papq1441

Upload: ernesto-macias

Post on 03-Apr-2018

213 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 7/28/2019 papq1441

    1/18

    THE ELIGIBILITY OF

    ETHICAL NATURALISM

    by

    DOUGLAS EDWARDS

    Abstract: Perhaps the two main contemporary formulations of ethical natu-

    ralism Synthetic Ethical Naturalism (SEN) and Analytical Descriptivism

    seem to conflict with plausible views about cases where moral debate anddisagreement is possible. Both lack safeguards to avoid divergence of reference

    across different communities, which can scupper the prospects for genuine

    moral disagreement. I explore the prospects for supplementing both views with

    Lewiss notion of eligibility, arguing that this can solve the problem for a

    modified form of analytical descriptivism, and for a modified form of SEN too

    (though perhaps more controversially). I close by considering the appropriate-

    ness of using the notions of eligibility and joint-carving in ethics.

    1. Introduction

    Synthetic Ethical Naturalism (SEN), which offers a causal theory of ref-

    erence for moral terms, can be shown to conflict with widely held views

    about cases where moral debate and disagreement is possible. A central

    problem is a lack of safeguards to avoid divergence of reference across

    different communities, which, in turn, scuppers the prospects for genuine

    moral disagreement and seems to imply relativism. In this article I suggest

    that this is not the end of the line for ethical naturalism, provided we can

    find a better semantic framework in which to cast the view. Unfortunately,

    we will see that the other main competitor Jacksons (1998) AnalyticalDescriptivism falls prey to the same problem. However, I go on to

    explore how more promising results can be found by supplementing both

    views with David Lewiss (1983) notion of eligibility. What these supple-

    ments give us is a safeguard against divergence in the reference of moral

    terms across different communities. Whether this is enough to ensure

    genuine disagreement is another matter, but, insofar as shared reference is

    a necessary condition for genuine disagreement, some progress at least is

    made. In the final section of the article I discuss the appropriateness of

    using the notions of naturalness and eligibility in ethics.

    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 94 (2013) 118 DOI: 10.1111/j.1468-0114.2012.01441.x

    2012 The Author

    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 2012 University of Southern California and Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

    1

  • 7/28/2019 papq1441

    2/18

    2. Synthetic ethical naturalism

    The version of ethical naturalism under discussion here can be minimally

    defined as the idea that moral properties can be identified with natural

    properties, or are at least definable in terms of natural properties. Thedriving thought is that they can be identified with properties that are fully

    explicable within our scientific picture of the world, and thus that there is

    nothing mysterious about properties like goodness or rightness: the moral,

    just like most other subject matters, is open to naturalistic explanation.

    This view thus holds that moral properties exist, and takes a cognitivist1

    view of moral discourse.

    SEN2 is a theory which identifies moral properties with natural proper-

    ties, but which does not make analytic claims about the meanings of moral

    terms being equivalent to natural terms. G. E. Moores (1903) influentialOpen Question Argument contended that moral properties cannot be

    identified with natural properties, because there is clearly not an analytical

    equivalence between the term good and the term for the relevant natural

    property, call it X. This is because it would always make sense to ask

    given that action Y is X, is action Y good?, which, Moore thought,

    entailed that goodness cannot be equated with property X.3 What SEN

    asks us to suppose, however, is that, whilst it may be the case that the

    terms good and X are not analytically equivalent, it may still be the case

    that they ultimately refer to the same property. The analogy used toexplain the idea is that of water and H20 in the post-Kripke (1980)/

    Putnam (1975) environment. Whilst it might be clear that the terms water

    and H20 are not analytically equivalent, most people suppose that they

    both pick out the same substance: the property of being water is identical

    to the property of being H20, due to the substance with the property of

    being H2O being the substance that causally regulates our use of the term

    water.

    SEN attempts a similar move in the case of moral properties, like

    goodness and rightness. SEN agrees with Moore that the terms good andX are not analytically equivalent, but this does not rule out the idea that

    they ultimately refer to the same property: that the property of being good

    is identical to the property of being X, with the property of being X the

    property that causally regulates the use of good.

    We can thus separate the main contentions of SEN so far into three

    components. Firstly, moral terms behave like natural kind terms: they

    have natural synthetic definitions that reveal the essence of the property

    the term expresses. Secondly, moral terms rigidly designate these natural

    properties. Thirdly, reference is a matter of there being certain causalrelations between peoples uses of the term and the relevant natural

    properties.

    PACIFIC PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY2

    2012 The Author

    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 2012 University of Southern California and Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

  • 7/28/2019 papq1441

    3/18

    3. A problem for SEN

    We can generate a problem for SEN by thinking about the moral terms of

    different communities.4 Recall that it is causal regulation which is the

    defining factor in reference: terms refer to the properties that causallyregulate their use. Now suppose that the moral terms of one community,

    call them T1, are causally regulated by natural property Tc, which, we

    suppose, generates a broadly consequentialist moral system. Suppose also

    that the moral terms of another community, call them T2, are causally

    regulated by a different natural property, Td, which generates a broadly

    deontological system. How then do we account for the intuitive moral

    disagreements that would occur if (or when) the two communities were to

    interact (suppose that their languages are sufficiently similar for them to

    understand one another, or that they are able to translate one anothersdialect into their own)? Their terms refer to different properties, so are they

    really disagreeing when a member of T1 says x is right, and a member of

    T2 says x is not right?

