schiller. ''phaedo'' 104-105_is the soul a form

Upload: blaise09

Post on 02-Jun-2018

219 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/11/2019 Schiller. ''Phaedo'' 104-105_Is the Soul a Form

    1/10

    "Phaedo" 104-105: Is the Soul a Form?

    Author(s): Jerome SchillerReviewed work(s):Source: Phronesis, Vol. 12, No. 1 (1967), pp. 50-58Published by: BRILLStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/4181792.

    Accessed: 13/03/2013 13:54

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at.http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

    .JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of

    content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms

    of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    .

    BRILLis collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Phronesis.

    http://www.jstor.org

    This content downloaded on Wed, 13 Mar 2013 13:54:29 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=baphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/4181792?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/4181792?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=bap
  • 8/11/2019 Schiller. ''Phaedo'' 104-105_Is the Soul a Form

    2/10

  • 8/11/2019 Schiller. ''Phaedo'' 104-105_Is the Soul a Form

    3/10

    (the

    absolute

    form)

    nor

    the form in

    things

    (the

    immanent

    form)

    will

    admit its opposite and become other than what it was, but sooner would

    depart

    or perish (102B-103B);

    that there are things,

    such as

    snow

    and fire, which,

    though

    not the

    forms cold and heat,

    behave

    just

    like

    these forms

    when the

    opposites

    of the

    forms

    approach: they

    either

    depart

    or

    perish

    (103C-103E);

    that this

    is true of other

    things,

    for

    instance,

    the number

    three

    (which

    will not admit the form even)

    and

    two (which

    will not admit

    the form odd) (103

    E - 104 C). Socrates

    then

    poses

    the

    question,

    What sort of

    things

    are these? and A is the

    answer.

    Between

    A and

    B,

    in

    addition

    to a

    summary

    of

    points

    made

    previously,

    we have the observation that we can now name such things as causes

    of the presence

    of

    a

    certain

    quality

    in

    something:

    thus

    fire

    (and

    not

    the old,

    'safe'

    heat)

    can be cited

    as the cause

    of

    something's being hot,

    or

    fever

    (and

    not

    illness)

    the cause

    of

    someone's

    being ill (104

    D

    -

    105

    C). B

    is

    then presented

    as an elaboration

    of

    an

    instance of the

    principle

    just

    developed:

    the soul is

    (parallel

    to fire) that which causes

    the body

    in which it

    is

    to

    be

    alive

    (parallel

    to its

    being hot).

    The

    immortality

    of the soul

    is

    then established

    by recalling

    the earlier

    admission

    that

    things,

    such as

    three,

    which are associated with

    particular

    forms,

    such

    as

    odd,

    cannot admit the

    opposite

    of

    those

    forms.

    And

    just

    as what

    cannot admit the

    even and has no

    part

    in

    the

    even

    is 'uneven'

    (aCvxpTLov),

    o the

    soul,

    which does not

    admit

    death,

    is 'immortal' (&Oavaoov) (105

    D

    -

    105

    E). (Then

    Socrates

    goes

    on to

    prove

    that

    if it is

    immortal,

    it is

    imperishable

    [105E-107A], but

    we

    are

    not concerned

    with this

    phase

    of his

    argument.)

    Does

    Plato

    view

    the

    soul, up

    to 105

    E

    at least, as an immanent

    form?

    The

    soul is introduced as

    being parallel

    to certain things

    -

    snow,

    fire,

    and three

    -

    each of

    which,

    while

    being

    so

    intimately

    associated

    with a form

    that it cannot exist

    without

    that

    form,

    is

    never really

    called

    a

    form, and,

    commonsensically,

    should not be taken as other

    than

    a concrete thing.

    Two

    points,

    however,

    seem to shatter

    this

    simple

    answer:

    one of these

    'things,'

    at

    least,

    does seem to be

    identified

    as a form

    in the

    course of the

    argument,

    namely,

    three at 104D5-6

    ( V

    TPv

    EpOv

    'L); moreover,

    this

    form

    is

    said to occupy

    (xorOCay-n)

    something, just

    as the

    soul

    is said to

    occupy

    (xc-aXa-)

    the body

    at

    105

    D3.

