -3?

WDLj-Hef Cejjvist oj/

(153) Hoj vaig [for OÍ I

(154) Lsj ho[ visto oj/

3.4.1.2 Complex verb incorporation and the FDC

There is a basic compatibility of syntactic incorporation and T-theory,

with its basic construal principle at LF, the FDC. As pointed out in the

preceding section, the fact that complex verbs are made up of a sequence of

verbs, the first of which is an auxiliary ensures previous T-marking, and ,

thus, only one possibility of construal: the XP complements of the first verb

in the sequence in complex verbs are always interpreted as part of a

comptes predicate

Syntactic V-movement in incorporation structures - as explained in

3.2 - requires antecedent government of the V trace. This is achieved, as

explained, by S-structure, so the LF construal principle, the FDC, should not

affect this relationship. The following structure shows that no principles are

violated, if we assume incorporation to have applied plus the FDC: VP-2 is

T-marked, and, thus, licensed as a VP, and the trace of V-2 satisfies the ECP

by antecedent government :

Page 155: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

(155) VP-l

I V-l

/ \

V*i/j VP-2j

V-lj V-2i V-2

V-2

¿i

(where j - as in section 3.4.1.1 - is the T-marking index )

As explained in 3.2, Theta-indexing between the X and the YP is

what devoids the Xmax dominating the trace of the incorporated item of its

barrierhood status, and, thus, allows antecedent government of the X-0

trace by the incorporated V*. In complex verb incorporation an equivalent

mechanism - i.e. either Chomsky(19ô6b) L-marking, or Balier (I960) theta -

indexing - must be assumed. Nevertheless, in G&H' s framework there is

another possibility, which I will assume: they assume that T-marking is

equivalent to L- marking. There is, thus, no need to recur to a special type

of theta-indexing in complex ver.bs in order to devoid the VP of its

barrierhood status if it is independently T -marked; antecedent government

of the trace holds. Note, nevertheless, that T-marking is alluded to in an LF

mechanism, the FDC. G&H, though, imply, to my mind, - and even more by

making it equivalent to L-marking - that it holds at S-structure - as does

Case marking, which is also alluded to in the FDC.

Page 156: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

It is crucial to distinguish between these sequences of verbs and the

behaviour of complex predicate verbal sequences in that precisely the fact

that syntactic V-movement; i.e. incorporation - a process which I do not

assume for complex predicates, as will be explained in section 3.4.2 - , has

applied accounts for their indivisibility - cf. 2.1 and 3.3.1.1 -. Consider some

more examples that show their indivisibility:

a) Interruption by lexical elements is not allowed:

( 15b)a. *No m Ms mai dit. que tenies tres fills

b. * Va, sense voier, tirar tots eispiatsper terra

(157) * No me nas nunca dicho que tenias tres nips

b) Preposing results in ungrammatical structures:

( 15ö)a. * Ens pensàvem que es casarien però casat no sñan

b. * Crèiem que ia Maria £osa iguaria pero baiiarnc va

(159) *¿ Yeliibro ? - ¡Comido no me io ne/

Another important aspect with regards to the relationship between

S-structure and LF in complex verb sequences is that they may be assumed

to be identical 3Ô: if no functional nodes intervene, the FDC has no effect in

eonstriung a CP/IP as a VP.

Page 157: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

3-4.2 LF-incorporation and /or tîie FDC

3.4.2.1 Another look, at LF-incorporation

Complex predicates are quasi-indivisible units - ci. 3.3.2.1 -, tîiey are

thus, structures for which syntactic incorporation cannot be posited. Baker

states that abstract incorporation - or Reanalysis - has the same properties

as movement because Reanalysis constructions form a natural class with

incorporation structures in other languages " whose properties follow from

the theory of movement ", he concludes that " it has the same properties as

movement simply because it too is movement, albeit, movement which one

cannot see." (p.203). If a simpler analysis, which is independently

motivated, explains this unseen movement I believe it must be chosen on

simplicity grounds.

It is also stated in Baker (19ÔÔ) that because of the presence of I in

the embedded sentential complement, the V must undergo movement

internal to the clauses - see section 3.3.2 -, in order to get into a position to

reanalyze. If no such structure is needed, movement will be made

unnecessary - cf. 3-4.2.2. and 3.4.3 -, provided that a mechanism like chain

formation, for instance, is independently needed, and, thus implies no

addition to the theory .

There are some dubious aspects of abstract incorpora tJcn which may

be considered to render it unnecessary as long as the notion of T-marking

of G&H (19ÔÔ) is sufficient to explain the behaviour of complex predicates

and makes the correct predictions. Firstly, the VP-to-Spec CP mechanism is

posited in order to obtain a government relation between higher verb and

Page 158: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

lower verb in biclausal structures, without there being a clear trigger for

this movement. It must be noted - cf. also 3.3.2 - that the V-projection

movement is interpreted as VP movement because in causative transitive

structures it is the subject which surfaces as oblique - i.e. preceded by the

preposition t? -. Furthermore, the usual targets for movement into Spec-CP

position are not VPs; i.e. it is usually wh-phrases that move to Spec-CP.

Obviously, this does not imply that a VP may not be subject to

move-alpha, there are obvious cases of VP preposing39, but in these cases,

the landing site for the VP is plausibly not Spec-CP but rather adjunction

positions created as in instances of extraposed constituents, as in: Nobody

would ride with Frod who know him -from Radford (19ÔÔ) P-565; an

instance of S"-adjunction -. (160) may also be analyzed as adjunction, in this

case, of a VP;

(160) Eido with Fr od. I wouldn't if I were you/

Moreover, an LF mechanism such as abstract incorporation is

questionable if reference must be made to an S-structure condition such as

Case. Baker refers to the Case Frame Preservation Principle (CPP) - cf.

3.3.2.2 -, which makes the proposal dubious crucially for Romance

languages, where incorporation is assumed abstract. VP-to-Spec-CP may

not be questionable for languages where there is syntactic VI -

incorporation. Note that Baker himself points out this problem in a footnote:

(161) " There is one important problem with this suggestion,

however. Given the standard view of GB, all "overt" movements

that occur between D-structure and S-structure are assumed to

strictly precede all "covert" movements, which happen

between S-structure and LF. Yet, I will have cause to claim at

Page 159: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

various points in what follows that covert Incorporation

crucially precedes overt Incorporation ( or seems to ) in certain

cases, giving rise to ordering paradoxes. This is even seen

directly below where VI "precedes"Case assignment which I

have assumedhappens at ¿structure. These facts may imply

that Reanalysis, although abstract incorporation' in some

sense, is not LF Incorporation after all. On the other hand , the

true relationship between LF and the other levels of syntactic

description is a controversial topic and may need to be revised.

[...] "( p. 462 in. 37) (italics mine)

Further related to Case considerations for Romance causatives , a

marked type of case-assignment - the a-insertion rule- is needed to Case-

mark the subject of transitive verbs. The NP direct object is assigned

accusative case by the verb of which it is a complement because the whole

VP moves. As Baker himself points out, there is no need to postulate a VP-

to-Spec-CP derivation for intransitive verbs, where V-movement is

sufficient for the subject to be assigned Case. The prediction is that the a-

insertion rule should not apply in intransitive causative structures. This,

however is not borne out especially in Spanish and also Catalan, as the

following examples of intransitive causative sequences illustrate:

(162) Hizo reir *(a) su hija

(163) Va fer riure (a) la seva filla

This marked type of case-assignment is, thus, independently needed,

whichever mechanism is posited for causatives in Romance languages.

