the georgian ossetian conflict.pdf

Upload: john-mcclain

Post on 14-Jan-2016

231 views

Category:

Documents


2 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • The Georgian - South Ossetian Conflict

    1 Methodological Considerations and Formulation of the Problem

    This thesis is the story of the so-called Georgian - South Ossetian ethno-

    nationalist conflict. In this thesis I will cast some theoretical light on the

    conflict, trying to reach an understanding of the specific features, roots and

    processes of the conflict. By the experienced conflict I will try to demystify

    and decipher the so commonly used an accepted notion of ethnic conflict.

    Among journalists but also some academics, the most conventional

    explanations for the ethnic conflicts that arose in Eastern Europe after the

    collapse of the communist regimes are the ones that can be called the "pot-lid-

    theories" or the "refrigerator-theories" (Sampson 1992, p.395, Brown 1993,

    p.5-6 and Suny 1993, p.3). The communist regimes, especially the Soviet

    Union, are said to have repressed national and ethnic sentiments and

    differences and frozen down national identity. The ethnic/national differences,

    grievances and/or conflicts that existed were repressed, and have now re-

    emerged, hence the metaphor of the pot-lid that has been lifted.

    These explanations generally see communism as a parenthesis, something that

    has interrupted a natural historical course. In this light ethnic conflict is seen

    as something almost natural, logically diverted by differences and as

    something which was frozen down by communist repression. Now that

    communism, and with that repression, have ended and the lid removed, nature

    can evolve as it should, and the eternal historical hatred will be expressed

    freely.

    In this explanation lies two main assumptions. One is that ethnic conflict is

    more or less natural, that when you have different ethnic groups in one setting

    conflict is inevitable. Hence that heterogeneous areas are unnatural. The

    multi-national states, such as Yugoslavia and the Soviet Union, are in this

    light seen as artificial constructions. The homogeneous nation-state is

    generally seen as the natural state - as things should be. Hence the titles of

    numerous articles and books on the Balkans or the Caucasus using the words

    ethnic powderkeg, mosaic, or puzzle. The other assumption is that the

    communist regimes of Eastern Europe and especially the Soviet Union did not

    tolerate expression of national or ethnic identity and hence suppressed it and

    instead tried to create an artificial Homo Sovieticus. In this view the recent

    conflicts are seen as a reaction to this artificial situation. The nations and the

    ethnic groups are now moving towards the natural situation of one state - one

    nation.

    1.1 The Problems of the Thesis

  • The overarching aim of the thesis will be to demystify and decipher the notion

    of ethnic conflict. Understanding specific features and processes of ethnic

    conflicts. The thesis will however be two-stringed in the way that it will

    consist of a theoretical and empirical understanding of ethnic conflict. The

    emphasis will be put on an understanding of the experienced Georgian - South

    Ossetian conflict. The theoretical part should thus be seen as developing

    concepts in order to shed some theoretical light on the experienced ethnic

    conflict. In the urge to understand the phenomenon of nationalism and ethnic

    conflict in Eastern Europe and the former Soviet Union as such I thus put

    strong emphasis on an understanding of the actual experienced conflict and

    this in its Soviet context.

    The aim of this report is exactly to question the above mentioned conventional

    explanations for the rise of ethnic conflict in Eastern Europe and the former

    Soviet Union, using the experienced example of the Georgian - South

    Ossetian conflict. To try to question the inevitability of ethnic conflict and to

    show that national and ethnic identities are constructions in themselves. That

    nations and ethnic groups do not, with Benedict Anderson's words, loom out

    of an immemorial past. That we are dealing with a socio-political and cultural

    phenomenon rather than a nature given. And in fact that we are dealing with a

    phenomenon that is multidimensional and only be can fully grasped if

    analysed contextually. In this respect I will try to show that the policies of the

    Soviet Union played an active part in the developing of national and ethnic

    identities and furthermore elaborated a system, which was inherently

    conflictual in respect to these identities. That in fact one even might say that

    the Soviet political system nursed and cultivated ethnic/national differences

    and inherent conflictual structures and identities rather than putting a lid on

    them or freezing them down.

    Furthermore it has been shown that wars defined as ethnic conflicts on an

    avarage have a significant longer duration than other types of war; that they

    are more vicious of nature and uncontrollable, and that more frequently than

    other forms of conflict, ethnic conflicts do not end by negotiated solutions but

    by outright military victory by either side (King 1997, p.13 and Scherrer 1997,

    p.42). The common explanations for this intractability and protracted nature of

    ethnic conflict are often ascribed to the uncontrollable irrational behaviour

    motivated by deeply rooted ancient hatreds and incompatible deeply felt

    values and identities of the belligerents in ethnic conflict (King 1997, p.13 and

    52). An explanation not only found in journalistic writings but also in

    arguments by the so-called international community for not intervening in

    these kind of conflicts (Snyder 1993, p.79 and King 1997, p.26).

    I shall look for alternative explanations to the nature of ethnic conflict.

    Looking specifically on the structure of conflict or armed conflict/warfare to

    be more precise; determining structural factors that can help explain the

  • protracted nature and intractability of ethnic conflict in another light than the

    above mentioned explanations.

    Summing up this thesis will be about the Georgian - South Ossetian conflict.

    A conflict with the label of an ethno-nationalist conflict. Determining what it

    is that makes this conflict an ethno-nationalist conflict. Looking specifically

    on theories of nationalism and ethnicity, the dynamics of armed ethnic intra-

    state conflict and on the specific roots and processes in the Georgian - South

    Ossetian conflict. But let us turn to some methodological considerations

    where I also will argue for the choice of theories and empirical material.

    1.2 Methodological Considerations

    The first theoretical part of this thesis, nationalism and ethnicity, is more an

    attempt to give an overview and an interpretation of the theoretical approaches

    to the phenomenon of nationalism and ethnicity, rather than lining up a couple

    of different theories and use them on the experienced conflict. In doing so I

    am aware of the fact that I may reduce the complexity of the different theories

    and thus a previous knowledge on the subject of nationalism may be required.

    At the same time it should be mentioned that my purpose is not to give an

    exhaustive typology or genealogy of the theories of ethnicity and nationalism

    but rather to show that nationalism is a contested and heterogeneous

    phenomenon. Though extensive enough to serve the purpose of this thesis, not

    to say that nationalism is really... but to show that nationalism can have several meanings, depending on space and time and is changeable depending

    on context and purpose. Therefore the purpose of this chapter should be seen

    as that of elaborating an applicable theoretical framework for the analysis.

    The second theoretical part of the thesis, the dynamics of armed ethnic intra-

    state conflicts, is an attempt to theorise on the more structural and inherent

    components of conflict as a counterweight to the more socio-political and

    cultural explanations of ethnic conflict, which should be given by the first

    theoretical part. To try and grasp the basic nature and extract the

    particularities of this kind of conflicts, but also to compare it to other forms of

    intra-state conflicts in order to demystify and decipher the notion of ethnic

    conflict.

    The empirical part also consists of two parts. The first part will deal with the

    actual experienced ethnic conflict, the so-called Georgian - South Ossetian

    conflict. Here I will line up the actual course of events based on interviews,

    first hand experience and written material. This will in effect be an attempt

    expose and describe the circumstances in which this conflict evolved, but also

    at the same time to line up the different perceptions on behalf of the involved

    parties.

  • The second part will so to speak focus a level back and up, looking on the

    Soviet setting in which you also will have to analyse the conflict. As written

    above one of my hypotheses is that the Soviet Union by its intended policies

    played an active role in the developing of national and ethnic identities and

    furthermore elaborated a system, which was inherently conflictual in respect

    to these identities. In this chapter I will thus look on both Marxist-Leninist

    theory on the nationalities question and the principle of national self-

    determination on the one hand, and the actual way the system functioned in

    practice on the other hand. In this putting more emphasis on how the system

    was implemented on the ground rather than putting emphasis on the

    theoretical aspects and historical developments in these discussions. This of

    course with an emphasis on the experienced conflict. Hence the part on

    Marxist-Leninist theory will be least studied, the principle of national self-

    determination more and the actual implementation and functioning most.

    As mentioned above this thesis is a linking of theory on nationalism and

    conflict dynamics to the specific experienced conflict. Linking theory and

    empirical material is however not just something you do without further

    methodological considerations. Without entering the apparently never-ending

    discussion within social sciences on the relation between theory and empirical

    material I will still try to argue for my chosen method.