    Hackforth

    develops

    his

    argument

    in this fashion: In

    103 C 10

    -

    105

    B 4,

    he claims, Plato

    is

    extending

    to other entities the

    principle

    of exclusion

    of opposites established earlier. These other entities are

    forms

    such as

    'twoness'

    and 'fieriness'. Though

    not

    themselves opposites, they

    51

    This content downloaded on Wed, 13 Mar 2013 13:54:29 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Schiller. ''Phaedo'' 104-105_Is the Soul a Form

    4/10

    exclude forms which are opposites. Hackforth defends his

    inter-

    pretation of these other entities being forms (and not things) in these

    words: "Here [104E10-105A1]

    at

    least,

    whatever be

    the case else-

    where...,

    -To-sup

    is conceived as a

    form, fieriness,

    not as

    a

    particular

    fire; not merely

    because

    it

    is

    mentioned

    in

    the

    same breath with

    a&uc,

    but also because

    the

    whole

    paragraph

    in

    which it

    occurs is

    concerned

    not with

    things

    but

    with forms...

    Plato

    defines

    [these

    forms] by

    reference to

    the

    things

    which

    they

    come

    to

    'occupy'

    (104 D1, 6): and

    that he should do so

    is

    quite natural, since the form

    which he

    has in

    mind

    - the form to which all the

    illustrations of his

    principles point - is soul, which occupies a body, and 'brings up' into

    that body

    the form

    of an

    opposite,

    viz.

    the form

    'aliveness'

    (life)

    ."3

    In commenting

    later on his

    interpretation

    of

    the soul as

    a

    form, he

    notes: Only

    if soul

    is

    regarded

    as

    a

    form

    "can

    what

    is

    now

    asserted of

    soul

    be

    a

    corollary,

    or

    deduction,

    or

    application

    -

    whatever

    one chooses

    to

    call

    it

    -

    of the

    elaborate

    argument

    about

    the

    exclusion of

    opposite

    forms:

    provided,

    that

    is,

    that

    I have

    been

    right

    in

    regarding

    that

    argument

    as

    concerned

    with

    forms...

    And

    if

    any

    doubt still

    lingers in

    the reader's

    mind, surely

    the

    use of the word

    XoaraGZ-n

    n

    105

    D

    3 is,

    despite

    Burnet's

    note, conclusive;

    to

    my mind,

    at all

    events,

    it

    is

    inconceivable

    that

    it could mean there

    anything

    other than

    what it

    meant

    at 104

    D

    1, namely

    the

    occupation

    of a

    subject by

    an

    immanent

    form."4

    In

    light of

    this

    last

    statement,

    Archer-Hind's comment

    on

    araCaxB

    at

    105

    D

    3

    is

    perplexing:

    "It is to be

    noted that the

    usage

    of

    xa-nxa-j&

    here

    is

    different from

    that

    in

    104

    D.

    The soul

    does not

    occupy

    the

    body

    in the sense

    in which

    IpL&'

    occupies -pta:

    the triad

    is

    the cause

    why

    three

    are

    three,

    the

    soul

    is

    not

    the cause

    why body

    is

    body,

    but

    the

    cause

    why

    it

    is

    alive.

    The

    difference

    lies

    in

    this:

    the triad is

    the idea

    of

    three;

    the soul which

    quickens

    the

    body

    is not the

    idea of

    soul,

    but

    a

    particular soul, just

    as the fever

    is

    a

    particular

    fever."5

    How

    shall

    we decide between

    these

    readings?

    We

    might suspect

    Archer-Hind of

    sacrificing

    the

    parallelism

    of the

    passages

    because

    he

    is

    convinced

    -

    on

    evidence

    external

    to

    the

    argument

    -

    that

    there

    cannot be an

    'idea of

    soul,'

    but

    only particular

    souls. But he

    cannot

    be

    guilty

    of

    such

    prejudice,

    for he

    goes on,

    in

    this

    very note,

    to claim

    that the

    argument

    commits

    Plato to an idea of

    soul

    -

    though

    this

    is

    a

    3Hackforth, op. cit., 156.

    4

    Hackforth,

    op. cit., 162.

