organism asnatural purpose

Upload: albertolecaros

Post on 03-Apr-2018

220 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 7/28/2019 Organism Asnatural Purpose

    1/21

    Organisms as natural purposes: The contemporaryevolutionary perspective

    D.M. Walsh

    Department of Philosophy and Institute for the History and Philosophy of Science and Technology,

    University of Toronto, 91 Charles Street West, Toronto M5S 1K7, Canada

    Abstract

    Kants conception of organisms as natural purposes raises a challenge to the adequacy of mech-anistic explanation in biology. Certain features of organisms appear to be inexplicable by appeal tomechanical law alone. Some biological phenomena, it seems, can only be accounted for teleologi-

    cally. Contemporary evolutionary biology has by and large ignored this challenge. It is widely heldthat Darwins theory of natural selection gives us an adequate, wholly mechanical account of thenature of organisms. In contemporary biology, the category of the organism plays virtually noexplanatory role. Contemporary evolutionary biology is a science of sub-organismal entitiesrepli-cators. I argue that recent advances in developmental biology demonstrate the inadequacy of sub-organismal mechanism. The category of the organism, construed as a natural purpose should playan ineliminable role in explaining ontogenetic development and adaptive evolution. According toKant the natural purposiveness of organisms cannot be demonstrated to be an objective principlein nature, nor can purposiveness figure in genuine explain. I attempt to argue, by appeal to recentwork on self-organization, that the purposiveness of organisms is a natural phenomenon, and, byappeal to the apparatus of invariance explanation, that biological purposiveness provides genuine,

    ineliminable biological explanations. 2006 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.

    Keywords: Kant; Purpose; Teleology; Mechanism; Self-organization; Replicator biology; Development; Invari-ance; Explanation

    1369-8486/$ - see front matter 2006 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.

    doi:10.1016/j.shpsc.2006.09.009

    E-mail address: [email protected]

    Stud. Hist. Phil. Biol. & Biomed. Sci. 37 (2006) 771791

    www.elsevier.com/locate/shpsc

    Studies in Historyand Philosophy ofBiological andBiomedical Sciences

    mailto:[email protected]:[email protected]
  • 7/28/2019 Organism Asnatural Purpose

    2/21

    0. Introduction

    Kants third critique, in particular the Analytic of the teleological power of judgment,famously introduces a tension between our conception organisms and our understanding

    of the natural world as governed by unified mechanical law. Organisms, Kant tells us, arenatural purposes and as such are subject to teleological explanation. We account for thenatures and capacities of their constituent parts and processes by appeal to those purposesof the organism that they fulfill. At the same time, organisms are natural entities subject tomechanical laws. Mechanical laws give us complete scientific explanations of all the phe-nomena of the world and concedes no irreducible explanatory role to goals or purposes.The tension gives rise to Kants famous Antinomy of the teleological power of judg-mentroughly, that organisms both must be and cannot be judged to be wholly the prod-ucts of mechanical processes. The tension Kant articulates regarding organisms as naturalpurposes is as germane today as it ever was. Organisms really do have the astonishingproperties by which Kant identifies them as natural purposes. Moreover, scientific expla-nation, today just as in Kants time, is cast in the mechanical mode. The tension ought tosurvive in contemporary biology, perhaps not as an antinomy, but nevertheless as a gen-uine challenge to the adequacy of our conception of the biological world.

    My objective here is to draw to the attention of contemporary biology (and philosophyof biology) the relevance of Kants conception of organisms as natural purposes. Kantsproblematic may have been largely forgotten by contemporary biology, but it has strongresonances with issues that are only now beginning to attract biologists attentionsself-organization, the emergent properties of organisms, their adaptability, their capacity to

    regulate their component parts and processes. I do not attempt to persuade biologists toadopt the critical philosophy. Indeed there is a question whether it is consistent with mod-ern day naturalism.1 I do claim that Kants Critique of the teleological power of judg-ment offers a particularly vivid articulation of the challenge raised to any theoreticalbiology by the nature of organisms, a challenge encapsulated in the Antinomy of the tel-eological power of judgment. I contend that contemporary biology has (inadvertently)embroiled itself in an analogous antinomy, one of teleological explanation. Recentresearch on organismal development suggests that biological phenomena cannot be whollyexplained unless we consider organisms as both mechanical and purposive entities. I wouldlike to suggest, however, that biologists have the conceptual resources, without recourse to

    the critical philosophy, to reconcile the mechanical nature of biological processes with thefact that the conception of organisms as natural purposes has an ineliminable explanatoryrole to play.

    1. The Antinomy of the teleological power of judgment

    An organism, according to Kant, constitutes a functional unity whose parts and pro-cesses contribute to its development, sustenance and reproduction, indeed whose parts seemto exist in the form they do precisely because they fulfil these roles. Organisms are distin-

    guished by three diagnostic features: (i) self-organization: the growth and interaction of partsis evidently caused by the organizational structure of the organism as a whole and is directed

    1 See John Zammitos discussion (2006).

    772 D.M. Walsh / Stud. Hist. Phil. Biol. & Biomed. Sci. 37 (2006) 771791

  • 7/28/2019 Organism Asnatural Purpose

    3/21

    toward the attainment of a viable adult form; (ii) self-reproduction: each organism is capableof securing the existence of other such organisms similar in structure and function; (iii) andself-nourishment (McLaughlin, 2000). During its ontogeny, Kant tells us, an organism

    first processes the matter that it adds to itself into a specifically-distinct quality,which the mechanism of nature outside of it cannot provide, and develops itself fur-

    ther by means of a material which, in its composition, is its own product. (Kant,

    2000, p. 371)2

    The constituent parts and processes of a living thing are related to the organism as awhole by a kind of reciprocal causation.

    The essential definition Kant offered of : : : organic form : : : was that of the recipro-

    cal interrelation of parts as means to ends, and consequently, of the priority of the

    whole over the parts in the constitution of the entity. (Zammito, 1991, p. 218)

    The definition of an organic body is that it is a body, every part of which is there forthe sake of the other (reciprocally as an end, and at the same time, means). : : : Anorganic (articulated) body is one in which each part, with its moving force, necessar-ily relates to the whole (to each part in its composition). (Opus postumum, quoted inGuyer, 2005, p. 104)

    I would provisionally say that a thing exists as a natural end if it is cause and effect ofitself. (Kant, 2000, p. 371)

    The self-motivating, self-forming capacities of organisms, the reciprocal dependence of

    part on whole and whole on parts, the supple goal-directed, compensatory capacities char-acteristic of organismal development, these, Kant tells us are all essential to our concept ofan organism to think of an organism qua organism is to think of it as a purposive entity.Moreover, an organisms purposes are immanent in it; they are not extrinsic purposes, likethose of artifacts. Hence, organisms are natural purposes.

    Organized beings are thus the only ones in nature which : : : must nevertheless be

    thought of as possible only as ends, and which thus first provide the objective reality

    for the concept of an end that is not a practical end but an end of nature, and thereby

    provide natural science with the basis for a teleology : : : (Ibid., pp. 375376)

    Kants concern about this conception of organisms is that while it is obligatorywecannot take ourselves to be studying organisms qua organisms unless we consider themas natural purposesit seems to put the defining features of organisms beyond the ambitof scientific explanation.

    For Kant all genuine explanation is mechanical. To explain mechanically the propertiesof a naturally occurring entity, one cites the properties of its parts that determine thewhole. His conception of scientific explanation appears to conform to what C. D. Broadhas called Pure Mechanism, according to which, there is:

    : : : (a) a single kind of stuff, : : : (b) a single fundamental kind of change, : : : (c) a sin-

    gle elementary causal law,: : :

    and (d) a single and simple principle of composition,

    2 All citations from the Critique of judgement are taken from the translation by P. Guyer & E. Matthews, Kant(2000). References give the pages in the Akademie edition.