Page 160: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

In restructuring constructions in Romance - rule 3 in 3.3.2.3,

repeated here -:

(164) Rule 3 (p. 204 (125) in Baker (19ÔÔ)

Initial GF Final GF

embedded object object

embedded subject 0

matrix subject subject

there seems to be no real GF-changing process; a function

"disappears" but there is no change. This fact, the already noted

dubiousness of VP-to-Spec-CP movement, plus the fact that there is no

phonologically realized subject in "restructuring" (Control) structures, seem

to give even less motivation to posit a VP-to-Spec-CP derivation for these

structures.

34.2.2.CanT-markingreplace LF-incorporation?

" The hypothesis that causative, perception, and, often, modal

verbs function as auxiliaries simplifies the grammar. It obviates

the need for a number of powerful syntactic devices which have

been proposed in the literature essentially in order to eliminate

the CP node of the complement of such verbs." G&H( 19ÔÔ)(p.55)

As already briefly noted in section 2.5, most mechanisms

summarized in Chapter 2 are not wholly valid in the present framework.

G&H (I960) argue against some of these on the basis of : a) their not being

independently motivated; b) their violating constraints in the present

framework; and c) implying an addition of undesirable powerful

Page 161: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

mechanisms to the grammar. In the previous section I have attempted to

extend the criticism to Baker"s LF-incorporation mechanism. In this section

I will try to show that T-theory, T-marking and the FDC, make correct

predictions, and, thus, there is no need to allude to abstract incorporation.

Note also that for G&H (i960) - with obviously different aims than Baker

(I960) - the causative and "restructuring" constructions are not regarded as

GF-changing processes as in Baker (I960). The GF-changing process is here

"reinterpreted" as a construal of a complex predicate because of the

special nature of the first verb in the sequence. Quoting G&H: " ... IP is

construed as a nominal projection nondistinct from NP when assigned case

by Infi, V, or P, but as a verbal projection non-distinct from VP when

governed by an auxiliary verb." (p.37). This allows for a propositional

complement- - as in the case of complex predicate structures - to be

construed as either an argument or as part of a comptez predicate at LF

provided that the first verb in a complex predicate sequence may be

granted an auxiliary status in certain configurations.

This paves the way for a different explanation within the present

framework of the special behaviour of verbs that diverge from "typical"

main verbs - as already noted by Rizzi (1982a) and in all the works

summarized in section 2.3 -; i.e. their semantic and syntactic cohesion, plus

the degree of divisibility that they allow - cf. 3-3-2.1 -, which distinguishes

them crucially from complex verb sequences. What they share with

complex verb sequences, nevertheless, is independently predicted by the

FDC, in G&H" s words:

(165) "The rules proposed by previous authors in order to

account for clitic climbing or NP raising in complex structures

derive output configurations which are syntactically equivalent

to base structures headed by auxiliary verbs. These structures

Page 162: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

independently allow clitic climbing and NP raising. Moreover,

reanalysis and parallel structure rules do not apply to

auxiliary structures, which contain no embedded CP to begin

with. If, as we propose, "restructuring" causative and modal

verbs are analyzed as auxiliary verbs, the syntactic behaviour

which characterizes auxmarv -headed structures automatical^ * »

applies to structures headed by causative and modal verbs."

(p-50)

To briefly summarize the aspects of complex predicates which will

concern us we may consider a few examples to recall their "double nature"

- cf 2.1.2 and 3-3-2.1 - in order to focus on the relevant aspects for the two

theories that are being made use of in this thesis; namely Baker(19Ôô) and

G8tHil9ôô). On the one hand, complex predicates are syntactically (and

semantically) united: a)(l66) and (167) show their non-interference with

the theta-grid of the main verb:

(166) a. EiMiquoi fa pot caminar

b. Una casa teta do fusta pot cromar-so fàciimont

(167) a. Aianyapuodo cantar aiguna canción

b. Una casa do madorapuodo quomarso faciimonto

b) and clitic climbing is possible over complex predicate structures:

( 16ô) a. la pot utiiitzar

b. Sompro Ja fa proparar ai sou marit (iapaoiia)

( 169)a. Lo quioro vor

Page 163: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

b. Siempre se la hace preparar a su marido

On the other hand, the possibility of separating the two components

of a verbal sequence of a comptez predicate, points towards the non-

application of incorporation, as i will assume below - and already noted in

3.4.I.2 -: a) Interruption by lexical elements is marginal, but acceptable:

(170) a.? Fa sempre preparar Ja paella ai seu marit

b.? Vol sovint veure Ja matensapelJícula dues vegades seguides

c. ? Pots, sempre que vulguis, fer servir el meu eotse

( 171 ) a. Le hace siempre planchar la ropa a su marido

b.(?) Quiere a menudo ver la misma película dos veces seguidas

c.(?) Puedes, siempre que qiueras, utilizar mi eoLYe

b) Preposing is also (marginally) accepted:

(172) a. ? Sabiemque voldria anar-hi i anar-hi va voler

b.? freiem que el faria cantar però cantar no el va fer

( 173) a.? Pensábamos que podría ir, pero ir no pudo

b.? Sabíamos que lo haría cantar y cantarlo hizo

Having briefly reviewed their behaviour, an account in terms of

G&H's proposal is due. As already noted, it will be in the following line: *' If

the infinitival is construed as a verbal projection, it is T-marked by the

morpheme of an auxiliary verb , as in causative and modal structures in

many languages ..."(p.73). Note that reference to the auxiliary type to which

the first verbal element belongs is not alluded to in this section - cf. section

Page 164: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

3.4.3 for reference to it -; here I will only refer to the possibilities of T-

marking of the first verbal element in certain complex predicate structures.

The account of complex predicate constructions by the FDC is sufficient to

explain the behaviour of complex predicates if everytime a complex

predicate is formed, VP construal is ensured . This would account for their

syntactic and semantic cohesion, - and, thus, possibility of phenomena such

as clitic climbing and NP raising- and, the fact that the FDC is an LF

mechanism would account for their S-structure divisibility possibilities. If

their account is correct, G&H (19ÔÔ) provide the mechanisms for an

infinitival S to be construed as a verbal projection, without making use of

undesirable nor unallowed mechanisms in the present framework of

generative grammar, and they account for both complex verb and predicate

structures.

Hence, even if there may be reasons to posit a biclausal structure -

cf. 2.2.1; basically the arguments for positing a Control or ECM structure -,

in the T-theory framework there is no need to appeal to movement of a

verbal projection - cf. Baker (I960) mainly, but also Rouveret & Vergnaud

(I960), Burzio (1956), as summarized in section 2.3 -, the syntactic and

semantic unity of complex predicates is maintained, because of the FDC,

granting V-1 an auxiliary status.

The above assumptions imply that there is a parallel explanation for

complex verbs and certain complex predicate structures, as the following

examples - G&HU9ÔÔ) (76)a.-c. - illustrate:

( 174) a. Je Jj aJ fej vu ej 1

b. Je Jej ferai! ypJire ej/

c. Loj voglio / yp/eggere ej /

Page 165: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

G&H grant a biclausal status to complex predicate constructions in the

syntax, which allows for general principles of the framework, to be

maintained, for instance, that the external theta-role is assigned to the NP

in subject position via INFL - p. 65 (67) -:

Í175) The external theta-roie is assigned to INFL by VP

The Visibility condition wiii aiiow ÁGR in Infi to retain the theta-role

assigned to it - and not transmit it to the subject position as long as it is

assigned Case - cf. below for constructions of modals and causatives where

this is assumed to take place -.