    5

    R. D. Archer-Hind,

    The

    Phaedo

    of

    Plato

    (2nd

    ed. London, 1894), 115-116.

    52

    This content downloaded on Wed, 13 Mar 2013 13:54:29 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Schiller. ''Phaedo'' 104-105_Is the Soul a Form

    5/10

    'metaphysical

    monstrosity'

    -

    which

    supplies

    the idea of life to

    par-

    ticular souls, which in turn bear this idea to bodies. Even though this

    idea

    of soul

    is not mentioned in the

    argument,

    he claims that it

    is

    necessitated

    by

    'the

    elaborate parallel'

    and

    supported

    by

    other

    passages

    from

    early

    Plato.6

    I

    believe

    that

    three features of this

    argument

    conclusively support

    Archer-Hind's

    reading

    that the soul functions here as a

    particular

    thing,

    not

    as an

    immanent

    form.

    First,

    if

    Hackforth

    is

    correct,

    Plato

    has not

    only equivocated

    on

    'soul,'

    but he would also be

    forced to

    accept

    the absurd

    implication

    that the

    body

    is

    immortal.

    Second,

    the

    shift in xovraX necessitated by Archer-Hind's interpretation does not

    spoil

    the

    argument,

    but fits

    naturally

    into its

    development. Third,

    a

    study of

    the locutions Plato uses

    for

    'three'

    undermines Hackforth's

    reading.

    Hackforth

    translates

    104 D5-7 of

    passage

    A above

    (olaOo

    ..

    7rept-ToZq)

    in this way: "You

    know presumably that

    anything occupied by the

    character of three must

    be not

    only

    three but also

    odd."7

    Plato

    continues

    (104D9-10):

    'E7r.L

    rO' oLtQov

    8",

    Y04LEV, I

    EVOCVT'CBea ?XCSLVy)

    fn

    UopqPn

    asxv

    7OUO

    iUMpYOCJTOC

    L

    OUU7MOT

    OaV E'XOOL.

    Here Hackforth translates:

    "Well,

    what we

    maintain

    is

    that such a

    thing

    can never be

    visited

    by

    the character that is

    opposite to the

    form which

    brings

    that

    about."8 The

    second passage clearly

    indicates

    that the

    thing

    occupied by

    the character of

    three (ro toLoitov)can

    never

    admit of

    evenness. Now if

    xoc-&aX-n

    ere

    being

    used in a

    perfectly

    parallel

    fashion here and at

    105 D3,

    as

    Hackforth

    maintains,

    the thing

    occupied

    in

    that

    passage (the

    body)

    could

    never be visited

    by the

    character that is

    opposite

    to

    the

    form which

    brings life about

    (death):

    in other words, Plato would have shown that the body cannot admit of

    death,

    that

    is,

    that the

    body

    is

    immortal.

    Three considerations show that

    the shift in the

    use of

    xot&aXj

    from

    104

    D

    to 105

    D

    is

    a natural

    and

    expected one. First, the use

    of

    xovc(X&a

    at

    105 D3

    may

    be

    viewed

    as

    reminding the reader

    of

    a

    previous part

    of the

    argument and not

    necessarily

    as

    asserting any

    parallels with its

    previous use. It is

    certainly clear that Plato is

    pressing the parallel

    6

    Archer-Hind, op. cit., 116.

    7Hackforth,

    op.

    cit.,

    152.

    8

    Idem.

    53

    This content downloaded on Wed, 13 Mar 2013 13:54:29 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Schiller. ''Phaedo'' 104-105_Is the Soul a Form

    6/10

    between

    the

    soul and

    three. Thus at

    104E1

    ff. he

    claims

    successively

    that the even never visits three

    (O86no'Te i"s),

    that three has no part

    (o`4otpa)

    in

    the

    even, and

    that

    it is

    thus uneven

    (iv0ap'ro4).

    At 105 D

    lOff.

    he notes that the

    soul

    will

    never

    admit

    (ou'

    .o$no'r

    8r6-iqto)

    death,

    that

    we

    now

    (v5v) agree

    to call

    that which does not

    admit the even,

    the uneven

    (v6p4rtov);

    so we

    should

    call the

    soul

    immortal

    (iOOvourov).