    D.M. Walsh / Stud. Hist. Phil. Biol. & Biomed. Sci. 37 (2006) 771791 773

  • 7/28/2019 Organism Asnatural Purpose

    4/21

    according to which the behaviour of any aggregate of particles, or the influence of

    any one aggregate on any other, follows in a uniform way from the mutual influences

    of the constituent particles taken by pairs. (Broad, 1925, p. 45)

    On the one hand, the functional unity of an organism can be explained in the mechan-ical mode; an organism is a causal consequence of the capacities of its parts. But, on theother hand, the parts themselves seem to be the effects of the structural and functionalunity of the organism. Consequently, we cannot account for the nature of organisms bymere mechanical explanation alone:

    : : : it is quite certain that we can never adequately come to know the organized

    beings and their internal possibility in accordance with merely mechanical principles

    of nature, let alone explain them; and indeed this is so certain that we can boldly say

    that it would be absurd for humans even to make such an attempt or to hope that

    there may yet arise a Newton who could make comprehensible even the generationof the a blade of grass according to the natural laws that no intention has ordered;

    rather, we must absolutely deny this insight to human beings. (Kant, 2000, p. 400)

    This tension between the requirement to conceive of organisms as natural phenomena,explicable in the mechanical mode, and the requirement to think of them as purposive enti-ties whose natures defy mechanical explanation, is articulated in The Antinomy of the tel-eological power of judgment:

    The first maxim of the power of judgment is the thesis: All generation of material things

    and their forms must be judged as possible in accordance with merely mechanical laws.

    The second maxim is the antithesis: Some products of material nature cannot bejudged as possible according to merely mechanical laws (judging them requires anentirely different law of causality, namely that of final causes). (Ibid., p. 387).

    2. Sub-organismal biology

    Contemporary biology has responded to the problem posed by the natural purposive-ness of organisms by the simple expedient of ignoring it. There is a general thought now-

    adays that biology has no need of teleological thinking. There are a couple of reasons. Thefirst is that the project of contemporary comparative biology is substantially different fromthat of Kants time. The second is that the range of explanatory resources available tobiologists has expanded significantly. These reasons both derive from the influence ofDarwin.

    Darwins most significant achievement was the understanding that biologys two greatexplanandathe fit of organisms to their conditions of existence and the diversity oforganic formare both the consequence of a single mechanical process, natural selection.That process is not to be found occurring within organisms, but within populations. Selec-tion causes populations to change their constitution over time, which in turn realizes the

    increase in both the adaptedness and diversity of organisms. Darwins theory of selectionchanges the explanatory project of biology from that of explaining the natures of organ-isms by appeal to some principle immanent in organisms themselves to one of explainingthe nature of organisms by appeal to a causal process occurring within populations. The

    774 D.M. Walsh / Stud. Hist. Phil. Biol. & Biomed. Sci. 37 (2006) 771791

  • 7/28/2019 Organism Asnatural Purpose

    5/21

    problematic features of organisms that impelled Kant to identify them as natural pur-posesthe exquisite integration of organisms, their adaptive plasticity, their self-organiz-ing capacitiesare simple causal consequences of change in population structure wroughtby natural selection. This line of thought led Michael Ghiselin to proclaim Darwins tri-

    umph over teleology: he developed a new way of thinking that allows us to dispense alto-gether with that metaphysical delusion (Ghiselin, 1993, p. 483) and occasioned ErnstMayrs insistence that Darwin had solved Kants great puzzle (Mayr, 1988, p. 58).

    Darwins theory is explicitly structured according to the mechanistic model (Cornell,1986; Hull, 2003). Darwin took Herschels Preliminary discourse (1987) as the canonicalsource on the proper conduct of scientific enquiry. Herschel, in turn, held Newtonsmechanics and Lyells geology as paradigms of the scientific method. Herschel was partic-ularly impressed with (what he took to be) the insistence by Newton and Lyell on veracausae explanations. A vera causa explanation, according to Herschel, invokes only thoseprocesses as causes that can be directly observed. Moreover, they must be observable inde-pendently of the effect to be explained. The degree of effect of a true cause must vary with thedegree of the cause itself. Darwin prided himself on the conformance of his theory of naturalselection to Herschels methodological precepts. Variation and struggle for existence aredirectly observable in a population, quite independently of their influence on populationchange. They are sufficient to cause population change. The rate of change in a populationis proportional to the degree of variation in a population and the severity of the struggle.Thus, in Darwins entangled bank all its various organisms, : : : so different from eachother, and so dependent on each other in so complex a manner, have all been producedby laws acting around us (Darwin, 1972, p. 462). Darwins theory is a strictly causal,

    mechanical one. Natural selection allows us to assert the thesis of the antinomy and pre-scind from the antithesis.It does so only if those features of organisms that so impressed Kant have no indispensable

    explanatory role to play in biology. As John Cornell expresses it: To reject Kants argumentwe would have to explain away the organism (Cornell, 1986, p. 408). This is precisely whatmuch of contemporary biology has undertaken to do. Current evolutionary biology is largelydirected toward the study of how supra-organismal entitiespopulationschange as aresult of the causal powers of sub-organismal entitiesreplicators. The most thoroughand provocative exponent of the sub-organismal nature of biology is Richard Dawkins:

    Evolution is the external and visible manifestation of the survival of alternative repli-

    cators: : :

    Genes are replicators; organisms: : :

    are best not regarded as replicators;

    they are vehicles in which replicators travel about. Replicator selection is the process

    by which some replicators survive at the expense of others. Vehicle selection is the

    process by which some vehicles are more successful than others in ensuring the sur-

    vival of their replicators. (Dawkins, 1982, p. 82)

    Organisms are mere middlemen in evolution, a sort of interface between the organism-building activities of replicators and the selecting role of the environment. Their salientcharacteristics, and indeed their very existence, are to be explained by appeal to the causal

    capacities of replicators.The integrated multi-cellular organism is a phenomenon which has emerged as a

    result of natural selection on primitively independent selfish replicators. It has paid

    replicators to behave gregariously. (Ibid., p. 264)

    D.M. Walsh / Stud. Hist. Phil. Biol. & Biomed. Sci. 37 (2006) 771791 775

  • 7/28/2019 Organism Asnatural Purpose

    6/21

    There are good reasons why replicators, rather than organisms, enjoy this privilegedposition. They play a distinctive unifying role in our account of evolution.

    Evolution comprises three constituent processes: inheritance of traits, ontogeny oforganisms and change within populations. Replicator biology offers us an elegant account

    of how these three processes taken together lead to the fit and diversity of organisms. (i)Inheritance: Evolution requires variation in heritable traits. Replicators, we are told, arethe units of inheritance. They are the only entities that are both copied within parentsand transmitted from parent to offspring in reproduction. (ii) Ontogeny: Development,according to the sub-organismal view, is simply the implementation of a developmentalprogram, the expression of phenotypic information encoded, or programmed, in the repli-cators (e.g. Maynard Smith, 2000). Organisms may be what are selected, but replicatorsbuild organisms. (iii) Population Change: Evolution by natural selection occurs when pop-ulations change their structure as a consequence of the differential survival and reproduc-tion of organism. But not just any old change in population structure counts asevolutionary change, only changes in the relative frequency of replicators. Indeed naturalselection is usually defined as changes in replicator frequencies that result from the differ-ential contribution of replicators to survival and reproduction (Bell, 2000). Replicators,then, are the only entities that take part in all the constituent processes of evolutioninheritance, ontogeny and population changeand whose activities unite these processesinto the process of evolution.

