masson v. new yorker magazine, inc., 501 u.s. 496 (1991)

Upload: scribd-government-docs

Post on 06-Jul-2018

215 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/17/2019 Masson v. New Yorker Magazine, Inc., 501 U.S. 496 (1991)

    1/26

    501 U.S. 496

    111 S.Ct. 2419

    115 L.Ed.2d 447

    Jeffrey M. MASSON, Petitioner

    v.NEW YORKER MAGAZINE, INC., Alfred A. Knopf, Inc. and

    Janet Malcolm.

     No. 89-1799.

     Argued Jan. 14, 1991.

     Decided June 20, 1991.

    Syllabus

    Petitioner Masson, a psychoanalyst, became disillusioned with Freudian

     psychology while serving as Projects Director of the Sigmund Freud

    Archives, and was fired after advancing his own theories. Thereafter,

    respondent Malcolm, an author and contributor to respondent The New

    Yorker, a magazine, taped several interviews with Masson and wrote alengthy article on his relationship with the Archives. One of Malcolm's

    narrative devices consists of enclosing lengthy passages attributed to

    Masson in quotation marks. Masson allegedly expressed alarm about

    several errors in those passages before the article was published. After its

     publication, and with knowledge of Masson's allegations that it contained

    defamatory material, respondent Alfred A. Knopf, Inc., published the

    work as a book, which portrayed Masson in a most unflattering light. He

     brought an action for libel under California law in the Federal DistrictCourt, concentrating on passages alleged to be defamatory, six of which

    are before this Court. In each instance, the quoted statement does not

    appear in the taped interviews. The parties dispute whether there were

    additional untaped interviews, the notes from which Malcolm allegedly

    transcribed. The court granted respondents' motion for summary

     judgment. It concluded that the alleged inaccuracies were substantially

    true or were rational interpretations of ambiguous conversations, and

    therefore did not raise a jury question of actual malice, which is requiredwhen libel is alleged by a public figure. The Court of Appeals affirmed.

    The court found, among other things, that one passage—in which Masson

    was quoted as saying that Archive officials had considered him an

  • 8/17/2019 Masson v. New Yorker Magazine, Inc., 501 U.S. 496 (1991)

    2/26

  • 8/17/2019 Masson v. New Yorker Magazine, Inc., 501 U.S. 496 (1991)

    3/26

     punctuation, and the practical necessity to edit and make intelligible a

    speakers' perhaps rambling comments, make it misleading to suggest that

    a quotation will be reconstructed with complete accuracy. However, if 

    alterations give a different meaning to a speaker's statements, bearing

    upon their defamatory character, then the device of quotations might well

     be critical in finding the words actionable. Pp. 513-518.

    (d) Although the Court of Appeals applied a test of substantial truth, it

    erred in going one step further and concluding that an altered quotation is

     protected so long as it is a "rational interpretation" of the actual statement.

    The protection for rational interpretation serves First Amendment

     principle by allowing an author the interpretive license that is necessary

    when relying upon ambiguous sources; but where a writer uses a quotation

    that a reasonable reader would conclude purports to be a verbatim

    repetition of the speaker's statement, the quotation marks indicate that theauthor is not interpreting the speaker's ambiguous statement, but is

    attempting to convey what the speaker said. Time, Inc. v. Pape, 401 U.S.

    279, 91 S.Ct. 633, 28 L.Ed.2d 45; Bose Corp. v. Consumers Union of 

    United States, Inc., 466 U.S. 485, 104 S.Ct. 1949, 80 L.Ed.2d 502,

    distinguished. Pp. 2433-2435.

    (e) In determining whether Masson has shown sufficient falsification to

    survive summary judgment, it must be assumed, except where otherwise

    evidenced by the tape recordings' transcripts, that he is correct in denying

    that he made the statements Malcolm attributed to him, and that Malcolm

    reported with knowledge or reckless disregard of the differences between

    what he said and what was quoted. Malcolm's typewritten notes should

    not be considered, since Masson denied making the statements, and since

    the record contains substantial additional evidence to support a jury

    determination under a clear and convincing evidence standard that

    Malcolm deliberately or recklessly altered the quotations. While she

    contests Masson's allegations, only a trial on the merits will resolve thefactual dispute. Pp. 2434-2435.

    (f) Five of the six published passages differ materially in meaning from

    the tape recorded statements so as to create an issue of fact for a jury as to

    falsity. Whether the "intellectual gigolo" passage is defamatory is a

    question of California law, and to the extent that the Court of Appeals

     based its conclusion on the First Amendment, it was mistaken. Moreover,

    an "incremental harm" doctrine—which measures the incrementalreputational harm inflicted by the challenged statements beyond the harm

    imposed by the nonactionable remainder of the publication—is not

    compelled as a matter of First Amendment protection for speech, since it

  • 8/17/2019 Masson v. New Yorker Magazine, Inc., 501 U.S. 496 (1991)

    4/26

    does not bear on whether a defendant has published a statement with

    knowledge of falsity or reckless disregard of whether it was false or not.

    Pp. 2435-2437.

    2. On remand, the Court of Appeals should consider Masson's argument

    that the District Court erred in granting summary judgment to the New

    Yorker Magazine, Inc., and Alfred A. Knopf, Inc., on the basis of their respective relations with Malcolm or the lack of any independent actual

    malice, since the court failed to reach his argument because of its

    disposition with respect to Malcolm. P. 2437.

    895 F.2d 1535, (CA9 1989), reversed and remanded.

    KENNEDY, J., delivered the opinion of the Court, in which

    REHNQUIST, C.J., and MARSHALL, BLACKMUN, STEVENS,

    O'CONNOR, and SOUTER, JJ., joined, and in Parts I, II-A, II-D, and III-

    A of which WHITE and SCALIA, JJ., joined. WHITE, J., filed an opinion

    concurring in part and dissenting in part, in which SCALIA, J., joined.

    Charles O. Morgan, Jr., San Francisco, Cal., for petitioner.

    H. Bartow Farr, III, Washington, D.C., for respondents.

    Justice KENNEDY delivered the opinion of the Court.

    1 In this libel case, a public figure claims he was defamed by an author who, with

    full knowledge of the inaccuracy, used quotation marks to attribute to him

    comments he had not made. The First Amendment protects authors and

     journalists who write about public figures by requiring a plaintiff to prove that

    the defamatory statements were made with what we have called "actual

    malice," a term of art denoting deliberate or reckless falsification. We consider in this opinion whether the attributed quotations had the degree of falsity

    required to prove this state of mind, so that the public figure can defeat a motion

    for summary judgment and proceed to a trial on the merits of the defamation

    claim.

    2 * Petitioner Jeffrey Masson trained at Harvard University as a Sanskrit scholar,

    and in 1970 became a professor of Sanskrit & Indian Studies at the University

    of Toronto. He spent eight years in psychoanalytic training, and qualified as ananalyst in 1978. Through his professional activities, he came to know Dr. Kurt

    Eissler, head of the Sigmund Freud Archives, and Dr. Anna Freud, daughter of 

    Sigmund Freud and a major psychoanalyst in her own right. The Sigmund

  • 8/17/2019 Masson v. New Yorker Magazine, Inc., 501 U.S. 496 (1991)

    5/26

    Freud Archives, located at Maresfield Gardens outside of London, serves as a

    repository for materials about Freud, including his own writings, letters, and

     personal library. The materials, and the right of access to them, are of immense

    value to those who study Freud, his theories, life and work.