T-marking, as noted, implies the formation of a T-chain, and there

are several aspects of this phenomenon which also involve the

constructions of complex predicates. Most of these coincide with those

noted for complex verbs; i.e. the fact that a path is created for the

percolation of features, and that extension of chains is possible, allowing for

clitic climbing and NP-raising. Crucially, though, the fact that each CP

introduces a new T-index is only relevant for complex predicates, where an

extended chain is only possible if T-marking takes place and CP is

construed as a verbal projection.

Note the following examples of both, a causative and a modal

complex predicate structure, which G&H(19ôÔ) - (95X96) - analyze as VP

construal ; as noted in section 3.4.1.1, the fact that there is participle

agreement implies that an NP or clitic goes through SC subject position

interpreted as VP at LF; i.e. governed by an auxiliary : fare, and volere in

this case.

(176) a. Man'sfu faitsinvitare

b. Mariai {ypi fu ÍVP2 &i fstta fypj invitare ei / / /

Page 166: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

(177) a. Marls e voluta tornare a casa b. Mariai ívpj è í VP2 <?/ voluta f ypj tomare ei a casa / / /

Causatives as auxiliaries

G&H posit that French and Italian - the two languages on which they

focus - causatives are auxiliaries, and I will assume the same holds for

Catalan and Spanish. They also assume that English maÉe/let have an

auxiliary status, as will be illustrated below.

As noted, a consequence of the formation of a T-chain is that all the

Vs which intervene between an extracted element and its original position

must be auxiliaries - except the last one -, otherwise, there would be no

passing on of the T-index, and antecedent government would not hold. The

following examples show that this holds for French - G&H (173)a. - Catalan,

and Spanish for clitic climbing, but (Iô2)-(lô4) show that it only holds for

Italian for NP-raising - a fact unexplained in the framework-:

( 176) a. ft lalfalt voir

fc>- ft Í VP1 ii 'si / YP2 fait { ypj voir ei III

(179)a. La vaig fer llegir

b. ÍVP1 Lsi vaig í VP2 fer ( ypj itegir ei III

(100)a. L'lie fet llegir

b. / ypi L l'he [ VP2 fet [ VPJ Hegir ei III

( 1 ô 1 ) a. La ha hecho leer

b. / VPI Lai A? / VP2 he±o [ ypj leer ei III

(1Ô2) a. 1 llbrl furono fattl leggere

Page 167: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

b. llibriiypi fnroj2ûfvP2 ejfattifypj ej leggereei///

( 103) *&s llibres van serfetsllegir

( 104) *Loslibrosfueronneones leer ̂ 0,4. 1

The auxiliary status oi the causative faire is claimed to be

independently supported by G&H by several facts. One of these is the fact

that it allows VP anaphora. They cite Zribri-Hertz (1966) in claiming that

auxiliaries are those elements which may carry the tense of a null VP. Note

that this is in contradiction with the examples of section 2.1 and 2.1.2

which show that null VP is allowed by main verbs - (ô5)p. 174 G&H ( 19ÔÔ):

( 105) feao $ Í acnetédupain fee matin et

Pierre lejfera ej ce soir

Catalan and Spanish causatives have the same possibility:

( 156) En Joan Carlesna marxat aquêstmatfJ

la lsabel no farà aquesta tarda

( 167) Juan Alberto cocinó 'morallasayerporla noene

y José Marià lo Mará mañana

These facts, apart from possibly being independent evidence for the

status of faire/fer/nacer as auxiliaries - if we assume G&H's arguments -

are evidence showing that faire is a "support" verb in the three languages

mentioned. Note that for the hypothesis given in this thesis, the facts do not

disclaim it: the only reason why the auxiliary verbs in Catalan and Spanish

do not allow VP anaphora may be explained by the fact that they undergo

Page 168: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

obligatory incorporation, as opposed to a verb like the causative, which is

not part of a complex verb, but rather a complex predicate.

Another fact that G&H take into account as evidence for iet being an

auxiliary is that it takes a bare infinitival, supposedly a VP:

(lôô)a. They M /ypNoemaieave ]

b. * They iet Noema to leave

As opposed to French fairs Catalan fer, and Spanish hacer,

make/iet/iaisser are structural case assigners, so they can assign structural

case to the subject of their complement - even if it is contrued as a VP SC -

( 169) We made the students sit in rows

(190) Mous avons iaisséies étudiants sassoiri Iw derrière i'autre

(191) *Nous avons fait ies étudiants sassoirilw derrière i autre

(192) *Hem fet eis estudiants seure i'un darrera i'aitre

(193) * ¿femes hecho ios estudiantes sentarse en fila

Catalan and Spanish also have a causative predicate which allows

structural Case assignment of the subject of its subcategorized clause:

deisar/dejar: Deijca ai teu fifi venir amt> nosaitres //Deja a W hijo vivir

comoquiera.

In 3.4.3.2 this fact will be expanded and explained; the fact that the

theta-roles of the complement of the causative are all assigned within the

complement is a consequence of the type of auxiliary it is, which has a

specific type of complement.

Page 169: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

Modals as auxiliaries

Note that there are constructions in which modals function as lexical

verbs and constructions in which they are auxiliaries. As G&H point out,

they have many of the properties of auxiliaries that HAVE and BE have

over languages. In English, they occupy the INFL position and raise to

COMP, like other auxiliaries. No question has been raised as to the auxiliary

status of modals in English. Putting it differently, the fact is that we may

not find equivalent "restructuring" constructions in English as there is no

independent motivation for a "double nature", as there is in the Romance

languages considered here.

G&H allude to Pollock (19Ô7) - cf. Chapter 4 - in claiming that modals

in French are auxiliaries as they raise to INFL, like other auxiliary elements

in the language, and unlike lexical verbs. They reinterpret this in their

framework by granting them the ability of T-marking, thus, of being

auxiliary verbs in certain constructions. - ( 194)a. and b. are ( 19 l)d and f. in

G&H) and the contrast */? is an argument for giving the two verbs, pouvoir

and croire a different status -:

(194) a. ! Il pensait [ jp PRO no pouvoirj [yppastj dormir ici II

b * II pensait [jp PEO no croiroi

/ yppas ti aus histoires ¿to fan tomos / /

Again, the fact that modals may introduce a null VP is given as

evidence for their auxiliary status -(195) is adapted from G&H's ( 192) -:

( 195) Pierre voudrait aixorder le piano

a. mais il ne peut/Veut/doitpas ¡ypie faire ]

Page 170: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

b. maisilnepeutsveut/doitpas

c. * mais il ne croit/dédde pas

If the assumption that auxiliaries may be tense carriers in Romance

languages, and, thus, may introduce a null VP; the facts follow since, again,

in the case of modals, incorporation is not assumed to have taken place - as

they are complex predicates, and not complex verbs in the following

examples - :

(196) Es Fere volaría afinar elplano

a. però no pot/vol/VP fer-ho J

b. però nopotMoJ

c. *perànocreu/decideLY

( 197) Podro querría afinar eJpiano

a. pero no quiere/puede í VP hacerlo /

b. pero no quiere/puede

c. * pero no cree /decide

G&H assume that clitic climbing is possible in Italian in modal

structures because their complements may be construed as VPs at LF; if the

clitic remains in its original position, there is no VP construal. The way I

interpret this is that if the modal functions as an auxiliary, - thus, as a T-

marker- there is clitic climbing, and VP construal - by the FDC - takes place.