    It seems not. The difference in reference is sufficient to show that both

    sides are not talking about the same thing, and the legitimacy of the dispute

    between them suffers accordingly. Presumably we would at least want the

    view that genuine moral dispute between these communities is possible,

    but SEN seems to fail to give us this result, and, in the process, arguably

    forces us into a form of moral relativism. This example, then, seems toshow that the causal theory of reference cannot be applied to moral terms

    if ethical naturalism is to succeed (or, at least, if it is to avoid a fairly

    radical form of moral relativism). Due to difference in reference between

    different communities, moral debate between communities looks to be

    impaired, which is a problematic result.

    How else, then, could ethical naturalism proceed? Instead of holding

    that there is a causal relationship between the natural properties and the

    terms in question, we might instead say that the natural properties are

    selected by their ability to fit our use of those terms. A view of this kind ispresented by Frank Jackson (1998).

    4. Analytical descriptivism

    According to Jackson, coming to have an understanding of our moral

    concepts is a matter of mastering what he calls folk morality, which he

    describes as:

    . . . the network of moral opinions, intuitions, principles and concepts whose mastery is part

    and parcel of having a sense of what is right and wrong, and of being able to engage in

    meaningful debate about what ought to be done (Jackson, 1998, p. 130).

    THE ELIGIBILITY OF ETHICAL NATURALISM 3

    2012 The Author

    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 2012 University of Southern California and Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

  • 7/28/2019 papq1441

    4/18

    Folk morality is a raft of information regarding our moral concepts,

    which, as it were, locates each concept by its relation to other moral

    concepts, and indeed to non-moral concepts. It is composed of a number

    of intuitive thoughts about rightness and wrongness, goodness and

    badness, which, when taken together, give us a more or less complete bodyof information about our moral concepts. Such a body, argues Jackson,

    will contain what he calls input clauses, internal role clauses, and output

    clauses. Jackson writes:

    The input clauses of folk morality tell us what kinds of situations described in descriptive,

    non-moral terms warrant what kinds of description in ethical terms: if an act is an intentional

    killing, then normally it is wrong; pain is bad; I cut you choose is a fair procedure; and so

    on. The internal role clauses of folk morality articulate the interconnections between matters

    described in ethical, normative language: courageous people are more likely to do what isright than cowardly people; the best option is the right option; rights impose duties of respect;

    and so on. The output clauses of folk morality take us from ethical judgments to facts about

    motivation and thus behaviour: the judgement that an act is right is normally accompanied

    by at least some desire to perform the act in question; the realization that an act would be

    dishonest typically dissuades an agent from performing it; properties that make something

    good are the properties we typically have some have some kind of pro-attitude towards, and

    so on (Jackson, 1998, pp. 1301).

    Jackson argues that these input, internal role, and output clauses form a

    network, and, according to analytical descriptivism, the meaning of moralterms is determined by their relevant places in this network.

    However, as a large part of folk morality is controversial, and what may

    seem to be some of its most basic clauses are often disputed, it may turn

    out that there is not one stable body of folk morality at all. Jackson

    introduces the notion of mature folk morality in order to deal with this

    problem. Jackson sees folk morality as evolving over time, but believes

    that we can realistically posit a point where this evolution winds down,

    leaving us with a stable body of moral opinion. He says:

    . . . it is useful to have a term for where folk morality will end up after it has been exposed to

    debate and critical reflection. . . . I will call where folk morality will end up, mature folk

    morality. The idea is that mature folk morality is the best we will do by way of making good

    sense of the raft of sometimes conflicting intuitions about particular cases and general

    principles that make up folk morality (Jackson, 1998, p. 133).

    With the advent of mature folk morality, Jackson gives a procedure to

    analyse the moral terms within it, drawing upon Lewis (1970) work on

    defining theoretical terms.5 Jackson gives the name M to mature folkmorality as written out in a long conjunction of its various clauses, with

    each clause written out in such a way as to include explicit reference to

    properties. For instance, in Jacksons example, Killing is typically wrong

    PACIFIC PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY4

    2012 The Author

    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 2012 University of Southern California and Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

  • 7/28/2019 papq1441

    5/18

    becomes Killing typically has the property of being wrong. We then

    replace each moral term with a distinct variable, which gives us:

    M( , , , )x x xn1 2

    We then prefix each variable with an existential quantifier and introduce a

    uniqueness clause to give us the modified Ramsey sentence of:

    ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ( , ) & )MR iff = =x y y x y x y1 1 1 1 1 2 2 M

    According to analytical descriptivism (MR) is a formal statement of

    mature folk morality, and gives expression to how each moral term is fixed

    in the network. This is because the modified Ramsey sentence gives expres-

    sion to how each moral term is fixed in the network. For example, byreplacing being right in M with xr we can construct a definition for what

    it is for an action, A, to be right:

    ( ) ( ) ( & ( )) ( ( , ) & ))R is right iff has iff rA x A x y y x y =1 1 1 1 1 M

    This states that A is right iff it has the property that plays the rightness role

    specified in the right hand side of (R). Moreover, Jackson states, this

    property is:

    . . . a property we can be confident is a purely descriptive one, given the unrestricted, global,

    a priori supervenience of the ethical on the descriptive (Jackson, 1998, p. 141).

    This leads us to the final aspect of analytical descriptivism. The formula

    devised above can be applied to all moral concepts, and thus we are able

    to find out what it is for an action to be good, bad, fair, and so forth using

    precisely the same method as (R). As Jackson notes, this does not tell us so

    much what the property of rightness is, but it does give us the truth

    conditions for an action to be right: A is right just in case it possesses aproperty that fills the role given in the right hand side of (R). This, then,

    gives us the rightness role, but does not tell us anything about what might

    realize this role.

    Once we have the network of mature folk morality, we can systematise

    it to provide an account of the job that, say, rightness does in our cognitive

    economy. That is, we carve out the specific features that we take rightness

    to have in our ordinary (or reflective) use of the term, or the specific role

    that rightness has in our ordinary speech and basic conceptual reflections.