    But between these

    two

    passages

    Plato

    introduces

    his

    extension of the

    causal

    principle (105B-C).

    The later use

    of

    xmrx-Zn

    may thusi be

    justified

    as

    welding together

    two

    parts of the

    argument. It preserves

    the

    continuity by being

    'a

    simple military metaphor' which

    'implies

    no metaphysical theory.'9

    A

    second reason

    for

    thinking the

    shift in the

    use of

    xoo&a/yr

    o

    be

    an

    easy one

    lies in

    the

    translation of

    104D1-3. Alternatetranslationsof

    this part of

    passage

    A above

    (TAp'

    o'v...

    -uvO4;) demand

    very

    different

    degrees

    of

    parallelism

    in

    the

    two

    uses.

    Contrast

    Hackforth's translation

    with

    Tredennick's:

    Hackforth:

    "Must

    they

    not be

    those

    which

    compel

    the object which

    they

    come

    to

    occupy

    to

    have

    not

    only

    its own

    character,

    but

    also the character

    of a

    certain

    opposite,

    which it

    will

    never lose?"10 Tredennick:

    "Well, then, Cebes,

    would

    this

    describe

    them

    -

    that they are things which are compelled by some form which

    takes possession

    of them

    to

    assume

    not

    only

    its own

    form

    but

    in-

    variably also

    that of some

    other

    form

    which

    is an

    opposite?"11

    No doubt

    Hackforth's translation conforms well

    to

    the

    Greek,

    but

    things

    can

    be said

    for

    Tredennick's

    rendering

    which

    perhaps

    over-

    weigh this.

    First,

    it

    makes

    the

    reference

    of

    X

    in

    D

    1

    consistent

    with that

    in D5 as 'things occupied.'

    Secondly,

    it

    obviates Burnet's note

    on the

    shift

    from

    the

    plural (1)

    to the

    singular (octu'ro5)

    n the

    reference

    to

    the

    occupying things.'2

    (Of

    course

    this note

    is

    also obviated

    in

    Hackforth's

    translation

    with

    ai&ro5 eing

    taken

    as

    referring

    to the

    thing

    occupied.13)

    9John

    Burnet, Plato's Phaedo

    (Oxford,

    1911),

    123.

    10

    Hackforth,

    op. cit.,

    151.

    11 Hugh Tredennick,

    'Phaedo,'

    in Last Days of Socrates,

    reprinted in E.

    Hamilton

    and

    H. Cairns, eds. Collected

    Dialogues

    of Plato

    (New York, 1961),

    86.

    3 Burnet, op.

    cit., 119-120.

    13

    Tredennick's

    or

    Burnet's

    translation

    of

    uT-rO

    in

    which

    it

    refers to

    the

    occu-

    pying form

    - "forces the thing occupied

    to assume the

    form of the occupier"

    -

    when coupled

    with

    Hackforth's

    interpretation

    of

    the

    parallels of 104

    I) and

    105

    D, may appear to

    lead to an even

    greater paradox

    than that

    of

    the

    body's

    immortality, namely, the paradox that the body is really a soul. Thus, following

    the

    lead of 103E3

    and 104A2

    where

    things

    other

    than forms are

    said to receive

    names

    of forms, it

    might be

    argued

    that

    the

    object occupied wouild lhave

    to

    54

    This content downloaded on Wed, 13 Mar 2013 13:54:29 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Schiller. ''Phaedo'' 104-105_Is the Soul a Form

    7/10

    As Burnet notes, 'the pronouns

    are

    a

    little puzzling' in this passage

    ;14

    perhaps in such a situation the advantages of Tredennick's translation

    outweigh those of

    Hackforth's.

    If we do adopt Tredennick's

    reading, there seems to be less demand

    for parallelism

    in

    the use

    of

    xcetaCXq

    t 104 D and 105 D. The 'things'

    which behave like opposites are things occupied

    by forms and not

    forms which

    actively occupy.

    Thus it is an

    object occupied by

    the form

    of three,

    and

    not

    the threeness which

    occupies

    it, which, not accepting

    the

    opposite

    of the

    form

    that

    accompanies threeness,

    is

    said to

    be

    uneven (104E).