    3 In 1980, Eissler and Anna Freud hired petitioner as Projects Director of the

    Archives. After assuming his post, petitioner became disillusioned withFreudian psychology. In a 1981 lecture before the Western New England

    Psychoanalytical Society in New Haven, Connecticut, he advanced his theories

    of Freud. Soon after, the Board of the Archives terminated petitioner as Projects

    Director.

    4 Respondent Janet Malcolm is an author and a contributor to respondent The

     New Yorker, a weekly magazine. She contacted petitioner in 1982 regarding the

     possibility of an article on his relationship with the Archives. He agreed, and

    the two met in person and spoke by telephone in a series of interviews. Based

    on the interviews and other sources, Malcolm wrote a lengthy article. One of 

    Malcolm's narrative devices consists of enclosing lengthy passages in quotation

    marks, reporting statements of Masson, Eissler, and her other subjects.

    5 During the editorial process, Nancy Franklin, a member of the fact-checking

    department at The New Yorker, called petitioner to confirm some of the facts

    underlying the article. According to petitioner, he expressed alarm at the

    number of errors in the few passages Franklin discussed with him. Petitioner 

    contends that he asked permission to review those portions of the article which

    attributed quotations or information to him, but was brushed off with a never-

    fulfilled promise to "get back to [him]." App. 67. Franklin disputes petitioner's

    version of their conversation. App. 246-247.

    6 The New Yorker published Malcolm's piece in December 1983, as a two-part

    series. In 1984, with knowledge of at least petitioner's general allegation that

    the article contained defamatory material, respondent Alfred A. Knopf, Inc.,

     published the entire work as a book, entitled In the Freud Archives.

    7 Malcolm's work received complimentary reviews. But this gave little joy to

    Masson, for the book portrays him in a most unflattering light. According to

    one reviewer,

    8 "Masson the promising psychoanalytic scholar emerges gradually, as a

    grandiose egotist—mean-spirited, self-serving, full of braggadocio, impossibly

    arrogant and, in the end, a self-destructive fool. But it is not Janet Malcolm who

  • 8/17/2019 Masson v. New Yorker Magazine, Inc., 501 U.S. 496 (1991)

    6/26

    calls him such: his own words reveal this psychological profile—a self-portrait

    offered to us through the efforts of an observer and listener who is, surely, as

    wise as any in the psychoanalytic profession." Coles, Freudianism Confronts Its

    Malcontents, Boston Globe, May 27, 1984, pp. 58, 60.

    9 Petitioner wrote a letter to the New York Times Book Review calling the book 

    "distorted." In response, Malcolm stated:

    10 "Many of [the] things Mr. Masson told me (on tape) were discreditable to him,

    and I felt it best not to include them. Everything I do quote Mr. Masson as

    saying was said by him, almost word for word. (The 'almost' refers to changes

    made for the sake of correct syntax.) I would be glad to play the tapes of my

    conversation with Mr. Masson to the editors of The Book Review whenever 

    they have 40 or 50 short hours to spare." App. 222-223.

    11 Petitioner brought an action for libel under California law in the United States

    District Court for the Northern District of California. During extensive

    discovery and repeated amendments to the complaint, petitioner concentrated

    on various passages alleged to be defamatory, dropping some and adding

    others. The tape recordings of the interviews demonstrated that petitioner had,

    in fact, made statements substantially identical to a number of the passages, and

    those passages are no longer in the case. We discuss only the passages relied on

     by petitioner in his briefs to this Court.

    12 Each passage before us purports to quote a statement made by petitioner during

    the interviews. Yet in each instance no identical statement appears in the more

    than 40 hours of taped interviews. Petitioner complains that Malcolm

    fabricated all but one passage; with respect to that passage, he claims Malcolm

    omitted a crucial portion, rendering the remainder misleading.

    13 (a) " Intellectual Gigolo." Malcolm quoted a description by petitioner of his

    relationship with Eissler and Anna Freud as follows:

    14 " 'Then I met a rather attractive older graduate student and I had an affair with

    her. One day, she took me to some art event, and she was sorry afterward. She

    said, "Well, it is very nice sleeping with you in your room, but you're the kind

    of person who should never leave the room—you're just a social

    embarrassment anywhere else, though you do fine in your own room." And youknow, in their way, if not in so many words, Eissler and Anna Freud told me

    the same thing. They like me well enough "in my own room." They loved to

    hear from me what creeps and dolts analysts are. I was like an intellectual

  • 8/17/2019 Masson v. New Yorker Magazine, Inc., 501 U.S. 496 (1991)

    7/26

    gigolo—you get your pleasure from him, but you don't take him out in public. .

    . .' " In the Freud Archives 38.

    15 The tape recordings contain the substance of petitioner's reference to his

    graduate student friend, App. 95, but no suggestion that Eissler or Anna Freud

    considered him, or that he considered himself, an " 'intellectual gigolo.' "

    Instead, petitioner said: "They felt, in a sense, I was a private asset but a publicliability. . . . They liked me when I was alone in their living room, and I could

    talk and chat and tell them the truth about things and they would tell me. But

    that I was, in a sense, much too junior within the hierarchy of analysis, for these

    important training analysts to be caught dead with me." Id., at 104.

    16 (b) "Sex, Women, Fun." Malcolm quoted petitioner as describing his plans for 

    Maresfield Gardens, which he had hoped to occupy after Anna Freud's death:

    17 " 'It was a beautiful house, but it was dark and sombre and dead. Nothing ever 

    went on there. I was the only person who ever came. I would have renovated it,

    opened it up, brought it to life. Maresfield Gardens would have been a center of 

    scholarship, but it would also have been a place of sex, women, fun. It would

    have been like the change in The Wizard of Oz, from black-and-white into

    color.' " In the Freud Archives 33.

    18 The tape recordings contain a similar statement, but in place of the reference to

    "sex, women, fun," and The Wizard of Oz, petitioner commented:

    19 "[I]t is an incredible storehouse. I mean, the library, Freud's library alone is

     priceless in terms of what it contains: all his books with his annotations in

    them; the Schreber case annotated, that kind of thing. It's fascinating." App.

    127.

    20 Petitioner did talk, earlier in the interview, of his meeting with a London

    analyst:

    21 "I like him. So, and we got on very well. That was the first time we ever met

    and you know, it was buddy-buddy, and we were to stay with each other and

    [laughs] we were going to pass women on to each other, and we were going to

    have a great time together when I lived in the Freud house. We'd have great

     parties there and we were [laughs]— 

    22 . . . . .

  • 8/17/2019 Masson v. New Yorker Magazine, Inc., 501 U.S. 496 (1991)

    8/26

    " . . . going to really, we were going to live it

    up." Id., at 129.23

    24 (c) " It Sounded Better." Petitioner spoke with Malcolm about the history of his

    family, including the reasons his grandfather changed the family name from

    Moussaieff to Masson, and why petitioner adopted the abandoned family nameas his middle name. The article contains the passage:

    25 " 'My father is a gem merchant who doesn't like to stay in any one place too

    long. His father was a gem merchant, too—a Bessarabian gem merchant, named

    Moussaieff, who went to Paris in the twenties and adopted the name Masson.

    My parents named me Jeffrey Lloyd Masson, but in 1975 I decided to change

    my middle name to Moussaieff—it sounded better.' " In the Freud Archives 36.

    26 In the most similar tape recorded statement, Masson explained at considerable

    length that his grandfather had changed the family name from Moussaieff to

    Masson when living in France, "[j]ust to hide his Jewishness." Petitioner had

    changed his last name back to Moussaieff, but his then-wife Terry objected that

    "nobody could pronounce it and nobody knew how to spell it, and it wasn't the

    name that she knew me by." Petitioner had changed his name to Moussaieff 

     because he "just liked it." "[I]t was sort of part of analysis: a return to the roots,

    and your family tradition and so on." In the end, he had agreed with Terry that"it wasn't her name after all," and used Moussaieff as a middle instead of a last

    name. App. 87-89.