On the other hand, if the modal 'does not T-mark its complement, but

instead assigns Case to it - i.e. functioning as a lexical verb - then there is

no VP construal, but rather its complement is interpreted as an argument,

instead of a predicate.

Page 171: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

Root modals assign an external theta-roie, accusative case F, and

optionally an internal theta-role. On the basis of which element retains

Case F, the basic distinction noted in the "restructuring" literature is made

in G&H's framework. Basically, two options are possible for Case F: a) that

IP retains it, and, thus, that IP is construed as an argument by the FDC; b)

that Case F is absorbed by I and, by Visibility, Agr may retain the external

theta-roie assigned via IHFL. In this case, Ágr is a pronominal. V raises to Ï,

and IP is construed - by the FDC - as a verbal complement. Another

assumption they also make is that a modal must control an ec in their

embedded SC complement. The a) option is illustrated by (195), and b) by

(199)-(193H194)-:

(19Ô) Marioj vuotefjp PWj [j'fyp loggore il libro ] 11

theta-1 theta-1

(199) Marioj vuote {jp leggoroj [ yp tj il libro 11

theta-1 theta- \\

As illustrated and explained in 2.4, the ECP blocks clitic climbing

when the modal does not function as an auxiliary, (196) ; i.e. there are two

different T-chains, so antecedent government does not hold. Whenever

there is clitic climbing, the modal imitions as a T-marker, and by T-chain

formation, the embedded verb antecede-governs the ec. Therefore, the

account is parallel for complex predicate and complex verb structures.

Note, though, that even if there is the possibility of a modal

functioning as a T-marker - an auxiliary -, it is still necessary to have an IP

in the syntax, although it is construed as a VP in LF; an INFL node accounts

for Control in modal structures, where agr is assumed to function as a

syntactic argument.

Page 172: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

The lack oí clitic climbing in modal structures in French - cf. also 2.4

- is attributed to the pro-drop parameter. Basically, where Italian has an

inflectional argument position in INFL - finite clauses and modal

structures-, French needs a Spec-IP argument position, which prevents the

formation of a T-chain. The position is syntactically active because it is

subject to a syntactic rule like Control. Hence, the difference with causative

structures, where French allows clitic climbing; the pronominal in AGR is

not syntactically active, it is not an A-position.

Epistemic modals are analyzed in a parallel fashion - but cf. 3.4.3.2

for a different proposal for epistemic modals -; they also have both options

although they do not assign an external theta-role. The AGR in INFL may

absorb Case F of the verb, but in this case, it functions as an expletive

pronoun, not PRO. IP is construed as VP in LF. In French, the modal, again,

does not have the ability of T-marking; it assigns Case to the IP , which is

construed as an argument in LF.

In Catalan and Spanish, modals may also be claimed to have the

possibility of functioning as auxiliaries; i.e. to have the ability of T-marking,

on the basis of the fact that they allow clitic climbing, which by T-chain

formation, ensures antecedent government:

(200) a. La MariaJosep la j vol* [ yp llegir *: ejf

b. En Josep Maria noi deuJ [yp agrentendreJejf

(2 01} a. Juan Carlos Ay quiere ¿Y ypleer¿ ei /

b. Carmen loi debe1 [yp entender1 eil

To sum up, a point in common that LF-incorporation'and T-theory

have as regards complex predicates is that they both posit a biclausal

structure , and, thus, an identical D-structure for all types of complex

Page 173: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

predicates. An important difference - which I have used to attempt an

invalidation of LF incorporation in favour of T-theory- is that I-theory

with respect to complex predicates alludes to a specific sort of movement

versus awstnmJ posited in T-theory, which is , to my mind more in line

with the present framework.

3-4.3 Neutral auxiliaries / T-auxiliaries and incorporation

3.4.3.1 Properties of N(eutral)- auxiliaries and T-auxiliaries

All auxiliaries assign a T-index; i.e. T-mark/- or pass on a T-index -

to a non-finite VP complement; nevertheless, there are systematic

properties across and within languages of different auxiliary items that

suggest a classification into basically two different types of auxiliaries:

N(eutral)-auxiliaries and T-auxiliaries. In this section I will review some of

these properties - cf. also 2.4 -. HAVE will be taken as the paradigmatic

example of a Neutral-auxiliary; BE as the corresponding T-auxiliary. The

differences will obviously become important when I reconsider complex

verb and complex predicate structures in section 3.4.3.2 .

N-auxiliaries combine with the tense morpheme of its VP

complement to form a complex tense morpheme, which defines the tense of

the S 42 T-auxiliaries govern a VP with an independent tense morpheme.

G6:H refer to this as the assignment of a T-role. T-auxiliaries, thus, asign T-

roles, whereas N-auxiliaries do not assign T-roles. G&H make a difference

between theta-roles, assigned by lexical verbs, and T-roles assigned by T-

auxiliaries: T-roles give an independent tense value to their complement;

theta-roles give a referential value to their complement. Another difference

between the two auxiliary types is that T-auxiliaries have the possibility of

Page 174: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

assigning structural case, whereas N-auxiliaries do not, as the following

example shows-.p.4ô (33)b. - In the following example HAVE is an instance

of a causative construction:

(202) John had fnJsnouse burned I

Note that the same lexical item, in this case HAVE, may be a T-

auxiliary or a N-auxiliary in different contexts. - as already noted in 2.4 -.

The other crucial difference between N-auxiliaries and T-auxiliaries is that

the former allow percolation of the theta-role assigned by the VP

complement main verb - assigned to NP subject by subj-I agreement ;

indirectly by I. A T-auxiliary does not allow percolation of theta-roles

assigned in its complement. This is related to the notion of Complete

Thematic Constituent 43, repeated here - (30) p.4ô -:

(203) An XP which is assigned a T-role is a Complete Thematic

Constituent (CTC): all theta-roles associated with X, the head

of XP, are assigned internal to XP.

The following examples form G&H ( p. 49(35X(36) and(37) ) illustrate

the difference:

(204) John[j-1[vphas[ VPlaughed///

theta-1

(205) fohnj was f $j seen e//

theta-1 theta-2

(206) /eanjest [ ej venu ej/

theta-1

Page 175: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

In (204) the theta-role percolates, as indicated by the arrows. In

(205) and (206), all theta-roles are assigned within the complement of the

T-aux, BE.

As a reminder of G&H"s auxiliary restrictions, which will also become

relevant in the next section, I will repeat here the general restrictions on

auxiliaries (p.50, (40):

(207) a. A T-chain may not contain two auxiliaries of the same class,

b. Neutral auxiliaries precede T-auxiliaries.

In the next section I will propose - with the exception of epistemic

modal verbs - that those lexical verbs which may also function as

auxiliaries, those in complex predicate structures, may only function as T'­

auxiliaries not as N-auxiliaries.

3.4.3.2 N- auxiliaries and T-auxiliaries in complex verb and complex

predicate structures

The hypothesis that I will propose in this section is that the complex

verb sequences considered in this thesis are made up of neutral auxiliaries

and that neutral auxiliaries in Catalan and Spanish trigger obligatory

incorporation. They are made up of N-aux precisely because these allow

percolation of theta-role from the lower verb to the matrix subject position.

As noted, this is one of the basic properties of N-auxiliaries and a

fundamental property of complex verbs as opposed to complex predicates;

i.e. only complex verbs have one theta-grid - as explained in Chapter 2 ; cf.