    Replicator biology also furnishes a ready explanation of the adaptiveness of evolution.The adaptedness of organisms is the result of the accretion of adaptive (that is, selected)replicators. Fitness-promoting replicators are assembled by selection into integrated suites

    of traits (Ayala, 1970). The appearance of biological design is the consequence of an iter-ated process of the introduction of variant replicators, their recombination and selection.Here again, the influences of Pure Mechanism run deep. Sub-organismal biologys pro-

    prietary processes and explanations are mechanical, one and all. The properties of organ-isms are explained by appeal to the capacities of their parts. The parts of organism(replicators) have an explanatory and ontological primacy over the whole.

    Replicators exist. That is fundamental. Phenotypic manifestations of them : : : may

    be expected to function as tools to keep replicators existing. Organisms are huge and

    complex assemblages of such tools : : : (Dawkins 1986, p. 263).

    The success of sub-organismal biology depends upon replicators having the sort ofeffects that in Newtons words should esteem them in the highest (Newton, 1963, p.398) There are basically three: (i) Constancy of quality: The role of replicators requires thateach replicator has a reasonably constant, or predictable, phenotypic effect across con-texts. Replicators ground the inheritance of phenotypes only if their effects are reliablyconstant across different organisms, i.e. across associations with different replicators; (ii)Constancy of quantity: The fitness consequences of a trait must be reasonably constantacross contexts. Were this not the case evolution by natural selection could not be cumu-lative.3 (iii) Independence: The constancy of phenotypic effect across contexts requires thatreplicators exert their effects on phenotype more or less independently of one another.4

    3 See Kauffman (1995) on the conditions for populations of organisms to adapt on smooth, multiply-peakedlandscapes.4 Fisher (1930) makes the independence assumption explicitly.

    776 D.M. Walsh / Stud. Hist. Phil. Biol. & Biomed. Sci. 37 (2006) 771791

  • 7/28/2019 Organism Asnatural Purpose

    7/21

    The effects of individual replicators on an organisms phenotype are thus decomposable.The degree of similarity of organism is a function of the degree of similarity in their repli-cators. Given the enormous number of replicators in each organism, it more or less followsfrom (i)(iii) that the effect of each replicator on fitness is on average small. So, the adverse

    effect of new mutant replicators will generally be minimal. Taken together these conditionstell us that organisms are, in Broads terminology, resultant effects of the capacities o ftheir replicators. Replicators are vera causae of organisms (at least in Herschels sense).5

    Two further conditions must be met by replicators if populations of them are toundergo adaptive evolution. Lewontin has dubbed these continuity and quasi-independence:

    By continuity we mean that very small changes in character result in very small

    changes in : : : reproductive fitness. Neighborhoods in character space map into

    neighborhoods in fitness space. : : : By quasi-independence we mean that there exist

    a large variety of paths by which a given character may change, and: : :

    , a non-neg-lible proportion of these paths will not result in countervailing effects of sufficient

    magnitude to overcome the increase in fitness from the adaptation. (Lewontin,

    1978, p. 247)

    Populations of replicators certainly meet these conditions. Because replicators provideus with mechanical explanation for both the natures of organisms and the process of evo-lution, there should be no residual temptation to teleology (Cummins, 2002).

    Sub-organismal biology has its detractors. Most attempts to dislodge it from its privi-leged position in biology involve pointing out the degree to which the above assumptions

    are violated (for example, epistasis) or that the adaptation promoting power of replicatorselection is curtailed (Amundson, 2001; Gould & Lewontin, 1979). Another strategy is toargue that replicator biologys claim to comprehensiveness is ill deserved. Replicators arenot the only units of inheritance. Acquired morphological traits, behaviours, culturallytransmitted capacities can all be inherited and selected without replication (Boyd & Rich-ardson, 2004; Jablonka & Lamb, 2005; Mameli, 2004). Nor are sub-organismal replicatorsthe sole determinants of phenotype; the control of development is distributed throughoutthe organism/environment system (Griffiths & Gray, 2001; Oyama, 1985; Oyama, Grif-fiths, & Gray, 2001; Moss, 2002). These are important checks against what appears to havebeen an almost uncritical embrace of sub-organismal biology in the late 20th century. Nev-

    ertheless, sub-organismal replicators do play an important causal role in inheritance, evenif they are not the only things that do. They often correlate strongly with both fitness andphenotype. They are at least important difference makers in the development of a widerange of phenotypes. So, wholly comprehensive or not, replicators have a central explan-atory role to play in contemporary biology.

    The pressing question, one that contemporary biology has largely declined to broach, iswhat conditions secure the capacities of replicators to act in this way? A tempting answeris that replicators possess these remarkable capacities by their natures. A tradition inau-gurated by Max Delbruck maintains that the startling stability of DNA and its capacityto make high-fidelity copies are inherent in the structure of the genetic material; these

    are what make life possible. A starkly different answer, one that seems just recently to

    5 Peter McLaughlin has pointed out to me how far short replicators fall as genuine Newtonian vera causae.

    D.M. Walsh / Stud. Hist. Phil. Biol. & Biomed. Sci. 37 (2006) 771791 777

  • 7/28/2019 Organism Asnatural Purpose

    8/21

    be gathering some empirical support, is that replicators have their remarkable capacitiesbecause of the capacities of the organisms of which they are a part.

    3. Organismal biology

    Against the tide of sub-organismal mechanism of the 20th century biology, a few biol-ogists, for example Waddington (1957) and Schmalhausen (1949), continued to stress thesignificance of features of entire organisms for our understanding of biological processes(Sarkar & Gilbert, 2000). The features of organisms as natural purposes were consideredof particular significance: you cannot even think of an organism : : : without taking intoaccount what variously and rather loosely is called adaptiveness, purposiveness, goal seek-ing and the like (Von Bertalanffy, 1969, p. 45). Organicism is once again getting a hearing,at least among some biologists, due to the recent resurgence of interest in organismaldevelopment.

    The most explanatorily significant feature of organisms is their plasticity. Plasticity,according to Mary Jane West-Eberhard (2005a, 2003) is a universal principle of all livingthings. It consists in : : : the ability of an organism to react to an internal or external envi-ronmental input with a change in form, state, movement, or rate of activity (ibid., p. 33).West-Eberhards account of plasticity is strongly reminiscent of Kants description of thedistinctive features of organisms. Plasticity consists in the adaptive capacity of organismsto regulate their developmental sub-systems in order to build and maintain a stable, work-ing organism.

    The plasticity of organisms is pivotal in adaptive evolution. Plasticity engenders robust-

    ness, the capacity to maintain viability by making compensatory, adaptive changes to phe-notype. This in turn endows organisms with a broad phenotypic repertoire; an organismis capable of producing any of a wide range of stable phenotypic outcomes. According toWest-Eberhard plasticity and the phenotypic repertoire of organisms are the principalcauses of adaptive evolution. On this view, adaptive evolution proceeds in two stagesphenotypic accommodation followed by genetic accommodationboth of which dependupon the plasticity of organisms. West-Eberhard defines phenotypic accommodation asthe immediate adaptive adjustment of phenotype to the production of a novel trait or traitcombination (ibid., p. 147). She defines genetic accommodation as adaptive evolutionthat involves gene-frequency change (West-Eberhard, 2005b, p. 6544).

    The process, as envisaged by West-Eberhard, goes as follows. A mutation or environ-mental change, or change in development produces a new phenotype through phenotypicaccommodation. The organism responds to the new circumstances by the production of anovel phenotype. Given the phenotypic repertoire of organisms, there is latent genetic anddevelopmental variation in a population for the production of any particular phenotype.The introduction of a novel phenotype exposes this variation. Some gene combinations ordevelopmental structures may underwrite more robust, reliable or efficient ways of pro-ducing a novel adaptive phenotype. The effect is that the threshold for the developmentof the trait is lowered (Waddington, 1957). Recombination and selection of these develop-mental and genetic variants occurs. The consequence is evolutionchange in genetic

    structure of the populationas a consequence of the developmental plasticity of organisms.There are two important features that distinguish this conception adaptive evolution

    from the version offered by replicator biology. The first is that it is a property of organ-ismstheir plasticitythat explains why evolution is adaptive. The second is that novel

    778 D.M. Walsh / Stud. Hist. Phil. Biol. & Biomed. Sci. 37 (2006) 771791

  • 7/28/2019 Organism Asnatural Purpose

    9/21

    adaptive phenotypes are not caused by changes in replicator frequency, as the sub-organ-ismal model has it. On the contrary, adaptive novelties, brought about by plasticity oforganisms, cause changes replicator frequencies.