    27 (d) " I Don't Know Why I Put It In." The article recounts part of a conversation

     between Malcolm and petitioner about the paper petitioner presented at his

    1981 New Haven lecture:

    28 "[I] asked him what had happened between the time of the lecture and the

     present to change him from a Freudian psychoanalyst with somewhat outre

    views into the bitter and belligerent anti-Freudian he had become.

    29 "Masson sidestepped my question. 'You're right, there was nothing

    disrespectful of analysis in that paper,' he said. 'That remark about the sterility

    of psychoanalysis was something I tacked on at the last minute, and it was

    totally gratuitous. I don't know why I put it in.' " In the Freud Archives 53.

    30 The tape recordings instead contain the following discussion of the New Haven

    lecture:

  • 8/17/2019 Masson v. New Yorker Magazine, Inc., 501 U.S. 496 (1991)

    9/26

    "A few days after my return to New York, Masson, in

    a state of elation, telephoned me to say that Farrar, Straus & Giroux has taken The

     Assault on Truth [Masson's book]. 'Wait till it reaches the best-seller list, and watch

    how the analysts will crawl,' he crowed. 'They move whichever way the wind

     blows. They will want me back, they will say that Masson is a great scholar, a major 

    analyst—after Freud, he's the greatest analyst who ever lived. Suddenly they'll be

    calling, begging, cajoling: "Please take back what you've said about our profession;

    our patients are quitting." They'll try a short smear campaign, then they'll try to buy

    me, and ultimately they'll have to shut up. Judgment will be passed by history. There

    is no possible refutation of this book. It's going to cause a revolution in

     psychoanalysis. Analysis stands or falls with me now.' " In the Freud Archives 162.

    31 Masson: "So they really couldn't judge the material. And, in fact, until the last

    sentence I think they were quite fascinated. I think the last sentence was an in,

    [sic] possibly, gratuitously offensive way to end a paper to a group of analysts.

    Uh,—"

    32 Malcolm: "What were the circumstances under which you put it [in]? . . ."

    33 Masson: "That it was, was true.

    34 . . . . .

    35 " . . . I really believe it. I didn't believe anybody would agree with me.

    36 . . . . .

    37 " . . . But I felt I should say something because the paper's still well within the

    analytic tradition in a sense. . . .

    38 . . . . .

    39 " . . . It's really not a deep criticism of Freud. It contains all the material thatwould allow one to criticize Freud but I didn't really do it. And then I thought, I

    really must say one thing that I really believe, that's not going to appeal to

    anybody and that was the very last sentence. Because I really do believe

     psychoanalysis is entirely sterile. . . ." App. 176.

    40 (e) "Greatest Analyst Who Ever Lived." The article contains the following self-

    explanatory passage:

    41

  • 8/17/2019 Masson v. New Yorker Magazine, Inc., 501 U.S. 496 (1991)

    10/26

    42This material does not appear in the tape recordings. Petitioner did make the

    following statements on related topics in one of the taped interviews with

    Malcolm:

    43 " . . . I assure you when that book comes out, which I honestly believe is an

    honest book, there is nothing, you know, mean-minded about it. It's the honest

    fruit of research and intellectual toil. And there is not an analyst in the countrywho will say a single word in favor of it." App. 136.

    44 "Talk to enough analysts and get them right down to these concrete issues and

    you watch how different it is from my position. It's utterly the opposite and

    that's finally what I realized, that I hold a position that no other analyst holds,

    including, alas, Freud. At first I thought: Okay, it's me and Freud against the

    rest of the analytic world, or me and Freud and Anna Freud and Kur[t] Eissler 

    and Vic Calef and Brian Bird and Sam Lipton against the rest of the world. Not

    so, it's me. It's me alone." Id., at 139.

    45 The tape of this interview also contains the following exchange between

     petitioner and Malcolm:

    46 Masson: " . . . analysis stands or falls with me now."

    47 Malcolm: "Well that's a very grandiose thing to say."

    48 Masson: "Yeah, but it's got nothing to do with me. It's got to do with the things I

    discovered." Id., at 137.

    49 (f) " He Had The Wrong Man." In discussing the Archives' board meeting at

    which petitioner's employment was terminated, Malcolm quotes petitioner as

    giving the following explanation of Eissler's attempt to extract a promise of 

    confidentiality:

    50 " '[Eissler] was always putting moral pressure on me. "Do you want to poison

    Anna Freud's last days? Have you no heart? You're going to kill the poor old

    woman." I said to him, "What have I done? You're doing it. You're firing me.

    What am I supposed to do—be grateful to you?" "You could be silent about it.

    You could swallow it. I know it is painful for you. But you could just live with

    it in silence." "Why should I do that?" "Because it is the honorable thing to do."

    Well, he had the wrong man.' " In the Freud Archives 67.

     

  • 8/17/2019 Masson v. New Yorker Magazine, Inc., 501 U.S. 496 (1991)

    11/26

      , ,

     part of petitioner's explanation (italicized below), and petitioner argues that the

    "wrong man" sentence relates to something quite different from Eissler's

    entreaty that silence was "the honorable thing." In the tape recording, petitioner 

    states:

    52 "But it was wrong of Eissler to do that, you know. He was constantly putting

    various kinds of moral pressure on me and, 'Do you want to poison Anna

    Freud's last days? Have you no heart?' He called me: 'Have you no heart?

    You're going to kill the poor old woman.

    53 Have you no heart? Think of what she's done for you and you are now willing

    to do this to her.' I said, 'What have I, what have I done? You did it. You fired

    me. What am I supposed to do: thank you? be grateful to you?' He said, 'Well

    you could never talk about it. You could be silent about it. You could swallowit. I know it's painful for you but just live with it in silence.' 'Fuck you,' I said,

    'Why should I do that? Why? You know, why should one do that?' 'Because it's

    the honorable thing to do and you will save face. And who knows? If you never 

     speak about it and you quietly and humbly accept our judgment, who knows

    that in a few years if we don't bring you back?' Well, he had the wrong man."

    App. 215-216.

    54 Malcolm submitted to the District Court that not all of her discussions with petitioner were recorded on tape, in particular conversations that occurred while

    the two of them walked together or traveled by car, while petitioner stayed at

    Malcolm's home in New York, or while her tape recorder was inoperable. She

    claimed to have taken notes of these unrecorded sessions, which she later typed,

    then discarding the handwritten originals. Petitioner denied that any discussion

    relating to the substance of the article occurred during his stay at Malcolm's

    home in New York, that Malcolm took notes during any of their conversations,

    or that Malcolm gave any indication that her tape recorder was broken.

    55 Respondents moved for summary judgment. The parties agreed that petitioner 

    was a public figure and so could escape summary judgment only if the

    evidence in the record would permit a reasonable finder of fact, by clear and

    convincing evidence, to conclude that respondents published a defamatory

    statement with actual malice as defined by our cases. Anderson v. Liberty

     Lobby, Inc., 477 U.S. 242, 255-256, 106 S.Ct. 2505, 2513-2514, 91 L.Ed.2d

    202 (1986). The District Court analyzed each of the passages and held that thealleged inaccuracies did not raise a jury question. The court found that the

    allegedly fabricated quotations were either substantially true, or were " 'one of a

    number of possible rational interpretations' of a conversation or event that

  • 8/17/2019 Masson v. New Yorker Magazine, Inc., 501 U.S. 496 (1991)

    12/26

    II

    A.

    'bristled with ambiguities,' " and thus were entitled to constitutional protection.