    Once we have this role established, we then consider what properties arecapable of realizing this role. We can take it that realization may be a

    matter of degree: some properties might do a better job of realizing the role

    than others.

    THE ELIGIBILITY OF ETHICAL NATURALISM 5

    2012 The Author

    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 2012 University of Southern California and Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

  • 7/28/2019 papq1441

    6/18

    On this view, then, it is the way in which terms function in our system of

    thought which determines the property that they refer to. However, some

    simple considerations show that this view also struggles with the problem

    we noted for the causal account.6

    5. The problem for analytical descriptivism

    The structure of the objection follows the objection to the causal view. The

    thought is, again, that we have two communities, T1 and T2. The mature

    folk morality of T1 is such that a consequentialist natural property, Tc,

    best realizes the role carved out by the network for rightness. The mature

    folk morality of T2, however, has a slightly different character, and has adifferent, deontological natural property, Td, as the rightful referent of

    right. Slight differences in the use of moral terms in the network of the

    respective mature folk moralities thus means that members of T1 refer to

    Tc with their use of the term right, and members of T2 refer to Td with

    their use of the term right. Again, we have difference in reference, so

    when a member of T1 asserts x is right, and a member of T2 asserts x is

    not right, their terms refer to different properties, thus making it look as

    though this is not a substantial dispute: they are merely talking past one

    another.T1 and T2 have different folk moralities, hence different properties best

    realize their respective rightness roles. Substantial disagreement between

    them thus looks tricky, as they are still referring to different properties.

    Jacksons theory, then, is not enough to guarantee sameness of reference.

    The minor fluctuations in use of moral terms between T1 and T2 is

    sufficient to show that they would be referring to different properties, just

    as they were in the causal case. Analytical descriptivism thus cannot

    provide the semantic picture the ethical naturalist needs.

    A more promising route can be found, I propose, by supplementinganalytical descriptivism with Lewiss notion of eligibility. The resultant

    theory accepts that realization of the rightness role plays a role in the

    theory of meaning, but not that it plays the only role, and, indeed, not that

    it plays the decisive role. What is also significant is the nature of the

    property on the worldly end of the reference relation. In particular, what

    matters is the naturalness of the property to be referred to. The more

    natural the property, the more eligible it is to be considered the referent of

    the term. The basic idea, then, is that, on this view, there will not be

    divergence in reference: moral terms will always refer to the same proper-ties those properties that are the most eligible referents for the terms. To

    explain this idea, we need to look in more detail at the notions of natu-

    ralness and eligibility.

    PACIFIC PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY6

    2012 The Author

    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 2012 University of Southern California and Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

  • 7/28/2019 papq1441

    7/18

    6. Lewis on naturalness and eligibility

    Lewis takes properties to be classes, and primarily classes of actual and

    possible objects. Properties are taken to be abundant on this view:

    Any class of things, be it ever so gerrymandered and miscellaneous and indescribable in

    thought and language, and be it ever so superfluous in describing the world, is nevertheless a

    property (Lewis, 1983, p. 346).

    However, properties thus abundantly conceived are of little help when it

    comes to some of the more traditional tasks theories of properties have

    been taken to undertake, in particular, the explanation of similarities

    between objects in terms of shared properties. As Lewis puts it:

    Properties carve reality at the joints and everywhere else as well. If its distinctions we want,

    too much structure is no better than none (Lewis, 1983, p. 346).

    We need more than the abundant properties, then, if we are to be able to

    use properties to say anything significant about the world. Lewis proposes

    that we consider a sparse subset of the abundant properties to take on the

    more heavyweight metaphysical tasks. He proposes that we have an elite

    minority of special properties . . . the natural properties (Lewis, 1983,

    p. 346). These properties are still classes of things, but the members ofthese classes all share something significant in common, something which

    ensures the privileged status of these classes. As Lewis puts it:

    Sharing of [the natural properties]7 makes for qualitative similarity, they carve at the joints,

    they are intrinsic, they are highly specific, the sets of their instances are ipso facto not entirely

    miscellaneous, there are just enough of them to characterise things completely and without

    redundancy (Lewis, 1986, p. 60).

    On Lewiss picture, then, we have the vast array of abundant properties,

    and a small, elite, minority of natural properties. On Lewiss view, the

    natural properties or, more carefully, the perfectly natural properties

    are the properties which constitute the fundamental level of reality. At

    various points Lewis suggests that these will be the properties posited by

    fundamental physics, for instance:

    . . . physics discovers which things and classes are the most elite of all; but others are elite

    also, though to a lesser degree. The less elite are so because they are connected to the most

    elite by chains of definability. Long chains, by the time we reach the moderately elite classes

    of cats and pencils and puddles . . . (Lewis, 1984, p. 228).

    As this quote suggests, for Lewis, naturalness is a matter of degree. The

    perfectly natural properties are the properties at the most natural end of

    THE ELIGIBILITY OF ETHICAL NATURALISM 7

    2012 The Author

    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 2012 University of Southern California and Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

  • 7/28/2019 papq1441

    8/18

    the scale, and the most highly abundant, disjunctive, gerrymandered prop-

    erties are at the least natural, or most unnatural end of the scale. The

    thought is, then, that the less natural properties are connected to the

    perfectly natural properties by means of chains of definition: we can,

    ultimately, trace all properties back to the perfectly natural properties bydiscerning the proper chain of definition. This also gives us a handle on the

    notion of the scale of definition: the longer the chain of definition from the

    perfectly natural properties, the less natural the property.