    The theoretical parts will first of all be a rewriting or reconstruction of the

    theories to a form that makes these applicable as steering-tools in the analysis

    of the empirical material. The aim of the project is not to confirm the

    existence of nationalism or its prominent role in the conflict, but to use

    theories on nationalism and internal conflict to shed some theoretical light on

    the conflict and to determine what role ethnicity and nationalism play in this

    conflict.

    It is not a verification or falsification, of the theories I will make, which would

    be methodological inappropriate as you would, so to speak, operate within the

    realm of the theories themselves, and as the saying goes in Danish som man rber i skoven fr man svar. But still it is to use the theories (or the rewritten theories) to shed an explaining and interpreting light on the conflict. In other

    words to use the theories to decipher the notion of ethnic conflict and in this

    way extract from the theories some analytical tools to be used in analysis of

    the phenomena and the case. But on the other hand also to look for the

    possibility of the empirical material to provide background for possible

    critique of the theoretical apparatus.

    The theoretical part on nationalism and ethnicity consists of an overview of

    the landscape of theories of nationalism, were I will try to reach my

    understanding of nationalism. Of course it has been impossible for me to get

    acquainted with all contributions to the theoretical debate on nationalism over

  • the years. The chosen theorists represent what others and I call, the modern classics, and these theories are building on previous contributions and cover the vast part of the theoretical space. It should however, also be mentioned

    that I draw on additional theoretical material where I find it necessary.

    Although most of these theoreticians deal with the subject in order to seek and

    understand the historical roots of nationalism, they also describe the nature of

    nationalism and its conflictual aspects, which is the main focus of this project,

    and thus what I will focus on.

    The first theoretical part is mainly based on more general theories of

    nationalism, namely Benedict Anderson "Imagined Communities", Eric J.

    Hobsbawm Nations and Nationalism Since 1780, Anthony D. Smith "National Identity", Ernest Gellner "Nations and Nationalism", and last but

    not least Paul R. Brass Ethnicity and Nationalism from 1991, who more specifically deals with ethnicity.

    I have made use of the chosen theories because they say something about

    nationalism and ethnicity. But one could easily ask the question, why use

    theories about nationalism and ethnicity to shed light on an ethnic conflict,

    why not use theories on class struggle, modernisation, state theory, theories on

    international politics etc.?

    On the one hand the point is exactly to look at ethnic conflict as a specific

    theoretical problem. One can choose to look at ethnic conflict or ethnic

    politics as just another form of politics where other theoretical approaches can

    be used to explain the phenomenon. But one can also choose, as I do, to look

    at ethnic conflict, or ethnic mobilisation, as a special form of politics, where

    exactly the culture, or more specifically ethnicity, functions as the mobilising

    basis. Then it is interesting to use theories on ethnicity and nationalism as

    something different from other more general theories of social sciences, which

    probably can explain a deal, but not the processes and dynamics in the

    conflicts, which are specific because they are articulated in ethnic terms. Here

    it is not a question of taking the arguments of the participants in ethnic

    conflicts for granted, but to accept that it leads to specific conflict patterns,

    which theories dealing exactly with nationalism can shed light on.

    On the other hand I should also state that one of the aims of this thesis, as

    mentioned initially, is to demystify and decipher the notion of ethnic conflict.

    Therefore I have chosen to use theories of nationalism and ethnicity to so to

    speak play their ballgame in order to see what this framework offers. I exactly

    want to study the specifities of ethno-national conflict, demystifying and

    deciphering the ethno-national elements, and therefor I have to study ethnicity

    and nationalism.

  • At the same time I have felt the necessity of drawing on another theoretical

    approach. Besides making use of theories of nationalism I have decided to use

    theoretical work on what you could call the dynamics and nature of armed

    ethnic intra-state conflicts. This I have chosen to do not from the start but as I

    went deeper into the jungle of this study. This need appeared because of the

    fact that several questions surfaced as I went along. The question of what

    makes an ethnic conflict different from other internal conflicts and the

    questions of the possible presence of inherent structural factors in intra-state

    conflict situations that makes ethnic conflicts more protracted and severe.

    Hence looking at other explanations than culture and identity which is offered

    by the theories of nationalism. Trying to find something rational or logical in a seemingly or at least depicted irrational phenomenon.

    The fact that there does not, to my knowledge, exist comprehensive

    theoretical works on this[1] have made this chapter a bit of a puzzle, taking

    bits and parts mainly from working papers, articles and journalistic writings.

    Comprehensive literature retrieval has made this chapter possible and

    hopefully not puzzle-like to read.

    The main sources of this part is based on Charles King Ending Civil Wars, Michael Ignatieff Blood and Belonging, several working papers from the Copenhagen Peace Research Institute (COPRI), and literature from

    international relations theory and peace research theory that in a more indirect

    manner deals with intra-state/ethnic conflicts.

    1.3 Method of Gathering Empirical Material

    The second empirical part of this thesis - the Soviet Setting - is mainly written

    on a documentary style of method. Gathering information on the Soviet

    setting from books and articles written by scholars focused on the Soviet

    Union and its policies on the national question and not least area specialists of

    the region. Furthermore I have made use of Soviet and Georgian/South

    Ossetian empirical data on population figures and ethnic compositions in

    different arenas. This of course raises certain questions as to the validity of

    such empirical data, since some of it can be interpreted as biased.

    First of all most, if not all, scholars dealing with the nationality question of the

    former Soviet Union agrees to the fact that the Soviet Union had fairly reliable

    census data at least when it comes to the recognised nationalities as the ones I

    am dealing with (see for example Gurr 1993, p.12-13). Secondly this data I

    shared and discussed with the parties and others on location, and found no

    mayor discrepancies or objections.

    This part of the thesis has on my part been carefully written, knowing that

    ethnic composition figures often are at the hart of the matter in ethnic conflict.

  • Comparing and double-checking all statistical data where possible. Where this

    has not been possible or there has been a high danger of apparent biased data I

    have used it as an indication rather than as fixed and precise figures. However,

    I should also state that as I had most of the empirical data gathered when I was

    in the area I confronted the different parties with the data and found no mayor

    objections. At the same time I should also mention that incorrect' statistical material is also of relevance since ethnic conflict is not necessarily about facts

    but more important about perceived facts.

    As for the first part of the empirical material, the actual conflict, it is first of

    all important to state that I was in Georgia to fulfil a certain job position not to

    do research on Georgia and the specific Georgian - South Ossetian conflict.

    This in itself laid down some restrictions on my other role as a student of

    ethnic conflict. However I came to Georgia as well with the agenda to study

    ethnic conflict and my job created certain opportunities to study this conflict

    not as an observer but rather as a participant, as you must include international

    organisations and NGOs on this side[2].

    However in late 1995 I was asked by my organisation to write a small paper

    on the history and course of conflict (which is also the basis of these two

    sections in this thesis), to be published as background material for the

    international community (international organisations and embassies). This

    gave me a change to study the conflict a bit closer and to learn how sensitive it

    is put such events and perceptions of history down on paper. I made an effort

    not to present this as the objective truth, as this of cause is impossible, but as

    the perceptions of both the Georgian and South Ossetian side. This was one of

    the first times, if not the first, that the South Ossetians had their perspective on

    the history of the conflict presented on paper in English. This I state to

    emphasise that this, regardless of its obvious small scope, was a kind of

    pioneer work. Not only did I get the label of professor of history I also

    experienced how history change according to present circumstances as I on

    several occasions was asked to change certain previously stated facts.

    The restrictions and dangers of the position of an employee of a foreign NGO

    were that the conflicting parties of course could become more cautious as to

    how close they would let me in into their worlds so to speak, as I through this

    position became a small part of the overall political game. However, at the same time this got me into a position where I could operate with more

    authority and generally they were very forthcoming. This has also something to do with the fact that very little international attention was directed towards

    the South Ossetian issue. In this way I had weekly meetings with senior

    officials and other administrative personnel through my job position.

    Arranging practical things like setting up meetings and conferences with

    South Ossetian participation, which of course led to more opportunities of

    informal talks on the overall issue of the Georgian - South Ossetian conflict.

  • I am making a clear distinction between my contact with the Georgians and

    South Ossetians because there was a clear difference in the way of having

    contact with them. First of all I lived in Tbilisi, the capital of Georgia, not in

    Tskhinvali, the capital of South Ossetia. They all saw me as an outsider, a

    stranger, but at the same time the South Ossetians were conscious about the

    fact that I lived on the other side. The South Ossetian authorities would at first not let me stay for a period of time in South Ossetia as I requested. But as

    they got used to my organisation intentions and me they asked me to stay for a

    longer period of time, but unfortunately then I had run out of time to do so.

