kuhn and conceptual change: on the analogy between ... · loughborough university institutional...

45

Upload: dinhhanh

Post on 23-May-2018

220 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Loughborough UniversityInstitutional Repository

Kuhn and conceptualchange: on the analogy

between conceptual changesin science and children

This item was submitted to Loughborough University's Institutional Repositoryby the/an author.

Citation: GREIFFENHAGEN, C. and SHERMAN, W., 2008. Kuhn and con-ceptual change: on the analogy between conceptual changes in science andchildren. Science and Education, 17 (1), pp. 1 - 26

Additional Information:

• This article was published in the journal, Science and Educa-tion [ c© Springer Verlag]. The definitive version is available at:http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s11191-006-9063-5

Metadata Record: https://dspace.lboro.ac.uk/2134/14190

Version: Accepted for publication

Publisher: c© Springer Verlag

Please cite the published version.

This item was submitted to Loughborough’s Institutional Repository (https://dspace.lboro.ac.uk/) by the author and is made available under the

following Creative Commons Licence conditions.

For the full text of this licence, please go to: http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/2.5/

Page 1 of 43

Greiffenhagen, C. and W. Sherman (2008). Kuhn and conceptual change: on the analogy between conceptual changes in science and children. Science & Education 17 (1), 1-26.

Kuhn and Conceptual Change:

On the Analogy between Conceptual Changes in

Science and Children

Christian Greiffenhagen and Wendy Sherman

Version: October 27, 2006

Abstract. This article argues that the analogy between conceptual changes in the history

of science and conceptual changes in the development of young children is problematic.

We show that the notions of ‘conceptual change’ in Kuhn and Piaget’s projects, the two

thinkers whose work is most commonly drawn upon to support this analogy, are not

compatible in the sense usually claimed. We contend that Kuhn’s work pertains not so

much to the psychology of individual scientists, but to the way philosophers and

historians should describe developments in communities of scientists. Furthermore, we

argue that the analogy is based on a misunderstanding of the nature of science and the

relation between science and common sense. The distinctiveness of the two notions of

conceptual change has implications for science education research, since it raises serious

questions about the relevance of Kuhn’s remarks for the study of pedagogical issues.

Keywords. Conceptual change; misconceptions; paradigm; Kuhn; Piaget; Ryle

Page 2 of 43

Greiffenhagen, C. and W. Sherman (2008). Kuhn and conceptual change: on the analogy between conceptual changes in science and children. Science & Education 17 (1), 1-26.

1 Introduction

Thomas Kuhn’s work in the history and philosophy of science has played a highly

influential role in the programme of Conceptual Change in science education (henceforth

CC)1. Adapting Kuhn for their own purposes, proponents of CC have argued that the

conceptual changes that young children undergo in school science classrooms, when they

are asked to make the move from an intuitive way of understanding natural phenomena to

a scientific one, resembles conceptual changes in the history of science2. On this reading,

historical studies of paradigm changes in science can help us understand the conceptual

problems faced by pupils in school science. For example, Hewson (1981, p.383) argues:

Learning science is complex – a student has at different times to acquire new information, reorganize existing knowledge and even discard cherished ideas. In addressing this issue, the analogy between individual learning and conceptual change in scientific disciplines has been fruitful in providing aspects of a suitable framework for analysing science learning.

Driver (1983, pp.9-10) asks:

[…] children sometimes need to undergo paradigm shifts in their thinking. Max Planck suggested that new theories do not convert people, it is just that old men die. If scientists have this difficulty in reformulating their conceptions of the world, is it a wonder that children sometimes have a struggle to do so?

Vosniadou & Brewer (1987, pp.54-55) express the analogy in the following way:

According to Kuhn, the exercise of ‘normal science’ involves the articulation of an existing paradigm that may result in theory change. Only when these attempts at articulation fail repeatedly does the motivation for a true paradigm shift arise. Paradigm shifts happen in an effort to resolve anomalies that exist in the relation of existing theory to observations (Kuhn [1996], p.97). The development of knowledge in the child can be seen in similar terms, as a process of enriching and elaborating existing ‘theories’ that can give rise to theory change, in other words to weak restructurings. Occasionally, when the child is faced with major anomalies that existing conceptual structures cannot account for, a new paradigm is required, giving rise to radical restructurings.

As part of research in science education, CC investigates the ways in which what pupils

already know impacts on what they are supposed to learn in school science. One

Page 3 of 43

Greiffenhagen, C. and W. Sherman (2008). Kuhn and conceptual change: on the analogy between conceptual changes in science and children. Science & Education 17 (1), 1-26.

fundamental assumption of CC is the view that pupils’ prior knowledge – alternatively

called ‘naïve knowledge’ (Vosniadou 1989), ‘naïve beliefs’ (McCloskey 1983; Reiner et

al. 1988), ‘informal science’ (Driver et al. 1994), or ‘children’s science’ (Osborne 1980;

Gilbert et al. 1982; D. Kuhn 1989) – is ‘in conflict’ or ‘in competition’ with what they

are supposed to learn in school science. The problem for science education then seems to

be one of inducing conceptual change in pupils, from naïve/informal to scientific

knowledge3. Given this picture, the attraction of Kuhn’s work for practitioners in CC is

immediately apparent: conceptual changes that supposedly occur in school science

classrooms are seen as analogous to paradigm changes in the history of science

documented by Kuhn (e.g., the change from Ptolemaic to Copernican astronomy). The

perhaps most famous formulation of the analogy is by Posner et al. (1982, p.212):

Contemporary views in philosophy of science suggest that there are two distinguishable phases of conceptual change in science. Usually scientific work is done against the background of central commitments which organize research. These central commitments define problems, indicate strategies for dealing with them, and specific criteria for what counts as solutions. Thomas Kuhn [1996] calls these central commitments ‘paradigms’ and paradigm-dominated research ‘normal science’. […] The second phase of conceptual change occurs when these central commitments require modification. Here the scientist is faced with a challenge to his basic assumptions. If inquiry is to proceed, the scientist must acquire new concepts and a new way of seeing the world. Kuhn terms this kind of conceptual change a ‘scientific revolution’. […]

We believe there are analogous patterns of conceptual change in learning. Sometimes students use existing concepts to deal with new phenomena. This variant of the first phase of conceptual change we call assimilation. Often, however, the students’ current concepts are inadequate to allow him to grasp some new phenomenon successfully. The student must replace or reorganize his central concepts. This more radical form of conceptual change we call accommodation.

In this article we argue that the analogy between conceptual change in science and

conceptual change in children is misleading (see also Levine 2000). We contend that

Page 4 of 43

Greiffenhagen, C. and W. Sherman (2008). Kuhn and conceptual change: on the analogy between conceptual changes in science and children. Science & Education 17 (1), 1-26.

proponents of CC misread Kuhn and do so as the result of a mistaken view about the

nature of school science and the relationship between science and common sense. We do

not disagree with Kuhn’s analysis of conceptual change in the history of science, but

wonder whether that analysis can be fruitfully applied to what happens in school

classrooms.

In our view the analogy suggests that pupils are akin to scientists (engaged in

building explanations of the natural world) and that what pupils know, their common-

sense knowledge of the natural world, has the same ‘purpose’ or ‘aim’ as a scientific

theory (since a paradigm change has to occur between comparable entities). The analogy

is thus based on the assumption that science and common sense are both theoretical

schemes and can therefore be, in some way or other, in competition. If that were the case,

then it would seem sensible to argue that pupils should adopt scientific instead of

ordinary ways of speaking (cf., Maxwell & Feigl 1961). However, we wonder whether

science and common sense really are in conflict in the sense intimated by CC researchers.

In our view, what pupils learn in school does not stand in conflict with what they already

know, but is better characterised as a (selective) specialisation of their prior knowledge4.