    686 F.Supp. 1396, 1399 (1987) (quoting Bose Corp. v. Consumer's Union of 

    the United States, Inc., 466 U.S. 485, 512, 104 S.Ct. 1949, 1965, 80 L.Ed.2d

    502 (1984)). The court also ruled that the "he had the wrong man" passage

    involved an exercise of editorial judgment upon which the courts could not

    intrude. 686 F.Supp., at 1403-1404.

    56 The Court of Appeals affirmed, with one judge dissenting. 895 F.2d 1535 (CA9

    1989). The court assumed for much of its opinion that Malcolm had

    deliberately altered each quotation not found on the tape recordings, but

    nevertheless held that petitioner failed to raise a jury question of actual malice,

    in large part for the reasons stated by the District Court. In its examination of 

    the "intellectual gigolo" passage, the court agreed with the District Court that

     petitioner could not demonstrate actual malice because Malcolm had not altered

    the substantive content of petitioner's self-description, but went on to note thatit did not consider the "intellectual gigolo" passage defamatory, as the quotation

    merely reported Kurt Eissler's and Anna Freud's opinions about petitioner. In

    any event, concluded the court, the statement would not be actionable under the

    " 'incremental harm branch' of the 'libel-proof' doctrine," id., at 1541 (quoting

     Herbert v. Lando, 781 F.2d 298, 310-311 (CA2 1986)).

    57 The dissent argued that any intentional or reckless alteration would prove actual

    malice, so long as a passage within quotation marks purports to be a verbatimrendition of what was said, contains material inaccuracies, and is defamatory.

    895 F.2d, at 1562-1570. We granted certiorari, 498 U.S. ----, 111 S.Ct. 39, 112

    L.Ed.2d 16 (1990), and now reverse.

    58 Under California law, "[l]ibel is a false and unprivileged publication by writing

    . . . which exposes any person to hatred, contempt, ridicule, or obloquy, or 

    which causes him to be shunned or avoided, or which has a tendency to injure

    him in his occupation." Cal.Civ.Code Ann. § 45 (West 1982). False attribution

    of statements to a person may constitute libel, if the falsity exposes that person

    to an injury comprehended by the statute. See Selleck v. Globe International,

     Inc., 166 Cal.App.3d 1123, 1132, 212 Cal.Rptr. 838, 844 (1985); Cameron v.

    Wernick, 251 Cal.App.2d 890, 60 Cal.Rptr. 102 (1967); Kerby v. Hal RoachStudios, Inc., 53 Cal.App.2d 207, 213, 127 P.2d 577, 581 (1942); cf. Baker v.

     Los Angeles Herald Examiner, 42 Cal.3d 254, 260-261, 228 Cal.Rptr. 206, 208-

    210, 721 P.2d 87, 90-91 (1986). It matters not under California law that

  • 8/17/2019 Masson v. New Yorker Magazine, Inc., 501 U.S. 496 (1991)

    13/26

    B

     petitioner alleges only part of the work at issue to be false. "[T]he test of libel is

    not quantitative; a single sentence may be the basis for an action in libel even

    though buried in a much longer text," though the California courts recognize

    that "[w]hile a drop of poison may be lethal, weaker poisons are sometimes

    diluted to the point of impotency." Washburn v. Wright, 261 Cal.App.2d 789,

    795, 68 Cal.Rptr. 224, 228 (1968).

    59 The First Amendment limits California's libel law in various respects. When, as

    here, the plaintiff is a public figure, he cannot recover unless he proves by clear 

    and convincing evidence that the defendant published the defamatory statement

    with actual malice, i.e., with "knowledge that it was false or with reckless

    disregard of whether it was false or not." New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376

    U.S. 254, 279-280, 84 S.Ct. 710, 726, 11 L.Ed.2d 686 (1964). Mere negligence

    does not suffice. Rather, the plaintiff must demonstrate that the author "in fact

    entertained serious doubts as to the truth of his publication," St. Amant v.Thompson, 390 U.S. 727, 731, 88 S.Ct. 1323, 1325, 20 L.Ed.2d 262 (1968), or 

    acted with a "high degree of awareness of . . . probable falsity," Garrison v.

     Louisiana, 379 U.S. 64, 74, 85 S.Ct. 209, 215, 13 L.Ed.2d 125 (1964).

    60 Actual malice under the New York Times standard should not be confused with

    the concept of malice as an evil intent or a motive arising from spite or ill will.

    See Greenbelt Cooper- ative Publishing Assn., Inc. v. Bresler, 398 U.S. 6, 90

    S.Ct. 1537, 26 L.Ed.2d 6 (1970). We have used the term actual malice as ashorthand to describe the First Amendment protections for speech injurious to

    reputation and we continue to do so here. But the term can confuse as well as

    enlighten. In this respect, the phrase may be an unfortunate one. See Harte-

     Hanks Communications, Inc. v. Connaughton, 491 U.S. 657, 666, n. 7, 109

    S.Ct. 2678, 2685, n. 7, 105 L.Ed.2d 562 (1989). In place of the term actual

    malice, it is better practice that jury instructions refer to publication of a

    statement with knowledge of falsity or reckless disregard as to truth or falsity.

    This definitional principle must be remembered in the case before us.

    61 In general, quotation marks around a passage indicate to the reader that the

     passage reproduces the speaker's words verbatim. They inform the reader that

    he or she is reading the statement of the speaker, not a paraphrase or other 

    indirect interpretation by an author. By providing this information, quotations

    add authority to the statement and credibility to the author's work. Quotationsallow the reader to form his or her own conclusions, and to assess the

    conclusions of the author, instead of relying entirely upon the author's

    characterization of her subject.

  • 8/17/2019 Masson v. New Yorker Magazine, Inc., 501 U.S. 496 (1991)

    14/26

    62 A fabricated quotation may injure reputation in at least two senses, either 

    giving rise to a conceivable claim of defamation. First, the quotation might

    injure because it attributes an untrue factual assertion to the speaker. An

    example would be a fabricated quotation of a public official admitting he had

     been convicted of a serious crime when in fact he had not.

    63 Second, regardless of the truth or falsity of the factual matters asserted withinthe quoted statement, the attribution may result in injury to reputation because

    the manner of expression or even the fact that the statement was made indicates

    a negative personal trait or an attitude the speaker does not hold. John Lennon

    once was quoted as saying of the Beatles, "We're more popular than Jesus

    Christ now." Time, Aug. 12, 1966, p. 38. Supposing the quotation had been a

    fabrication, it appears California law could permit recovery for defamation

     because, even without regard to the truth of the underlying assertion, false

    attribution of the statement could have injured his reputation. Here, in likemanner, one need not determine whether petitioner is or is not the greatest

    analyst who ever lived in order to determine that it might have injured his

    reputation to be reported as having so proclaimed.

    64 A self-condemnatory quotation may carry more force than criticism by another.

    It is against self-interest to admit one's own criminal liability, arrogance, or lack 

    of integrity, and so all the more easy to credit when it happens. This principle

    underlies the elemental rule of evidence which permits the introduction of admissions, despite their hearsay character, because we assume "that persons

    do not make statements which are damaging to themselves unless satisfied for 

    good reason that they are true." Advisory Committee's Notes on Fed.Rule Evid.

    804(b)(3), 28 U.S.C.App., p. 789 (citing Hileman v. Northwest Engineering 

    Co., 346 F.2d 668 (CA6 1965)).

    65 Of course, quotations do not always convey that the speaker actually said or 

    wrote the quoted material. "Punctuation marks, like words, have many uses.