    Without developmental plasticity, the bare genes and the impositions of the environ-ment would have no effect and no importance for evolution. (West-Eberhard, 2005b,

    p. 6544)

    3.1. Modularity of development

    The key to the adaptive plasticity of organisms lies in the architecture of development:development is modular. Developmental modules have two defining features, their inter-nal structure and their mutual dissociation.

    The integrated internal structure of modules makes them robust; they are capable ofproducing their characteristic output despite the vagaries of their contexts, and despitechanges to their structure (von Dassow & Munro, 1999). Gene modules offer a vivid exam-ple. To the extent that genes exert control over phenotype it is not through individualgenes working in isolation; genetic control of development is exerted through suites (mod-ules) of genes working in concert. Genetic modules are characterised by complex regula-tory feedback relations among the module components. One significant consequence isthat gene modules exhibit a significant degree of robustness. The function of a modulecan withstand the loss or malfunction of one or more of its component genes. Conse-quently, each gene module produces its characteristic output across an enormous range

    of conditions (Gibson, 2002; von Dassow et al., 2000). This buffering also turns gene net-works into evolutionary capacitors (Bergman & Siegal, 2002). Gene networks are capableof producing novel stable products in novel circumstances (Greenspan, 2002).

    The dissociation of modulesthe nature of the regulatory relations among themexerts another kind of phenotypic effect. The repertoire of a developmental module, therange of its capacities taken in isolation, is considerably greater than the range of its real-ized effects. Typically each module is capable of producing any number of a large array ofstable outputs (Von Dassow et al., 2000). Which of its capacities is manifested on a par-ticular occasion is determined by the context in which the module finds itself. Modules arearranged in interacting hierarchies. Typically, each module directly influences and is influ-

    enced by other modules (but not many).The plasticity of development not only permits the adaptability of organisms, it also

    secures continuity, quasi-independence and high fidelity of replication, those conditionsnecessary for replicators to act as they are required to do by the precepts of our mecha-nistic replicator biology. Continuity is caused by the buffering (or canalization) broughtabout by the modular structure of development causes continuity. It guarantees that agene, or gene network, will have similar phenotypic effects across contexts, its broad phe-notypic repertoire notwithstanding. The robustness of development produces phenotypesthat are remarkably constant despite the enormous amount of underlying genetic variationwithin the population, and the unpredictability of environments. Furthermore, ontoge-

    netic buffering enables organisms to consolidate the developmental roles of genes; theactions of genes become routinised, locked into the production of particular phenotypes(Newman & Muller, 2001). Genes (replicators) may exert phenotypic control during devel-opment and ensure the reliable inheritance of phenotypes, but only because the entire

    D.M. Walsh / Stud. Hist. Phil. Biol. & Biomed. Sci. 37 (2006) 771791 779

  • 7/28/2019 Organism Asnatural Purpose

    10/21

  • 7/28/2019 Organism Asnatural Purpose

    11/21

    by appeal to the causal capacities of sub-organismal parts and processes, genes, geneticand developmental modules. This is a strictly mechanical form of explanation. But we can-not explain the capacities of sub-organismal components without appeal to the ways inwhich organisms construed as natural purposes control and regulate them. This is a decid-

    edly unmechanical, teleological form of explanation.We have something very like Kants Antinomy of the teleological power of judgment,

    recast in explanatory terms. We might call it the Antinomy of teleological explanation:

    Thesis: All biological phenomena must be explainable in accordance with merely

    mechanical laws.

    Antithesis: Some biological phenomena cannot be explained according to merelymechanical laws only (explaining them requires the teleology of natural purposes).

    This is no cause for rejoicing; an antinomy is a sign of something gone wrong. I believe,though, that we can consistently hold both the thesis and antithesis. But some work needsto be done. The thesis and antithesis look like formal contradictions, so they cannot beconsistent, unless there is some equivocation in their respective use of the terms. I thinkthere is an equivocation on the notion of explaining biological phenomena: biological phe-nomena can be explained severally or collectively. Mechanism, or some contemporary var-iant, may be able to explain of each organism, how the causal powers of its constituentparts combine to produce the organism in question. But mechanism alone may fall wellshort of explaining why the kinds of organisms that actually exist do so, or why organis-mal structure is so regular. Natural purposes, I shall argue, explain biological regularities.

    I take this challenge up in Section 5. But first we need to set aside the Kantian convictionthat natural purpose is inimical to mechanical law.

    4. Natural purpose

    Kants strategy for resolving the Antinomy of the teleological power of judgment isprobably unavailable to the modern day naturalist wishing to resolve the revised antinomyof explanation (Zammito, 2006). Available or not, it is not clear that Kants approachwould be particularly palatable to the modern day naturalist, for a couple of reasons.The first is Kants conviction that purposiveness cannot be demonstrated to be an objec-

    tive feature of the world. Nevertheless, Kant insists, we must treat teleology and mecha-nism alike as regulative principles, guiding discursive thought (Guyer, 2005;McLaughlin, 1990). The second is Kants insistence that teleology does not figure in gen-uine explanation: all explanation is mechanistic. A contemporary naturalist committed tothe revised antinomy should first attempt to demonstrate that the phenomenon of organ-isms as natural purposes is an objective, natural phenomenon, consistent with the rule ofmechanical law. The naturalist should then proceed to show, if possible, that natural pur-pose has the same explanatory credentials, as does mechanism. This section and the nextattempt to demonstrate these things in turn.

    One of Kants reasons for denying that teleology is an objective feature of the natural

    world is the inconsistency he perceives between the purposiveness of organisms and thenature of matter. A mechanical explanation, according to Kant, demonstrates that thephenomenon to be explained is wholly a consequence of the nature of matter. But organ-isms are self-organizing and self-building, and matter, by its nature, is inert.

    D.M. Walsh / Stud. Hist. Phil. Biol. & Biomed. Sci. 37 (2006) 771791 781

  • 7/28/2019 Organism Asnatural Purpose

    12/21

    However, the possibility of a living matter (the concept of which contains a contra-

    diction, because lifelessness, inertia, constitutes its essential characteristic), cannot

    even be conceived : : : (Kant, 2000, p. 394)

    The choice of inertia as the constitutive property of matter, of course, is no accident.Kant is affirming Newtons first law. Indeed, Kant reinterprets Newtons law of inertiaas one that holds that all changes in matter have extraneous (external) causes ( Watkins,2001). If Newtons first law articulates the nature of matter, then matter could not beself-moving, self-organizing or self-building.

    Kants argument has strong resonances with a conundrum raised by Erwin Schrodinger(1944) in his classic essay What is life?. Living things, according to Schrodinger, embody aparadox. They appear not to be consistent with the most basic principle of physics, and yetthey must be. Whereas for Kant the fundamental principles of physics were embodied inNewtons laws, for Schrodinger they are enshrined in thermodynamics. The material

    world inexorably moves toward a state of maximum entropydisorder. The distinctivefeature of organisms, however, is that they spontaneously build order and actively main-tain it. In metabolism they convert unstructured matter into highly structured, organicmaterials. In the process, they concentrate and store energy. Organisms are radically neg-entropic.6 Self-organizing matter is as problematic for Schrodinger as it is for Kant.