"selectional restrictions" test.

Page 176: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

G&H point to the fact that Eater but not avoir is always a neutral

auxiliary-(10Ô) p. 70-:

(206) HAVE is solely a neutral auxiliary in Spanish but either a

neutral or a T-auxiliary in French

In French they posit that it is a neutral auxiliary in its temporal

aspect, but a T-auxiliary in - (109) in G&H -:

(209) a. Ele a deuxfrères

b. We a son fils malade

They link this with the fact that in Spanish HAVE may never have a

lexical meaning, as the corresponding translations of the French sentences

show -G&H (110)-:

(210) a. *Ha dosHermanos

b. *Ha su È1 jo enfermo

Note that the consideration that one lexical item may function as one

type or another type of auxiliary in one context or another, plus their

relating it with the fact that it may or may not have a lexical meaning links

up with the main hypothesis in this thesis that N-auxiliaries trigger

obligatory incorporation in Catalan and Spanish but not in English nor

French; in Catalan and Spanish - as noted above - they may never function

as lexical verbs; in English and French, they may. I repeat here an

illustration of a complex verb sequence where the theta-role is assigned to

the NP in subject position via INFL, by the percolation through the N-

auxiliary, HAVE, and the corresponding Catalan and Spanish translations:

Page 177: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

(211 ) a. John Ij'Iívp has { yplaughed HI

~^L_-theta-l b. En Joan / / • J [ypha { yp rigut 11

I——theta-1

c./uan fj'If ypha í yp reído //

i theta-1

In preceding sections, I have been giving examples oí another

complex verb sequence in Catalan , which is equivalent to the simple past,

but is made up of a sequence of verbs: anar * infinitive. By the examples

given so far, it must be concluded that this auxiliary also triggers obligatory

incorporation in this sequence, so it should be an N-auxiliary if my

hypothesis is correct. Nevertheless, I have alluded to the lack of lexical

meaning in both Catalan and Spanish of the N- auxiliary HAVE, precisely as

a factor that might contribute to its triggering incorporation - as opposed to

English and French HAVE -. The fact that anar has not lost its lexical

meaning, and yet, it triggers obligatory incorporation may be related to the

different development in Catalan as opposed to other Romance languages of

the verb anar+ infinitive. In Catalan it has developed into a simple past

equivalent - the one form simple past is practically out of use -, whereas in

other Romance languages it has developed into a periphrastic future

aspectual sequence.^

Note that one of the basic properties of an N-auxiliary, apart from

allowing the percolation of the external theta-role of the V heading the

main VP, is that they " combine with the tense morpheme of their

complement to form a complex tense morpheme defining the tense of S ", as

Page 178: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

opposed to T-auxtlianes which " govern a VP with an independent tense

morpheme" (p.4ô). An illustration of the fact that this "periphrastic" simple

past allows percolation of the external theta role is that there are no reason

to claim a biclausal structure, as in the example; it combines with the tense

morpheme of its complement :

(2 í 2) En Joan ¡i • /•* / VP va ¿ í VP riure & /

theta-1

The hypothesis in this section as regards complex predicates - when

they arise - is that they are made up of T-auxiliaries and they do not

trigger obligatory incorporation - with the exception of epistemic modal

verbs -. When the first verb in a sequence of a complex predicate functions

as a main verb, its complement is interpreted as an argument, when it is an

auxiliary, its complement is interpreted as part of a aimpJ&Ypr#tâc3te.45

The fact that there are two theta-grids in some sequences of

complex predicates, and these are still construed as VPs at LF is not a

problem for G&H's framework by their introduction of their concept of T-

auxiliary and of CTC - cf. (219) below - plus the possibility of assigning a

theta-role to AGR in INFL - as explained in 3.4.2.2 - Basically, when the

Case assigned by the verb is absorbed by the I, AGR functions as a

pronominal, retaining the external theta-role.

Note that in complex predicate verbal sequences incoporation should

not be posited because their degree of separatibility shows that they are

not an amalgamated unit. Nevertheless, the VP dominating a main verb

may still be devoided of barrierhood by T-marking, so incorporation is

predicted possible. Nevertheless, it is the fact that the complement of a T-

aux in causative and restructuring constructions is construed as a VP at LF

Page 179: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

which makes syntactic incorporation unmotivated, thus allowing preposing

and clitic climbing :

(213)a. (VP1 V-1 Icp IIP (VP2 V-2 NP ] ] ] ] S-structure

b.lypiV-llvP2 V-2 NPH LF

At S-structure, V-1 may T-mark VP2, so V-2 can move and NP can

also "climb" out. Interruption by lexical elements is also predicted possible

by the assumption that incorporation does not apply - cf. HOC, section 3-2 ;

there is no "opaque" constituent -j adjunction sites for adverbs are

available.

I will thus assume that in Catalan and Spanish complex predicate

structures the T-auxiliary does not trigger obligatory incorporation.

According to G&H, the fact that causatives are T-aux is supported by

the following ungrammatical examples, which follow from independent

ordering and distribution restrictions on auxiliaries - cf. 3.4.1 and 2.4 -

(G&H(25)and(26):

(214) * /e fais [ vp avoir [ yp travaille Marie II

T-aux N-aux

(215) *Imad&[yp Mary be wording I

T-aux T-aux

*

As they point out for English, if the causative were not considered an

auxiliary, but a lexical verb, it would have no access to the auxiliary

structure of its complement. The same holds for Catalan and Spanish:

Page 180: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

(216) *ßä [ yp haver [yp treballat la Maria II

(217) *Hace { yphaber / yp trabajado (a)Maria II

As noted, the complement of a causative is a CTC, which is what

defines it, basically, as a T-aux. If the causative is not a structural case

assigner - such as make/let - so that the subject in the complement cannot

be assigned a theta-role, " the grammar contains alternative strategies to

ensure that the complement of the causative is a CTC" ( p. 56 ). As already

explained in previous sections - especially 3-4.1.1 -, this is basically the

reason why IP is still postulated in the syntax, so that the I node can

absorb Case F, and the AGR in INFL may function as a pronominal, taking

up the external theta-role assigned by the main verb. VP construal is

ensured in LF.

G&H account for the different types of causatives - cf. section 2.3, and

basically Kayne (1975) - in different ways. Basically, the /«r-construction

is seen as a doubling of the external argument, as in passive by- phrases;

the FI construction is regarded as involving Aux-to-Comp - V raises to

assign Case to its own subject -, because faire is not a structural case

assigner. The external theta-role is assigned to the dative NP embedded

under IP2 - (lôô)p. Ô9-.

Page 181: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

(21Ô)

lire ej aux enfants

Quoting G&H: " Silice V1 T-marks IP2, there is no barrier between the

clitic tej and its trace. IP2 receives no case from faire and is construed as

VP in LF. V2 is then part of the same T-chain as the matrix causative. Since

V2 bears the same index as the matrix verb which carries the clitic, ej is

antecedent-governed." (p. 59)

G&H do not classify modals «as either N-auxiliaries or T-auxiliaries.

Nevertheless, given the definition of CTC; repeated here:

(219) An XP which is assigned a T-role is a Complete Thematic

Constituent (CTC): all theta-roles associated with X, the head

of XP, are assigned internal to XP.

Page 182: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

Root modals can be claimed to be T-auxiliaries: when they function as

auxiliaries, despite the fact that they assign an external theta-role, this

same theta-role is borne by the PRO in their complement, which is a

possible interpretation of the CTC requirements. It is true that root modals

do not satisfy another of the characteristics of T-auxiliaries; i.e. that they

may be structural case assigners, but G&H do assume that they have a Case

F to assign which may be absorbed by INFL and give rise to a complex

predicate structure, as explained in the previous section.