In order to demonstrate that CC’s picture of conceptual change is

‘incommensurable’ with Kuhn’s picture of conceptual change we give a brief review of

Kuhn’s main arguments. Since proponents of CC have noted that Kuhn mentions the

developmental psychologist Piaget, we then discuss the possible contribution of Piaget’s

writings to Kuhn’s project (since this would seemingly licence the analogy between

developments in the psychology of children and developments in the history of science).

Page 5 of 43

Greiffenhagen, C. and W. Sherman (2008). Kuhn and conceptual change: on the analogy between conceptual changes in science and children. Science & Education 17 (1), 1-26.

We will then use this discussion of Kuhn to review the relationship between common

sense and school science.

2 The View of Kuhn in Science Education

Kuhn’s writings, especially his The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (1996), are widely

known in science education. Although Loving & Cobern (2000) found that the majority

of citations to Kuhn made in The Journal of Research in Science Teaching and Science

Education between 1985 and 2000 were overwhelmingly ‘supportive of Kuhnian

positions’ (p.201), more recently, some strongly critical voices have emerged (Matthews

2003; special issue of Science & Education 2000). In what follows, we want to argue for

an understanding of Kuhn’s work that does not fit neatly into either side of the ‘for’ or

‘against’ debate currently being played out in science education.

In our view, Kuhn is grappling with the question, ‘Do we have a good picture of

science?’. Kuhn wants to examine standard textbook presentations in which science is

portrayed as continuously cumulative and straightforwardly progressive. These textbook

presentations, says Kuhn, give a distorted reading of the history of a science, looking at

its past achievements only in relation to its present concerns. In contrast, Kuhn

recommends a more ‘anthropological’ perspective, i.e., to approach earlier scientific

theories as one would approach an alien culture, where what might seem strange to ‘us’

might make sense to ‘them’.

In Structure, Kuhn argues that there is progress in science, in the sense that the

mature natural sciences have developed out of a pre-paradigm stage, and into the much

more complex and sophisticated condition they are now in. However, he objects to the

view that this evolution is progress towards anything. Science evolves ‘from primitive

Page 6 of 43

Greiffenhagen, C. and W. Sherman (2008). Kuhn and conceptual change: on the analogy between conceptual changes in science and children. Science & Education 17 (1), 1-26.

beginnings but toward no goal’ (p.172). The reason for saying that a science does not

evolve toward a goal is that Kuhn claims that there is no independent standard according

to which scientists can judge whether one theory (e.g., Ptolemaic) is better than another

(e.g., Copernican). In other words, Kuhn argues that scientific theories cannot be

compared wholesale. Of course, one can compare theories with respect to specific

questions (e.g., whether they give a more satisfying explanation for a certain anomaly),

and this may influence the choice of theory. However, this does not mean that one theory

is ‘better’ in every aspect. In our view, Kuhn aims to steer a careful path between both the

‘realist’ extreme (that there is a reality that can be appealed to for judging which theory is

better) and the ‘relativist’ extreme (that nothing constrains scientific theories).

3 Kuhn’s View of Conceptual Change in Science

We want to emphasise three issues in Kuhn’s argument that have a bearing on the

possibility of applying Kuhn’s ideas to what happens in school science. These are:

(1) the target of Kuhn’s writings, which is the picture or image of science;

(2) the nature of a paradigm or conceptual scheme, which could be characterised as a

shared set of beliefs providing scientists with a programme of work;

(3) the scope or scale of Kuhn’s notion of conceptual change, which is change at the

level of science (as a social institution) rather than scientists (as individuals).

Firstly, Kuhn is concerned with how outsiders and insiders understand what science ‘is’,

i.e., with the image or picture of science. He starts the introduction to Structure with the

following observation:

History, if viewed as a repository for more than anecdote or chronology, could produce a decisive transformation in the image of science by which we are now possessed. That image has previously been drawn, even by scientists

Page 7 of 43

Greiffenhagen, C. and W. Sherman (2008). Kuhn and conceptual change: on the analogy between conceptual changes in science and children. Science & Education 17 (1), 1-26.

themselves, mainly from the study of finished scientific achievements as these are recorded in the classics and, more recently, in the textbooks from which each new scientific generation learns to practice its trade. Inevitably, however, the aim of such books is persuasive and pedagogic; a concept of science drawn from them is no more likely to fit the enterprise that produced them than an image of a national culture drawn from a tourist brochure or a language text. This essay attempts to show that we have been misled by them in fundamental ways. Its aim is a sketch of the quite different concept of science that can emerge from the historical record of the research activity itself. (Kuhn 1996, p.1)

Kuhn is drawing attention to the fact that most presentations of science look at the past

only from the point of view of its contribution to present theories, methods, and

problems. Textbooks, for Kuhn, are very successful pedagogic exercises, but they are a

poor source for a (historical-philosophical) image of science, since they give a misleading

picture of how the enterprise of science works and changes. Kuhn’s Structure is an

attempt to come up with an alternative picture.

In order to provide that alternative, Kuhn adopts an ‘anthropological’ perspective

and treats earlier scientific communities as ‘alien’ cultures, which have to be understood

in their own terms and which may initially seem strange to us:

A historian reading an out-of-date scientific text characteristically encounters passages that make no sense. That is an experience I have had repeatedly whether my subject was an Aristotle, a Newton, a Volta, a Bohr, or a Planck. (Kuhn 1989a, p.9)

Kuhn’s concept of ‘incommensurability’ is an attempt to draw attention to the fact that

while earlier scientific theories may seem strange to us, this does not mean that they are

less ‘rational’ or ‘scientific’ than our current theories, and may have made perfect sense

to the scientists of the time. In other words, Kuhn objects to the tendency to portray

aspects of earlier scientific theories that are in conflict with our current theories as

‘mistakes’ or ‘confusions’ without first making sure that, in the context in which those

ideas were coined, they would not make very good sense:

Page 8 of 43

Greiffenhagen, C. and W. Sherman (2008). Kuhn and conceptual change: on the analogy between conceptual changes in science and children. Science & Education 17 (1), 1-26.

Incommensurability is a notion that for me emerged from attempts to understand apparently nonsensical passages encountered in old scientific texts. Ordinarily they had been taken as evidence of the author’s confused or mistaken beliefs. My experiences led me to suggest, instead, that those passages were being misread: the appearance of nonsense could be removed by recovering older meanings for some of the terms involved, meanings different from those subsequently current. (Kuhn 1990, p.4)

Kuhn does not provide textbook introductions to, for example, Ptolemaic astronomy, but

accounts of how to look at Ptolemaic astronomy. Kuhn thus argues against a ‘Whig

history’ of science (cf., Butterfield 1931), which looks at scientific developments in the

past solely in terms of the present and treats earlier theories as underdeveloped precursors

to current ones. Instead, Kuhn wants to understand earlier scientific theories from the

point of view of the scientists of the time. The effect of this anthropological approach is

to present an alternative picture of science from that communicated through the textbook

tradition.

Secondly, paradigms for Kuhn constitute the working assumptions of scientists.

That is to say, Kuhn characterises normal science as puzzle solving, with paradigms the

source of the puzzles scientists seek to solve. For Kuhn, a paradigm is a programme of

work and not just a cognitive ontological worldview. Consequently, conceptual change

for Kuhn is not so much a change in ‘looking’ but in ‘doing’ (cf., Sharrock & Read 2002,

p.162). A paradigm gives scientists things to do (puzzles to solve, measurements to

make). Although what scientists ‘believe’ may be important, what they actually do as

their day-to-day work is even more so. If we may put it this way: Kuhn’s focus is not just

what is in scientists’ ‘heads’, but what is in their ‘hands’.

Thirdly, Kuhn’s remarks about ‘normal science’ and ‘scientific revolutions’ in

Structure are meant to apply at the level of science as a social institution, and not at the

level of the psychology of individual scientists:

Page 9 of 43

Greiffenhagen, C. and W. Sherman (2008). Kuhn and conceptual change: on the analogy between conceptual changes in science and children. Science & Education 17 (1), 1-26.