    Although the paradoxes have similar forms, Schrodingers resolution is starkly differentfrom Kants. Schrodinger points out that organisms do not, in fact, violate the second lawof thermodynamics. The second law applies to closed systems in which energy is neitheradded nor lost. The tendency to increase in entropy is a global property of such systems.So long as closed systems as a whole increase in entropy, open sub-systems may consistentlydecrease in theirs. How do systems decrease entropy locally with systematic regularity? Insystems far from thermodynamic equilibrium, where significant energy gradients occur, itmay well be that the most efficient way of dissipating energy is to build ordered structures todo the job. The marvellous order of convective (Benard) cells provide an illustrative exam-ple. Heat applied to the underside of a pan containing a thin layer of oil will set up a dense,stable arrangement of hexagonal convective cells (Benard cells) of uniform size. Thisorganization is robust; if perturbed it will return to its stable configuration. The explanationof this phenomenon is that this configuration is the most effective means for dissipatingenergy from the bottom of the layer of fluid to the top. These structures are negentropic,

    but they do not violate the second law. In Schrodingers phrase, they pay their debt to thesecond law by greatly increasing the entropy around them. Schrodinger concludes, rathertriumphantly, that the self-organizing, self-regulating features of living things do not vio-late the laws of thermodynamics. The spontaneous construction of stable, ordered struc-tures is to be expected in systems far from thermodynamic equilibrium. Rather thanviolating the second law of thermodynamics either, self-organization is predicted bythermodynamics.

    Schrodinger contends that the constitutive property of living things is metabolism:organisms maintain their negentropic structures by synthesizing the materials from whichthey are built (cf. Kant, 2000, p. 371). Maturana, Varela & Uribe (1974) appeal to a similar

    form of self-organizationautopoiesisin their definition of living things. A living thing is

    6 These features that Schrodinger took to be constitutive of living things are the very properties of organisms asnatural purposes that occasioned such disquiet in Kant.

    782 D.M. Walsh / Stud. Hist. Phil. Biol. & Biomed. Sci. 37 (2006) 771791

  • 7/28/2019 Organism Asnatural Purpose

    13/21

    an autopoietic machinean embodied, self-organizing entity that actively maintains itsstructure. Embodiment here means that the machine synthesises the materials out ofwhich it is built (Boden, 2000). Stuart Kauffman endorses this account of the nature ofliving things, and he explicitly invokes Kants reciprocity of causes in describing the

    self-organizing, self-sustaining autocatalytic reactions characteristic autopoietic machines:

    Immanuel Kant : : : saw organisms as wholes. The whole existed by means of the

    parts: the parts existed because of, and to sustain, the whole. This holism has been

    stripped of a natural role in biology, replaced with the image of the genome as the

    central directing agency that commands the molecular dance. Yet an autocatalytic

    set of molecules is perhaps the simplest image one can have of Kants holism.

    (Kauffman, 1995, p. 69)

    Kant and Schrodinger both take metabolismself-organization and self-buildingto

    be the mark of an organism. Kant takes these processes to be the mark of purposiveness.Whereas Kant avers that this purposiveness cannot be an objective principle, Schrodingerargues that it can. But Schrodinger locates self-organization as an objective property, notof matter as such, but of an organized system.7

    Self-organization has become one of the most fruitful avenues of research in modernevolutionary biology (Camazine et al., 2003). The mechanisms that underwrite self-orga-nization and the capacities of self-organizing systems are becoming increasingly wellunderstood (Heylighen, 2001). Organisms are complex self-organizing systems that existon the edge of chaos, neither too sensitive to perturbations to be thrown into chaos,nor too resistant to them to be fixed and frozen (Kauffman, 1993, 1995). In such systems

    the whole is the consequence of the causal capacities and activities of its component parts.Yet the capacities and activities of the component parts are the consequences of the adap-tive plasticity of the system as a whole. These systems are both cause and effect of theirconstituent parts. The robust, adaptively plastic, self-organization that marks organismsout as natural purposes is a simple consequence of a natural tendency of matter far fromthermodynamic equilibrium.

    Kant errs in his claim that natural purposes are inconsistent with the nature of matter.We can now locate purposiveness as an objective part of the mechanistic, natural world.

    : : : teleological behaviour directed toward a characteristic final state or goal is not

    something off limits for a natural science and an anthropomorphic misconceptionof processes which, in themselves, are undirected and accidental. Rather it is a form

    of behaviour which can be well defined in scientific terms and for which the necessary

    conditions and possible mechanisms can be indicated. (Von Bertalanffy, 1969, p. 46)

    The thesis of the antinomy is true; organisms as natural purposes are susceptible ofmechanical explanation. But this naturalization of biological teleology does not particu-larly promote the project of resolving the revised antinomy. To the extent that these sys-tems-theoretic, approaches to teleology offer a passably mechanistic explanation ofteleology, at the same time they weigh heavily against the truth of the antithesis.8 What

    7 I thank Joan Steigerwald and Peter McLaughlin for help here.8 Ginsborg (2004), p. 64 n. 47, expresses a similar worry, that naturalizing teleology in this way threatens the

    presumed indispensability of organisms as ends.

    D.M. Walsh / Stud. Hist. Phil. Biol. & Biomed. Sci. 37 (2006) 771791 783

  • 7/28/2019 Organism Asnatural Purpose

    14/21

    needs to be shown now is that the antithesis is true, despite the naturalization of teleology:some biological phenomena cannot be explained except by appeal to natural purposes,even though natural purpose itself is mechanistically explicable.

    5. Causes, laws and explanations

    The concept of a law of nature is ambiguous; at least it is compound. It is used vari-ously to cover two distinct but related concepts: governance and systematicity. By gover-nance I mean that the laws of nature govern the occurrences of things. An increasinglyprominent view of laws of nature holds that laws derive from fundamental capacities ofthings, the capacities that constitute their natures. These capacities necessitate their effects.The laws that describe how things with various causal powers are intrinsically disposed toact in virtue of having these powers are the causal laws of nature (Ellis, 2001, p. 206). This

    view of natural law, it would seem, is quite congenial to Kant. Kants conception of gov-ernance reflects this idea of laws of nature deriving from the natures of things: : : : the lawsof nature depend upon the natures that things have, and it is these natures that govern theactivities of substances in determining what happens (Watkins, 2005, p. 406). By systema-ticity I mean that laws of nature are supposed to be manifested as counterfactually robustempirical regularities. Kant appears to assume the systematicity of laws at least as a reg-ulative principle (Breitenbach, 2006). According to Kant the regularities of the physicalworld are to be explained by appeal to the governance of laws that constitute the natureof matter.

    Governance and systematicity of law are intimately associated in the Pure Mechanismof Newton, so admired by Kant. The world is regular precisely because it is governed by afew fundamental, systematic laws. Wherever we see an instance of regularity we are enti-tled, according to Newton, to infer the action of a particular law, acting on the same initialconditions. Therefore to the same natural effects we must, as far as possible, assign thesame causes (Newton, 1963, p. iii). On the Pure Mechanism model of explanation forany effect e, that instantiates regularity R, the factor that explains es occurrence is thesame as the factor that explains its instantiation of R. This has been enshrined in thecanonical concept of explanation throughout much of the 20th century, the DN model.According to the DN model of explanation, to explain an effect, e, is to subsume it under

    a general law, R, such that R (in conjunction with some initial conditions) entails theoccurrence of e.Nevertheless, governance and systematicity can be dissociated.9 Natural law does not

    invariably issue in systematicity of effects and the systematicity, or regularity, of effectsmay not be the consequence of unity of governing natural law. Chaotic and self-organizingsystems offer interesting illustrations. Chaos theory gives us an example of governance with-out systematicity. Chaotic systems are deterministic. Given the laws of nature and preciseinitial conditions, a given chaotic system will produce its outcome as a matter of nomicnecessity. But the laws governing chaotic systems do not figure in anything like systematicempirical regularities. Chaotic systems are characterised by hypersensitivity to initial condi-

    tions. A minor variation in initial conditions can result in an enormous difference in

    9 Nancy Cartwright (1999), for example, argues that the laws governing the workings of the world are notsystematic, but make up a patchwork of merely local regularities.