The same cannot be claimed for epistemic modal verbs , which do

not impose selectional restrictions on the matrix subject -i.e. they do not

assign an external theta-role, - cf. 2.3 especially Picallo (19Ô5) -- In this

sense, they function more like complex verb sequences. Picallo (1990)

argues against their being considered raising verbs and allows them to be

generated in a different, inflectional, node. Assuming this might lead to a

postulation of a different structure for epistemic modals - as in Picallo

(19Ô5)-(1990) ; i.e. not involving a biclausal structure. Nevertheless, it is

possible to still grant them a "typical" complex predicate structure in the

syntax - i.e. a biclausal structure; cf. 2.2.1 - and assume that syntactic

incorporation takes place following the HMC; as there is no need for the

whole VP to move. Recall that Baker's main reason to claim that the whole

VP moves was the fact that the subject of a transitive causative complex

predicate surfaced as oblique. He nevertheless does not posit such a

movement for intransitive structures - cf. section 3.3.2 -. Note that in modal

complex predicate structures, precisely, subjects do not surface.

In favour of Picallo's hypothesis is the fact that one of the original

claims - cf. 2.1.2 - for postulating a biclausal status for modal sequences is

not obtained with modal epistemic verbs. Quoting Picallo (1990):

" Epistemic modals are the only type of predicates ( verbal or adjectival)

Page 183: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

that do not assign a theta-role to the subject position, and cannot

subcategorize for [+AGR] sentential complements (indicative or

subjunctive)." (p.295):

(7ô)a. *P¿>¿ que no em trobin quan tornin 46

b. *ßeu que en Pavarotti canti a IFstadi Olimpio

(79) *Bebe que José María no se acuerde demi

Moreover, the fact that they do not contribute to theta-role

assignment of the external argument of the predicate seems to me a crucial

piece of evidence to classify them as constituting complex verbs as opposed

to complex predicates.

Given the above observations, I will claim that epistemic modals are

N-auxiliaries, displaying the typical behaviour of an N-aux in that they

allow for the percolation of the theta-role assigned by the main verb. Now,

if epistemic modal verbs are claimed to be neutral auxiliaries, then they

should trigger obligatory incorporation, as other N-auxiliaries in Catalan

and Spanish do. This prediction seems to be borne out by the fact that

dividing complex predicates made up of epistemic modals - or modals with

an epistemic modal reading - gives rise to ungrammatical structures,

whereas those made up of root modals do not:47,4ô

Consider some examples of interruption and preposing in Catalan and

Spanish with epistemic and root modal verbs:

a) (epistemic)

(222) *M'han dit que en Pavarotti M de cantar a liceu, però

cantar no deu

(2 2 3) *?Peu sempre marjztr desprès de classe

(224) * Encara que el Joan sigui mal conductor, tenir un accident per

la Meridiana no pot

Page 184: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

(2255* Aunque Pepita sea mala cocinera, quedar tan mal con sus

invitados no puede

(226)?? Debe a menudo salir corriendo después de classe

b) (root)

(227) a.(?) No podria, de cap manera, viiwe a Anglaterra

X>.ll Bisabet.pot dissenyar plans d édifias amb el seu ordinador

pero imprimir-los no pot.

(2 2 ô)a.? Tengo unas ganas de poder un dia dormir 12ñoras seguidas/

b. ? Juan Alberto puede pilotar aviones con su ordenador, pero

los de verdad, pilotarlos no puede

I repeat here the examples where VP anaphora was considered a

property of modals being auxiliaries. Note that these are also root modals:

( 196) En Pere voldria afinar el piano

a. però no pot/volIyp fer-ho I

b. però nopotsvol

c. *però no creu/deddeiK

( 197) Pedro querría afinar el piano

a. pero no quiere/puede / ¡/placerlo /

b. pero no quiere/puede

c. * pero no cree /decide

Page 185: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

A note on English T- and N- auxiliaries

As postulated also in G&H's framework the classification into T-

auxiliaries and neutral auxiliaries is also applied to English. The patent

differences with Catalan and Spanish obviously call for an explanation. G&H

themselves point out that " auxiliary verbs do not have the same syntactic

properties over or within languages" (p.47). It was already noted - cf.

section 2.4 - that Italian essere, although it is a T-auxiliary, may refrain

from assigning its T-role, while another T-auxiliary, English ¿>e, may not. It

is evident that the fact that there are properties which are shared and

constant over languages is what has brought G&H to their dual classification

of auxiliaries.

In this section I have linked the notion of W-auxiliary with the

triggering of obligatory incorporation; i.e. in complex verb structures - and,

possibly in epistemic verb structures -. English N-auxiliaries obviously do

not trigger incorporation - cf. the differences pointed out in section 3.3-1.4-.

English HAVE, the paradigmatic N- auxiliary, when occurring in equivalent

complex verb structures, does not prevent interruption nor disallow

preposing; moreover, there is not even marginality in the preposing

examples of complex verb sequences in English, so incorporation is utterly

unmotivated :

(2 2 9) My son said he had passed his examination and

passed it he has

(2 30) *E! seu fill va dir-Jj que havia passat l'examen i passat 1 ha

(231) * Su hijo le di/o que haMa pasado el examen y pasado lo ha

Page 186: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

Note also that English has the support vert» do which has no

equivalent in Catalan or Spanish, since even in preposing examples of

simple past - which needs do-support in English -, the use oí a substitute

verb in Catalan and Spanish does not give rise to grammatical results:

(232) I/o said ño would jump ovor tno balcony., andjump no did/

(233) * Va dir quo saltaria pol balcó i saltar va (fer)

(2 34) *I)jjo quo saltar/à por ol balcon y saltar t'ñisoj

The fact that the past participle and the auxiliary form an X-0

constituent - i.e. as well as in the other Catalan complex verb sequence

analyzed in this thesis, anar + infinitive - is a language particular fact

about Catalan and Spanish. Note, though, that this cannot be extended to

other Romance languages, nor to pro-drop languages: as for the first

observation, French, a Romance language, is obviously a non-V-

incorporation language:

(235) p£ 'aipas /jamais/ encoró vu uno cnoso aussi atroco

And as for the second observation, Italian, a Romance and pro-drop

language, is also a non -obligatory -V -incorporation language - cf. also

section 3.3.I.4 for a summary of Belletti (1990) -:

(236) Non no mal visto queseo

The lack of lexical meaning of the verbal elements ñavor/Mbor has

already been alluded to in claiming their status as a clitic - cf. section

3.3.I.I -, and as a factor which, to my mind, is crucial in the triggering of

obligatory incorporation. This stands in clear constrast with English, French

Page 187: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

and Italian where the equivalents for HAVE have not lost their lexical

meaning.

As regards complex predicates in English an important difference

must be noted. Firstly, modals are INFL elments, so no equivalent modal

"restructuring" constructions are found in the language. Aspectual complex

verb sequences give the same results in English, Catalan, and Spanish,

which is predicted by the fact that there is no incorporation in any of the

three languages in these sequences.49,50

(237) / said I would begin to dance,, and to dance 1 will begin

(2 30) Us ne dit çue començaria a bailari a bailar començaré

(239) Os dije çue empezaría a bailar y a bailar empezaré

As regards causative sequences in English, it has already been

explained and shown - cf. 2.3.1 - that there is no equivalent configuration

to the Romance causative complex predicate sequences. Nevertheless, G&H

posit that English causatives are T-auxiliaries which have the ability to

assign structural case to the subject of their SC complement.