    Hence my freedom of movement was restricted in South Ossetia, it was

    simply not save to move around on your own without local escort and the authorities preferred to control the situation. Therefore my contact was limited

    to official and semi-official persons, but on the other hand my work with

    youth organisations and journalists gave me a broader insight as well as the

    writing of the small paper.

    In Georgia proper I had no such restrictions, I lived there, and made contact

    with all sorts of people, I felt the atmosphere of the place in a different way.

    Having said this it is important to note that I made good contacts and

    friendships on both sides. And in a way I got intimate in another way with the

    South Ossetians because of their isolated position, especially as I at a couple

    of occasions functioned as an international escort to Georgia proper at meetings and conferences arranged by my organisation.

    Writing this I have to say something about the way of getting close to the

    people of the Caucasus, Georgian or South Ossetian. I had plenty of official

    meetings and formal interview situations, but in Caucasus this is not the way

    of getting close to the heart of the matter. To get to the heart of the matter

    requires intimacy and in the Caucasus intimacy is inseparably connected to

    food and drinking.

    You can read methodological books about how to do an interview or how to

    observe but in the Caucasus you must drink and eat your way to the core of

    the matter. If you dont like Caucasian food or the smell and taste of Georgian wine, South Ossetian beer or vodka and its local variants then dont bother doing research in the Caucasus. It can sound very unscientific on paper but I

    would not have been honest to my method and the truth if I had not written this. On the other hand one could also see this as part of an anthropological

    method where it precisely is about being in the centre and not on the side line.

    Observing but also participating and thereby acquire the experience necessary

    to reflect and understand.

    Of course I got a lot of information and empirical material from written

    sources from both sides and formal interviews, not to mention material written

    by other scholars. The point is however that I had been no where if I had not

  • been there in the Caucasus, smelling the fresh air from the Caucasian

    Mountain Range, the gasoline in the streets of Tbilisi, listening to the personal

    stories told around the Caucasian Table after having been forced to eat a lot of food and drink a lot of alcohol. These were the situations were I began

    to see and understand the situation, this was the intimacy required, on the

    behalf of the involved parties, if they were to let me into their understanding,

    perceptions and views on the situation. This is part of my method, or maybe

    should I say their required condition for doing research in the region.

    [1] Christian P. Scherrer states in a working paper from COPRI that

    this field is far from as advanced as for instance inter-state conflicts and

    this especially concerning ethnic intra-state conflicts (Scherrer 1997,

    p.4 and 34).

    [2] This was however only one of the many tasks I had within the organisation.

    See in appendix 2 for a description of my work at the organisation.

    2 Nationalism and Ethnicity - A Theoretical Overview

    A great deal of ambiguity and confusion surrounds the use of terms like ethnic group, nation, state, and nationalism. The different terms are being used and understood in a variety of often related, but different meanings by academics, nationalists, journalists and in everyday language.

    The idea of this chapter is to shed an explaining light on these terms and concepts and to give an

    overview of the theories of nationalism and my interpretation of the phenomenon.

    What I would call the modern classics of theory of nationalism, have mostly dealt with the subject from a historical point of view, explaining the emergence of nationalism and the nation-

    state. In this chapter I will try to focus on the nature of nationalism and on the conflictual aspects

    of this. Nevertheless I will also draw on the historical angle because it shows, as we shall see, that

    we are not dealing with one phenomenon but several forms and shapes formed by the last 200

    years.

    The different theories of nationalism evolves around certain focal points which are also the main

    elements in an understanding of the phenomenon:

    - Nationalism as a political phenomenon legitimising actions or systems as opposed to

    nationalism as a cultural phenomenon, providing meaning/raison dtre.

    Nationalism as either a modern phenomenon inseparably connected to the emergence of the

    modern centralising state or nationalism as a primordial phenomenon, something natural and

    rooted in the past.

    These two sets of opposing views are furthermore reflected by the angle of analysis either

    primarily from a structural or an actor-oriented angle.

  • In order to understand these different aspects of nationalism better, I will start off with the

    classical distinction of nationalism, as either a political or an organic phenomenon, which then

    later hopefully should give us a better opportunity of understanding the conflictual aspects of

    nationalism.

    2.1 The Genealogy of Nationalism

    The nation-state and democracy are so to speak twins born out of the French and American

    revolutions. With the French Revolution the nation became the source of state sovereignty. Not

    understood as if each nation is supposed to be granted the right to political self-determination, but

    rather, in the way that the people living within the given territory of the state constitute the nation.

    This is the so-called French or political-civic notion or principle of the nation. According to this

    notion the nation of citizens does not derive its identity from some common ethnic or cultural

    characteristics, but rather from the praxis of citizens who actively exercise their civil rights and

    duties (Habermas 1992, p.2-3). Hence the primary meaning of nation was political, patriotism

    was conceived as love to the nation (in the meaning of state and state-patriotism) expressed by the

    wish to renew it by reform or revolution, and thereby breaking with former loyalties. In this way

    their patrie, opposed to an existential, pre-existing unit, was a nation created by their free choice.

    American are those who wish to be. French nationality was French citizenship and the nation was un plbiscite de tous les jours. Ethnicity, language and history were irrelevant to the French nation (Hobsbawm 1990, p.87-88). It was the ideals of the Age of Enlightenment that were

    pronounced - universalism and rationality. It represented the common interests against particular

    interests. This kind of nationalism is aimed to extend and unify, rather than to restrict and

    separate (Hobsbawm 1992, p.23), or in the words of Mary Kaldor, to unify and centralise rather

    than decentralise and fragmentize (Kaldor 1993, p.108). The Romantic Movement, mainly

    German, reacted on the ideas of the Enlightenment, with its mechanical and rational view on

    society and humanity.

    The Romantic Movement stood for the defence of the national characters; what was unique had value and with these ideas emerged a romantic worship and study of genuine volks-art, and the notions of a Volk and its Volksgeist. In this way the so-called German notion of the nation, or the organic-ethnic, is to be seen in opposition to the French, political-civic notion of the nation.

    It is an objective ethnic definition of the nation which draws the conclusion that there should be a

    congruency between the nation and the state (in ethnic terms), understood in the manner that

    every nation (ethnic group) has the right to its own state. Hence the concept encompasses

    collective self-determination and expression of national character. In conclusion nations are seen

    as natural entities and with the development of national consciousness, nations, by the laws of

    nature, have the right to express themselves in a national idiom.

    Many of the authors I deal with in this chapter have developed typologies of nationalism evolving

    around this distinction, calling it political/organic, French/German, official/vernacular,

    revolutionary-democratic/ethnic etc. One of the first and, according to Smith, most influential

    typologies was made by Hans Kohn, in which he distinguishes between a Western and an Eastern version:

    Fig 1.: Kohns Dichotomy[1]:

    Western Nationalism Eastern Nationalism

    Great Britain, France, America. Eastern Europe (east of the Rhine).

    Rational. Mystical.

  • A product of the middle classes (bourgeoisie),

    whom came to power at the end of the 18th

    century.

    Eastern Europe had no developed middle class;

    instead nationalism became a product of a few

    intellectuals, which made it more authoritarian.

    An association of human beings living on the

    same territory, under the same government and

    laws.

    The nation as a seamless, organic unit with a

    mystical 'soul' and 'mission'.

    Smith has several reasons for criticising this typology. First of all because of its geopolitical

    dimension which overlooks the influence of both kinds of nationalisms in different European

    communities: the organic version in Ireland and later 19th century France, the rational ideal in

    some versions of Czech, Hungarian and Zionist nationalism, as well as in early West African

    nationalisms (Smith 1991, p.81). Furthermore the western nationalisms owe much to the earlier

    monarchies (as seen as well in Andersons chapter on official nationalism, where the old monarchies of Europe tried to legitimise themselves by naturalisation (Anderson 1983, p.86-87)). Finally Smith states that there should be made a distinction between German and Italian

    nationalisms opposed to the relatively underdeveloped Balkan and Eastern Europe. But despite

    these criticisms, Smith finds Kohns distinction between a more rational and a more organic version valid and useful. But it is important, he stresses, that both models can be found in the

    East and in the West, in Asia, Africa, and Latin America, and as a mixture with greater or lesser emphasis on one or the other (Smith 1991, p.79-82).

