to save the phenomena: constructive empiricism

21
1 To save the phenomena: constructive empiricism [The] belief involved in accepting a scientific theory is only that it ‘saves the phenomena’, that is that it correctly describes what is observable (van Fraassen,185-186)

Upload: martena-cooper

Post on 01-Jan-2016

35 views

Category:

Documents


3 download

DESCRIPTION

To save the phenomena: constructive empiricism. [The] belief involved in accepting a scientific theory is only that it ‘saves the phenomena’, that is that it correctly describes what is observable (van Fraassen,185-186). Term paper and final exam. - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: To save the phenomena: constructive empiricism

1

To save the phenomena: constructive empiricism[The] belief involved in accepting a scientific

theory is only that it ‘saves the phenomena’, that is that it correctly describes what is observable

(van Fraassen,185-186)

Page 2: To save the phenomena: constructive empiricism

2

Term paper and final exam

Final exam is scheduled for Thursday April 19, 6 pm in SBE 1220

Term paper is due March 22nd. Hard copy to me and electronic copy to Turnitin.com. Note the proviso in penalty for late submissions however

Please set up your account at Turnitin.com and familiarize yourself with the site before the due date.

Remember you are presenting an argument in support of a conclusion in your paper. You cannot just string together quotes!

Page 3: To save the phenomena: constructive empiricism

3

Steps leading to constructive empiricism

What is the argument used by anti-realists to motivate our acceptance of their position?

Strong underdetermination

1) For every theory there exist an infinite number of strongly empirically equivalent but incompatible rival theories

2) If two theories are strongly empirically equivalent then they are evidentially equivalent

3) No evidence can ever support a unique theory more than its strongly empirically equivalent rivals

4) Therefore, theory-choice is radically underdetermnined.

Page 4: To save the phenomena: constructive empiricism

4

Steps leading to constructive empiricism Focus on the second premise: If two theories are

strongly empirically equivalent then they are evidentially equivalent

Distinguish between empirical and evidential equivalence

Theory choice involves non-empirical features. E.g. Kinetic theory of motion

Page 5: To save the phenomena: constructive empiricism

5

Steps leading to constructive empiricism What is the constructive empiricist’s response to

the challenge? The underdetermination is resolved by pragmatic

considerations, not epistemological ones

Page 6: To save the phenomena: constructive empiricism

6

The difference between Scientific realism and Constructive Empiricism Scientific realism:

“science aims to give us … a literally true story of what the world is like; and acceptance of a scientific theory involves the belief that it is true” (van Fraassen cited on 185)

Constructive empiricism: “science aims to give us theories which are empirically adequate, and acceptance of a theory involves … belief only that it is empirically adequate” (ibid)

Page 7: To save the phenomena: constructive empiricism

7

Difference between scientific realism and constructive empiricism The realist thinks science aims at truth with respect to unobservable processes and entities that explain observable phenomena

The constructive empiricist thinks that science aims to tell the truth about what is observable and rejects the demand for explanation for all regularities in what we observe; they are agnostic with respect to unobservables

Page 8: To save the phenomena: constructive empiricism

8

The realist fights back: defending scientific realism against constructive empiricism1. Challenge the observable/unobservable distinction

2. Acceptance of theory involves a commitment to interpret and talk about the world in its terms

3. The strong form of the underdetermination argument applies to both unobservables and observables. The constructive empiricist is guilty of selective skepticism. The constructive empiricist is being inconsistent.

Page 9: To save the phenomena: constructive empiricism

9

First objection: observable/unobservable First objection: no meaningful distinction can be

drawn between the observable and the unobservable. Furthermore, no epistemological significance hangs on the distinction.

The realist’s point is that there is nothing special about unobservable entities that prevents us knowing about their existence. That is, “nothing is unobservable in principle” (Ladyman 188).

This point was raised by Grover Maxwell in 1962.

Page 10: To save the phenomena: constructive empiricism

10

Observable/unobservable distinction Maxwell: there is a continuum between seeing

normally, seeing with binoculars, seeing with a microscope, seeing with an electron microscope. Where is the line between observable and unobservable?

van Frassen: vague predicates, like ‘red’, ‘tall’, can do epistemological work.

van Frassen: what we can and cannot know coincides with the observable and unobservable.