Again the hypothesis of non-incorporation accounts for the fact that

preposing gives grammatical results in English:

(240) We tñougnt sne would ma^e mm sing, and sing sne made Mm

But interruption results in ungrammmaticality:

(241)* Sne mal-es always ner nusband sing

Page 188: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

This may be accounted for by StowelK 19Ô D's Case adjacency Priciple

which holds for English, and would rule the sequence out.

Note that Spanish and Catalan perception verbs - also noted as

candidates for complex predicate sequences - may also be assumed to be

structural case assigners, which is not incompatible with their possible T-

auxiliary status:

(242) Juan vio a María salir del coche

(243) En Joan va pleure (à) Ja Maria sortir del cotxe

Note that non-syntactic incorporation predicts interruption and

preposing to be ( at least marginally) acceptable:

(2 44)a.? Juan creyó ver a María salir del coche, pero en realidad

salir no la vio

b. Juan vio sin ninguna duda a Maria salir del coche

(245) a. ? En Joan va creure que vela a la Maria sortir del cotse.però

de fet sortir no la va veure

b. En Joan va veure sense cap mena de duMe a la Maria sortir

delcotse

Page 189: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

Notes to Chapter 3

(1) This brief "note" does not intend to go further than this observation. See

section 3.3.1.1 for comments and reference to ctitJazatÀw, which is,

obviously "behind" this observation.

(2) As will become clear in the la ter sections, he does not use the term

JnœrporatÂw in Baker's sense.

(3) Aarts ( 19Ô9) argues against analyses of this type for such constructions

- and others - positing instead a rightward NP movement adjunction to VP

- instead of incorporation - and small clause subcategorization.

(4) Crucially, as will be noted in section 3.3.1, this principle does not hold of

the verbal sequences under analysis in that section.

(5) This, again, will not be relevant for the sequences under analysis for

Romance languages - cf. section 3.3.1 -, where morphology is not as

productive as in agglutinating languages.

(6) Baker's account of passive is summarized in Note (3D. There he

proposes abstract (LF) - mœrpûratÀw.

(7) See Spencer (forthcoming), and Ouhalla (1990) for a review and critical

analysis of Baker ( 1986).

(Ô) His theory is based on the barriers framework - cf. section 1.2.2 -, with

several modifications that will be included if they are relevant to the

explanation.

Page 190: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

(9) See section 3.3.1.4 for some comments on language variation; namely,

differences among Italian, French, and English with respect to Catalan and

Spanish.

( iô) Baker uses S/'S: notation, I wiii keep to this usage for simplicity

reasons.

( 11) See (34) in the text for the notion of distinctness.

( 12) In 3.4 we will be led to the assumption that in complex verb

structures, T-marking- G&H ( 19ÔÔ)- is a sufficient requirement for

incorporation in complex verb sequences; there will be no need to allude to

theta-indexing of VPs.

( 13) I must note that I will be omitting for the most part a more complex

phrase structure posited basically in Pollock ( 19Ô7), until Chapter 4, for

simplicity reasons. The structure I am referring to is one which includes

more functional nodes in the phrase structure. See note (25) below.

(14) Note that the VA sequence is not found in Spanish; the "simple past" is

expressed only through the use of the inflected form of the main verb:

(i) Imprimió el documento

(ii)a. Imprimí el document

b. Va imprimir el document

The use of the verb ir with an infinitive in Spanish, Va a imprimir, is a

future aspectual periphrastic sequence, or a sequence of two main verbs -

cf. section 2.1.1, Test 7-

Page 191: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

(15) This could obviously be argued to be a counterexample to the modified

HOC ,(54) in the text.

( 16) As already noted in the review of literature on complex predicates,

there are many views on how clitic+host sequences are to be characterized;

the two basic positions are represented by Kayne (1975), Rizzi (19Ô2),

Aoun ( 19Ô5) - movement - among others, and Borer (1964), Jaeggli ( 19Ô2)

- base-generation - among others.

(17) In this section - cf also note (13) - I will not make use of a more

complex structure where participles are dominated by a non-lexical node,

as in Belletti (1990) - although I will mention her structure in section

3-3.1.4 - The same issue arises in 3.4, as will be noted, cf. Note (25) -

( 16) In the revised version of the paper - Manzini ( 19ÔÔ) - an identical

structure is not posited. Nevertheless, I have included it because it is in line

with the structure proposed in this thesis for complex verbs in Catalan and

Spanish, as well as English.

(19) This obviously does not apply to VP-adjunction in extraction

structures, a basic mechanism in Barriers - cf. section 1.2.2 -

(20) I will not go into the details of the type of indexing involved in these

VP complements; nevertheless, as stated in 3-4, T-marking will be assumed

to subsume theta-indexing in complex verb structures

(21) pas- may be argued to be a clitic in these constructions - i.e. where it

"interrupts" a complex verb -, as it clearly does not bear stress.

Page 192: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

Nevertheless, ií pas follows the complex verb sequence, it may bear stress

-: None vist pas la nena.

It must also be noted that there is another element which may

marginally interrupt the sequence both in Catalan and in Spanish, ni:

(i)? No nan ni provat la sopa

(ii)? No nan ni probado la sopa

As pointed out to me by J.M. Brucart, both of these elements are

negative scope-markers, a fact which may bear on the explanation of their

position next to a lexical head; i.e. a head which may be negated.

(22) A possibly related fact may come from the English infinitival form,

where to * V are not morphophonologically amalgamated, and a certain

degree of non-cohesiveness seems possible:

(i)?? / want tú really go there/

Exampies in Pollock (19Ô7), to which he refers for other reasons may

bear on this issue - (27) in Pollock - :

(ii) To hardly understand Italian after years of hard work moans you

have no gift for languages

(23) in the case where a verb is not subcategorized for, or does not select,

a VP, LF incorporation is not necessary - possibly not even needed, as will

be argued for in 3.4 -.

*

(24) This structure is based on recent proposals summarized in Chapter 4 -

especially section 4.2 -. Basically, the INFL (I) node - cf. 1.1, 1.2.2 - which

was assumed to be the head of S ( = IP ) is now fleshed out into two other

distinct functional heads, AGR(eement) and T(ense), each of which has its

own maximal projection, AGRP, and TP. The order of these categories is a

matter of debate. I have included this specific structure in an attempt to

Page 193: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

answer the problem of the bearing of inflectional affixes by V1 and not by

V2 in complex verb sequences. For further explanation and comments on

this new structure see Chapter 4, section 4.2.

(25) Belletti's structure includes a functional node, AGR, above the VP

participle projection. I have included the whole structure for the sake of

faithfulness to the text which is being commented on. Nevertheless, I will

be disregarding the possible intervention of a functional node between the

auxiliary and the non-finite form in a complex verb sequence until Chapter

4 , where it is briefly touched upon in section 4.3. As argued in section

3-3.1.2,1 am assuming a consecutive VP-VP structure. - cf. also Notes (13)

and (17)-.

(26) By referring to "content" lexical status I am deliberately not alluding to

the difference between lexical/functional nodes. Note that although not

"content" lexical, I assume that auxiliaries in complex verb sequences are

generated in V lexical nodes.

(27) Note that the ? marks are included in parentheses because there is

variation in the acceptability of all of these examples; for some speakers

they are wholly acceptable, for others they are not.