Both normal science and revolutions are, however, community-based activities. (Kuhn 1996, p.179)

Again, many of my generalizations are about the sociology or social psychology of scientists. (Kuhn 1996, p.8)

That is to say, a paradigm or conceptual scheme is the property of the scientific group:

[…] if I am talking at all about intuitions, they are not individual. Rather they are the tested and shared possessions of the members of a successful group, and the novice acquires them through training as a part of his preparation for group-membership. (Kuhn 1996, p.191)

As Sharrock & Read (2002, p.115) put it:

The difference between revolutionary and normal science is a difference in the state of science rather than in the inclinations of individuals.

Thus, a scientific revolution for Kuhn occurs when the whole community of scientists

changes direction. For example, according to Kuhn (1957), Copernicus was

predominantly working within the old Ptolemaic paradigm and only proposed a minor

alteration to it. In a certain sense, Copernicus did not himself realise what he was

proposing, since it was only his successors that saw the radical implications in his work

(a similar thing could be said with respect to Planck who did not see what Einstein later

‘found’ in Planck’s work). As Kuhn (1957, p.183) puts it:

The work of a single individual may play a preeminent role in such a conceptual revolution, but if it does, it achieves preeminence either because like the De Revolutionibus, it initiates revolution by a small innovation which presents science with new problems, or because, like Newton’s Principia, it terminates revolution by integrating concepts derived from many sources. The extent of the innovation that any individual can produce is necessarily limited, for each individual must employ in his research the tools that he acquires from a traditional education, and he cannot in his own lifetime replace them all.

That is to say, although in retrospect (from the perspective of the historian) it may be

possible to characterize what Copernicus did as ‘revolutionary’, this was not how

Copernicus himself saw his work. Copernicus only proposed a minor alteration (a

moving earth) within the old system (keeping the sun as revolving around the earth). For

Page 10 of 43

Greiffenhagen, C. and W. Sherman (2008). Kuhn and conceptual change: on the analogy between conceptual changes in science and children. Science & Education 17 (1), 1-26.

Copernicus, the proposed modification of the Ptolemaic system constituted no radical

change. As Kuhn (1977 [1959], p.227) puts it:

Almost none of the research undertaken by even the greatest scientists is designed to be revolutionary, and very little of it has any such effect. On the contrary, normal research, even the best of it, is a highly convergent activity based firmly upon a settled consensus acquired from scientific education and reinforced by subsequent life in the profession. Typically, to be sure, this convergent or consensus-bound research ultimately results in revolution.

Kuhn argues against the picture of the individual ‘revolutionary’ scientist. Put very

succinctly: the Copernican revolution in science was not a scientific revolution ‘in’

Copernicus. The Copernican revolution described by Kuhn, in contrast, occurred over the

course of a century and concerned the status of a whole community of scientists. Kuhn

emphasises that although the historian can look at the history of science and identify

conceptual changes, these rarely (if ever) occur in individuals:

How, then, are scientists brought to make this transposition? Part of the answer is that they are very often not. Copernicanism made few converts for almost a century after Copernicus’ death. (Kuhn 1996, p.15)

The conceptual changes that are identified by Kuhn occurred over time and were brought

about by individuals who themselves did not change. Scientific revolutions are nobody’s

intent. Kuhn’s conceptual change is thus best understood as cultural-collective change at

the level of the community of scientists – not as cognitive-psychological change at the

level of individual scientists.

Kuhn does talk about individuals, but in the context of undergraduate and

graduate education, that is, in the context of the socialisation of novices into the scientific

community. In this situation Kuhn does not talk of ‘revolutions’, ‘conceptual changes’,

or ‘world changes’, since the paradigm that students are socialised in is the first paradigm

that they encounter. As he puts it in the Postscript to Structure:

Page 11 of 43

Greiffenhagen, C. and W. Sherman (2008). Kuhn and conceptual change: on the analogy between conceptual changes in science and children. Science & Education 17 (1), 1-26.

A scientific community consists, on this view, of the practitioners of a scientific speciality. To an extent unparalleled in most other fields, they have undergone similar educations and professional initiations; in the process they have absorbed the same technical literature and drawn many of the same lessons from it. (Kuhn 1996, p.177)

In his characterisation of the socialisation process, Kuhn does not talk of ‘conceptual

change’, but instead outlines how successful textbook presentations of science are for

socialising novice scientists. Science education, according to Kuhn, is typically

authoritarian and dogmatic (cf. Kuhn 1977 [1959]), a matter of getting novices ‘up to

speed’ in the current ways of the discipline. Kuhn emphasises that this is not necessarily a

bad thing, since it is this successful induction into an established tradition that lays the

groundwork for the possibility of later revolutions.

In our view, these three issues raise serious questions with respect to the

applicability of Kuhn’s ideas to what happens in school science.

Firstly, it would seem that the impact of Kuhn should be in school philosophy or

history (where pupils are taught how to look at, e.g., science) rather than school science

(where pupils are taught results and methods of certain scientific theories). It seems to us

that the main task of school science is not to provide philosophical views about science,

but to give an introduction to a particular scientific paradigm by familiarising students

with basic examples of scientific ‘good practice’, albeit perhaps on a simplified base

using outdated procedures. Classroom exercises are only the beginning of the long

educational journey that a student must make if he or she wants to become a professional

scientist. In other words, school science resembles the textbook presentations that Kuhn

thought were successful as pedagogic devices, but not adequate as philosophical accounts

about science.

Page 12 of 43

Greiffenhagen, C. and W. Sherman (2008). Kuhn and conceptual change: on the analogy between conceptual changes in science and children. Science & Education 17 (1), 1-26.

Secondly, Kuhn emphasises that scientists are engaged in professional work, and

this is certainly not the same kind of work in which school pupils take part. In other

words, school children do not form a community that shares similar goals and objectives

that they are trying to accomplish through science (this issue will be taken up below).

Thirdly, the changes that Kuhn talks about occur at the level of the scientific

community. However, science education wants to induce conceptual change in individual

pupils.

In sum, it does not seem that Kuhn’s insights could straightforwardly be applied

to science education. That said, perhaps his ideas could be merged with another

influential thinker, Jean Piaget, who is concerned with individual conceptual change.

Furthermore, Kuhn himself made occasional references to Piaget. It is thus this possible

influence of Piaget on Kuhn that we review next.

4 What did Kuhn learn from Piaget?

Although Piaget’s ‘genetic epistemology’ is as much an engagement with the philosophy

and history of science as it is with the psychological development of children, it is

certainly the case that Piaget’s impact was greatest in psychology and education (cf.,

Boden 1979, p.11). Here we do not wish to enter into debates about Piaget’s own theory

of conceptual change. Instead, we only want to discuss the similarities and differences

between the projects of Kuhn and Piaget – and the possible impact that Piaget’s writings

had on Kuhn.

As already pointed out, Kuhn’s focus is the history of science, while Piaget is

famous for his psychological experiments with children. So it is perhaps surprising that

Kuhn writes in the preface to Structure:

Page 13 of 43

Greiffenhagen, C. and W. Sherman (2008). Kuhn and conceptual change: on the analogy between conceptual changes in science and children. Science & Education 17 (1), 1-26.

A footnote encountered by chance led me to the experiments by which Jean Piaget has illuminated both the various worlds of the growing child and the process of transition from one to the next. (1996, p.viii)

So what was the impact of Piaget on Kuhn? In our view, Kuhn is likely to have been

impressed by Piaget’s attempt to understand people from an ‘alien tribe’ from their point

of view. In other words, Kuhn may well have admired Piaget’s patient exploration of

somebody else’s perspective. Such an ‘anthropological’ approach was absent from child

psychology before Piaget – and from the history of science before Kuhn. The ingenuity

of both Piaget and Kuhn lies in abandoning the a priori starting point of looking down at

young children or earlier scientists and dismissing their views as ‘faulty’,

‘underdeveloped’, or ‘primitive’, and instead to ask: ‘From their perspective, does what

they do/believe make sense?’ As Boden (1979, p.30) writes of Piaget:

For many people, babies are boring. And the more such people are interested in abstract intelligence or scientific knowledge, the more boring babies may appear to be. They cannot do much, it seems, and what they can do apparently bears little relation to the real stuff of human knowledge. Like kittens, they may be amusing; but they have little psychological and less epistemological significance.