    The

    stress on

    these things

    which

    passively receive

    their properties de-emphasizes

    xcnaz-p

    in its first appearance, while

    paving the way for

    a soul

    which

    is

    immortal, just

    as three is uneven.

    But though

    the

    way

    is

    prepared

    for

    an

    easy transition

    to

    the

    different

    use

    of

    xo&aXy,

    one

    further step is required: to associate these

    objects,

    hitherto characterized

    primarily

    in

    a

    passive fashion,

    with

    some sort of activity. The transition is accomplished

    by making these

    things

    into

    causes.

    Thus, according

    to

    the new, refined answer

    to the

    causal question,

    it

    is

    not

    heat

    which makes

    a

    body hot, but fire; not

    illness which makes

    a

    body ill, but fever. But

    this observation will not

    convince anyone who takes the fire or fever of 105 C to be forms, and

    not to

    be

    examples

    of

    things occupied.

    I

    suggest

    that Plato shows,

    in

    another difficult passage, 105

    A

    3-5, that the latter

    is the

    more

    plausible

    interpretation.

    As

    we have

    seen

    above,

    such

    things

    as three do not admit

    the

    opposite

    of the

    form

    accompanying

    their occupying

    form. Until

    104 E 10 these things

    are

    not characterized as

    engaging in any activity

    further

    than

    this

    refusal to admit forms.

    At

    104E7-105A1, however,

    they

    not

    only

    do not

    admit

    (axeLroc) the

    opposite,

    but

    they bring

    forward (Ernpepet)

    the opposite they contain against the intruding

    form,

    as

    three brings

    forth oddness against the even, two brings

    forth

    evenness,

    and

    fire,

    heat.

    In

    his

    next breath, Plato elaborates

    their

    receive the

    name of the occupying form, so

    that, assuming the parallelism of the

    two passages,

    the

    body would have to be named 'soul' in conformance

    with

    its

    occupying form.

    But there are two reasons

    for not pressing this paradox. First, the reference

    of

    muTro5

    s

    not at

    all

    clear.

    Second,

    even

    if

    Tredennick's translation

    is

    correct,

    Plato need

    not be taken as saying that

    the thing occupied must receive

    the

    name of the occupying

    form as

    its substantial

    name, but only as an attribute.

    Thus heat causes an object to be hot, not to be heat; life causes it to be alive,

    not life; so

    soul would cause body to be besouled,

    perhaps, and not soul.

    14

    Burnet,

    op. cit., 119.

    55

    This content downloaded on Wed, 13 Mar 2013 13:54:29 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Schiller. ''Phaedo'' 104-105_Is the Soul a Form

    8/10

    activity

    in another

    direction:

    not

    only will

    opposites

    not admit

    opposites, but (105A3-5):

    xalt

    ?XE6VO,

    O

    V

    k7r typpf

    tL

    &VOCVTLOV

    X'LVW,

    p'

    OTC V

    OC'r6

    t.

    aur

    TO

    ?7rvppOV

    V

    VO

    Lc7p[LSVOU

    V

    VLXV87OT

    S7tOt

    ?e

    a'XCaOC

    .

    Fowler translates this

    passage

    thus:

    "nothing which brings

    an opposite

    to that which it

    approaches

    will

    ever admit in

    itself

    the oppositeness of

    that which is

    brought."'5

    Note

    the

    important

    shift here.

    The context

    clearly

    indicates

    that

    the

    'things'

    being

    discussed

    are the

    same entities

    (such

    as

    three)

    which were first

    characterized

    as

    not

    admitting

    opposites,

    and then were said to

    bring

    forth

    an

    opposite

    against

    an

    approaching opposite. Now they are said to bring an opposite to some-

    thing

    which

    they approach

    (Xcp'

    -r

    xv

    cc&r6.