(20) Note that this differs from Chomsky ( 19ô6b)'s analysis of passive: BE

moves to INFL, but the lexical verb remains in its original position - cf.

section 1.2.2 -.

(29) Baker distinguishes between Chichewa-A, as opposed to Chichewa-B,

which differ in their case parameters. Only Chichewa-A follows rule (232)

in text.

Page 194: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

(30) Chichewa and Malayalam have another crucial objecthood test: verb

object agreement. They also have passivization, but they lack cliticization.

Actually, clitics may be regarded as a kind of object agreement.

(3D As Baker points out - p. 463, in. 36" -, this second test does not work

for all Romance languages - cf. also section 3.4 -.

(32) Bakers analysis of passivizatJon, a crucial GF changing phenomenon

also involves the assumption that there is abstract Jncûrporatjon, in this

case of V-to-I; i.e. of a lexical to a non-lexical node, both in English and

Romance. Passivization is, thus, argued to be a syntactic and not a

morphological phenomenon - Note that here I am not alluding to the

distinction made by Wasow (1977) between lexical/syntactic passive, as

noted in section 2.2.1, and cf. also 3.1 and the explanation of the Mirror

Principle in that section -. The fact that both morphological and copular

passive are attested in the languages of the world is regarded as - on a par

with causativization - as a consequence of the fact that incorporation may

apply at different levels of the grammar: in Chichewa, for instance,

passivization is morphological and thus an instance of incorporation from D-

structure to S-structure; but in English or Romance, passivization is copular

so an instance of LF incoporation. Both, nevertheless - as required by the

UTAH - have an identical D-structure.

Baker assumes that the PASS morpheme is a nominal element,

generated in INFL, as in (i), and is assigned - i.e. it does not absorb, as in

other accounts - the external theta-role.

Page 195: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

Vi NP

steal

The fact that a thematic nominal element is present is argued by

Baker on the basis oí evidence from Binding, Control and secondary

predication; i.e. it is syntactically active. Note that the fact that the external

theta-role is assigned to the PASS morpheme in INFL frees the NPsubj

position from thematic status and allows NP-movement.

The way a nominal element in INFL acquires case varies. In languages

where this nominal element is I it is by the asssignment of case by the V

which incorporates into INFL. The implicitly assumed principle that Baker

makes explicit: No category may assign case to itself implies that if the

PASS morpheme is I, it will not get case unless the verb has a case to assign

- which predicts the fact that only accusative-assigning verbs may be

passivized. Baker accounts for the fact that there are languages which allow

passivization of non-accusative verbs by positing variation in the category

type of nominal element in INFL.

(33) No reference to the structures showing the application of incorporation

will be given until section 3-4.1.2.

(34) See Pollock ( 19Ô7), and Chapter 4 for V-rnovement in French and

English.

Page 196: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

374

(35) Note that the actual T-chain formation has been illustrated above to be

equivalent in English, French, Catalan and Spanish, previous to

incorporation.

(36) G&H give a parallel explanation for complex predicate structures

where the first element is considered an auxiliary - cf. section 3.4.2.2 -.

(37) As already noted in 3-3.1.4, when summarizing Belletti (1990), for

some past participle sequences there is assumed to be a functional node

dominating the past participle. This is explicitly argued for in several recent

works such as Kayne (19Ô7), Pollock. (19Ô7), G&H (19ÔÔ), Chomsky (19ÔÔ),

Drijkoningen (19Ô9). The main difference fort most of these authors lies in

the fact whether there is participle agreement or not; i.e. in the former case,

there is a functional node, in the latter, there is not. In Spanish G&H

explicitly allow VP in the syntax because there is no agreement, as shown

in their examples - Í102) p. 69 -, as opposed to French:

(i) a. p JesêJprises

b. Losfj& tomaäo

Note that Catalan allows agreement:

(ii) Le hepres/pres&s

For further (brief) consideration of this matter see Chapter 4, especially

section 4.3-

(30) This holds as long as we assume that there are no functional nodes

intervening between the two verbs in the sequence. See Note (36).

(39) Zagona (19ÔÔ) notes that. VP-preposing is a type of A-bar movement,

and she assumes it may move to Spec- CP. Nevertheless, she herself gives

an alternative of Topicalization and and a null operator as in (i) - (p. 125) - ,

Page 197: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

which would account for the Subjacency effects that she notes for English

preposing structures :

(i)... and [TOPIC IVP leave] Icp Oi lip he will ei ] 3 ] )

(40) Another passive, the impersonal passive is possible, and used: (i) Els

llibres es van fer llegir ; (ii) Los libros se hicieron leer.

(41) As explained in 2.4, and further considered in 3.4.3, if Catalan and

Spanish BE are here considered T-auxiliaries, independent constraints on

auxiliaries explain the ungrammatical examples in Spanish and Catalan;i.e

basically the fact that no two auxiliaries with the same function may

appear in a sequence.

(42) G&H- footnote ô, pg. 4ô- make a difference between simple and

complex tense as in (i) and (ii): avoir may denote either a simple or

complex tense, whereas A?P<? may only denote a complex tense, as in (ii)*

(i) J'ai vu Pierre à quatre heures/souvent

(ii) I have seen Peter *at four o'clock/ often

(43) This has been explained and illustrated - with clitic climbing and

theta-role percolation examples - in 2.4; the main idea behind it being the

fact that it links up tense as an operator on a theta-domain.

(44) This use is also allowed in Catalan under restricted circumstances.

(45) An alternative explanation as regards modals - which I will not pursue

in this thesis - is in line with Picallo (1985)-(1990);i.e. granting root modals

an adjunct predicate status, an idea that springs from Zubizarreta (1952),

Page 198: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

and which Pollock (1967) - as Picallo (1990) notes in a footnote - also

illustrated with the following examples:

(i) Pierre a voulu partir

(ii) Pierre est parti volontairement

Modal verbs seem to contribute to the interpretation of the predicate in an

adverbial fashion rather than by being direct theta-role assigners

(46) In Spanish the equivalent is possible: (i) Puede que no me encuentren

cuando vuelvan. Picallo( 1990) refers strictly to Catalan. The hypothesis in

this section may also only apply to Catalan, although in respects to be seen

below, epistemics in Catalan and Spanish seem to function identically

(47) Note first that in those examples given in 33.2.1, the sentences where

interruption of complex predicates is acceptable, the first element is a root

modal, or has a root, interpretation. The fact that Spanish deber, as opposed

to Catalan deure, may also have a root reading explains example ( ) in

3.3-2.1 from H&RU9Ô4))-

(40) Note that there is an important exception, the negative particle may

interrupt, and gives marginal results, even if the reading is epistemic, both

in Catalan and Spanish. :

(i)? En Guillem deu no saber què fer

(ii)? Guillermo debe no saber qué hacer

As will be noted in Chapter 4, in the present, phrase structure proposals à-

la-Pollock, the negative particle status has a special status. I will briefly

point out some possibilities in the chapter Prospects

(49) The fact that some speakers of Catalan and Spanish consider the

examples not wholly acceptable obviously calls for an explanation.

Page 199: YERPAl SEQUENCES; A GENERATIVE APPROACH · agreement with the modal44, ... clitics, and, thus, no impersonal constructions with subjec- sf/s&t clitic - s either , therefore no object

(50) The fact that the preposing construction for Catalan and Spanish is not:

"... ballar començaré a" / "... AyJar empezaré a" may be linked to the lack

of preposition stranding in the two languages.