    According to Lewis, then, it is the natural properties (or at least those

    properties that are sufficiently far down the naturalness scale towards the

    perfectly natural properties) that carve nature at its joints. If we want to

    understand the world, we ought to make an inventory of these properties.

    As we will see below, taking this claim seriously in ethics means that moral

    properties are to be identified with properties of this kind.8

    Lewis introduces the notion ofeligibility to account for naturalness in a

    theory of meaning:

    [a set] is eligible to be the extension of a one-place predicate iff its members are just those

    things . . . that share some natural property (Lewis, 1983, p. 372).

    This applies not just to isolated cases, but to theories too: An eligible

    interpretation is one that assigns none but eligible extensions to the predi-

    cates (1983, p. 372). As was noted above, Lewis conceives of naturalnessas a matter of degree, and, consequently, eligibility too is a matter of

    degree. In short, the more natural a candidate referent is, the more eligible

    it is to be considered the referent of the term in question. Correspondingly,

    the more natural the candidate referents posited by a theory are, the more

    eligible the theory is. To use a popular phrase, natural properties are

    reference-magnets.9

    It is worth pointing out that facts about language-use are not discarded

    altogether when it comes to consider what the referent of a term is: if it

    were naturalness alone, then reference magnetism would draw the referentof every word towards the perfectly natural properties, which would not be

    a happy conclusion! What we have is the acknowledgement that there is

    another important feature, concerning the naturalness of the potential

    referents, which has a significant role to play, and may indeed trump other

    considerations.

    How might this transfer to the moral case that we have been discussing?

    Eligibility concerns the naturalness of the candidate referents for a term.

    Of course, this alone does not specify how we should understand what it is

    that establishes the candidate referents, and this is something extra that wehave to consider. In the discussion so far we have two options for how to

    do this. We have the SEN view which holds that such constraints are

    causal, and that the properties that constrain the use of predicates are

    PACIFIC PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY8

    2012 The Author

    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 2012 University of Southern California and Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

  • 7/28/2019 papq1441

    9/18

    those which are causally connected to the use of those predicates. Sec-

    ondly, we have the analytical descriptivist proposal which holds that can-

    didates are established by their ability to realize the role specified in the

    relevant mature folk morality. It will be my contention that we can solve

    the disagreement problems we have been discussing if we supplement bothof these views with eligibility, but that SEN may do so in a more contro-

    versial manner.

    I will begin by showing how incorporating eligibility into the analytical

    descriptivist account can solve the problem under discussion, before

    turning to discuss whether SEN can take a similar route. I will then close

    with some more general comments on the appropriateness of using con-

    siderations of naturalness and joint-carving in ethics.

    7. Analytical descriptivism and eligibility:

    solving the problem

    According to analytical descriptivism, we collect our raft of folk beliefs (or

    mature folk beliefs) about morality, and systematise them to provide the

    specific features of each of our moral properties. Once we have this role

    established, we then consider what properties are capable of realizing this

    role. We can take it that realization may be a matter of degree: some

    properties might do a better job of realizing the role than others. Jackson,of course, ends the story here, effectively holding that realizing the role is

    all that matters, and finding the property that best realizes the rightness

    role, gives us the property that is the best property to be considered as

    rightness.

    However, we do not want to end the story here if we incorporate

    eligibility into our account of meaning and reference. Realizing the right-

    ness role is one criterion, but the naturalness of the proposed property is

    another. Moreover, a significant gain in naturalness is worth sacrificing

    precise realization: if our project is to find a property which carves theworld at its joints, we can sacrifice maximal realization for a significant

    gain in joint-carving abilities this would serve us better in trying to

    understand the world. We must, then, do more than just examine our

    linguistic practice: we must examine what the world is providing for us,

    and assess the naturalness of the candidate properties (we must assess both

    the word and the world parts of the reference relation).

    Let us now examine how adding this component solves the problem that

    felled analytical descriptivism as initially described, and how it gives a

    clear account of sameness of reference for moral terms.Consider again the communities problem. Remember that, on this pro-

    posal, we can maintain the features of Jacksons account up to a certain

    point. For instance, we can accept that T1 and T2 use their moral terms

    THE ELIGIBILITY OF ETHICAL NATURALISM 9

    2012 The Author

    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 2012 University of Southern California and Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

  • 7/28/2019 papq1441

    10/18

    slightly differently, and that there is a slight divergence in their respective

    systems of mature folk morality. We can also suppose that, due to this

    difference, different properties will best realize the roles carved out by each

    communitys moral terms. As we saw earlier, if things end here, trouble is

    afoot, as it looks as though we have difference in reference. But, if weincorporate eligibility, things do not end here: there is still the matter of

    which of the candidate properties is more natural.

    The basic idea, of course, is that reference will be drawn to the property

    which is considered to be the most natural of all the available candidates,

    but exactly what we say requires us to look a little more carefully at the

    example. The example we are working with licenses us to suppose that the

    difference in the use of moral terms between T1 and T2 is fairly small

    (small enough to mask differences at first glance, for example), which

    means that there is good reason to think that the role carved out by eachsystem of mature folk morality is also quite similar. If this is so, and

    property Tc is the best fit for T1, and Td is the best fit for T2, then there

    is good reason to think that Tc must at least be a candidate for fitting the

    mature folk morality of T2, and Td is at least a candidate for fitting the

    mature folk morality of T1. This is secured by the similarities of the roles

    carved out in T1 and T2: they are similar enough so that any candidate

    property for one will also be a candidate property for the other, but of

    course, different candidates will best fit the roles carved out in each, due to

    the small differences in mature folk moralities.In this scenario, both Tc and Td are candidates for realizing the right-