    Like Smith I also find it appropriate for analytical purposes to describe the two different (in a

    Weberian understanding) ideal types of the nation, the cultural or organic and the political or the

    civic. As seen in the figure below:

    Fig. 2:[2]

    Nation

    The Political-Civic The Organic-Cultural

    A juridical-political community of laws and

    institutions with a single political will.

    Ethnic comprehension of the community as

    common descent.

    Political territory. Homeland - Vaterland.

    Social contract between citizen and state,

    individual, subjective consciousness. Volksgeist/descent, fictive super-family,

    collective, objective consciousness.

    Inclusive, in the way that it tries to unify and

    extend.

    Exclusive, in the way that it tries to restrict and

    fragmentize.

    Rational Irrational

    The nation is a choice; the nations are created

    by the will of the members.

    The individual is born into and organically

    connected to the nation, the will of the members

    is determined by the belonging to the specific

    nation.

    In this way the organic-cultural notion of the nation has as its basic assertion that the nation

    should be defined on the basis of ethnic criteria, and that every nation, ethnically defined, should

    be gathered in their own state. Contrary to this, the political-civic notion of the nation has as its

    basic assertion that everyone that lives within the boundaries of the state should become a part of

    the nation, which is what lies in the concept of nation-building. Both principles then stress the

    cultural similarity of their adherents but in fundamentally different manners. The political-civic in

    an inclusive way and the organic-cultural in an exclusive way.

  • Let us now turn to look a little bit closer at the different aspects of the phenomenon, as they are

    described by the different theories, and in this way see that this distinction is also reflected in the

    different views of nationalism. The typology I will return to later.

    2.2 Nationalism as a Political Doctrine

    Some authors view nationalism as a political phenomenon legitimising actions or systems. In this

    way nationalism is primarily viewed as a political principle, which holds that the political and the national unit should be congruent (Gellner 1983, p.1 and Hobsbawm 1990, p.9). According to this view the nation and nationalism can only be understood in relation to a certain kind of

    modern territorial state; the nation-state. In this understanding the state plays a central role in the

    process of building the nation. As Hobsbawm writes: It is the state which makes the nation and not the nation the state (Hobsbawm 1990, p.44-45). Nations and nationalism are hence in this perspective seen as something constructed mainly from above.

    In this respect it is interesting to see that both Gellner and Hobsbawm, refuses a fixed definition

    of the nation (Gellner 1983, p.6-7 and Hobsbawm 1990, p.7-10). According to Hobsbawm the

    question ought not to be what is the nation? but rather what has the notion - the nation - meant in different, often competitive, contexts, in different periods, for different groups with different

    political strategies?

    Hobsbawm generally sees the national question as situated at the point of intersection of politics, technology and social transformation. He states that nationalism should be seen as

    something essentially constructed from above but not only as that. According to Hobsbawm, it is

    also necessary to analyse it from below. Thus he criticises Gellner for being to one-sided, making

    it difficult to analyse nationalism from below, in terms of the assumptions and feelings of the

    ordinary people. However, although Hobsbawm mentions this duality of nationalism, he is mostly

    concerned with analysing nationalism from above and neglects to analyse it from below.

    Anderson deals in his book with what he calls official nationalism. Originally it is something that should be understood in connection to the decline of the monarchies of Western Europe,

    during which nationalism could function as legitimising the continuation of dynastic rule. The

    purpose was to unite dynasty and subjects. The king was no longer ruling as Gods representative on earth, but now as a number one among his fellow countrymen. In this way official nationalism

    was used to make the king a symbol of the nation. Furthermore the official nationalism developed

    after, and in response to the national/popular movements, the aim of the official nationalism being

    not only to legitimise the king, but also the empire, as Anderson writes: These official nationalisms can best be understood as a means for combining naturalisation with retention of dynastic power, in particular over the huge polyglot domains accumulated since Middle Ages, or,

    to put it another way, for stretching the short, tight, skin of the nation over the gigantic body of

    the empire (Anderson 1983, p.86).

    What is important here is that Anderson have a layer upon layer conception of nationalism, so

    that the different nationalisms that he speaks of (Creole nationalism, vernacular nationalism, etc.),

    can be copied, refined and mixed and then be used differently, depending on time, place and the

    concrete contents. In this way official nationalism can be seen as a model used for its

    manipulating abilities by those who are in control of the political apparatus, as he writes: The one persistent feature of this style of nationalism was, and is, that it is official - i.e. something emanating from the state, and serving the interests of the state first and foremost (Anderson 1983, p.159). In this way you can state that Anderson also (but not only as we shall see) view

  • nationalism as a political doctrine, legitimising actions or systems.

    An extreme, but nevertheless fruitful, version of viewing nationalism as something political we

    find at Paul R. Brass. He understands basically nationalism as something political. As a social and

    political creation by elites, whereby ethnic groups, or rather their elites, uses ethnic/national

    identity when it comes to put forward demands on the political or economical level to obtain

    political power or economic gains. A modern phenomenon inseparably connected to the activities

    of the modern centralising state.

    Brass sees two ways in which nations can be created. Either by the transformation of an ethnic

    group to a self-consciousness political identity in a multi-ethnic state or by the fusion of different

    ethnic groups creating a homogenous national culture by the modern state as promoter. An ethnic

    group he defines as a subjective self-conscious community that establishes criteria for in- or

    exclusion using cultural symbols in order to differentiate themselves from other groups (Brass

    1991, p.18-20)[3].

    Ethno-nationalism and state-centred or generated nationalism can therefore both be seen as

    subtypes of a general identity creating process, defined as a process whereby the subjective

    meaning of a number of symbols is intensified, and as a strive for obtaining a multisymbol congruence among a group of people defined initially by one or more central symbols, whether

    those symbols are ethnic attributes or loyalty to a particular state (Brass 1991, p.20).

    Brass instrumental approach is made clear when he states that ethnicity can be activated in special contexts or/and at specific times. The main point is that the formation or politicisation of

    ethnicity is seen as a process created in the dynamics of lite competition. The elites make use of

    the attributes of the ethnic groups as resources, intensifies them and thereby creates a political

    identity, which is used in the competition for political power and economic gain (Brass 1991,

    p.15-16). Basically he sees ethnic groups as mobilised by disgruntled elites to a growing sense of

    group solidarity (Brass 1991, p.41). Hence ethnic groups, or rather their elites, are using the

    ethnicity to put demands to the political system in order to improve their status, economic

    situation, civil rights or educational/job possibilities.

    2.3 Nationalism as a Modern Phenomenon

    In continuation of the view of nationalism as a political doctrine it is easy to view nationalism as

    a modern phenomenon, something understood in connection to the emergence of the modern

    centralising state.

    To illustrate what nationalism has meant in Europe, Gellner asks the reader to imagine two

    ethnographic maps, one drawn up before the age of nationalism and one after. The first would be

    a chaos of different colours, where no clear pattern would be found and where it would be

    difficult to make out, where one colour stops and the other takes over. In the other the colours are

    clearly separated, neat flat surfaces clearly separated from each other and there is little if any

    ambiguity or overlap. If one shifts to reality, one will discover that the prevailing part of the

    political authority has been placed in a certain kind of institution - the modern centralising nation

    state. This always identifies itself with one kind of culture and one style of communication within

    its boundaries. In order to exist, the state is dependent of a centralised educational system, the

    content of which it dictates as well as finances.

    If we look at the economy in a society with such a state, it will become clear why it has to be this

  • way. Its economy depends on communication between the individuals and their mobility at a

    level it would not be capable of maintaining, if the individuals had not been socialised into the

    culture of the concerned society (Gellner 1983, p.139-140).

    In this way Gellner sees nationalism as the organisation of human groups into large, centrally

    educated, culturally homogeneous units. Its roots should not be found in the human psyche but in

    the distinctive structural requirements of industrial society and modes of production (Gellner

    1983, p.34-35). The requirements of a mobile division of labour, and sustained, frequent and precise communication between strangers involving a sharing of explicit meaning, transmitted in

    a standard idiom and in writing when required (Gellner 1983, p.34).

    Also Hobsbawm views nations as new phenomenon, invented and socially produced, it belongs exclusively to a particular, and historically recent, period. It is a social entity only insofar as it

    relates to a certain kind of modern territorial state, the nation-state, but it is not exclusively a function of this. The emergence of nationalism should also be seen in the context of a particular

    stage of technological and economic development (Hobsbawm 1990, p.9-10), whereby he is in

    line with Gellners thesis.