Page 11: To save the phenomena: constructive empiricism

11

Reply to the first objection

van Fraassen’s aim: skepticism about unobservable. Maxwell: nothing is unobservable in principle. This

means that entities may be observed under the right sort of circumstances. Electron microscope, for example.

For van Frassen, ‘observable’ is to be understood as observable-to-us: “X is observable if there are circumstances which are such that, if X is present to us under those circumstances, then we observe it” (188).

Page 12: To save the phenomena: constructive empiricism

12

Reply to the first objection

What we can or cannot observe is due to the fact: “the human organism is, from the point of view of physics, a certain kind of measuring apparatus. As such it has certain limitations … it is these limitations to which the ‘able’ in ‘observable’ refers—our limitations qua human beings” (189)

Page 13: To save the phenomena: constructive empiricism

13

Reply to the first objection

The ‘us’ refers to the human epistemic community. The epistemology is our epistemology

However, if in the future, we encounter other beings whose senses are better than ours, and the two epistemic communities are integrated, then the observable/unobservable boundary shifts appropriately. We would be at the sight-impaired end of the community

Page 14: To save the phenomena: constructive empiricism

14

Reply to the first objection

What then is the difference between the moons of Jupiter and positrons?

Were we in a space ship and were close enough to Jupiter, we would observe the moons of Jupiter.

However, we do not directly observe positrons. We infer their existence by the tracks in a cloud chamber.

There may well be another theory which is empirical equivalent but denies that positrons exist—the leprechaun theory.

Page 15: To save the phenomena: constructive empiricism

15

Reply to the first objection

The realist may object: “why does van Frassen allow change in spatiotemporal location when determining what is observable, but not the constitution of our sensory organs?”

van Frassen’s response: we are like beings whose only difference is that they are closer to Jupiter, but we are not like beings with different sensory organs.

If we had electron microscopic eyes, we might not observe positrons.

Page 16: To save the phenomena: constructive empiricism

16

Second Objection: Acceptance and belief The objection: Acceptance of theory involves a

commitment to interpret and talk about the world in its terms

The scientific realist challenges van Fraassen’s distinction between belief and ‘acceptance’: the realist argues that van Fraassen’s position is incoherent.

Page 17: To save the phenomena: constructive empiricism

17

Second objection

The difference between belief and acceptance Does the following statement ‘I believe p (p be any

statement) but it is not true’, make sense? Believing in p implies one is committed to the truth

of p van Frassen claims that ‘I accept p’ does not imply

that one is committed to the truth of p. Is he right?

Page 18: To save the phenomena: constructive empiricism

18

Reply to second objection:

Does it make sense to say that ‘I accept p but p is not true’? Is there a contradiction in saying ‘I accept p but p is not true’?

Consider the case of Newtonian mechanics We accept it for use everyday but we are not

committed to saying that it is true, which it isn’t strictly speaking.

Page 19: To save the phenomena: constructive empiricism

19

Belief and acceptance:

The above example illustrates the difference in epistemic attitude between believing in and accepting a statement, or theory.

There appears to be no contradiction in accepting a theory for use but believe it to be false.

The realist objection fails.

Page 20: To save the phenomena: constructive empiricism

20

Third objection: selective skepticism In order to appreciate the third objection, we need

to consider what realists mean by ‘explanation’? Realists hold that the truth (or approximate truth)

of a hypothesis is a necessary condition for it to be part of a genuine scientific explanation.

That is why, for realists, explanations require more than empirical adequacy (what is ‘empirical adequacy?)

Page 21: To save the phenomena: constructive empiricism

21

Scientific explanations

Realists argue that there are principled ways of breaking underdetermination. A rational justification can be offered.

For them, inference to the best explanation (IBE) shows that empirical equivalence of theories does not imply evidential equivalence.

Realists use IBE to argue for the existence of unobservables.

The constructive empiricist must offer a critique of IBE if they are to succeed in arguing their case.