    ness roles in both T1 and T2, with Tc best realizing the rightness role in T1,

    and Td best realizing the rightness role in T2. As noted above, without any

    additional constraints on reference, we are stuck with divergence in refer-

    ence. However, if we are supplementing the view with eligibility, we have

    the additional factor of naturalness to consider. Of course, until we have

    substantive theories of the natures of Tc and Td we cannot evaluate the

    naturalness of the properties in question, but we can lay down some

    guidelines. If Tc is more natural than Td, then Tc is the proper referent ofright for both T1 and T2. On the other hand, if Td is the more natural

    property than Tc, then Td is the proper referent of right for both T1 and

    T2.10 The fact that, in both cases, the referent of right will not be the

    property that best realizes one communitys rightness role is not a

    problem: it is outweighed by the naturalness of the competing property.11

    There is also another possibility, which is that there is a third property that

    is a candidate for realization of the rightness role in both T1 and T2, but

    that is neither Tc or Td, and that is more natural than both Tc and Td. In

    this scenario reference of both communities use of right would be drawnto this property, and sameness of reference would still be secured.12

    This, then, is one way to respond to the puzzle for the reference of moral

    terms across communities, at least as we have been discussing it: what

    PACIFIC PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY10

    2012 The Author

    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 2012 University of Southern California and Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

  • 7/28/2019 papq1441

    11/18

    matters is realizing the rightness role plus the naturalness of candidate

    properties. This ensures that, in the type of cases under discussion, there

    will not be a divergence in reference: members of different communities

    will still be referring to the same properties with their moral terms, as

    reference will be drawn to the most natural candidate.13

    8. SEN and eligibility

    Supplementing analytical descriptivism with the notion of eligibility thus

    looks to provide a safeguard against divergence of reference, and thus

    responds positively to the problem of disagreement across communities.

    We noted at the beginning, though, that this problem also is significant for

    views like SEN, which hold that causal relations play an important role indetermining the referents of moral terms. I will now suggest that SEN

    can also use the notion of eligibility here, but perhaps slightly more

    controversially.

    In the case of analytical descriptivism we had a method that worked well

    for providing a number of candidate referents, with mature folk moralities

    yielding functional roles which could be realized to varying degrees. This

    idea that there is the possibility of a number of candidates was important,

    as the similarity of the mature folk moralities of the communities T1 and

    T2 enabled us to hold that the property that best realizedthe role of rightin T1 was also a candidate for realizing the role of right in T2 (despite not

    realizing it perfectly) and vice versa. This then enabled us to assess the

    naturalness of the properties best realizing the rightness role of in T1 and

    T2, along with other candidates, to yield the appropriate referent for both

    communities.

    One way for causal theories of reference to yield multiple candidates in

    this case is to notice that there is overlap in the extensions of the use of

    right in T1 and the use of right in T2, for there are many actions that are

    deemed to be right by both consequentialist and deontological theories.14

    Thus, when we are considering which property causally regulates the uses

    of right in both T1 and T2, we might well consider both Tc and Td to be

    candidates for each usage, as the closeness in extension seems to make

    interpreting right in T1 as referring to Td and right in T2 as referring to

    Tc at least prima facie reasonable. The large overlap in extension would

    mean that such interpretations would not alone saddle members of either

    community with a large number of false beliefs, for example, which allows

    us to conceive of both properties as being properties which their respective

    uses of right track.15

    There is a potential sticking point, however, which is that this criterion

    just gives us candidates for the property that causally regulates the use of

    a term. There is still, presumably, the further question of which property

    THE ELIGIBILITY OF ETHICAL NATURALISM 11

    2012 The Author

    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 2012 University of Southern California and Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

  • 7/28/2019 papq1441

    12/18

    does in fact causally regulate the use of the term. In other words, the

    procedure of looking at which properties a community could reasonably

    be interpreted as referring to with right guides us towards which property

    is causally regulating the use, but it is then a further question which of the

    candidate properties is actually doing this causal work. The worry is thatonce this is established (as it is in the example under consideration), we will

    be back to where we were above: there will be just one property that is a

    candidate for actually causing the use of right in T1 (Tc), and just one

    property that is a candidate for actually causing the use of right in T2

    (Td).

    To illustrate the point, compare a scientific experiment, where an effect

    is observed, a red colouring of a liquid, for example, and that there are a

    range of different gases, a, b and c that could have caused this colouration.

    Before analysing the liquid it would be reasonable to hold that a, b and care all candidates for causing the colouration. After the liquid is analysed,

    it turns out that a is present in the liquid, but not b or c. At this point it no

    longer seems reasonable to hold that b and c remain candidates for causing

    the colouration, as only the chemical structure ofa was found in the liquid:

    whilst there were many candidates for causing the colouration, there is

    only one actual cause.

    The worry then for the causal view in the case we are considering is that,

    to avail of eligibility, there needs to be a range of candidates at this final

    stage: the stage after the actual cause has been established. However,whilst we had a number of candidates prior to the establishment of the

    actual cause, we do not get a range of candidates at this final stage, only

    one. This seems to be of more concern for here than a parallel worry would

    be for analytical descriptivism, on the grounds that actually being the

    cause of the use of a term seems to be a more powerful feature to consider

    than being the best realizer of a role: indeed, it seems to be part of the very

    core of the initial SEN position. Moreover, built into analytical descrip-

    tivism is the idea that properties may realize a particular role to more or

    less of a degree, which left candidates that were less able realizers as stillcandidates (just less good ones), whereas, on the terms of SEN, it does not

    seem as though a property can actually causally constrain a particular use

    to some degree: it either actually causally constrains that use or it does

    not.16

    To respond to this worry the causal theorist who wants to adopt eligi-

    bility must insist that what matters is just the range of properties that at the

    initial stage are candidates for causally constraining the use of the term

    right. On this view it would be these properties those identified at the

    initial stage as candidates which would be assessed for naturalness, withthere being the potential for a significant gain in naturalness of one prop-

    erty being able to trump another propertys actually causally constraining

    a particular use. For instance, suppose that Tc actually causally constrains

    PACIFIC PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY12

    2012 The Author

    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 2012 University of Southern California and Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