    Anderson however, as we shall see, holding a primarily cultural understanding of nationalism,

    also relates the emergence of nationalism to the processes of modernisation and the emergence of

    capitalism, but this he relates to the weakening of two cultural systems. That of the kings divine

    right and the religious community. In this way the imagination of the nation was made possible

    by changes of some fundamental cultural conceptions. Anderson puts special emphasis on the

    role of print-capitalism, which made it possible for a rapidly growing numbers of people to think

    about themselves, and to relate themselves to others. Although he speaks of cultural systems he

    puts emphasis on some structural changes, in connection with the processes of modernisation,

    which made it possible to imagine the new community.

    Brass stresses specifically the relevance of the nature of the modern centralising nation-state in

    explaining ethnic conflict. He writes that there is nothing natural or inevitable about ethnic

    conflict, the answers should be found in the relations between the centralising state and the

    regional ethnic elites (Brass 1991, p.242 and 244). Brass sees the state, especially in societies

    undergoing secularisation, modernisation and industrialisation, as both a resource and as a

    distributor of resources and at the same time as promoting new values. Therefore, the state and its

    policies are described as a potential advantage for some groups and societies and a threat for

    others, especially for local elites and societies whose values differ (Brass 1991, p.272).

    The processes of modernisation in a society consists of a dual fight for control of resources and

    values between bureaucracies and political organisations at the centre and between the elites of

    the centre and local elites. The ethnic elites function as effective rivals to the civil and military

    bureaucracies because of their ability to mobilise popular support, exactly because they control

    symbolic resources and values on the grounds of their cultural fundament. In this way the

    necessity for local collaborators arises - in the sense that the state makes alliances and coalitions

    with local ethnic elites, both because of state intrusion by its centralising policies, but also

    because of the fact that the ethnic groups pose a threat to the state due to their position as

    competing systems.

    As to the fight over resources Brass states that the objective existence of disparity is an

    indispensable explanation of ethnic conflict but not an explanation in itself. The mere presence of

    disparity is not enough to explain or produce a nationalistic movement, nor can it explain why

  • dominant groups develop a such (Brass 1991, p.41-42). In Brass understanding elites and competition among elites and the relation to the state are the essential elements in ethnic group

    conflict and political mobilisation. All other factors, including size and richness of available

    cultural symbols, regional economic disparities or the like, are just background material for the

    elites to draw from to their aims. Without the elites these differences or disparities will just vanish

    or be accepted or maybe be the cause of sporadic or isolated incidents of conflict or disorder. In

    this way Brass explains the rise of Croatian nationalism, not as a feeling of relative deprivation or

    deprivation at all, but due to the fact that there existed advantages for the lite that could be

    gained by emphasising Croatian distinctiveness (Brass 1991, p.44).

    Basically Brass puts emphasis on the interaction between the state and the peripheral ethnic elites

    in times of modernisation and drastic changes in the society, such as changes in the political

    context and in the balance of the centre-periphery relations. Ethnic conflicts emerge especially

    under three types of conditions: ...during transfer of power from colonial to post-colonial states, during succession struggles, and at times when central power appears to be weakening or the

    balance in centre-periphery relations appears to be changing (Brass 1991, p.244).

    2.4 Nationalism as a Cultural Phenomenon

    Other authors put more emphasis in explaining nationalism from the angle of fulfilling a basic

    need in people, meaning from a more actor-oriented angle. Benedict Anderson, who takes the task

    of explaining, what it is that make people love and die for nations - as well as hate and kill for it,

    finds it necessary, like Gellner and Hobsbawm, to understand how nations have come into

    historical being. In this sense you can say that he too holds a structuralistic historical approach.

    Unlike the other theorists, Anderson looks closely at the emotional power nationalism holds, and

    in this way he states that it would, I think, make things easier if one treated it (nationalism) as if it belonged with kinship and religion, rather than with liberalism or fascism (Anderson 1983, p.5).

    Andersons definition of the nation as an imagined political community - imagined as both inherently limited and sovereign (Anderson 1983, p.6) reveals that he as well puts emphasis on the political aspect of nationalism and the importance of the emergence of the modern

    centralising state. But unlike especially Gellner, he seeks to understand the emotional appeal and

    cultural nature of nationalism, this is especially underlined in his descriptions on the effects of

    print-capitalism, as a structural condition, but in the light of making it possible to imagine the

    community in a different way.

    Theories, like Gellners, are good for explaining the changes in linguistic and cultural standardisation that happened during the transition from agrarian society to industrial society.

    Gellners theoretical construction suffers however, from a very instrumentalist understanding of nationalism as such. It is as if he has never known the feeling or felt the need to confront with

    people that have felt it. Gellner lacks the ability to explain the emotional appeal nationalism

    holds. Therefore, as much as you can agree with his definition of nationalism as a political principle, which holds that the political and the national unit should be congruent as much you can disagree with his definition of nationalist sentiment as the feeling of anger aroused by the violation of this principle and a nationalist movement as one acurated by a sentiment of this kind (Gellner 1983, p.1).

    The imagination of the community plays a central role in Andersons understanding of nationalism. The community of the nation reaches beyond social and religious layers in society.

  • In spite of inequality and exploitation, the community is always imagined as a deep horizontal

    brotherhood. Thus Anderson looks at the strength of the community as a brotherhood, assuming a

    common past and destiny, in the course of which enormous sacrifices in the name of the nation

    was made in wars. Nationalism is strong as opposed to ideologies because these are not capable

    of giving answer to human sufferings and basic questions such as the meaning of death, illness

    and life in general.

    In this way nationalism is viewed as a transverse, cultural phenomenon which offers a feeling of

    community and identity in the nation which religion previously could offer (Anderson 1983,

    p.12). The nation is eternal, it offers a feeling of common destiny - it is worth dying for. Anderson points to the fact that nearly every West-European nation has a tomb for the Unknown Soldier. A symbol of the continuance of the nation, in spite of the fact that the soldier is dead and even not in the tomb. Because of the nature of the nation, the soldier is so to say still alive and the

    sacrifice that he made for his country is not forgotten (Anderson 1983, p.9). This is also the case

    when one refers to his homeland. This often happens in the style and vocabulary of kinship:

    Motherland, Vaterland, Patria, etc. These terms refer to something natural that one is naturally - by birth - tied to (Anderson 1983, p.143). In everything natural there is always something not chosen, things are just as they are. You are a part of the above-mentioned community of destiny.

    As a result, the nation can appeal for sacrifice and patriotism.

    Anderson makes in this way a comparison between family and patriotism/nation-ness. The nation

    calls for unselfish love and solidarity. This is what the family traditionally has been conceived as

    being the domain of. His conclusion is that patriotism is the same form of unselfishness, and that

    the nation therefore - via peoples patriotism - can make people sacrifice their life in war.

    Another important exponent of viewing nationalism as a cultural phenomenon rather than as an

    ideology or form of politics is Anthony D. Smith. According to him national identity provides for

    the individual a satisfying answer to the problem of personal oblivion, through the creation of a community of history and destiny which saves the individual from obliviation and restores collective faith (Smith 1991, p.160-161).

    He stresses the close relationship between the family, the ethnic community and the nation. He

    sees nationalism as a collective cultural identity, a sense of continuity over generations of a given

    cultural unit (the myth of common descent, rather than actual continuity of cultural patterns), as

    shared memories of earlier events, and as the idea of a collective destiny entertained by each

    generation. The pattern is the myths, symbols, collective memories and values which bind the

    generations together and demarcates the outsiders (Smith 1991, p.25). In this way it is as to become part of a political super-family, to realise the ideal of fraternity. Nations are in this way understood simply as families writ large, a large sum of many interrelated families, brothers and sisters all (Smith 1991, p.162).

    However, Smith still terms nationalism as an ideological movement, but here it is important to

    stress that he sees it as an ideology of the nation rather than the state. Smiths definition of the nation, as a named human population sharing an historic, common myths and historical memories, a mass, public culture, a common economy and common legal rights and duties for all

    members...sets it clearly apart from any conception of the state (Smith 1991, p.14). In this connection it is also interesting that his definition of nationalism does not necessarily include the

    wish for statehood but for maximal control of the homeland and its resources. But still this

    definition makes it possible to see national identity and nationalism as multi-dimensional and

    hence easily connected to political ideologies like liberalism, fascism, and communism.