    Writers often use quotation marks, yet no reasonable reader would assume that

    such punctuation automatically implies the truth of the quoted material." Baker 

    v. Los Angeles Examiner, 42 Cal.3d, at 263, 228 Cal.Rptr., at 211, 721 P.2d, at

    92. In Baker, a television reviewer printed a hypothetical conversation between

    a station vice president and writer/producer, and the court found that no

    reasonable reader would conclude the plaintiff in fact had made the statement

    attributed to him. Id., at 267, 228 Cal.Rptr., at 213, 721 P.2d, at 95. Writers

    often use quotations as in Baker, and a reader will not reasonably understandthe quotations to indicate reproduction of a conversation that took place. In

    other instances, an acknowledgement that the work is so-called docudrama or 

    historical fiction, or that it recreates conversations from memory, not from

  • 8/17/2019 Masson v. New Yorker Magazine, Inc., 501 U.S. 496 (1991)

    15/26

    C

    recordings, might indicate that the quotations should not be interpreted as the

    actual statements of the speaker to whom they are attributed.

    66 The work at issue here, however, as with much journalistic writing, provides

    the reader no clue that the quotations are being used as a rhetorical device or to

     paraphrase the speaker's actual statements. To the contrary, the work purports

    to be nonfiction, the result of numerous interviews. At least a trier of fact couldso conclude. The work contains lengthy quotations attributed to petitioner, and

    neither Malcolm nor her publishers indicate to the reader that the quotations are

    anything but the reproduction of actual conversations. Further, the work was

     published in The New Yorker, a magazine which at the relevant time seemed to

    enjoy a reputation for scrupulous factual accuracy. These factors would, or at

    least could, lead a reader to take the quotations at face value. A defendant may

     be able to argue to the jury that quotations should be viewed by the reader as

    nonliteral or reconstructions, but we conclude that a trier of fact in this casecould find that the reasonable reader would understand the quotations to be

    nearly verbatim reports of statements made by the subject.

    67 The constitutional question we must consider here is whether, in the framework 

    of a summary judgment motion, the evidence suffices to show that respondents

    acted with the requisite knowledge of falsity or reckless disregard as to truth or falsity. This inquiry in turn requires us to consider the concept of falsity; for we

    cannot discuss the standards for knowledge or reckless disregard without some

    understanding of the acts required for liability. We must consider whether the

    requisite falsity inheres in the attribution of words to the petitioner which he did

    not speak.

    68 In some sense, any alteration of a verbatim quotation is false. But writers and

    reporters by necessity alter what people say, at the very least to eliminategrammatical and syntactical infelicities. If every alteration constituted the

    falsity required to prove actual malice, the practice of journalism, which the

    First Amendment standard is designed to protect, would require a radical

    change, one inconsistent with our precedents and First Amendment principles.

    Petitioner concedes this absolute definition of falsity in the quotation context is

    too stringent, and acknowledges that "minor changes to correct for grammar or 

    syntax" do not amount to falsity for purposes of proving actual malice. Brief for 

    Petitioner 18, 36-37. We agree, and must determine what, in addition to thistechnical falsity, proves falsity for purposes of the actual malice inquiry.

    69 Petitioner argues that, excepting correction of grammar or syntax, publication

  • 8/17/2019 Masson v. New Yorker Magazine, Inc., 501 U.S. 496 (1991)

    16/26

    of a quotation with knowledge that it does not contain the words the public

    figure used demonstrates actual malice. The author will have published the

    quotation with knowledge of falsity, and no more need be shown. Petitioner 

    suggests that by invoking more forgiving standards the Court of Appeals would

     permit and encourage the publication of falsehoods. Petitioner believes that the

    intentional manufacture of quotations does not "represen[t] the sort of 

    inaccuracy that is commonplace in the forum of robust debate to which the NewYork Times rule applies," Bose Corp., 466 U.S., at 513, 104 S.Ct., at 1966, and

    that protection of deliberate falsehoods would hinder the First Amendment

    values of robust and well-informed public debate by reducing the reliability of 

    information available to the public.

    70 We reject the idea that any alteration beyond correction of grammar or syntax

     by itself proves falsity in the sense relevant to determining actual malice under 

    the First Amendment. An interviewer who writes from notes often will engagein the task of attempting a reconstruction of the speaker's statement. That author 

    would, we may assume, act with knowledge that at times she has attributed to

    her subject words other than those actually used. Under petitioner's proposed

    standard, an author in this situation would lack First Amendment protection if 

    she reported as quotations the substance of a subject's derogatory statements

    about himself.

    71 Even if a journalist has tape recorded the spoken statement of a public figure,the full and exact statement will be reported in only rare circumstances. The

    existence of both a speaker and a reporter; the translation between two media,

    speech and the printed word; the addition of punctuation; and the practical

    necessity to edit and make intelligible a speaker's perhaps rambling comments,

    all make it misleading to suggest that a quotation will be reconstructed with

    complete accuracy. The use or absence of punctuation may distort a speaker's

    meaning, for example, where that meaning turns upon a speaker's emphasis of a

     particular word. In other cases, if a speaker makes an obvious misstatement, for example by unconscious substitution of one name for another, a journalist

    might alter the speaker's words but preserve his intended meaning. And

    conversely, an exact quotation out of context can distort meaning, although the

    speaker did use each reported word.

    72 In all events, technical distinctions between correcting grammar and syntax and

    some greater level of alteration do not appear workable, for we can think of no

    method by which courts or juries would draw the line between cleaning up andother changes, except by reference to the meaning a statement conveys to a

    reasonable reader. To attempt narrow distinctions of this type would be an

    unnecessary departure from First Amendment principles of general

  • 8/17/2019 Masson v. New Yorker Magazine, Inc., 501 U.S. 496 (1991)

    17/26

     Milkovich v. Lorain Journal Co., 497 U.S. 1, ----, 110 S.Ct. 2695, ----, 111 L.Ed.2d 1

    (1990). As we have recognized, "[t]he legitimate state interest underlying the law of libel is the compensation of individuals for the harm inflicted on them by

    defamatory falsehood." Gertz v. Robert Welch, Inc., 418 U.S. 323, 94 S.Ct. 2997, 41

    L.Ed.2d 789 (1974). If an author alters a speaker's words but effects no material

    change in meaning, including any meaning conveyed by the manner or fact of 

    expression, the speaker suffers no injury to reputation that is compensable as a

    defamation.

    applicability, and, just as important, a departure from the underlying purposes

    of the tort of libel as understood since the latter half of the 16th century. From

    then until now, the tort action for defamation has existed to redress injury to the

     plaintiff's reputation by a statement that is defamatory and false. See [516]

    73

    74 These essential principles of defamation law accommodate the special case of inaccurate quotations without the necessity for a discrete body of jurisprudence

    directed to this subject alone. Last Term, in Milkovich v. Lorain Journal Co.,

    we refused "to create a wholesale defamation exemption for anything that

    might be labeled 'opinion.' " 497 U.S., at ----, 110 S.Ct., at 2705 (citation

    omitted). We recognized that "expressions of 'opinion' may often imply an

    assertion of objective fact." Ibid. We allowed the defamation action to go

    forward in that case, holding that a reasonable trier of fact could find that the

    so-called expressions of opinion could be interpreted as including falseassertions as to factual matters. So too in the case before us, we reject any

    special test of falsity for quotations, including one which would draw the line at

    correction of grammar or syntax. We conclude, rather, that the exceptions

    suggested by petitioner for grammatical or syntactical corrections serve to

    illuminate a broader principle.