    784 D.M. Walsh / Stud. Hist. Phil. Biol. & Biomed. Sci. 37 (2006) 771791

  • 7/28/2019 Organism Asnatural Purpose

    15/21

    outcome. Consequently, for any given chaotic system, if we know the initial conditions andthe laws it is obeying, we get a complete explanation of its evolution. But this gives us noprediction or explanation of what would happen in other counterfactual situations in whichthe initial conditions are even minutely different. Self-organizing systems, on the other hand,

    offer an example of systematic regularity of phenomena that is not attributable to the unityof governing law. The robustness of self-organizing systems enables them to produce andmaintain a trajectory toward a particular endpoint despite significant differences in initialconditions and perturbations in the process. It is not the unity of law, or of underlyingcauses, that determines the systematic regularity of self-organizing systems; it is somethingelse, a structural property of the system as a whole. Where governance and systematicity peelapart in this way, it is natural to suppose that an explanation of the mechanical causes of aparticular event is not eo ipso an explanation of some regularity (and vice versa).

    Kant appears to countenance the important distinction between the mechanical explana-tion of regularities and the mechanical explanation of singular occurrences. Some phenom-ena, while explicable mechanistically, are nonetheless contingent with respect to mechanicallaw (Breitenbach, 2006; Ginsborg, 2001). One source of this contingency may be that someevents, while wholly explicable causally, are not likely to be regular. An example might be aparticular avalanche or volcanic eruption (chaotic systems in general will have this prop-erty). There is nothing about the general nature of matter that explains the specific detailsof these occurrences. They are highly irregular. What is so puzzling about organisms is thatthey are both so contingent with respect to mechanical law and also regular.

    Thus when Kant says that we cannot conceive of how unorganized matter left to itsown workings could spontaneously form itself into an organism, his point is that the reg-

    ularities exhibited by organisms cannot be accounted for in terms of fundamental regular-ities that characterize the behaviour of matter at the most general level (Ginsborg, 2001,p. 245). Biological regularity is not explicable by appeal to mechanical law.

    5.1. Difference making

    Intuitively, to explain an event is to single out those conditions that make the differencebetween the events occurrence and its non-occurrence: to explain is to identify a differencemaker. Typically the relation between the phenomenon to be explained, P, and its differ-ence maker, D, is one of invariance (Woodward, 2000). Invariance is a relation between a

    range of properties {d1, d2,: : :

    , dn} that D might possess and a range of properties {p1, p2,: : :, pn} that Pmight possess. The relation di, pi is invariant if and only if it is (i) changerelating and (ii) robust. Change relating is meant to capture the idea that a difference in thevalue ofdi brings about a difference in the value ofpi. Robustness is meant to capture theidea that the relation between di and pi is insensitive to a range ofother factors extrinsic todi, pi; as Garfinkel points out : : : an explanation must have a certain amount of stabilityunder perturbations of its conditions (Garfinkel, 1990, p. 448). When the invariance rela-tion holds, we can use it answer questions of the what-if-things-had-been-different sort(Woodward, 2000).10 To be in a position to answer such a question of some phenomenon,P, is to be able to explain P.

    10 We need also to be in the position to answer the question: what would have to be the same for things to workout this way again?.

    D.M. Walsh / Stud. Hist. Phil. Biol. & Biomed. Sci. 37 (2006) 771791 785

  • 7/28/2019 Organism Asnatural Purpose

    16/21

    The difference making approach to explanation reveals how, for some event or processe, that instantiates regularity R, the explanation of es occurrence may differ from theexplanation of es instantiating R. An example (misappropriated) from Elliott Sober(1984) illustrates the point. Suppose we observe that all the children in a particular class-

    room read at the grade three level and want to know why. The appeal for an explanationmay be read in either of two ways. We may want to know of all the children severally whyeach reads at that level. If so we must look to the particular history of each child, and wecite that factor that makes the difference between her reading at the grade three level,rather than some other. Alternatively, we may want to know why the constitution ofthe classroom is such that all the children read at that level. Here we advert to those fea-tures that make the difference between this class having this particular composition ratherthan some other. In Sobers example, the class is constituted this way because there isselection for reading ability; only those students who can read at the grade three levelare allowed into the class. This is a case in which the occurrence of an event token esay, Sarahs reading at the grade 3 leveland es instantiating a regularity Rthat all chil-dren in the class read at that levelcall for different explanations. The occurrence of e andits instantiation of R are sensitive to (stable across) different difference makers.

    5.2. Mechanical difference making and purposive difference making

    Using the apparatus of difference making we can demonstrate that Kants conceptionof organisms as natural purposes deserves a central, irreducible place in the understanding

    of evolutionary biology. This requires two steps, each of which exploits a distinctive fea-ture of the invariance account of explanation. In the first step, we demonstrate the consis-tency of the thesis and antithesis of our revised antinomy of teleological explanation. Inthe second, we establish the reciprocal causal relation between an organism and its parts.

    The first step, resolving the revised antinomy, avails itself of the fact that for sometoken event e that instantiates a regularity R, the explanation ofes occurrence may be dis-tinct from the explanation of es instantiation of R.

    Suppose we wish to explain some biological even token e, say the development of somea particular vertebrates eye; e is both an effect of local causes and an instance of a partic-ular (heritable and developmental) regularity, R. There will be a complete microstructural,

    mechanical explanation which cites all the causal factors in the etiology ofe, call these col-lectively ci, : : :, ck. The occurrence ofe is counterfactually dependent upon ci, : : :, ck. If cihad been different, for instance, so would the chain of subsequent events leading to e. Yetci, : : :, ck reliably produces e across a range of extraneous circumstances; ci, : : :, ck is amechanical difference maker for e. As a genuine mechanical explanation, this will demon-strate that the occurrence of ci, : : :, ck necessitates the occurrence of e as a matter of law.

    Kants conception of mechanistic explanation allows that effects of this sort are suscep-tible, severally, of mechanistic explanations:

    : : : the claim that organisms are inexplicable on mechanical laws : : : does not itself

    entail that we could never explain the origin of an individual bird as a lawlike con-sequence of the precise arrangement of matter to be found in an intact egg (as we

    might explain the ringing of an alarm clock as a lawlike consequence of its state just

    after having been wound up). (Ginsborg, 2001, pp. 242243)

    786 D.M. Walsh / Stud. Hist. Phil. Biol. & Biomed. Sci. 37 (2006) 771791

  • 7/28/2019 Organism Asnatural Purpose

    17/21

    By the same token, the mechanical explanation ofe, by appeal to its causal antecedents,ci, : : :, ck, fails to explain why e instantiates R. At this point, Kant cannot appeal to theidea that purpose plays a role in explaining biological regularities in just the way thatmechanism explains occurrences severally. For Kant, as we have seen, purposiveness is

    not an objective feature of the world. Moreover, for Kant, purposiveness does not figurein any genuine natural explanations. But, given the account offered above of purposivenessas a natural phenomenon, and the apparatus of difference making, we can help ourselvesto a solution unavailable to Kant.

    Organisms exhibit a startling degree of what Garfinkel calls redundant causality(Garfinkel, 1990, p. 448). There are many alternative causal paths that an organism canexploit in attaining its stable end state. This is just, of course, a consequence of their plas-ticity. Because of the redundant causality in organisms, R is not counterfactually depen-dent upon ci, : : :, ck. There are many ways to achieve R and if our particular individualhad not taken path ci, : : :, ck to e, plasticity would have ensured some other route tothe instantiation of R. So ci, : : :, ck is not a difference maker for R; plasticity is. So thereare two distinct aspects of our target event e to be explained, its occurrence and its instan-tiation ofR, and these are sensitive to different difference makers: the microphysical causesof e and the purposiveness (plasticity) of the organism respectively. Biology, then, has adivision of explanatory labour between the mechanical nature of biological processesand their purposiveness.