    Though Plato

    proceeds

    to

    sum

    up

    his

    argument

    at

    105

    A8ff. by

    noting

    that

    these

    objects

    will

    not

    admit

    (ou taerxL)

    opposites,

    he

    almost

    immediately utilizes their

    newly acquired

    activity

    in

    his

    refined

    theory

    of

    causes. He

    does not

    say

    explicitly

    that fire and fever

    cause

    bodies

    to

    be

    hot and

    ill

    by

    bringing

    an

    opposite

    to

    them,

    but

    this mechanism

    becomes obvious

    in his

    parallel

    treatment of

    the soul. Just before

    the

    passage

    we have

    called

    B

    above,

    Plato establishes

    that it is the

    soul

    which always

    causes the body

    in which

    it

    is

    to be alive. He then relates cause and

    activity

    in

    these

    words

    (in

    Hackforth's

    translation)

    B:

    "Then soul

    always brings

    life

    along

    with

    it

    to

    anything

    that

    it

    occupies.'"16

    This sentence seems

    simply

    to

    relate

    105A3-5 to

    the soIl.

    In

    105A3-5

    something

    is

    said

    to

    bring something opposite

    (ea7rp6pn

    -n

    Spvaw'tov)

    to

    what it

    approaches

    (sup'

    oa

    ocv&'CU-6

    ).

    Here

    the

    soul

    brings

    life

    ("xze cppouao

    Ccov)

    to

    what

    it

    occupies

    (xartas).

    The

    military

    overtones

    of

    &

    c

    1

    are

    caught

    in the

    xoavraaX?n

    f

    the

    second

    passage.

    The use

    of

    xcxra'C^n

    at

    105 D

    3 in a

    fashion not

    perfectlv

    16

    H. N. Fowler, Plato with an English Translation,

    Vol.

    1

    (London, 1914), 361.

    Hackforth translates the passage thus: "if any

    form brings up one

    of

    two

    opposites

    into

    that

    which

    it

    itself enters, that

    form itself will never admit the

    character opposite

    to

    the one brought up." (Hackforth, op. cit., 152-153)

    Fowler's 'oppositeness' is a bit clumsy, but Hackforth's

    'form' is clearly not

    indicated in the Greek, and prejudices the discussion.

    Fowler's translation seems

    also preferable to Tredennick's,

    which

    underemphasizes

    the

    thing's activity.

    (See Tredennick, op. cit., 86.)

    16

    Hackforth, op. cit., 159.

    17

    See Hackforth, op. cit., 152

    n.

    4; Burnet, op. cit.,

    121.

    56

    This content downloaded on Wed, 13 Mar 2013 13:54:29 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Schiller. ''Phaedo'' 104-105_Is the Soul a Form

    9/10

    parallel to

    its earlier use at

    104

    D

    is thus natural and

    required

    by

    the

    development of the argument."8

    The third

    support for Archer-Hind's

    interpretation

    is Plato's

    mode

    of

    referring to

    numbers in

    104-105. We saw above that

    Hackforth

    feels

    that this mode of reference

    actually supports

    his

    interpretation:

    thus

    a

    reason

    for

    thinking

    that

    rO7Up is a form at

    lOSA1

    is

    "that it is

    mentioned in the same breath

    with

    n

    aua&.'.

    But I think

    Hackforth is

    mistaken.

    The most

    noteworthy

    feature here is Plato's

    studied

    in-

    difference to the locutions

    by

    which he refers to

    numbers. Thus

    he

    explains, at 104A7ff., that

    n rpr.&4,

    and half of numbers in general

    (o

    %uavUq

    'o0

    &pLO0,oii

    &7rtCo)

    are odd

    though

    not

    identical to the

    odd,

    'and in the same

    way'

    (xc'

    cx

    ')

    r'c

    3o and

    all

    the other series of

    numbers

    (OC7=a

    o

    -TpOG

    o

    U

    a-TLZoq

    ro5

    OpLOV?o5)

    re

    even, though not

    identical

    to

    evenness. But if

    rpL&4 nd

    Ta&

    36o are

    equaUy parts of the

    number

    series,

    so

    similarly,

    we

    might

    expect, would

    be TL0C

    pLoC and n 8uG.

    Indeed,

    Plato's

    easy moves

    from

    r-'

    tptL

    to

    n

    'pLacq

    at

    104C1-5 and

    104E3-5, which

    indicate no

    obvious change in

    his reference,

    support

    this view.

    In light of this situation Hackforth's notes at 104C2 and 104E3

    can

    only

    be

    misleading.