    75 The common law of libel takes but one approach to the question of falsity,

    regardless of the form of the communication. See Restatement (Second) of Torts § 563, Comment c (1977); W. Keeton, D. Dobbs, R. Keeton, & D. Owen,

    Prosser and Keeton on Law of Torts 776 (5th ed. 1984). It overlooks minor 

    inaccuracies and concentrates upon substantial truth. As in other jurisdictions,

    California law permits the defense of substantial truth, and would absolve a

    defendant even if she cannot "justify every word of the alleged defamatory

    matter; it is sufficient if the substance of the charge be proved true, irrespective

    of slight inaccuracy in the details." B. Witkin, Summary of California Law, §

    495 (9th ed. 1988) (citing cases). In this case, of course, the burden is upon petitioner to prove falsity. See Philadelphia Newspapers, Inc. v. Hepps, 475

    U.S. 767, 775, 106 S.Ct. 1558, 1563, 89 L.Ed.2d 783 (1986). The essence of 

    that inquiry, however, remains the same whether the burden rests upon plaintiff 

  • 8/17/2019 Masson v. New Yorker Magazine, Inc., 501 U.S. 496 (1991)

    18/26

    D

    or defendant. Minor inaccuracies do not amount to falsity so long as "the

    substance, the gist, the sting, of the libelous charge be justified." Heuer v. Kee,

    15 Cal.App.2d 710, 714, 59 P.2d 1063, 1064 (1936); see also Alioto v. Cowles

    Communications, Inc., 623 F.2d 616, 619 (CA9 1980); Maheu v. Hughes Tool 

    Co., 569 F.2d 459, 465-466 (CA9 1978). Put another way, the statement is not

    considered false unless it "would have a different effect on the mind of the

    reader from that which the pleaded truth would have produced." R. Sack, Libel,Slander, and Related Problems 138 (1980); see, e.g., Wheling v. Columbia

     Broadcasting System, Inc., 721 F.2d 506, 509 (CA5 1983); see generally R.

    Smolla, Law of Defamation § 5.08 (1991). Our definition of actual malice relies

    upon this historical understanding.

    76 We conclude that a deliberate alteration of the words uttered by a plaintiff does

    not equate with knowledge of falsity for purposes of New York Times Co. v.

    Sullivan, 376 U.S., at 279-280, 84 S.Ct., at 725-726 and Gertz v. Robert Welch, Inc., supra, 418 U.S., at 342, 94 S.Ct., at 3008, unless the alteration results in a

    material change in the meaning conveyed by the statement. The use of 

    quotations to attribute words not in fact spoken bears in a most important way

    on that inquiry, but it is not dispositive in every case.

    77 Deliberate or reckless falsification that comprises actual malice turns upon

    words and punctuation only because words and punctuation express meaning.

    Meaning is the life of language. And, for the reasons we have given, quotationsmay be a devastating instrument for conveying false meaning. In the case under 

    consideration, readers of In the Freud Archives may have found Malcolm's

     portrait of petitioner especially damning because so much of it appeared to be a

    self-portrait, told by petitioner in his own words. And if the alterations of 

     petitioner's words gave a different meaning to the statements, bearing upon their 

    defamatory character, then the device of quotations might well be critical in

    finding the words actionable.

    78 The Court of Appeals applied a test of substantial truth which, in exposition if 

    not in application, comports with much of the above discussion. The Court of 

    Appeals, however, went one step beyond protection of quotations that convey

    the meaning of a speaker's statement with substantial accuracy and concluded

    that an altered quotation is protected so long as it is a "rational interpretation" of 

    an actual statement, drawing this standard from our decisions in Time, Inc. v. Pape, 401 U.S. 279, 91 S.Ct. 633, 28 L.Ed.2d 45 (1971), and  Bose Corp. v.

    Consumers Union of United States, Inc., 466 U.S. 485, 104 S.Ct. 1949, 80

    L.Ed.2d 502 (1984). Application of our protection for rational interpretation in

  • 8/17/2019 Masson v. New Yorker Magazine, Inc., 501 U.S. 496 (1991)

    19/26

    this context finds no support in general principles of defamation law or in our 

    First Amendment jurisprudence. Neither Time, Inc. v. Pape, nor Bose Corp.,

    involved the fabrication of quotations, or any analogous claim, and because

    many of the quotations at issue might reasonably be construed to state or imply

    factual assertions that are both false and defamatory, we cannot accept the

    reasoning of the Court of Appeals on this point.

    79 In Time, Inc. v. Pape, we reversed a libel judgment which arose out of a

    magazine article summarizing a report by the United States Commission on

    Civil Rights discussing police civil rights abuses. The article quoted the

    Commission's summary of the facts surrounding an incident of police brutality,

     but failed to include the Commission's qualification that these were allegations

    taken from a civil complaint. The Court noted that "the attitude of the

    Commission toward the factual verity of the episodes recounted was anything

     but straightforward," and distinguished between a "direct account of events thatspeak for themselves," 401 U.S., at 285, 286, 91 S.Ct., at 637, 637, and an

    article descriptive of what the Commission had reported. Time, Inc. v. Pape

    took into account the difficult choices that confront an author who departs from

    direct quotation and offers his own interpretation of an ambiguous source. A

    fair reading of our opinion is that the defendant did not publish a falsification

    sufficient to sustain a finding of actual malice.

    80 In Bose Corp., a Consumer Reports reviewer had attempted to describe inwords the experience of listening to music through a pair of loudspeakers, and

    we concluded that the result was not an assessment of events that speak for 

    themselves, but " 'one of a number of possible rational interpretations' of an

    event 'that bristled with ambiguities' and descriptive challenges for the writer."

    466 U.S., at 512, 104 S.Ct., at 1966 (quoting Time, Inc. v. Pape, supra, 401

    U.S., at 290, 91 S.Ct., at 639). We refused to permit recovery for choice of 

    language which, though perhaps reflecting a misconception, represented "the

    sort of inaccuracy that is commonplace in the forum of robust debate to whichthe New York Times rule applies." 466 U.S., at 513, 104 S.Ct., at 1966.

    81 The protection for rational interpretation serves First Amendment principles by

    allowing an author the interpretive license that is necessary when relying upon

    ambiguous sources. Where, however, a writer uses a quotation, and where a

    reasonable reader would conclude that the quotation purports to be a verbatim

    repetition of a statement by the speaker, the quotation marks indicate that the

    author is not involved in an interpretation of the speaker's ambiguous statement, but attempting to convey what the speaker said. This orthodox use of a

    quotation is the quintessential "direct account of events that speak for 

    themselves." Time, Inc. v. Pape, supra, 401 U.S., at 285, 91 S.Ct., at 637. More

  • 8/17/2019 Masson v. New Yorker Magazine, Inc., 501 U.S. 496 (1991)

    20/26

    III

    A.

    accurately, the quotation allows the subject to speak for himself.

    82 The significance of the quotations at issue, absent any qualification, is to

    inform us that we are reading the statement of petitioner, not Malcolm's rational

    interpretation of what petitioner has said or thought. Were we to assess

    quotations under a rational interpretation standard, we would give journalists

    the freedom to place statements in their subjects' mouths without fear of liability. By eliminating any method of distinguishing between the statements

    of the subject and the interpretation of the author, we would diminish to a great

    degree the trustworthiness of the printed word, and eliminate the real meaning

    of quotations. Not only public figures but the press doubtless would suffer 

    under such a rule. Newsworthy figures might become more wary of journalists,

    knowing that any comment could be transmuted and attributed to the subject, so

    long as some bounds of rational interpretation were not exceeded. We would ill

    serve the values of the First Amendment if we were to grant near absolute,constitutional protection for such a practice. We doubt the suggestion that as a

    general rule readers will assume that direct quotations are but a rational

    interpretation of the speaker's words, and we decline to adopt any such

     presumption in determining the permissible interpretations of the quotations in

    question here.