  • Furthermore Smith does not deny the close historical relationship between the state and the

    nation, but he sees them as two clearly separated concepts. Nationalism in this way is seen as a

    sort of culture rather than a political doctrine and should not be mixed up with the fact that states

    use nationalism for legitimising purposes, which they have done and still do. The main difference

    then between Smith and Anderson is that Smith ascribes nationalism a cultural inner core while

    Anderson consistently views nationalism as an abstract phenomenon.

    2.5 Nationalism as a Primordial Phenomenon

    As noted above most of the theoreticians of nationalism understand the phenomenon in

    connection with the emergence of the modern centralising state and the related processes of

    modernisation. However, some of the authors put, more or less, emphasis on the so-called

    primordial aspects of nationalism in their understanding of the phenomenon. Primordialism

    means that the modern nation is seen as a representation of age-old cultural patterns. A modern

    form of group belonging formerly expressed in clans, kinship and ethnic groups. In this lies the

    understanding that nationalism should be seen as an expression for the human need of group

    belonging (which we also can recognise from Anderson).

    The rhetoric of nationalists themselves is the closest we come a pure primordial understanding.

    From this perspective nations are regarded as natural phenomena of great antiquity, to this picture

    we can add the nationalist myths of the nation waiting, Sleeping Beauty-like, to be awaken from its slumber, to fulfil its predestined goal of attaining freedom and autonomy (Anderson 1983,

    p.195 and Gellner 1983, p.48). As we have seen, Gellner views nationalism and nations as

    creations, and in describing them as such, he pictures the nationalist rhetorics and myths well.

    The myth of the nation as nature-given and eternal is false, he states, and goes on by writing that

    Nations as a natural, God-given way of classifying men, as an inherent though long-delayed political destiny, are a myth; nationalism, which sometimes takes pre-existing cultures and turns

    them into nations, sometimes invents them, and often obliterates pre-existing cultures: that is a

    reality... (Gellner 1983, p.48-49).

    In Smiths book National Identity he focuses exactly on the continuity between pre-modern ethnic identity and the modern nations. This puts him within the primordial school, although, as

    we shall see, he holds a more differentiated view. Contrary to the modernist, who claims that

    nations are inventions, Smith stresses that nationalism is not more invented than other forms of

    culture, ideology or social organisation (Smith 1991, p.71). Smith argues for a view in between

    the primordialists and modernists, stating that an ethnie (the French word he uses for ethnic

    communities) is formed, neither by actual ancestry nor by lines of physical descent (which is

    irrelevant). But through a sense of continuity, shared memory and collective destiny. Ethnies are

    so to speak formed by lines of cultural affinity, expressed in distinctive myths, memories,

    symbols, and values which are maintained and retained by a given cultural unit of the population

    (Smith 1991, p.29).

    Collective cultural identity, he writes, refers not to a uniformity of elements over generations but

    rather, to a sense of continuity on the part of successive generations of a given cultural unit of population, to shared memories of earlier events and periods in the history of that unit and to

    notions entertained by each generation about the collective destiny of that unit and its culture (Smith 1991, p.25).

    Smith is of the opinion that there is a relation between the modern nation and the premodern

    ethnie; ...many nations have been formed in the first place around a dominant ethnie, which

  • annexed or attracted other ethnies or ethnic fragments into the state to which it gave a name and a

    cultural charter (Smith 1991, p.39). But the connection is complex because of the fact that not all modern nations are based on this, i.e. United States of America, Australia and most of the African

    post-colonial states.

    Despite this fact, Smith states that there are some reasons why, the origins of the nation should be

    looked for in the pre-modern ethnic ties. First of all, the first nations were formed on the basis of

    pre-modern ethnic cores, and because they were so powerful and culturally influential, they

    became models for other cases of nation-formation. The second reason is that the ethnic model of

    the nation became increasingly popular and widespread, because it fitted so well to the premodern

    demotic kind of community that had survived into the modern era. The ethnic model was hence

    sociologically fertile. Third, even in the cases where there were no ethnic antecedents of

    importance, nations anyway need to create a certain coherent mythology and symbolism around a

    historical-cultural community (Smith 1991, p.41-41).

    2.6 Ethnicity

    In this section I would like to expand on the issue of ethnicity. First of all the difference between

    ethnicity and nationalism, an ethnic group and a nation. This mainly because of the fact that the

    chosen theoretical writings I have used so far are not specifically focused on ethnicity. Secondly

    from my point of view they also generally lack, what one might call, a social comprehension of

    ethnicity and national identity. I have therefore allowed myself to seek some answers from an

    anthropological perspective using mainly Thomas Hylland Eriksen Ethnicity and Nationalism.

    Basically the difference between nations and ethnic groups is seen to be a question of size but that

    the structural composition and functioning are of the same kind. Hylland Eriksen states that yes

    they are kindred conceptions but a distinction is worthwhile because of the relationship to the

    modern state (Eriksen 1993, p.98-99 and 105).

    In this respect you can speak of the difference between the notions of nation and ethnic group

    corresponding to the earlier mentioned distinction (section 2.1), between the nation seen as either

    political-civic or organic-cultural. In the organic-cultural the nation is defined in ethnic terms. In

    the political-civic the nation is defined in political terms inseparably connected to the notion of

    the nation state.

    But as we have seen, nations defined initially political-civic still are not to be understood

    exclusively as political organisations. They also have had and have to draw on symbolic resources

    in order to uphold a collective identity. Nations are thus seldom defined only by citizenship, but

    also by culture. Nations can contain different ethnic groups or be defined mainly or only by the

    dominant ethnic group. Both nationalism and ethnicity strives for and stresses the cultural

    similarity of their adherents, but in different ways. When we speak of this in relation to the two

    ideal types, the important difference is as mentioned, that the political-civic, is unifying and

    expanding, striving for inclusion. So even though we are dealing with ideal types, in the way that

    they are seldom found in a pure form, this does not make the distinction irrelevant. The

    governments of Mandela and Yeltsin are not nationalistic in the same way, as the governments of

    Tudjman or Landsbergis, who contrary to the first mentioned, have had an exclusive

    understanding of the nation and thus have agitated for fragmentation and restriction.

    The term ethno-nationalism should therefore be used to refer to the claim, of an ethnic group or a

    state, to an ethnically homogenous state. The conflictual aspect lies thus in the fact that many

  • states or ethnic groups do strive towards this goal or behave as if it was the case. In this way

    nationalism differentiate from ethnicity by its relation to the state, even though Smith have a point

    in not including the state in his definition of the nation and speak of maximal control of the

    homeland and its resources.

    Smith is one of the few who include this in his definition of the nation, whereas most others have

    it as the major difference between nation and ethnic group. In this way ethnicity is exactly not

    necessarily about attaining statehood. The statistics of the former Soviet Union spoke of 104

    nations comprising the union, they were in fact ethnic groups in as much as they didnt want full independence (Eriksen 1993, p.119). On the other hand however, one could also state, as Hylland

    Eriksen point out, that the phenomenon of ethnicity like nationalism is inseparable from the

    notion of the modern centralising territorial nation state since this has meant a politicisation of

    culture (Eriksen 1993, p.125). Ethnic groups become relevant because of the homogenising nature

    of the modern centralising nation state.

    Still we have to account for the differences between nation and ethnic group or what Anthony

    Smith calls an ethnie, the latter, according to Smith, being a premodern basis on which most

    nations are formed. Both Smith and Brass describes levels of ethnicity, from ethnic category

    through ethnic community to nations, which imply a focus on consciousness but also more or less

    on objective criteria. Objective criteria - since the starting point of this ladder is a set of criteria -

    which separate the different groups from each other. Smiths starting point is the ethnic category, which by others are seen to constitute a separate entity without any special self-consciousness to ethnie defined by believed common cultural traits and a self-consciousness and finally to the nation. Brass also operates with the difference between ethnic category and ethnic community defined by ethnicity as self-consciousness and then finally the nation. The ethnic category being defined by some more or less objective but chosen criteria, amongst many

    possible, which through the ethnic community to the nation increases in number as well as

    subjective meaning.

    Hylland Eriksen also operates with different levels of ethnicity but with another agenda. That is

    looking specifically on the relationship between groups and in this way showing that ethnicity can

    have different social importance, be up- or downgraded according to the social context (Eriksen

    1993, p.41).

    Brass also states, as we have seen, that ethnicity can be activated in special context or/and at

    specific times. The difference is however, that Hylland Eriksen has a more social angel than, as

    Brass, a mere instrumental angel to this. Before entering this discussion I have to dwell a bit on

    Hylland Eriksens overall position on ethnicity, which will shed some light on the subject.