  • 7/28/2019 papq1441

    13/18

    the use of right in T1, and Td actually causally constrains the use of

    right in T2, but that, as noted above, due to their overlap in extension,

    both were established as legitimate candidates for properties that causally

    constrain the use of right in both communities. Now suppose that Tc is

    significantly more natural than Td. If we are allowing naturalness totrump actual causing, then we could assign Tc as the referent of right in

    both T1 and T2, which would secure sameness of reference. Conversely, if

    Td were more natural, then Td would be assigned as the referent of right

    in both T1 and T2. Thirdly, as above, we can also allow that a third

    candidate might be the most natural candidate, thus drawing the reference

    of right in T1 and T2 to that property.

    As a consequence, adopting eligibility can also offer a solution to the

    disagreement problem for SEN. Whether it does so in a way that departs

    more significantly from the original form of SEN than the modified formof analytical descriptivism departs from the original form of analytical

    descriptivism will depend on ones views about a potential difference in

    significance between eligibility trumping best realization and eligibility

    trumping actual causal constraints on use.

    9. Carving at the moral joints

    It seems, then, that using the notion of eligibility in the process of deter-mining the referents of moral terms ought to ensure sameness of reference,

    and thus remove some of the obstacles to genuine disagreement that we

    saw on the basic analytical descriptivist and SEN accounts. In this final

    section I wish to consider a potential concern about the eligibility

    approach, namely whether it is appropriate to consider Lewisian natural-

    ness as a measure for moral properties.

    We can offer some thoughts on the matter, though they are likely to

    appeal most strongly to those who already think that some form of ethical

    naturalism is plausible.17 The first is in regard to the thought that moralproperties are natural properties in the sense that they are able to be

    accounted for by natural science: the definition of ethical naturalism we

    began with. Holding that moral properties are reasonably natural in the

    sense of Lewisian naturalness can be seen as a companion to this view,

    especially when supplemented with the physicalist picture Lewis advo-

    cates. Of course, it is doubtful that one would claim that moral properties

    are amongst the perfectly natural properties that are the fundamental

    physical properties, but ethical naturalism as we have defined it does think

    that moral properties are accountable in the terms of natural science,which suggests that they will be definable in not-too-long chains of defi-

    nitions from the Lewisian perfectly natural properties, thus making them

    reasonably natural in the Lewisian sense. In this aspect, being reasonably

    THE ELIGIBILITY OF ETHICAL NATURALISM 13

    2012 The Author

    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 2012 University of Southern California and Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

  • 7/28/2019 papq1441

    14/18

    natural in the Lewisian sense of naturalness coincides with being account-

    able in the terms of natural science, thus aligning the standard claim of

    ethical naturalism with a view that holds that moral properties are natural

    in Lewiss sense of the term.

    There is, of course, another dimension to Lewisian naturalness, which isthat natural properties mark significant, as opposed to gerrymandered,

    kinds: why believe that moral properties have a significant degree of

    naturalness in this sense, as opposed to being highly unnatural, abundant,

    gerrymandered properties? One good reason to think that moral proper-

    ties are higher up on the naturalness chain than these properties concerns

    another issue mentioned earlier: joint-carving. In other words, one wants

    theories to hit upon the structure of reality; to carve the world at its joints.

    Presumably we want to be able to discern genuine moral kinds: we want to

    clearly demarcate what is right from what is wrong, what is good fromwhat is bad, and so forth, and, in doing so, what want to get our distinc-

    tions correct. If we want to form such genuine kinds, highly unnatural

    properties will not do, as they will fail to provide us with the qualitative

    similarity between the members of each kind that we require (they will still

    be kinds, of course, just not particularly interesting ones). If we want to

    ensure that our categories even our moral ones are latching onto the

    more genuine features of the world, then we ought to take the naturalness

    of the candidate properties very seriously indeed: the more natural the

    property, the better it carves at the joints; the better it carves at the joints,the better it distinguishes right from wrong, or good from bad. In other

    words, we want to be sure that all right actions share some substantial

    feature in common rightness and we can only ensure this if rightness is

    considered to be a fairly natural property.

    Obviously, joint-carving might not be the only consideration in play

    when considering moral properties, but it is an important one nonetheless.

    If we want right actions to form a genuine kind which presumably ethical

    naturalists would then this constraint is pretty high up on the list. So,

    there are good reasons to want moral properties to come out as reasonablynatural properties, even on Lewiss conception of naturalness, and espe-

    cially if we are already offering the view to ethical naturalists. This is

    something that the use of eligibility proposed here can offer.

    I have argued that using the notion of eligibility in ethics offers a more

    promising line in the face of problems about disagreement for modified

    forms of both analytical descriptivism and (perhaps more controversially)

    SEN. It is also worth noting that the utility of eligibility for moral terms is

    evidently not restricted to the cases discussed. What it guarantees is a

    safeguard against divergence of reference across communities. Whilst itmay not guarantee that all moral disputes are substantial, and not verbal,

    it does ensure, at the very least, that any failures of genuine disagreement

    will not be the fault of the reference of the moral terms in question: it will

    PACIFIC PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY14

    2012 The Author

    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 2012 University of Southern California and Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

  • 7/28/2019 papq1441

    15/18

    be because of some other factor. This is true even for people who have

    different moral beliefs, or who subscribe to different moral theories.