    This demonstrates that the thesis of the revised antinomythat all phenomena (sever-ally) have causal explanations that advert to mechanical lawdoes not entail the falsity ofthe antithesisbiological phenomena, taken collectively, may have non-mechanical, non-

    nomic, teleological explanations.Thesis: All biological phenomena must be explainable [severally] in accordance with

    merely mechanical laws.

    Antithesis: Some biological phenomena cannot be explained [collectively] according tomerely mechanical laws only (explaining them requires the teleology of natural

    purposes).

    Taken by itself, however, this resolution of the revised antinomy concedes too much toPure Mechanism, in doing so it falls short of establishing the most important feature of

    Kants conception of organisms as natural purposes. The consistency of the thesis andantithesis, as I have reconstructed them, does not preserve the idea that an organism isboth cause and effect of itself. For all it tells us, organisms may be merely effects ofthe suite of component processes. There has been no real gain on sub-organismal biology.

    The second step in rehabilitating Kants conception of the organism involves demon-strating that the suite of causal processes that actually occurs in the development of anorganism is also (reciprocally) dependent upon the purposiveness of the organism as awhole. This step also exploits the invariance approach to explanation. As we have seen,the component processes of ontogeny are mechanical difference makers for the purposive-ness of organisms. At the same time, the purposiveness of organisms is the difference

    maker for the suite of component causal processes. Uniquely in organisms, mechanismand purpose are reciprocal difference makers.

    The phenomena of phenotypic repertoire and phenotypic accommodation demonstratethis. An organism has a broad phenotypic repertoire. Each of its component parts can

    D.M. Walsh / Stud. Hist. Phil. Biol. & Biomed. Sci. 37 (2006) 771791 787

  • 7/28/2019 Organism Asnatural Purpose

    18/21

    produce a wide range of developmental outputs. The particular output each part produceson an occasion depends on the regulatory relations of the organism as a whole. In pheno-typic accommodation the component processes of development are altered by the adap-tive, regulatory capacities of the organism as a whole. Should one part of the

    developing organism be impinged upon by environmental pressure, or mutation, the restof the developmental system of the organism implements compensatory changes in orderto maintain a well functioning, viable organism. Phenotypic accommodation reduces theamount of functional disruption occasioned by developmental novelty (West-Eberhard,2003, p. 147). Kant appears to anticipate West-Eberhards concept of phenotypic accom-modation, to some degree, in his discussion of how the purposiveness of the organism as awhole regulates the component processes of development: If birth defects occur, or defor-mities come about during growth, certain parts : : : form in an entirely new way, so as topreserve what is there and so produce an anomalous creature (Kant, 2000, p. 372).

    The important point for our purposes is that the particular suite of causal processes thatactually occur within a developing organism only do so because of their regulation by thepurposiveness (plasticity) of the whole organism. We would have no explanation of whythe mechanisms of development play the causal roles they actually play in the productionand maintenance of a viable organism typical of its kind, without the purposiveness (plas-ticity) of organisms. This may be part of what Kant is adverting to by his claim that theorganism is contingent with respect to mechanistic causes (Ginsborg, 2001); that is, : : :that nature, considered as a mere mechanism, could have formed itself in a thousands dif-ferent ways without hitting upon the unity in accordance with such a rule [the structure ofa particular organism] (Kant, 2000, p. 360).

    There is, then, an invariance relation between the plasticity of the organism as a wholeand the causal powers of its component processes. It is (i) change involving: a change inthe overall structure of the organism would occasion a change in causal properties ofthe components; and (ii) robust: a developmental component has its particular causalpowers despite internal and external perturbations. This invariance relation is the exactreciprocal of the invariance relation between the causal powers of an organisms compo-nent processes and its plasticity. So, mechanical and purposive explanations in biology aremutually dependent. Each kind of difference maker (mechanical and purposive) has theother kind of difference maker as a difference maker. This is the sense in which organismsare causes and effects of themselves.

    6. Conclusion

    It goes without saying that the organismal perspective has fallen largely out of favour inpost-Darwinian biology. The very idea of explanation by appeal to the purposes of organ-isms has come to be seen as problematic, a metaphysical delusion. Besides, orthodoxopinion in contemporary evolutionary biology holds that there is no need to extend toorganismsmuch less their purposivenessan explanatory role if sub-organismal causalmechanisms are explanatorily adequate. To the extent that Kants conception of organ-isms as natural purposes has received any consideration from contemporary biology at

    all, it has been largely dismissed as an irrelevance.I have attempted to do two things here. The first is to emphasize that the properties of

    organisms which, according to Kant, mark them out as natural purposes, areobservable. It does not require immersion in the critical philosophy to see that organisms

    788 D.M. Walsh / Stud. Hist. Phil. Biol. & Biomed. Sci. 37 (2006) 771791

  • 7/28/2019 Organism Asnatural Purpose

    19/21

    are self-organizing, self-building adaptive systems. If recent evolutionary developmentalbiology is to be believed, the purposiveness of organisms is a contributing cause of bothontogeny and adaptive evolution. The second is to carve out an explanatory role fororganismal purposes that is consistent with the modern commitment to mechanism. Here,

    contemporary biologyand contemporary metaphysicsencounter precisely the problemthat motivated Kants Antinomy of the teleological power of judgment: teleologyappears to be inconsistent with mechanism. Mechanical causes explain; purposes cannot.Moreover, explanation by purpose appears to be otiose. If each natural phenomenon canbe fully explained by adverting to its mechanical causes, there is no unexplained residuefor which purposes are needed.

    As I see it, anti-teleological scruples such as these are motivated by the lack of a plau-sible model for how purposes could explain. I have tried to sketch out such a model hereusing the notion of invariance explanation, which yields two results, one fairly specific, theother quite general. The specific result is that there is an explanatory invariance relationbetween the purposiveness of an organism and the causal capacities of its parts thatdirectly mirrors the invariance relation between the causal capacities of an organismsparts and its overall purposiveness. Purpose and mechanism are reciprocal causes. Giventhat, even if the occurrence of each biological event has a complete mechanical, sub-organ-ismal explanation, it does not follow that there is no explanatory role for the purposive-ness of organisms to play. Purposiveness explains the regularity of these occurrences, andthis is crucial for the understanding what makes adaptive evolution adaptive. The moregeneral result is that, on the invariance model, purpose explains just like any other kindof cause.

    Acknowledgements

    I wish to thank Peter McLaughlin for comments on an early draft, Marcel Quarfoodfor engaging discussion on these issues, and audiences at IHPST, Toronto and the Con-sortium for the History and Philosophy of Biology workshop in Montreal. I would par-ticularly like to thank Joan Steigerwald, first for the invitation to contribute and thenfor patience and acumen as editor.

    References

    Amundson, R. (2001). Development and selection: On the lack of a common ground. In S. Orzack, & E. Sober(Eds.), Adaptation and optimality (pp. 303334). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Ayala, F. (1970). Teleological explanations in biology. Philosophy of Science, 37, 115.Bell, G. (2000). Selection: The mechanism of evolution. New York: Chapman Hall.Bergman, A., & Siegal, M. (2002). Evolutionary capacitance as a general feature of complex gene networks.

    Nature, 424, 549552.Boden, M. (2000). Autopoiesis and life. Cognitive Science Quarterly, 1, 117145.Boyd, R., & Richardson, P. (2004). Not by genes alone. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Breitenbach, A. (2006). Mechanical explanation of nature and its limits in Kants Critique of judgment. Studies in

    History and Philosophy of Science, this issue. doi:10.1016/j.shpsc.2006.09.001 .