    Hylland Eriksen defines ethnicity as a special kind of consciously communicated and manifested

    cultural identity. An identity building on the consciousness of being different. However, cultural

    difference between two groups is not the decisive feature of ethnicity, only in so far as cultural

    differences are perceived as being important, and are made socially relevant do relationships have

    an ethnic element. Ethnicity is rather constituted through social interaction than cultural content

    (Eriksen 1993, p.18 and p.36). Hence ethnic groups does necessarily emerge because of contacts

    between groups. Ethnicity is therefore an aspect of a social relation between groups (Eriksen

    1993, p.11-12). To speak of an isolated ethnic group is like to hear a sound from one hand

    clapping as he writes (Eriksen 1993, p.1).

    Hylland Eriksen also draws on the work of Frederik Barth from 1969, which can be characterised

  • as a watershed within the study of ethnicity. Barth precisely turned the focus from the cultural

    content to looking at ethnicity as emerging in the borderland between groups. Therefore it is the

    boundaries - as a social and not territorial phenomenon upon, which the focus should be put.

    Ethnicity is always about culture - people or groups that subjectively maintain cultural

    peculiarity. The problem is precisely that cultures, which subjectively differentiate from each

    other, not always do so objectively. But when the mutual subjective understanding is such that the

    groups do differ from each other, then it constitutes a social reality, which is manifested as ethnic

    identity. The maintenance of ethnic boundary is therefore, from the point of view of Barth, a

    social phenomenon, rather than a cultural, and therefore it is exactly the life and movements of

    the boundary that must be studied and not the cultural content. Cultural variation is rather an

    effect then a cause of boundaries. Hence a focus on the social relations, the way the borders are

    maintained and changed over time and in that way also how the meaning changes.

    This corresponds to the view on culture as complex, something fluid and dynamic. Culture is not

    something that is, but something that takes place in a constant process of change and negotiation.

    This also implies a view on persons as complex entities with several social identities, which are

    created, undergo change and that is activated in different social situations. In this paradigm

    ethnicity is defined as fluid and negotiable. The importance varies situational. The we category can be expanded and contracted according to the situation and the individual can choose to

    emphasise different social identities at different times (Eriksen 1993, p.20-35).

    Although somewhat unfair to most of the theories, as their main focus rest upon other aspects, we

    may use this discussion to criticise the body of theoretical work so far used. They have, I would

    not say a too categorical view on nations and ethnic groups, but do exactly not stress this fluid,

    situational and negotiable aspect of ethnicity and national identity. Most of them, as we have

    seen, do emphasise the constructed aspect of ethnic and national identity but roughly speaking I

    would still say that they treat nations in a too fixed and categorical manner.

    Thus I find this anthropological approach by Hylland Eriksen and Barth very useful because they

    turn the focus on boundaries rather than cultural content and by doing so particularly points to the

    fluid or situational character of ethnicity. This opens up for a more complex view on these

    collective categories. Not just as something that is not static but also not treated as a totality. This

    point became very obvious to me in the field, working closely with the different UN agencies and

    the OSCE. These organisations, as well as several NGOs, very often treated the different ethnic groups almost as if they were singular actors. Thereby playing along in the continuos

    entrenchment of the us and them dichotomy.

    Of cause one could say to their defence that this is exactly what nationalism and ethnicity is

    about, as the Croatian writer Slavenka Draculic so nicely puts it: The problem with this nationalism is however, that where I previously was defined by my education, profession, my

    thoughts, my personality - and yes also my nationality, - I now feel deprived from all of this. I am

    nothing, no longer a person. I am one of 4.5 million Croats (Draculic 1993, p.49-50, my translation).

    But academically, and in the field for that sake, it is still important to have an eye for the fact that

    ...identities are never completed, never finished, that they are always as subjectivity itself is, in process...all of us are composed of multiple social identities not of one (Stuart Hall 1991, p.47 and p.57). In this lies the assumption that identities can crosscut one another and sometimes even

    be contradictory. This opens up for not just treating these aggregated groups as totalities, but to

    look at the internal role-divisioning and the possibility for individuals to not only over- or under-

  • communicate their ethnic or national identity but to shift between different identities and in some

    instances even change affiliation[4].

    2.7 Summing Up and Conclusions

    Nationalism as we have seen above has not one, but several meanings depending on space and

    time and is changeable as well. Nationalism or rather nationalisms are multidimensional and

    ambiguous phenomena. Most of the theoreticians not only emphasise one aspect of nationalism

    but include several different aspects, although to a greater or lesser extend.

    Nevertheless nationalism can broadly be understood as a socio-political phenomenon, as an

    emotional affiliation to a country and/or a group of people, as a form of collective consciousness.

    I.e. the nation-state can be understood as a territory where the population is united in a nation by

    the bond of nationalism, that being mainly defined in a civic-political or in a mainly organic-

    ethnic manner. But nationalism can also be attached to people or ethnic groups across or within

    the framework of the state and might be expressed in demands of grades of autonomy of own

    affairs or in the more extreme cases, as ours, separatism.

    Nationalism is a relatively modern phenomenon, but it is a mixture of old and new, politics and

    culture. Nationalism would not possess the strength in emotional appeal if it couldnt draw on the feelings of a shared community, cultural, historical memories and fulfil a need in the individual.

    This is a very important fact to note in relation to ethnic conflict; ethnic mobilisation is only

    possible where these symbolic resources have been continuously maintained and developed in

    order to command its emotional strength and thus function as the basis of mobilisation. The

    nation is imagined and a construction, but also a social reality, and it should not be treated as

    something false and unreal.

    The argument, that states such as the Soviet Union or Yugoslavia are artificial implies that there are natural nations. As we have seen the nation is a modern phenomenon, all nation states are artificial, i.e. social and political constructions. In fact only 10 per cent of states can claim to be true nation-states, in the sense that the boundaries of the state coincide with the nation, defined ethnically (Smith 1991, p.15). And then again ethnicity is, as we also have seen, no less imagined,

    but also a social phenomenon. Culture is not something, which is but something we do.

    Although I agree up to a point, that contrary to many nationalist ideologies, it is not nations that

    make states, it is at the same time important not to reverse the argument and simply claim the

    opposite like Hobsbawm does, when he writes that Nations do not make states and nationalisms but the other way around (Hobsbawm 1990, p.10). Nations can be developed without the agencies of the state and strive for statehood. One should not only see nations as creations, or

    something made imaginable by the elites of the state-apparatus. This can also happen through

    ethnic elites without a state-structure at hand. Here it is often intellectuals or academics that are

    having an important role in shaping and maintaining the symbolic resources of the group. But it is

    a point worth stressing, in the spirit of Brass that this is often happening exactly as a consequence

    of the policies of the modern centralising nation state.

    Already now we can thus draw some conclusions. Ethnic conflict does not steam from old ancient

    hatreds. Ethno-national identities are a modern phenomenon. Multinational or heterogeneous

    states are not artificial constructions. The idea of the nation is artificial - a construction or an

    imagination - a social reality - yes - but the idea of the homogeneous nation-state is an illusion.

    The fact is that 90 percent of present days states are ethnic heterogeneous makes homogeneity an

  • illusion. And this illusion or strive towards homogeneity is the conflictual aspect - not

    heterogeneity.

    Finally it should be mentioned that despite the acknowledged strength in the emotional appeal of

    nationalism and its spread as a principle all over the world, most of the authors however, agree

    with the point, that nationalism is theoretically and ideologically weak, especially due to its

    abstract and multidimensional character.

    In this way Anderson notes the philosophical poverty and incoherence of nationalism (Anderson

    1983, p.5). But this emptiness also reflects the strength of nationalism (besides its emotional

    appeal), which lies in its chameleon-like nature and its facility in combing with other issues and

    ideologies (Smith 1991, p.144). Nationalism ...once created, they (different forms of early nationalisms) became modular, capable of being transplanted, with varying degrees of self-consciousness, to a great variety of social terrains, to merge and be merged with a correspondingly wide variety of political and ideological constellations (Anderson 1983, p.4).