    Moreover, it does this whilst maintaining that our moral terms will latch

    onto the moral structure of the world as best they can.18

    Northern Institute of Philosophy

    University of Aberdeen

    NOTES

    1 Intended here to mean that sentences involving moral terms express beliefs, as opposed

    to attitudes. The opposing view would be non-cognitivism, such as that of Simon Blackburn

    (1998).2 Synthetic Ethical Naturalism is associated with the work of Richard Boyd (1988), and

    David Brink (1986, 1989). Horgan and Timmons discuss the view in 1992a, pp. 1226. It is

    also referred to as Cornell Realism in, for example, Jackson, 1998.3 For more on this argument see Kalderon, 2006.4 The case presented is of a similar structure of Horgan and Timmons (1992a, 1992b,

    1992c) Moral Twin Earth thought experiment. Here I speak of different communities, and

    intend to stay neutral on the issue of whether the communities need to be communities on

    Earth and Twin Earth or, alternatively, two different (but perhaps isolated) communities on

    Earth instead (as in Hares [1952] discussion of the missionary and the tribe). For more

    discussion on the development of Horgan and Timmons formulation of the problem, and

    some responses to it, see the Horgan and Timmons papers, and also Copp, 2000; Geirsson,

    2005; Gert, 2006; and Sayre-McCord, 1997. van Roojen (2006) offers a response based on the

    ability of speakers in a community to express knowledge using their moral terms, which also

    incorporates a criterion of naturalness, albeit a different one to the version under discussion

    here. I briefly discuss the differences between van Roojens conception of naturalness and

    Lewiss conception in Note 8 below.5 The explanation of this procedure is taken from Jackson, 1998, pp. 1401.6 See Horgan and Timmons (2009) for their account of why analytical descriptivism fails.

    The outline of the problem given here again broadly follows their line of argument.7 Lewis also uses the term sparse properties, but he takes what he calls natural prop-

    erties to play the role of sparse properties in his theory. This also fits with Lewiss talk of thefeatures of natural properties throughout Lewis, 1983. The way Lewis uses natural here is

    not strictly the same as the use of natural in ethical naturalism as defined earlier in Section

    2, but, as I note in Section 9 below, there are important similarities. Indeed, in Section 9 I

    suggest that it is plausible to think that ethical naturalism as defined earlier should not have

    any problem with the thought that moral properties are natural properties in the Lewisian

    sense of natural.8 Lewiss account of naturalness, whilst influential, is not the only account in town. Van

    Roojen (2006), for example, offers a different account of naturalness, suggesting that natu-

    ralness is, in some sense, discipline-relative. Thus, on his view, properties that are considered

    ethically natural might not be considered to be physically natural, for example, but both areequally natural nonetheless. I do not have space to address the issue in great depth here, but

    it is worth noting that adopting this view of naturalness would not affect the claims made

    later in this article about the roles naturalness and eligibility can and cannot play in relation

    to analytical descriptivism and SEN. As a brief note on my preference for Lewiss account,

    THE ELIGIBILITY OF ETHICAL NATURALISM 15

    2012 The Author

    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 2012 University of Southern California and Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

  • 7/28/2019 papq1441

    16/18

    it is worth noting that there is an intuitive sense in which there is a non-discipline relative scale

    of naturalness in that we commonly take moral properties to be in some sense dependent

    (or supervenient) on fundamental physical properties. Whilst this should not affect the claim

    of moral properties to be reasonably natural, it does suggest that they are less privileged (or

    perhaps less natural) than fundamental physical properties, which is a point Lewiss concep-

    tion can accommodate.9 Lewis discusses two applications of eligibility to solve two important problems in the

    philosophy of language: Goodmans (1955) puzzle of induction, and the Kripkenstein

    paradox (Kripke, 1982). For reasons of space, I will not discuss the problems and Lewiss

    solutions to them here, but for the full story see Lewis, 1983. For more on Lewiss notion of

    eligibility, see Williams, 2007.10 Of course, there is the objection that both properties may possess an equal level of

    naturalness (a criticism of Lewis made by Lakoff (1987, pp. 2434)). There are two things I

    wish to note about this, however. The first is that it is questionable whether it is possible that

    we would get two properties that are equally natural, at least on the Lewis scale of natural-

    ness, as each property occupies a particular place on the chain of definability from the

    perfectly natural properties. If we suppose that this chain is single-file, then there will not be

    two properties that occupy the same level on the scale, thus not two properties that are

    equally natural. The only potential case of equally natural properties would be the perfectly

    natural properties, and I dont think anyone would wish to suppose that moral properties are

    amongst their number. Secondly, even if there were two equally natural properties in play,

    this would not lead to divergence in reference, rather indeterminacy of reference. We would

    not thus have the relativist proposals entailed by SEN and Jackson, but rather a view where

    it was genuinely indeterminate which properties our moral terms refer to, and genuinely

    indeterminate because the world provides equally natural candidates. I am inclined to think

    that, were this to occur, such indeterminacy would be unavoidable on any view.11 This might be so even in cases where there is a significant difference in the role specified,

    as in these cases naturalness may still be the deciding factor. See, e.g. Weatherson, 2003 on

    knowledge as justified true belief.12 I am grateful to an anonymous referee for pointing out this possibility.13 Whether this is enough to guarantee genuine disagreement is a slightly different matter.