    At

    104C2

    he writes

    "-o&

    -cpLa

    s

    not of course

    three

    things,

    but

    (as

    is

    evident

    from the immediate substitution

    of

    'rptoc

    in

    C5) immanent

    'threeness'"';19 at

    104E3, "here

    again the

    meaning

    of

    ro-c

    rpca is

    determined

    by

    the substitution

    of

    -

    rpLmqn

    ES."20

    I

    would

    certainly

    agree with

    Hackforth, as

    against Archer-

    Hind,

    for

    instance,

    that ra'

    tpLoc t

    104E1, does

    not

    refer

    to three

    things.21

    But I

    cannot

    accept

    his

    implication

    that it thus

    must

    refer to

    'threeness.' It

    seems

    plausible,

    in

    this

    argument

    at

    least, to see it

    as

    referring to

    the number

    three, which is

    different both from

    things

    (which it

    occupies)

    and threeness

    (which

    occupies it).

    Plato

    explicitly

    refers

    to threeness

    only

    once in

    the argument

    (

    '&v TpLWV

    Be'a

    at

    104

    D5-6)

    in

    stating

    that

    this form

    occupies 'things'

    in such a

    way

    18

    Hackforth himself

    notes the

    importance of

    105

    A3-5

    as an

    amplification of the

    earlier

    argument

    (Hackforth,

    op. cit., 152

    n.). But he reads

    it

    as an

    explanation

    of the

    &vayxaCe,t

    of

    104 D

    1-3 to the

    effect that

    the form

    wlich

    possesses

    things

    carries an

    accompanying form

    and will

    not allow either

    itself

    or

    the

    thing it

    occupies to

    admit the

    opposite of this

    accompanying form.

    But I

    believe that

    my

    interpretation better

    prepares

    us for the

    causal

    account to

    come.

    19

    Hackforth,

    op. cit.,

    151 n.

    20

    Hackforth, op.

    cit., 152 n.

    21

    Archer-Hind, op.

    cit., 113 n.

    57

    This content downloaded on Wed, 13 Mar 2013 13:54:29 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Schiller. ''Phaedo'' 104-105_Is the Soul a Form

    10/10

    that they must be odd as well as three. The things possessed,

    which

    have no part in the even and are uneven, are the r& ptoac

    n

    trp6xqf

    104E1-5, that is, the number three.

    The use of the alternate forms

    p

    pcq

    and TrcX

    pLto

    or the number

    three seems to support this intermediate status between forms and

    things.

    I do

    not

    wish to

    comment

    further

    on this suggestion, either to

    try to clarify the nature of such 'intermediates' or to argue for their

    appearance in other Platonic writings.

    I

    want

    merely

    to emphasize

    their seeming difference from

    rv

    rptv

    'am

    and thus

    change what

    seems to be a support for Hackforth's position to a

    support

    for our

    interpretation.22

    In

    conclusion, the paradoxical consequence of Hackforth's inter-

    pretation, the plausibility of the new use of

    xovmaxn

    at 105D3, and

    the evidence of Plato's references

    to numbers in

    104-105

    force

    us to

    accept Archer-Hind's interpretation that the soul is construed

    as a

    thing in this argument, and

    not

    as a form

    as

    claimed

    by

    Hackforth

    and

    Keyt.23 We might

    have to

    agree with

    Archer-Hind

    that the argument

    implies the existence of that metaphysical monstrosity,

    an idea of

    soul.

    But such an idea is never used in this argumenit. And thus we can at

    least free Plato from the logical monstrosity

    of

    equivocation

    which

    Hackforth claims he commits.

    Washington University, St. Loutis,

    Missouri

    22

    The parallel

    between

    the number three (uneven)

    and soul (immortal) which

    assures the

    support has been developed

    above. Keyt seems

    also to rely too

    heavily on

    104 D5-6 as

    setting the tone for all references

    to three (Keyt, op.

    cit.,

    168 n.).

    23

    I

    should perhaps note that Archer-Hind offers a translation of 104 D 1-3

    close to Hackforth's. I

    find, however, that this

    makes the transition

    between

    the two uses

    of

    xor&axn

    more

    difficuilt

    to accept.

    58