    83 We apply these principles to the case before us. On summary judgment, we

    must draw all justifiable inferences in favor of the nonmoving party, including

    questions of credibility and of the weight to be accorded particular evidence.

     Anderson v. Liberty Lobby, Inc., 477 U.S., at 255, 106 S.Ct., at 2513. So we

    must assume, except where otherwise evidenced by the transcripts of the tape

    recordings, that petitioner is correct in denying that he made the statementsattributed to him by Malcolm, and that Malcolm reported with knowledge or 

    reckless disregard of the differences between what petitioner said and what was

    quoted.

    84 Respondents argue that, in determining whether petitioner has shown sufficient

    falsification to survive summary judgment, we should consider not only the

    tape-recorded statements but also Malcolm's typewritten notes. We must

    decline that suggestion. To begin with, petitioner affirms in an affidavit that hedid not make the complained of statements. The record contains substantial

    additional evidence, moreover, evidence which, in a light most favorable to

     petitioner, would support a jury determination under a clear and convincing

  • 8/17/2019 Masson v. New Yorker Magazine, Inc., 501 U.S. 496 (1991)

    21/26

    B

    standard that Malcolm deliberately or recklessly altered the quotations.

    85 First, many of the challenged passages resemble quotations that appear on the

    tapes, except for the addition or alteration of certain phrases, giving rise to a

    reasonable inference that the statements have been altered. Second, Malcolm

    had the tapes in her possession and was not working under a tight deadline.

    Unlike a case involving hot news, Malcolm cannot complain that she lackedthe practical ability to compare the tapes with her work in progress. Third,

    Malcolm represented to the editor-in-chief of The New Yorker that all the

    quotations were from the tape recordings. Fourth, Malcolm's explanations of 

    the time and place of unrecorded conversations during which petitioner 

    allegedly made some of the quoted statements have not been consistent in all

    respects. Fifth, petitioner suggests that the progression from typewritten notes,

    to manuscript, then to galleys provides further evidence of intentional

    alteration. Malcolm contests petitioner's allegations, and only a trial on themerits will resolve the factual dispute. But at this stage, the evidence creates a

     jury question whether Malcolm published the statements with knowledge or 

    reckless disregard of the alterations.

    86 We must determine whether the published passages differ materially in

    meaning from the tape recorded statements so as to create an issue of fact for a jury as to falsity.

    87 (a) " Intellectual Gigolo." We agree with the dissenting opinion in the Court of 

    Appeals that "[f]airly read, intellectual gigolo suggests someone who forsakes

    intellectual integrity in exchange for pecuniary or other gain." 895 F.2d, at

    1551. A reasonable jury could find a material difference between the meaning

    of this passage and petitioner's tape-recorded statement that he was considered

    "much too junior within the hierarchy of analysis, for these important traininganalysts to be caught dead with [him]."

    88 The Court of Appeals majority found it difficult to perceive how the

    "intellectual gigolo" quotation was defamatory, a determination supported not

     by any citation to California law, but only by the argument that the passage

    appears to be a report of Eissler's and Anna Freud's opinions of petitioner. Id.,

    at 1541. We agree with the Court of Appeals that the most natural interpretation

    of this quotation is not an admission that petitioner considers himself anintellectual gigolo but a statement that Eissler and Anna Freud considered him

    so. It does not follow, though, that the statement is harmless. Petitioner is

    entitled to argue that the passage should be analyzed as if Malcolm had

  • 8/17/2019 Masson v. New Yorker Magazine, Inc., 501 U.S. 496 (1991)

    22/26

    reported falsely that Eissler  had given this assessment (with the added level of 

    complexity that the quotation purports to represent petitioner's understanding of 

    Eissler's view). An admission that two well-respected senior colleagues

    considered one an "intellectual gigolo" could be as or more damaging than a

    similar self-appraisal. In all events, whether the "intellectual gigolo" quotation

    is defamatory is a question of California law. To the extent that the Court of 

    Appeals based its conclusion in the First Amendment, it was mistaken.

    89 The Court of Appeals relied upon the "incremental harm" doctrine as an

    alternative basis for its decision. As the court explained it, "[t]his doctrine

    measures the incremental reputational harm inflicted by the challenged

    statements beyond the harm imposed by the nonactionable remainder of the

     publication." Ibid.; see generally Note, 98 Harv.L. Rev. 1909 (1985); R.

    Smolla, Law of Defamation § 9.10[4][d] (1991). The court ruled, as a matter of 

    law, that "[g]iven the . . . many provocative, bombastic statements indisputablymade by Masson and quoted by Malcolm, the additional harm caused by the

    'intellectual gigolo' quote was nominal or nonexistent, rendering the defamation

    claim as to this quote non-actionable." 895 F.2d, at 1541.

    90 This reasoning requires a court to conclude that, in fact, a plaintiff made the

    other quoted statements, cf. Liberty Lobby, Inc. v. Anderson, 241 U.S.App.D.C.

    246, 251, 746 F.2d 1563, 1568 (1984), vacated and remanded on other grounds,

    477 U.S. 242, 106 S.Ct. 2505, 91 L.Ed.2d 202 (1986), and then to undertake afactual inquiry into the reputational damage caused by the remainder of the

     publication. As noted by the dissent in the Court of Appeals, the most

    "provocative, bombastic statements" quoted by Malcolm are those complained

    of by petitioner, and so this would not seem an appropriate application of the

    incremental harm doctrine. 895 F.2d, at 1566.

    91 Furthermore, the Court of Appeals provided no indication whether it considered

    the incremental harm doctrine to be grounded in California law or the First

    Amendment. Here, we reject any suggestion that the incremental harm doctrine

    is compelled as a matter of First Amendment protection for speech. The

    question of incremental harm does not bear upon whether a defendant has

     published a statement with knowledge of falsity or reckless disregard of 

    whether it was false or not. As a question of state law, on the other hand, we are

    given no indication that California accepts this doctrine, though it remains free

    to do so. Of course, state tort law doctrines of injury, causation, and damages

    calculation might allow a defendant to press the argument that the statementsdid not result in any incremental harm to a plaintiff's reputation.

    92 (b) "Sex, Women, Fun." This passage presents a closer question. The "sex,

  • 8/17/2019 Masson v. New Yorker Magazine, Inc., 501 U.S. 496 (1991)

    23/26

    women, fun" quotation offers a very different picture of petitioner's plans for 

    Maresfield Gardens than his remark that "Freud's library alone is priceless."

    See supra, at 503. Petitioner's other tape-recorded remarks did indicate that he

    and another analyst planned to have great parties at the Freud house and, in a

    context that may not even refer to Freud house activities, to "pass women on to

    each other." We cannot conclude as a matter of law that these remarks bear the

    same substantial meaning as the quoted passage's suggestion that petitioner would make the Freud house a place of "sex, women, fun."

    93 (c) " It Sounded Better." We agree with the District Court and the Court of 

    Appeals that any difference between petitioner's tape-recorded statement that he

    "just liked" the name Moussaieff, and the quotation that "it sounded better" is,

    in context, immaterial. Although Malcolm did not include all of petitioner's

    lengthy explanation of his name change, she did convey the gist of that

    explanation: Petitioner took his abandoned family name as his middle name.We agree with the Court of Appeals that the words attributed to petitioner did

    not materially alter the meaning of his statement.