    Because of the emptiness, it becomes possible to fill the void with other elements like ideologies

    and political programmes. So the conclusion must be that in order for nationalism to have success

    it needs more than cultural differences it must be attached to political questions. As Gellner

    writes, nationalism is not as strong as it seems like, who for the simplicity of his argument

    mentions language as the criteria for culture, and states that then we have 8000 potential

    nationalisms but only around 200 states (Gellner 1983, p.44-45). Cultural, national, and linguistic

    etc. differences are constituent parts of nationalism, but in themselves not enough to produce

    nationalism. As even Smith writes ...national aspirations tend to combine with other non-national economic, social or political issues, and the power of the movement often derives from

    this combination (Smith 1991, p.145).

    In further continuation of this it is a theoretical point that an analysis of ethno-national conflicts

    must be contextual. The specificity of the individual ethnic conflict is thus interesting, i.e. socio-

    economic, historic, political etc. conditions and relations. At the same time I want to stress that

    one should not only focus on rational calculations in an understanding of ethnic conflict. The

    power of nationalism lies in the combination of the rational with the irrational. You might see the irrational as being the fuel of nationalism and the rational the catalyst. In this way the

    imagination of the community, the feeling of belonging, the shared myths, collective memories of

    earlier events in history, symbols etc. should be understood as the irrational fuel of nationalism in

    order to give it or uphold its emotional strength.

    [1] Based on Smith 1991, p.80-81.

    [2] This figure is made on the basis of Smith 1991, Hobsbawm 1990 and Marlene Wind

    1992, p.41-51.

    [3] I will return to a closer definitional discussion of ethnic groups and ethnicity in section

    2.6.

    [4] The latter part of this section I owe a great deal from the article by Stuart Hall, Old and New Identities, Old and New Ethnicities.

  • 3 The Dynamics of Ethnic Conflict

    t has been shown that wars defined as ethnic conflicts on an average have a

    significant longer duration than other types of war; that more frequently ethnic

    conflicts do not end by negotiated solutions but by outright military victory by

    either side, and finally that ethnic civil war is of a more vicious nature (though

    not necessarily more destructive) than other forms of conflict (King 1997,

    p.13 and 24-25 and Scherrer 1997, p.42). The common explanations for this

    intractability and protracted nature of ethnic conflict have often been ascribed

    to the uncontrollable irrational behaviour motivated by deeply rooted ancient

    hatreds and incompatible deeply felt values and identities of the belligerents in

    ethnic conflict (King 1997, p.13 and 52).

    In this chapter I shall look for alternative explanations to the nature of ethnic

    conflict. Looking specifically on the structure of conflict or armed

    conflict/warfare to be more precise; determining structural factors that can

    help explain the protracted nature and intractability of ethnic conflict in

    another light than the above mentioned. Some of these factors may be

    applicable to inter-state conflicts and other intra-state conflicts as well. The

    purpose of this chapter is however, not only to determine and characterise the

    specific nature of ethnic conflicts but in fact mainly to focus on conflict

    dynamics of ethnic conflict contrary to the previous theoretical chapter which

    focused on ethnicity and nationalism. The specific characteristics or relevant

    differences between ethnic conflict and other kinds of intra-state conflicts I

    shall return to at the end of this chapter, for now I will use the different terms

    for intra-state conflicts more or less indiscriminately.

    A final opening remark should be made about the fact that despite that most of

    the wars since 1945 has been intra-state conflicts there exist little, if any,

    comprehensive theoretical research on the dynamics and even the causes of

    intra-state conflicts (Scherrer 1997, p.50 and Nielsen 1997, p.2). This is

    therefore based mainly upon working papers and articles and should therefore

    be seen as theoretical reflections rather than as a coherent theoretical chapter

    in comparison to the previous theoretical chapter on nationalism and

    ethnicity.

    3.1 The Scene of Conflict

    One of the most distinguishing features of ethnic conflict is that it is typically

    a non-state conflict wholly or partly (Hobsbawm 1993, p.41). The main

    characteristic of intra-state conflict is the absence of a state structure or the

    existence of a weak one. They are mainly taking place in either collapsing

    states or emerging states in the process of state building. This is according to

    all the authors I have encountered in this field the key to an understanding of

    intra-state conflict (Brown 1993, p.6, Mller 1996, p.20, King 1997, p.50-51,

  • Vorkunova 1997, p.49, Hobsbawm 1993, p.41-42 and Snyder 1993, p.86).

    This factor may not be sufficient for conflicts to break out, but definitely

    makes them possible, and of interest for the present purpose, determine the

    specific course of these conflicts (Brown 1993, p.12).

    Hobsbawm writes in an article that almost everyone, who have experienced

    both civil wars and ordinary inter-state wars, are likely to think that civil wars

    are worse:

    The major reason why this should be so lies precisely in the disappearance of the accepted mechanisms of public order. The Hobbesian argument that,

    however deficient and unjust the state, it is better than its absence, the

    Hobbesian state of nature or public anarchy, carries substantial force, as many people in ex-Yugoslavia and the ex- USSR will confirm (Hobsbawm 1993, p.42).

    Eric Hobsbawm sees the existence of a functioning state as the most important

    condition or perhaps as indispensable for the control of ethnic conflicts. Here

    it is not so much the question whether the institutional anarchy is a cause of

    ethnic conflict or a prerequisite, this I will return to later. But that it is in this

    anarchical setting that ethnic conflict unfolds and this determine the dynamics

    and nature of this form of conflict. As Michael Ignatieff writes:

    Thomas Hobbes would have understood Yugoslavia...There is one type of fear more devastating in its impact than any other: the systemic fear which

    arises when a state begins to collapse. Ethnic hatred is the result of the terror

    which arises when legitimate authority disintegrates (Ignatieff 1994, p.16).

    Even though he implies the collapse of state-structure as a reason for conflict

    (which we for now will keep in mind), the main point here is his emphasis on

    terror - or in other words the brutal way this kind of conflict evolves - the way

    anarchy prevails (Brown 1993, p.6).

    This, which by some has been called the institutional anarchy of civil war

    (King 1997, p.51), brings me to a description of the nature of conflict.

    3.2 The Nature of Conflict

    Inter-state wars can be characterised by more or less clear-formed parties, not

    necessarily of same strength, but of same structure. It is fought between

    recognised states and their respectively subordinated regular armed forces,

    which usually are identifiable from each other and from the civilian

    population (Wallensteen 1994, p.74). The application of the Geneva

  • Convention is unproblematic (Scherrer 1997, p.8, though not always followed

    I would add), and the conflict is taking place in an overall international state-

    system where certain rules are followed and observed.

    In the institutional anarchy of intra-state war, which of course can be of

    different degrees, there is a lack or absence of organisational or

    institutionalised practises. No sharply defined borderlines, which simplify

    inter-state confrontations, even when it comes to the uniforms or other

    identifying marks which, distinguish combatant from non-combatant

    (Hobsbawm 1993, p.41).

    In intra-state wars we are not dealing with two or more national armies. Combatants in civil wars are most often of a very non-traditional nature

    without a traditional military line of command. This is again often exacerbated by the fact that the communication network is in a bad shape or

    even non-existing. Guerrilla fighters, child soldiers and soldier bandits can

    moreover, in contrast to professional soldiers or conscripts, be very difficult to

    control (King 1997, p.33-35 and Mller 1996, p.iv).

    In short intra-state wars tend to be more messy and bloody, even just because

    of the fact that at least one of belligerents is a non-state actor, operating under

    more permissive rules than states tend to (Mller 1996, p.23). However, as

    another author points out, its is not only, or in fact it is often, the states (read

    weak states) rather than the insurgents, that are the main actors in a not

    spontaneous but organised brutal warfare (Scherrer 1997, p.47).

    Furthermore, in comparison to inter-state conflicts it is often more difficult or

    sometimes made deliberately difficult to determine who the belligerent sides

    are in intra-state conflicts. Who are the leaders in charge or spokespersons,

    who represents the real interests at stake in the conflict and who are entitled to

    negotiate, compromise and enforce of reached decisions (Mller 1996, p.39

    and King 1997, p.33).

    This may be further complicated by the fact that factionalism is likely to be

    more intense in intra-state conflicts. The argument here is that intra-state

    conflicts overall is about legitimacy and/or sovereignty and once this has been

    questioned, factionalism can continue to the smallest nucleus (Rana 1995, p.9

    and King 1997, p.34). Several parties and likely leaders can emerge and the

    question is then who should and can sign a final peace-agreement. This of

    course also deepens mutual suspicions and prolongs the way to peace (Mller

    1996, p.39).

    The above mentioned factors makes an assessment of military costs and

    benefits with the overall political objectives extremely difficult. Superior

    logistics is the hallmark of war