    We might think that shared reference is a necessary condition of genuine disagreement, but

    not necessarily a sufficient condition. In other words, there may be other factors that make it

    such that genuine disagreement is not secured, even though shared reference is. As I noted at

    the beginning of the article, my project here is just to secure shared reference, and not to

    engage directly with the notion of genuine disagreement, which is a project suitable for aseparate inquiry. Of course, if members of both communities thought that eligibility ought to

    be a factor, they could then themselves establish which property is the proper referent, and

    conduct any further debates with that in mind. This would look to be progress in the way of

    securing genuine disagreement (and is similar to the kind of process Sider [2009] recommends

    regarding existence), but that would perhaps build too much into the example at this stage.14 This distinguishes the case from, for example, the original Twin Earth case, as, in that

    case, there is no substance that is both H2O and XYZ, meaning that there is no overlap in

    extension between the respective uses of water.15 I would like to thank an anonymous referee for their comments here.16 If one disagrees, though, note that, either way, the response to the worry in both cases

    is the same as outlined below, with eligibility having the ability to trump actual causing or

    best realization.17 There is of course a lot of room for debate about the project of ethical naturalism in

    general, and I again note that the eligibility proposal is primarily offered to those already

    PACIFIC PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY16

    2012 The Author

    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 2012 University of Southern California and Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

  • 7/28/2019 papq1441

    17/18

    tempted by some form of ethical naturalism. I am not directly trying to convince those

    sceptical of the project (e.g. those who think, say, that there are no moral properties!) that

    moral properties should be considered to be reasonably natural.18 Earlier versions of parts of this article were presented at workshops at University

    College Dublin, Trinity College Dublin, and at the 2010 Joint Session of the Mind Associa-

    tion and Aristotelian Society at University College Dublin. I would like to thank audiences

    at these talks for their comments, along with the Irish Research Council for the Humanities

    and Social Sciences for the postdoctoral award that funded part of the work on this article.

    I would also like to thank the anonymous referee for their very helpful comments. This

    research was supported by a Marie Curie Intra European Fellowship within the 7th Euro-

    pean Community Framework Programme.

    REFERENCES

    Blackburn, S. (1998). Ruling Passions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Boyd, R. (1988). How to be a Moral Realist, in G. Sayre-McCord (ed.) Essays on Moral

    Realism. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Brink, D.O. (1986). Externalist Moral Realism, The Southern Journal of Philosophy

    XXIV(Suppl), pp. 2342.

    Brink, D.O. (1989). Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge

    University Press.

    Copp, D. (2000). Milk, Honey, and the Good Life on Moral Twin Earth, Synthese 124,

    pp. 113137.

    Geirsson, H. (2005). Moral Twin Earth and Semantic Moral Realism, Erkenntnis 62(3),

    pp. 353378.

    Gert, J. (2006). Problems for Moral Twin Earth Arguments, Synthese 150(2), pp. 171183.

    Goodman, N. (1955). Fact, Fiction and Forecast. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Hare, R.M. (1952). The Language of Morals. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Horgan, T. and Timmons, M. (1992a). New-Wave Moral Realism Meets Moral Twin

    Earth, in J. Heil (ed.) Rationality, Morality and Self-Interest. Lanham, MD: Rowman and

    Littlefield Publishers.

    Horgan, T. and Timmons, M. (1992b). Troubles on Moral Twin Earth: Moral Queerness

    Revived? Synthese 92, pp. 221260.

    Horgan, T. and Timmons, M. (1992c). Troubles for New Wave Moral Semantics: The

    Open Question Argument Revived, Philosophical Papers XXI, pp. 153175.Horgan, T. and Timmons, M. (2009). Analytical Descriptivism Meets Moral Twin Earth, in

    I. Ravenscroft (ed.) Minds, Ethics and Conditionals: Themes from the Philosophy of Frank

    Jackson. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Jackson, F. (1998). From Metaphysics to Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Kalderon, M.E. (2006). Open Questions and the Manifest Image, Philosophy and Phenom-

    enological Research, LXVIII, pp. 251289.

    Kripke, S. (1980). Naming and Necessity. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Kripke, S. (1982). Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language. Cambridge, MA: Harvard

    University Press.

    Lakoff, G. (1987). Women, Fire, and Dangerous Things: What Categories Reveal about theMind. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Lewis, D. (1970). How to Define Theoretical Terms, Journal of Philosophy, 67, pp. 427446.

    Lewis, D. (1983). New Work for a Theory of Universals, Australasian Journal of Philosophy

    61(4), pp. 343377.

    THE ELIGIBILITY OF ETHICAL NATURALISM 17

    2012 The Author

    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 2012 University of Southern California and Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

  • 7/28/2019 papq1441

    18/18

    Lewis, D. (1984). Putnams Paradox, Australasian Journal of Philosophy 62, pp. 221236.

    Lewis, D. (1986). On the Plurality of Worlds. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Moore, G.E. (1903). Principia Ethica. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Putnam, H. (1975). The Meaning of Meaning , in K. Gunderson (ed.) Language, Mind

    and Knowledge, Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol.7. Minneapolis, MN:

    University of Minnesota Press.

    Sayre-McCord, G. (1997). Good on Twin Earth, Philosophical Issues 8, pp. 267292.

    Sider, T. (2009). Ontological Realism, in D. Chalmers, D. Manley and R. Wasserman (eds)

    Metametaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    van Roojen, M. (2006). Knowing Enough to Disagree: A New Response to the Moral Twin

    Earth Argument, in R. Shafer-Landau (ed.) Oxford Studies in Metaethics, Volume I.

    Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Weatherson, B. (2003). What Good are Counterexamples? Philosophical Studies 115,

    pp. 131.

    Williams, J.R.G. (2007). Eligibility and Inscrutability, Philosophical Review 116(3),

    pp. 361399.

    PACIFIC PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY18

    2012 The Author

    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 2012 University of Southern California and Blackwell Publishing Ltd.