    Broad, C. D. (1925). Mind and its place in nature. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Camazine, S., Deneubourg, J.-L., Franks, N. R., Sneyd, J., Theraulaz, G., & Bonabeau, E. (2003). Self-organization in biological systems. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Cartwright, N. (1999). The dappled world: A study in the boundaries of science. Cambridge: Cambridge UniversityPress.

    D.M. Walsh / Stud. Hist. Phil. Biol. & Biomed. Sci. 37 (2006) 771791 789

    http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsc.2006.09.001http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsc.2006.09.001
  • 7/28/2019 Organism Asnatural Purpose

    20/21

    Cornell, J. J. F. (1986). Newton of the grassblade? Darwin and the problem of organic teleology. Isis, 77,405421.

    Cummins, R. (2002). Neo-teleology. In A. Ariew, R. Cummins, & J. Perelman (Eds.), Functions: New essays in thephilosophy of biology and psychology (pp. 157173). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Darwin, C. (1972). The origin of species (6th ed.). Toronto: Dent. (First published 1859)

    Dawkins, R. (1982). The selfish gene. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Dawkins, R. (1986). The extended phenotype. Oxford: W. H. Freeman.Ellis, B. (2001). Scientific essentialism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Fisher, R. A. (1930). The genetical theory of natural selection. New York: Dover.Fox Keller, E. (2000). The century of the gene. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Garfinkel, A. (1990). Reduction. In R. Boyd, P. Gaspar, & J. D. Trout (Eds.), The philosophy of science (pp. 443

    459). Cambridge MA: MIT Press. (First published 1981)Ghiselin, M. (1993). Darwins language may have been teleological, but his thinking was a different matter.

    Biology and Philosophy, 9, 482492.Gibson, G. (2002). Getting robust about robustness. Current Biology, 12, R347R349.Ginsborg, H. (2001). Kant on understanding organisms as natural purposes. In E. Watkins (Ed.), Kant and the

    sciences (pp. 231258). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Ginsborg, H. (2004). Two kinds of mechanical inexplicability in Kant and Aristotle. Journal of the History ofPhilosophy, 42, 3365.

    Gould, S. J., & Lewontin, R. C. (1979). The spandrels of San Marco: A critique of the Panglossian paradigm.Proceedings of the Royal Society, Series B, 205, 581598.

    Greenspan, R. J. (2002). The flexible genome. Nature Reviews Genetics, 2, 383387.Griffiths, P. E., & Gray, R. (2001). Darwinism and developmental systems. In S. Oyama, P. E. Griffiths, & R.

    Gray (Eds.), Cycles of contingency (pp. 195218). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Guyer, P. (2005). Organisms and the unity of science. In P. Guyer (Ed.), Kants system of nature and freedom:

    Selected essays (pp. 86111). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Haynes, R. (1988). Biological context of DNA repair. In E. C. Friedberg, & P. C. Hanawalt (Eds.), Mechanisms

    and consequences of DNA damage processing (pp. 577584). New York: Alan Liss.

    Herschel, J. (1987). A preliminary discourse on the study of natural philosophy. Chicago: University of ChicagoPress. (First Published 1830)

    Heylighen, F. (2001). The science of self-organization and adaptivity. In L. D. Kiel (Ed.), Knowledge management,organizational intelligence and learning, and complexity. The Encyclopedia of Life Support Systems (EOLSS).www.eolss.net.

    Hull, D. (2003). Darwins science and Victorian philosophy of science. In J. Hodge, & G. R. Radick (Eds.), TheCambridge companion to Darwin (pp. 168191). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Jablonka, E., & Lamb, M. (2005). Evolution in four dimensions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Kant, I. (2000). Critique of the power of judgment (P. Guyer, & E. Matthew, trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge

    University Press. (First published 1793)Kauffman, S. (1993). The origins of order: Self-organization and selection in evolution. Oxford: Oxford University

    Press.

    Kauffman, S. (1995). At home in the universe: The search for the laws of self-organization and complexity. Oxford:Oxford University Press.

    Lewontin, R. C. (1978). Adaptation. Scientific American, 239, 212230.Mameli, M. (2004). Non-genetic selection and non-genetic inheritance. British Journal for the Philosophy of

    Science, 55, 3571.Maturana, H., Varela, F., & Uribe, R. (1974). Autopoiesis: The organization of living systems, its

    characterization and a model. Biosystems, 5, 187196.Maynard Smith, J. (2000). The concept of information in biology. Philosophy of Science, 67, 177194.Mayr, E. (1988). The multiple meanings of teleological. In idem, Towards a new philosophy of biology:

    Observations of an evolutionist (pp. 3866). Cambridge: Harvard University Press.McLaughlin, P. (1990). Kants critique of teleology in biological explanation. Lewiston, NY: Mellon.McLaughlin, P. (2000). What function explains. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Moss, L. (2002). What genes cant do. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Newman, S., & Muller, G. (2001). Epigenetic mechanisms of character origination. In G. Wagner (Ed.), The

    character concept in evolutionary biology (pp. 549579). New York: Academic Press.

    790 D.M. Walsh / Stud. Hist. Phil. Biol. & Biomed. Sci. 37 (2006) 771791

    http://www.eolss.net/http://www.eolss.net/
  • 7/28/2019 Organism Asnatural Purpose

    21/21

    Newton, I. (1963). Sir Isaac Newtons mathematical principles of natural philosophy, Vol. 2: The system of the world(A. Motte, trans.; revised by F. Cajori). Berkeley: University of California. (First published 1729)

    Oyama, S. (1985). The ontogeny of information: Developmental systems and evolution. Durham, NC: DukeUniversity Press.

    Oyama, S., Griffiths, P., & Gray, R. D. (Eds.). (2001). Cycles of contingency: Developmental systems and evolution.

    Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Sarkar, S., & Gilbert, S. (2000). Embracing complexity: Organicism for the 21st century. Developmental

    Dynamics, 219, 19.Schmalhausen, I. I. (1949). Factors of evolution. Philadelphia: Blakeston.Schrodinger, E. (1944). What is life? New York: Dover.Sober, E. (1984). The nature of selection. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Von Bertalanffy, L. (1969). General systems theory. New York: George Barziller.von Dassow, G. E., & Munro, E. M. (1999). Modularity in animal development and evolution: Elements of a

    conceptual framework for evodevo. Journal of Experimental Zoology (Mol. Dev. Evol.), 285, 307325.Von Dassow, G. E., Meir, M., Munro, E. M., & Odell, G. M. (2000). The segment polarity network is a robust

    developmental module. Nature, 406, 188192.

    Waddington, C. H. (1957). The strategy of the genes. London: Allen & Unwin.Wagner, A. (2005). Robustness and evolvability in living systems. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Watkins, E. (2001). Kants justification of the laws of mechanics. In E. Watkins (Ed.), Kant and the sciences

    (pp. 136159). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Watkins, E. (2005). Kant and the metaphysics of causality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.West-Eberhard, M. J. (2003). Developmental plasticity and evolution. Oxford: Oxford University Press.West-Eberhard, M. J. (2005a). Phenotypic accommodation: Adaptive innovation due to developmental plasticity.

    Journal of Experimental Zoology, 304B, 610618.West-Eberhard, M. J. (2005b). Developmental plasticity and the origin of species differences. Proceedings of the

    National Academy of Sciences in the United States, 102, 65436549.Woodward, J. (2000). Explanation and invariance in the special sciences. British Journal for the Philosophy of

    Science, 51, 107254.

    Zammito, J. (1991). The genesis of Kants Critique of Judgment. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Zammito, J. (2006). Teleology then and now: The question of Kants relevance for contemporary controversies

    over function in biology. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, this issue. doi:10.1016/j.shpsc.2006.09.008.

    D.M. Walsh / Stud. Hist. Phil. Biol. & Biomed. Sci. 37 (2006) 771791 791

    http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsc.2006.09.008http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsc.2006.09.008http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsc.2006.09.008http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsc.2006.09.008