Part of Piaget’s achievement is to have shown how fundamentally mistaken this attitude is.

Just as Piaget took babies and young children seriously, so Kuhn took earlier scientific

theories seriously. In that sense, Piaget could be seen as giving Kuhn a vocabulary to

describe methodological mistakes in the history and philosophy of science.

There is an interesting parallel with cultural anthropology here. While early

anthropologists treated non-Western cultures as ‘primitive’, proposing that the minds (or

even brains) of the people of those societies were in some sense less developed than their

Western counterparts, Evans-Pritchard (1937) set out to reject that assumption. For

Evans-Pritchard the Azande were not less intelligent than people in the West. Like Piaget

Page 14 of 43

Greiffenhagen, C. and W. Sherman (2008). Kuhn and conceptual change: on the analogy between conceptual changes in science and children. Science & Education 17 (1), 1-26.

and Kuhn, Evans-Pritchard tried to look at the Azande in their own terms. However,

Evans-Pritchard was not able to take this step to its conclusion, since for him (Western)

science had a special (objective) status. For Evans-Pritchard it was obvious that science

produces true and objective knowledge, which then created the following problem: Why

do the Azande, who are as intelligent as Westerners, not ‘see’ that Western science is true

while their own beliefs (e.g., concerning witchcraft and oracles) are obviously false?

This question was based in Evans-Pritchard’s picture of science. Science, for

Evans-Pritchard, was not one practice among many but the practice underlying all others.

Put differently, for Evans-Pritchard the aim of every practice is to produce knowledge –

knowledge of the kind that Western science produces that is. However, as Winch (1964)

points out, that is to seriously mischaracterise Azande practices. Consulting an oracle is

not akin to making a scientific prediction – neither is rain dancing. So if our goal is to

understand what they are doing, then there simply may be no conflict between ‘their’ and

‘our’ practices. Looking at religious practices from the perspective of science is a bit like

scoring a play of soccer according to the rules of tennis (cf., Wittgenstein 1979).

Evans-Pritchard’s ‘problem’ is a result of his attempt to compare the practices of

science and witchcraft. When examining his work, we should ask whether these two are

enough alike to be compared, and what standard we could invoke to make the

comparison. ? In effect, Evans-Pritchard stipulates the standard ‘truth’ (or ‘corresponding

with reality’) as the means for comparing both sets of practices. However, it seems less

than adequate to characterise the practice of witchcraft as being concerned with

producing truth. As Winch (1964, p.315) put it:

Zande notions of witchcraft do not constitute a theoretical system in terms of which Azande try to gain a quasi-scientific understanding of the world. This in its turn suggests that it is the European, obsessed with pressing Zande thought

Page 15 of 43

Greiffenhagen, C. and W. Sherman (2008). Kuhn and conceptual change: on the analogy between conceptual changes in science and children. Science & Education 17 (1), 1-26.

where it would not naturally go – to a contradiction – who is guilty of misunderstanding, not the Zande. The European is in fact committing a category-mistake.

We are trying to emphasize that although we admire Evans-Pritchard’s starting point of

not treating the Azande as primitive as compared to Western people, we object to his

scientism, i.e., the view that all practices are attempts to gain (objective) knowledge of

the world. In our view, Evans-Pritchard not only mischaracterises what the Azande are

doing, but also what we are doing, since many of our practices do not aim to produce or

propose (scientific) theories of the world: playing games (e.g., football or hopscotch),

cooking, reading and writing novels, and making friends are not in the same ‘business’ as

science.

Returning now to our discussion about the impact of Piaget on Kuhn, let us repeat

that Kuhn seems to have been inspired by Piaget’s attempt to understand children’s views

of the natural world from their perspective – rather than looking at children from the

perspective of adults or science. Furthermore, Kuhn by and large avoided Evans-

Pritchard’s mistake of mischaracterising other practices as ‘versions’ of science. This was

partly a result of Kuhn’s focus, which was explicitly with the history of science itself. It

is only very occasionally that Kuhn made remarks about issues outside the history of

science (e.g., 1957, end of Chapter 3; 1977 [1964]; 1977 [1971]). It seems to us that it is

these occasional remarks that have been (unfortunately) picked up by the proponents of

CC.

5 Differences between Kuhn and Piaget

Despite our characterization of Piaget’s possible influence on Kuhn, purported

similarities in methodological approach do not seem to be the reason that CC links the

Page 16 of 43

Greiffenhagen, C. and W. Sherman (2008). Kuhn and conceptual change: on the analogy between conceptual changes in science and children. Science & Education 17 (1), 1-26.

two. Instead, for many researchers within CC, the link is appropriate because there is a

striking similarity between Kuhn’s and Piaget’s notions of conceptual change. For

example:

In their search for a theoretical framework to conceptualize the learning of science some science educators turned to the philosophy and history of science as a major source of hypotheses concerning how concepts change (see Posner et al. 1982). They drew an analogy between Piaget’s concepts of assimilation and accommodation and the concepts of ‘normal science’ and ‘scientific revolution’ offered by philosophers’ [sic] of science such as Kuhn [1996] to explain theory change in the history of science. They derived from this analogy an instructional theory to promote ‘accommodation’ in students’ learning of science. (Vosniadou & Ioannides 1998, pp.1213-1214)

This analogy seems to have been licensed by Kuhn himself, who writes:

Why should a historian of science be invited to address an audience of child psychologists on the development of causal notions in physics? A first answer is well known to all who are acquainted with the researches of Jean Piaget. His perceptive investigations of such subjects as the child’s conception of space, of time, of motion, or of the world itself have repeatedly disclosed striking parallels to the conceptions held by adult scientists of an earlier age. (Kuhn 1977 [1971], p.21)

Obviously, we cannot deny that Kuhn himself seems to make an analogy between

conceptual changes in children and conceptual changes in science. However, we wish to

argue that although Kuhn may have been inspired by this analogy, his subsequent history

of science does not hinge on his views about the nature of children’s conceptions of the

world. Thus we agree with Cawthron & Rowell (1978, p.46) who argue that ‘Kuhn

appear[s] to ignore Piaget altogether, at least in [his] main discussion’.

As already pointed out, Kuhn makes only very occasional reference to children’s

conceptions of space, time, or motion and his philosophical-historical project can be seen

as entirely independent from such remarks. Kuhn’s aim was to investigate the scientific

theories of Aristotle, Copernicus, or Planck – not the views of an African tribe or of

young children. In our view, CC is therefore mistaken to assimilate Kuhn with Piaget,

Page 17 of 43

Greiffenhagen, C. and W. Sherman (2008). Kuhn and conceptual change: on the analogy between conceptual changes in science and children. Science & Education 17 (1), 1-26.

since there are fundamental differences between them. We will concentrate on two:

firstly, the nature of their projects, and, secondly, their picture of science.

Firstly, it was certainly Piaget’s goal to use a psychological study of the

development of children’s thought as a substitute or way into an understanding of the

genesis of Western science. For example, he writes:

[…] it may very well be that the psychological laws arrived at by means of our restricted method can be extended into epistemological laws arrived at by the analysis of the history of the sciences: the elimination of realism, of substantialism, of dynamism, the growth of relativism, etc., all these are evolutionary laws which appear to be common both to the development of the child and to that of scientific thought. (Piaget 1930, p.240)

According to the proponents of CC, Kuhn seems to accept Piaget’s parallel. As Matthews

(2000, p.7) writes in his editorial to the special issue on Kuhn:

Kuhn popularized Piaget’s ‘cognitive ontogeny recapitulates scientific phylogeny’ thesis among historians and philosophers of science, saying: ‘Part of what I know about how to ask questions of dead scientists has been learned by examining Piaget’s interrogations of living children’ (Kuhn 1977 [1971], p.21). This recapitulation thesis underlies Piaget’s Genetic Epistemology programme […], as Piaget says: ‘The fundamental hypothesis of genetic epistemology is that there is a parallelism between the progress made in the local and rational organization of knowledge and the corresponding formative psychological processes’ (Piaget 1970, p.13).