    94 (d) " I Don't Know Why I Put It In." Malcolm quotes petitioner as saying that he

    "tacked on at the last minute" a "totally gratuitous" remark about the "sterility

    of psychoanalysis" in an academic paper, and that he did so for no particular 

    reason. In the tape recordings, petitioner does admit that the remark was

    "possibly [a] gratuitously offensive way to end a paper to a group of analysts," but when asked why he included the remark, he answered "[because] it was true

    . . . I really believe it." Malcolm's version contains material differences from

     petitioner's statement, and it is conceivable that the alteration results in a

    statement that could injure a scholar's reputation.

    95 (e) "Greatest Analyst Who Ever Lived." While petitioner did, on numerous

    occasions, predict that his theories would do irreparable damage to the practice

    of psychoanalysis, and did suggest that no other analyst shared his views, no

    tape-recorded statement appears to contain the substance or the arrogant and

    unprofessional tone apparent in this quotation. A material difference exists

     between the quotation and the tape-recorded statements, and a jury could find

    that the difference exposed petitioner to contempt, ridicule or obloquy.

    96 (f) " He Had The Wrong Man." The quoted version makes it appear as if 

     petitioner rejected a plea to remain in stoic silence and do "the honorable thing."

    The tape-recorded version indicates that petitioner rejected a plea supported by

    far more varied motives: Eissler told petitioner that not only would silence be

    "the honorable thing," but petitioner would "save face," and might be rewarded

    for that silence with eventual reinstatement. Petitioner described himself as

  • 8/17/2019 Masson v. New Yorker Magazine, Inc., 501 U.S. 496 (1991)

    24/26

    C

    willing to undergo a scandal in order to shine the light of publicity upon the

    actions of the Freud Archives, while Malcolm would have petitioner describe

    himself as a person who was "the wrong man" to do "the honorable thing." This

    difference is material, a jury might find it defamatory, and, for the reasons we

    have given, there is evidence to support a finding of deliberate or reckless

    falsification.

    97 Because of the Court of Appeals' disposition with respect to Malcolm, it did not

    have occasion to address petitioner's argument that the District Court erred in

    granting summary judgment to The New Yorker Magazine, Inc., and Alfred A.

    Knopf, Inc. on the basis of their respective relations with Malcolm or the lack 

    of any independent actual malice. These questions are best addressed in the first

    instance on remand.

    98 The judgment of the Court of Appeals is reversed, and the case is remanded for 

    further proceedings consistent with this opinion.

    99 It is so ordered.

    100 Justice WHITE, with whom Justice SCALIA joins, concurring in part and

    dissenting in part.

    101 I join Parts I, II-A, II-D, and III-A, but cannot wholly agree with the remainder 

    of the opinion. My principal disagreement is with the holding, ante, at 517, that

    "a deliberate alteration of the words uttered by a plaintiff does not equate with

    knowledge of falsity . . . unless the alteration results in a material change in the

    meaning conveyed by the statement."

    102  New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U.S. 254, 84 S.Ct. 710, 11 L.Ed.2d 686

    (1964), "malice" means deliberate falsehood or reckless disregard for whether 

    the fact asserted is true or false. Id., at 279-280, 84 S.Ct., at 725-726. As the

    Court recognizes, the use of quotation marks in reporting what a person said

    asserts that the person spoke the words as quoted. As this case comes to us, it is

    to be judged on the basis that in the instances identified by the Court, the

    reporter, Malcolm, wrote that Masson said certain things that she knew Masson

    did not say. By any definition of the term, this was "knowing falsehood":Malcolm asserts that Masson said these very words, knowing that he did not.

    The issue, as the Court recognizes, is whether Masson spoke the words

    attributed to him, not whether the fact, if any, asserted by the attributed words

  • 8/17/2019 Masson v. New Yorker Magazine, Inc., 501 U.S. 496 (1991)

    25/26

    is true or false. In my view, we need to go no further to conclude that the

    defendants in this case were not entitled to summary judgment on the issue of 

    malice with respect to any of the six erroneous quotations.

    103That there was at least an issue for the jury to decide on the question of 

    deliberate or reckless falsehood, does not mean that plaintiffs were necessarily

    entitled to go to trial. If, as a matter of law, reasonable jurors could notconclude that attributing to Masson certain words that he did not say amounted

    to libel under California law, i.e., "expose[d] [Masson] to hatred, contempt,

    ridicule, or obloquy, or which causes him to be shunned or avoided, or which

    has a tendency to injure him in his occupation," Cal.Civ.Code Ann. § 45 (West

    1982), a motion for summary judgment on this ground would be justified.* I

    would suppose, for example that if Malcolm wrote that Masson said that he

    wore contact lenses, when he said nothing about his eyes or his vision, the trial

     judge would grant summary judgment for the defendants and dismiss the case.The same would be true if Masson had said "I was spoiled as a child by my

    Mother," whereas, Malcolm reports that he said "I was spoiled as a child by my

     parents." But if reasonable jurors could conclude that the deliberate

    misquotation was libelous, the case should go to the jury.

    104 This seems to me to be the straightforward, traditional approach to deal with

    this case. Instead, the Court states that deliberate misquotation does not amount

    to New York Times malice unless it results in a material change in the meaningconveyed by the statement. This ignores the fact that under New York Times,

    reporting a known falsehood—here the knowingly false attribution is sufficient

     proof of malice. The falsehood, apparently, must be substantial; the reporter 

    may lie a little, but not too much.

    105 This standard is not only a less manageable one than the traditional approach,

     but it also assigns to the courts issues that are for the jury to decide. For a court

    to ask whether a misquotation substantially alters the meaning of spoken words

    in a defamatory manner is a far different inquiry than whether reasonable jurors

    could find that the misquotation was different enough to be libelous. In the one

    case, the court is measuring the difference from its own point of view; in the

    other it is asking how the jury would or could view the erroneous attribution.

    106 The Court attempts to justify its holding in several ways, none of which is

     persuasive. First, it observes that an interviewer who takes notes of any

    interview will attempt to reconstruct what the speaker said and will often

    knowingly attribute to the subject words that were not used by the speaker.

     Ante, at 514-515. But this is nothing more than an assertion that authors may

    misrepresent because they cannot remember what the speaker actually said.

  • 8/17/2019 Masson v. New Yorker Magazine, Inc., 501 U.S. 496 (1991)

    26/26

    In dealing with the intellectual gigolo passage, the Court of Appeals ruled that

    there was no malice but in the alternative went on to say that as a matter of law

    the erroneous attribution was not actionable defamation. 895 F.2d 1535, 1540-

    1541 (CA9 1989).

    This should be no dilemma for such authors, or they could report their story

    without purporting to quote when they are not sure, thereby leaving the reader 

    to trust or doubt the author rather than believing that the subject actually said

    what he is claimed to have said. Moreover, this basis for the Court's rule has no

    application where there is a tape of the interview and the author is in no way at

    a loss to know what the speaker actually said. Second, the Court speculates that

    even with the benefit of a recording, the author will find it necessary at times toreconstruct, ante, at 515, but again, in those cases why should the author be

    free to put his or her reconstruction in quotation marks, rather than report

    without them? Third, the Court suggests that misquotations that do not

    materially alter the meaning inflict no injury to reputation that is compensable

    as defamation. Ante, at 517. This may be true, but this is a question of 

    defamation or not, and has nothing to do with whether the author deliberately

     put within quotation marks and attributed to the speaker words that the author 

    knew the speaker did not utter.

    107 As I see it, the defendants' motion for summary judgment based on lack of 

    malice should not have been granted on any of the six quotations considered by

    the Court in Part III-B of its opinion. I therefore dissent from the result reached

    with respect to the "It Sounded Better" quotation dealt with in paragraph (c) of 

    Part III-B, but agree with the Court's judgment on the other five misquotations.

    *