However, as we have pointed out in our exposition of Kuhn, Kuhn makes it very clear

that his remarks in Structure about conceptual change are made at an abstract level and

pertain to the community of scientists (or the institution of science) rather than individual

scientists. When Kuhn speaks of ‘psychology’, he refers to social psychology:

My recourse has been exclusively to social psychology (I prefer ‘sociology’), a field quite different from individual psychology reiterated n times. Correspondingly, my unit for purposes of explanation is the normal (i.e., non-pathological) scientific group, account being taken of the fact that its members differ but not of what makes any given individual unique. (Kuhn 1970b, p.240)

Page 18 of 43

Greiffenhagen, C. and W. Sherman (2008). Kuhn and conceptual change: on the analogy between conceptual changes in science and children. Science & Education 17 (1), 1-26.

That is to say, we think that Kuhn would object to CC’s ‘psychologising’ or

‘individualising’ of his history of science. In Structure, Kuhn is not so much concerned

with the psychology of individuals, but with the views and activities of groups. Kuhn is

comparing different historical ‘cultures’ (and thus would seem closer to cultural

anthropology than to child development). As Cawthron & Rowell (1978, p.47) put it:

While Piaget looks at the cognitive development of the human child and defines various developmental levels or stages, Kuhn looks at the cognitive development of a particular social group or epiorganism, the scientific community, and defines various paradigms or disciplinary matrices as he later calls them.

Kuhn’s notion of conceptual change is a picture of changes in the culture of science

rather than changes in individual scientists. This is often overlooked in the CC literature.

For example, Posner et al. (1982), in the quotation given at the beginning of our paper,

portray Kuhn’s picture of science in terms of ‘the scientist’, thereby applying conceptual

change to the individual rather than the group. However, it is not so much that ‘the

scientist must acquire new concepts’ (Posner et al. 1982, p.211), but more that science as

a whole that has to do so. It is this mischaracterisation of Kuhn that allows the analogy

between Kuhn and Piaget, i.e., between ‘earlier scientists’ and ‘young children’. For

example, when Posner et al. (1982, p.224) write:

If taken seriously by students, anomalies provide the sort of cognitive conflict (like a Kuhnian state of ‘crisis’) that prepares the student’s conceptual ecology for an accommodation.

They overlook that Kuhn’s ‘crises’ are at the level of science (as an institution), while

they talk at the level of the pupil (as an individual). A similar conflation is committed by

Clement (1982, p.70), who argues that

it should be remembered that historically, pre-Newtonian concepts of mechanics had a strong appeal, and scientists were at least as resistant to change as students are.

Page 19 of 43

Greiffenhagen, C. and W. Sherman (2008). Kuhn and conceptual change: on the analogy between conceptual changes in science and children. Science & Education 17 (1), 1-26.

In these discussions it is important to bear in mind the difference between the

incommensurability between different conceptual schemes (e.g., Ptolemaic and

Copernican astronomy or Newtonian and Einsteinian mechanics), and the psychological

difficulty of changing to a new conceptual scheme.

CC’s psychologistic or individualistic reading of Kuhn may have its origin in the

Popperian critique of Kuhn (cf., Lakatos & Musgrave 1970). Popper’s critique of Kuhn

amounts to reading Kuhn’s notion of ‘normal science’ as a prescription for the individual

scientist.

In my view the ‘normal’ scientist, as Kuhn describes him, is a person one ought to be sorry for. (Popper 1970, p.52)

However, Kuhn emphasises that he was not talking about normal scientists, but about

normal science:

When he rejects ‘the psychology of knowledge’, Sir Karl’s explicit concern is only to deny the methodological relevance to the individual’s source of inspiration or of an individual’s sense of certainty. With that much I cannot disagree. It is, however, a long step from the rejection of the psychological idiosyncrasies of an individual to the rejection of the common elements induced by nurture and training in the psychological make-up of the licensed membership of a scientific group. (Kuhn 1970a, p.22; emphasis in original)

In sum, the famous notions of ‘normal science’, ‘paradigm’, or ‘changes in world view’

are used by Kuhn in Structure to talk about historical developments in the community of

scientists.

Later Kuhn did make occasional reference to changes in individual scientists, but

most typically to contrast the perspective of the scientist with that of the historian. For

example:

In recent years I have increasingly recognized that my conception of the process by which scientists move forward has been too closely modelled on my experience with the process by which historians move into the past. For the historian, the period of wrestling with nonsense passages in out-of-date texts is ordinarily marked by episodes in which the sudden recovery of a long-

Page 20 of 43

Greiffenhagen, C. and W. Sherman (2008). Kuhn and conceptual change: on the analogy between conceptual changes in science and children. Science & Education 17 (1), 1-26.

forgotten way to use some still-familiar terms brings new understandings and coherence. In the sciences, similar ‘aha-experiences’ mark the periods of frustration and puzzlement that ordinary precede fundamental innovation and that often precede the understanding of innovation as well. […]

The transfer of terms like ‘gestalt switch’ from individuals to groups is, however, clearly metaphorical, and in this case the metaphor proves damaging. […] As the conceptual vocabulary of a community changes, its members may undergo gestalt switches, but only some of them do and not all at the same time. Of those who do not, some cease to be members of the community; others acquire the new vocabulary in less dramatic ways. (Kuhn 1989b, pp.49-50)

Kuhn here draws attention to the difference of perspective of the historian and the

scientist. He argues that changes in paradigm occur over time, and not all scientists

change at the same time. Note also that Kuhn’s remark about changes in individuals

apply to changes from one paradigm to another paradigm (e.g., Ptolemaic to Copernican),

not to the socialisation of novice scientists into their ‘first’ paradigm (cf., our remarks

above).

The second major difference between Kuhn and Piaget concerns their respective

picture of science. On closer inspection, Piaget’s picture of science seems to be the

opposite of that of Kuhn (and this tension is carried into CC). In other words, Piaget

subscribes to a picture of science as progress towards objective truth (cf., Rotman 1977,

p.23) that Kuhn explicitly objected to (cf., Kuhn 1996, pp.170-171). Piaget also has an

ahistorical view of science, since current scientific theories can provide a united

description of the accumulated theories of science. For example, Piaget’s account of

mathematics relies heavily on the foundational-philosophical writings of the Bourbaki

School, which has a ‘Whig history’ view of mathematics in that it treats earlier

development (e.g., among Greek mathematicians) in terms of current mathematics, in

Page 21 of 43

Greiffenhagen, C. and W. Sherman (2008). Kuhn and conceptual change: on the analogy between conceptual changes in science and children. Science & Education 17 (1), 1-26.

particular set theory (cf., Rotman 1977, pp.133-134). Thus while Kuhn argued against

Whig history, Piaget seems to have been a proponent of it:

If we step back from Piaget’s treatment of Greek mathematics and look again at his general approach to history we can discern an overall pattern. Behind all theories of history like Piaget’s which claim to reveal underlying laws there is a large and dubious assumption. This is that the past is interesting only to the extent that it can be seen to contribute to the present; that historical significance is confined to those events which were in some sense successful and led to the future. From this it is a small step to believing that the past exhibits a progressive movement towards the present, and that what did in fact happen had, in principle, to happen. Under the influence of Hegel’s idea of dialectical growth and over-rigid nineteenth-century conceptions of scientific law, this view (in Anglo-Saxon terms Whig history) emerges in the conception of history as the study of necessary and inevitable progress. (Rotman 1977, pp.139-140)

In short: Piaget’s view of the history of science is the opposite of that of Kuhn.

This difference is also reflected in Piaget’s and Kuhn’s notion of ‘conceptual

schemes’. For Piaget, subsequent conceptual schemes in children form a hierarchy.

However, although this may be the case for children, it is certainly not how Kuhn saw the

succession of paradigms in the history of science. While for Piaget conceptual schemes

are hierarchical, for Kuhn they are more in parallel. For Piaget a subsequent conceptual

scheme incorporates the earlier one completely: ‘according to Piaget’s theory, a higher

stage can do everything a lower stage can do, and more’ (Siegel 1982, p.380). In contrast,

Kuhn emphasises that earlier scientific theories can explain certain phenomena that a

later one can not. That is to say, conceptual change in science does imply loss in

explanatory power (for certain phenomena). For example, Siegel (1982, p.382) argues

that the Daltonian revolution resulted in a new chemistry that lost the ability to account

for certain phenomena for which the old chemistry could account. For Piaget, subsequent

conceptual stages are superior to previous one across the board, while for Kuhn they are

Page 22 of 43

Greiffenhagen, C. and W. Sherman (2008). Kuhn and conceptual change: on the analogy between conceptual changes in science and children. Science & Education 17 (1), 1-26.

only superior in certain respects. We thus agree with Siegel’s (1982) point about a

fundamental difference between Piaget and Kuhn:

While there are important and profound differences in the explanatory power of Einsteinian and Newtonian physics, those differences are not formal, or logical, in character. […] The logic of Einstein is in no way superior to the logic of Newton; but the logic of formal operational thought is indeed superior, according to Piaget, to the logic of concrete operational thought. Here then is another case of disanalogy between cognitive development and the development of science. (p.384)

6 Conceptual Change in School Science?

We have argued that an analogy between Kuhn’s and Piaget’s notion of conceptual

change seems to be misplaced. However, what about the more general analogy between

Kuhn’s notion of conceptual change and the kind of changes that may occur in school

science (where the latter may be seen as a conceptual change from everyday to scientific

conceptual schemes)?

In order to be able to apply Kuhn’s notions of ‘conceptual change’ and ‘scientific

revolution’ to what happens in schools, CC needs to treat what children already know

about the natural world as something akin to a scientific theory, since for Kuhn the

change is between two comparable things. That is to say, in Kuhn’s version of paradigm

shifts within science, both the new and the old paradigm serve a similar purpose or aim

(although the new paradigm may be more successful at certain aspects). Kuhn (1996,

p.92) explicitly makes an analogy between political and scientific revolutions. In both the

political and the scientific case, the change is between things that are comparable, i.e.,

that are the same kind of thing: on the one hand a form of government (e.g., a change

from Monarchy to Democracy) or on the other a type of scientific theory (e.g., a change

from Newtonian to Einsteinian physics).

Page 23 of 43

Greiffenhagen, C. and W. Sherman (2008). Kuhn and conceptual change: on the analogy between conceptual changes in science and children. Science & Education 17 (1), 1-26.

However, are pupils’ ‘naïve beliefs’ sufficiently close to a scientific theory? In

this section we will argue that they are not. Everyday understandings are not a

‘conceptual scheme’ in Kuhn’s sense, since the latter refers to a systematic theory with

interdefined terms (which is what his notion of incommensurability requires). In Kuhn’s

case, both the old and the new scientific theory serve the same kind of purpose (namely

explaining aspects of the natural world in scientific terms) and can therefore be in

competition:

Like the choice between competing political institutions, that between competing paradigms proves to be a choice between incompatible modes of community life. (Kuhn 1996, p.94)

In our view, common sense and science do not stand in this relation. In our society one

can be, e.g., an accountant, a football player, a movie star, or an artist with or without

knowledge of the latest scientific developments. People are not faced with a choice

between science or common sense as two ‘incompatible modes of community life’. It is

not as if we meet people on the street and ask them: ‘Which one are you – science or

common sense?’ Rather, some people choose to pursue a career in science – just as

others become football players or accountants.

6.1 HOW ARE WE TO THINK ABOUT OUR KNOWLEDGE OF THE

NATURAL WORLD?

Part of the reason why researchers may be compelled to draw a parallel between

everyday knowledge and scientific knowledge has to do with a conceptual confusion

about the former. In our view, CC has a strange picture of people’s common-sense

knowledge of the natural world (a picture that to a large extent is carried over from

cognitive science). Within CC, children (and adults) are often portrayed as miniature

Page 24 of 43

Greiffenhagen, C. and W. Sherman (2008). Kuhn and conceptual change: on the analogy between conceptual changes in science and children. Science & Education 17 (1), 1-26.

scientists. Such a view has its origin in Piaget (cf., Woodfield 1987) and is frequently

adopted by CC researchers, who speak of the ‘pupil as scientist’ or ‘children’s science’.

According to this picture, children are seen as a disengaged observing ‘brain’ that is

looking at the world, interpreting what it sees, storing the observations as a series of

factual statements, and creating causal theories to explain the observed events.

Portraying common sense in the image of science leads to a falsification of

children’s (and adults’) engagement with the world and their knowledge of it. This move

has frequently been criticised (e.g., Cook 1969; Coulter 1989; Shanker 2004) and we will

restrict our remarks to two mistakes in CC’s characterisation of common sense; firstly, a

neglect of practices (of what people do), secondly, an underlying theoreticism (turning

knowledge into versions of scientific theories).

Firstly, proponents of CC are almost exclusively concerned with how children

‘think’ about the world and completely neglect what children ‘do’ in the world. For CC,

it seems that we first need a theory of the world before we can act in it. However, this

reverses the way in which we develop knowledge of the world: what we know about the

world develops as part of what we do (cf., Wittgenstein 1953; Coulter 1989). That is to

say, we learn about the world as part of various activities and practices (eating, playing

…) and it is these practices that define what counts, in specific situations, as a mistake or

a fault (we will return to this when discussing ‘misconceptions’ below).

Secondly, common sense could be characterised as ‘socially-sanctioned-facts-of-

life […] that-any-bona-fide-member-of-the-society-knows’ (Garfinkel 1967, p.76), i.e.,

as an assortment of socially shared facts and recipes. It is not therefore (as proponents of

CC would have it) anything like a systematic causal theory. To give just two examples:

Page 25 of 43

Greiffenhagen, C. and W. Sherman (2008). Kuhn and conceptual change: on the analogy between conceptual changes in science and children. Science & Education 17 (1), 1-26.

‘Unsupported things fall down’ might be common-sense knowledge, but that does not

mean that we therefore have a (proto-)theory of gravity. ‘The sun rises in the east’ is part

of common-sense knowledge, but that does not imply that we therefore have an

astronomical theory of the universe. Adopting a quote by Sharrock & Anderson (1982,

p.111), we might say that CC researchers:

are the kind of people who would attribute a geocentric theory of the universe to us on the strength of the remark that we intend to get up tomorrow morning to watch the sun rise.

Education research – CC included – frequently stipulates that all our knowledge about the

natural world has the same purpose as an explanatory theory. For example:

‘Commonsense’ ways of explaining phenomena, as pictured here, represent knowledge of the world portrayed within everyday culture. (Driver et al. 1994, p.8)

Another well-supported finding is that all students, the weak as well as the strong learners, come to their first science classes with surprisingly extensive theories about how the natural world works. They use these ‘naïve’ theories to explain real world events before they have had any science instruction. (Resnick 1983, p.477)

The misconception appears to be grounded in a systematic intuitive theory of motion […]. (McCloskey 1983, p.123; our emphasis)

Again, the question is not whether pupils have knowledge of the natural world (of course

they do), but whether this knowledge has the form of a systematic, causal (proto-

scientific) theory. In other words: How much of our ‘naïve beliefs’ are attempts at

explaining, in a systematic and causal manner, what we have observed during the course

of our lives? In our view, common-sense knowledge (both of children and adults) does

not constitute a systematic theory, but rather a heterogeneous assortment of things (a

‘motley’ as Wittgenstein might put it). Although these things sometimes work together,

very often they do not. In particular, they do not express an underlying overall systematic

conception of the world. For example, it is common-sense knowledge that the earth

Page 26 of 43

Greiffenhagen, C. and W. Sherman (2008). Kuhn and conceptual change: on the analogy between conceptual changes in science and children. Science & Education 17 (1), 1-26.

moves around the sun; but it is also common-sense knowledge that the sun rises in the

East and sets in the West. These two statements do not form a contradiction, as they are

not expressions of two competing theories. Similarly, it is common-sense knowledge that

humans are mammals and that humans are therefore just another animal; but it is also true

that in many contexts we make a distinction between humans and animals (e.g., on signs

such as ‘No animals allowed’). Again, there is no conflict here, as the second statement

does not express an underlying classificatory theory (and we might note how some of

common sense is also ‘science’, e.g., expresses biological classificatory schemes).

In particular, common sense is not a ‘disciplinary matrix’ in Kuhn’s sense. It is

neither ‘composed of ordered elements of various sorts’ (Kuhn 1977 [1974], p.297) – but

a loosely connected heterogonous set of facts; nor is it part of a ‘discipline’ – what

general problem is common sense supposed to ‘solve’? This highlights the connection to

our first point (the neglect of practices): CC overlooks that theories are tied to practices

(and only science systematically tries to explain natural phenomena), but common sense

does not constitute a practice, since the purpose of our life could hardly be characterised

as ‘building explanations of the natural world’. As mentioned in our discussion of Evans-

Pritchard above, it is a form of scientism to stipulate that people are always in the

business of creating theoretical explanations of their world. We wonder whether CC

researchers, by characterising what children say about natural phenomena in the image of

science are not committing a similar category-mistake to Evans-Pritchard.

These points hopefully demonstrate that common-sense knowledge is not

anything like a scientific theory – and that therefore Kuhn’s picture of conceptual change

cannot easily be applied to what happens in school science. Before moving on, let us

Page 27 of 43

Greiffenhagen, C. and W. Sherman (2008). Kuhn and conceptual change: on the analogy between conceptual changes in science and children. Science & Education 17 (1), 1-26.

quickly comment on the frequent claim that children’s common-sense knowledge is akin

to Aristotle’s theory of physics. For example:

In fact, one might characterize early stages of students’ work as the confrontation of an essentially Aristotelian theory of physics, with a Newtonian reality. (di Sessa 1982, p.41)

The point is that the real world, that is to say, the practical world of everyday experience, is, to a large extent, an Aristotelian world. (Garrison & Bentley 1990, p.20)

Even Kuhn, in a side-remark, was tempted to say something very similar:

Today the view of nature held by most sophisticated adults shows few important parallels to Aristotle’s, but the opinions of children, of the members of primitive tribes, and of many non-Western people do parallel his with surprising frequency. (Kuhn 1957, p.96)

As mentioned in our discussion of Kuhn and Piaget, we agree with Kuhn’s history of

science, but we are sometimes uncomfortable with side-remarks such as these (which are,

however, largely independent from his general position). As should be clear by now, we

think that it is misleading to characterise common-sense knowledge as Aristotelian. We

understand the temptation of saying this, since it may serve as a reminder that how we

experience the material world is very different from the picture suggested by Newtonian

physics and therefore ‘closer’ to Aristotelian physics. For example, heavier objects

typically do fall faster than lighter ones. Of course, Newtonian physics does not deny this

(in an environment with friction, weight makes a difference), but Newton’s claim is about

a special case, a vacuum, and it is using this special case as the underlying general

principle that is Newton’s ingenuity – and that ‘removes’ Newtonian physics from direct

experience.

In our view the analogy is misleading, since it turns common-sense knowledge

into a systematic (proto-scientific) explanatory theory, which clearly it is not. For

example, it is sometimes claimed that ‘children usually think of the earth as a very big,

Page 28 of 43

Greiffenhagen, C. and W. Sherman (2008). Kuhn and conceptual change: on the analogy between conceptual changes in science and children. Science & Education 17 (1), 1-26.

extended, flat physical object’ (Vosniadou & Ioannidis 1998, p.1218) – but even for

Aristotle the earth was a sphere (Vosniadou & Brewer 1992, p.539). Furthermore, the

culture that children grow up in (e.g., as portrayed in TV programs) includes things like

spaceships or superman flying through the air, which clearly are not part of an

Aristotelian universe. Children are saturated in modern culture, but that does not mean

that they therefore have a systematic theory of the natural world. Common sense is not a

closed system (neither is language).

6.2 THE WORLD OF SCIENCE AND THE EVERYDAY WORLD

We have so far argued that common-sense knowledge of the natural world does not

constitute anything akin to a systematic, causal, proto-scientific theory. What about the

relationship between scientific knowledge and how people think and talk about the

natural world in their everyday lives? In this context it is often argued that scientific

knowledge and common-sense knowledge stand in competition, i.e., that the former is

more ‘precise’ or ‘correct’ than the latter, or that scientific language should replace

ordinary language.

The first thing we would like to ask is this: What might be ‘wrong’ with common

sense so that it would stand in need of improving or replacing? In our view, to

characterise common-sense knowledge as ‘faulty’ only make senses if we could identify

things that go awry in the conduct of our everyday lives, e.g., when playing football,

cooking a meal, or talking to a friend on the phone. Errors are tied to what people are

trying to accomplish.

Page 29 of 43

Greiffenhagen, C. and W. Sherman (2008). Kuhn and conceptual change: on the analogy between conceptual changes in science and children. Science & Education 17 (1), 1-26.

Secondly, we want to note that children’s and adults’ observations of the natural

world (e.g., that things fall down or that it is often difficult to move big objects) are

largely independent from developments in science:

[…] the whole of science is totally irrelevant to most people’s day-to-day lives. One can live very well without knowledge of Newtonian mechanics, cell theory and DNA, and other sciences. (Wolpert 1992, p.16)

We might characterize science and common sense as different ‘frames of reference’ that

can co-exist without being in conflict. This is partly a result of the differences between

what are sometimes called ‘phenomenal’ and ‘objective’ descriptions (the former would

be the aim of phenomenology, the latter of science). For example, for Newtonian physics

time is an objective measure, whereas our phenomenal experience of time is such that it

sometimes passes slowly and sometimes goes by very quickly. These scientific and

phenomenal descriptions of time do not, however, stand in competition, but constitute

different ‘frames of reference’ (and the problem for schools might be to teach how to

recognize and coordinate them).

For proponents of CC, however, different descriptions such as these are in

competition. Even Kuhn sometimes falls into this trap. For example, at the end the end

of a chapter in The Copernican Revolution, Kuhn speculates about the psychological base

of Aristotle’s explanation of motion. Kuhn argues that it

derives from the Aristotelian transmutation of a primitive perception of space. To the members of prehistoric civilizations and primitive tribes, space seems very different from the Newtonian space in which we were all brought up, usually without knowing it. The latter is physically neutral. A body must be located in space and move through space, but the particular part of space and the particular direction of motion exert no influence on the body. Space is an inert substratum for all bodies. Each position and each direction is like every other. In modern terminology, space is homogenous and isotropic; it has no ‘top’ or ‘bottom’, ‘east’ or ‘west’.

The space of the primitive, in contrast, is often more nearly a life space: the space in a room, or in a house, or in a community. It has a ‘top’ and ‘bottom’,

Page 30 of 43

Greiffenhagen, C. and W. Sherman (2008). Kuhn and conceptual change: on the analogy between conceptual changes in science and children. Science & Education 17 (1), 1-26.

and ‘east’ and ‘west’ (or ‘front’ and ‘back’ – in many primitive societies words for direction derive from words for parts of the body and reflect the intrinsic differences of these parts). Each position is a position ‘for’ some object or ‘where’ some characteristic activity occurs. Each region and direction of space is characteristically different from every other, and the differences partially determine the behavior of bodies in each region. Usually the primitive’s space is the active dynamic space of everyday life; distinct regions have distinct characteristics. (Kuhn 1957, pp.97-98)

We would argue that Kuhn is here talking outside his area of expertise and exhibits some

of the misconceptions of common sense that we have tried to dispel. It is hard to know

why he singles out primitives, since we ‘sophisticates’ operate pretty much the same way.

Notice that Kuhn writes of ‘Newtonian space in which we were brought up, usually

without knowing it’ (our emphasis). In our view, this demonstrates that Kuhn here

conflates phenomenal and scientific descriptions of ‘space’. Presumably we could also

say that people from primitive societies grew up in Newtonian space (without knowing it)

– so there is not necessarily a difference between ‘their’ and ‘our’ ordinary concepts of

space. The only difference lies in the fact that ‘we’ have a developed physics, and ‘they’

have not. A central feature of operating within the system of Newtonian space is that

space is the same everywhere (whether or not the people of that part of the world have

ever heard of physics) and anytime (even if the people have not yet developed physics,

i.e., prior to Newton). Kuhn here conflates a phenomenal description of space (akin to

Merleau-Ponty) with a scientific one.

We think that Kuhn’s reflections about the historical developments within science

could usefully be complemented by the philosophical reflections about the relationship

between common sense and science by Alfred Schütz and Gilbert Ryle.

Schütz (1962a,b) wants to emphasize the importance of the natural attitude of

everyday life as the paramount reality from which other ‘realities’ (e.g., that of science,

Page 31 of 43

Greiffenhagen, C. and W. Sherman (2008). Kuhn and conceptual change: on the analogy between conceptual changes in science and children. Science & Education 17 (1), 1-26.

drama, or dreams) derive from. In that sense, everyday life and science are not on the

same level, but rather science is a special project (just as theatre or soccer).

Consequently, science and common sense are not in competition, and neither are theatre

and common sense. For example, we can teach children that people on stage do not

‘really’ die, or that it is possible for people to fly in a movie, but that children should not

try to jump from a roof. Proponents of CC occasionally realise that there is

the possibility of individuals having plural conceptual schemes, each appropriate to specific social settings. (Scientists, after all, understand perfectly well what is meant when they are told ‘Shut the door and keep the cold out’ or ‘Please feed the plants’). (Driver et al. 1994, p.7)

However, it seems to us that proponents of CC subsequently place these different

‘conceptual schemes’ on the same level – rather than treating everyday conceptual

schemes as the bedrock, the paramount reality, from which other frames of reference

develop.

Ryle (1954a,b), from whom the title for this section is borrowed, also wants us to

notice that technical-scientific descriptions are not in competition with ordinary ones. He

writes:

When we are in a certain intellectual mood, we seem to find clashes between the things that scientists tell us about our furniture, clothes and limbs and the things that we tell about them. We are apt to express these felt rivalries by saying that the world whose parts and members are described by scientists is different from the world whose parts and members we describe ourselves, and yet, since there can be only one world, one of these seeming worlds must be a dummy-world. Moreover, […] it must be the world that we ourselves describe which is the dummy-world. (Ryle 1954a, p.68)

Ryle uses an analogy with accountancy to exhibit the category mistake inherent in this

picture. Ryle says that the descriptions about books in the library produced by

accountants and by pupils are not ‘in conflict’ as they are not interested in the same kind

of thing. For the accountant what matters is the price of the book – for the pupil it may be

Page 32 of 43

Greiffenhagen, C. and W. Sherman (2008). Kuhn and conceptual change: on the analogy between conceptual changes in science and children. Science & Education 17 (1), 1-26.

important whether the book is easy or difficult, borrowed or in the library, etc. Similarly,

our ordinary ways of talking about tables and chairs are not in conflict with scientific

ones (according to the former a table is solid without holes, according to particle physics

it is largely composed of holes):

A bit of the theory of ultimate particles has no place in it for a description or misdescription of chairs and tables, and a description of chairs and tables has no place in it for a description or misdescription of ultimate particles. A statement that is true or false of the one is neither true nor false of the other. It cannot therefore be a rival of the other. (Ryle 1954a, p.79)

6.3 MISCONCEPTIONS?

Given that there is no general conflict between common sense and scientific knowledge,

we think it is problematic to speak of ‘misconceptions’ (or of ‘naive knowledge’) without

specifying the context or standard according to which children’s knowledge is labelled as

‘misconceived’ or ‘naive’. Speaking of ‘misconceptions’ per se, i.e., without specifying a

standard according to which there is a fault or error, suggests that there is only one

correct conception – the one of science. This is wrong on two grounds:

Firstly, if proponents of CC took Kuhn seriously, they would have to realise that

there is no such thing as ‘the’ scientific explanation of a phenomenon – but different,

incommensurable, explanations that are employed according to the prevalent scientific

culture or the problem under consideration. For example, Kuhn (1957, p.38) emphasizes

that the Ptolemaic two-sphere universe is still used by many people today, e.g., in

navigation and surveying. In other words, Kuhn argues that it is not possible to speak

about ‘truth’ or ‘error’ per se, stressing that these have always to be considered within a

system. Nor, according to Kuhn, are earlier scientific theories (e.g., the two-sphere

model) wrong per se, since they may even better at calculating certain phenomena than

Page 33 of 43

Greiffenhagen, C. and W. Sherman (2008). Kuhn and conceptual change: on the analogy between conceptual changes in science and children. Science & Education 17 (1), 1-26.

subsequent theories. Rather, earlier scientific theories will fail to explain some

phenomena that later theories do cover, and it will be those failures which, in turn, give

rise to eventual scientific revolution. As a consequence, there can be no conflict between

common sense and science – since there is no such thing as ‘the’ scientific explanation of

a phenomenon.

Secondly, as we have argued in the previous section, science and common sense

are not in competition. Proponents of CC argue that there is a conflict between what

children already know and what they are supposed to learn in school science. However,

what children already know has developed as part of their out-of-school lives. Thus to

label this knowledge as simply ‘faulty’, ‘naïve’, or ‘erroneous’ is to imply that CC

researchers have identified mistakes or errors of judgement within children’s everyday

lives. A boy throwing a stone in the air and expecting it to fly into the sky is clearly

making an error of judgement (which he will realise as soon as the stone falls on his

head). However, CC researchers never identify errors or misconceptions of this kind.

They do not look at what pupils do outside school, i.e., identify misconceptions as part of

the various activities that children engage in. Instead, CC researchers only look at

‘misconceptions’ within the context of school science (or experimental situations). The

‘misconceptions’ identified by CC are only misconceptions within school science.

The irony of the programme of Conceptual Change in science education is that it

argues against a ‘blank slate’ conception of children’s prior knowledge, i.e., aims to take

into account children’s knowledge of the world. However, CC subsequently only

investigates children’s knowledge in the context of school science rather than in those

occasions in which the knowledge was acquired. This restriction of context and

Page 34 of 43

Greiffenhagen, C. and W. Sherman (2008). Kuhn and conceptual change: on the analogy between conceptual changes in science and children. Science & Education 17 (1), 1-26.

applicability sneaks in (usually in brackets) when CC researchers talk about

‘misconceptions’, e.g.:

Naïve knowledge [...] is often incorrect (when compared to formal knowledge) (Chi & Roscoe 2002, p.3; our emphasis)

The paradox of science education is that its goal is to impart new schemata to replace the student’s extent ideas, which differ from the scientific theories being taught. (Carey 1986, p.1123; our emphasis)

These theories are often labelled ‘misconceptions’ […], because they do not agree with the current scientific view. (Hewson & Hewson 1984, p.4; our emphasis)

All these quotations exhibit that what is ‘wrong’ with children’s knowledge is only so

from the point of view of the scientific theory that children should learn in school

science. In other words: these pupils simply have not yet mastered the specific kind of

science in question. CC overlooks how words and concepts are used as part of pupils’

everyday life and the practices that they engage in. However, it is these practices that set

the standards of adequacy needed to label them as ‘misconceptions’ (or not).

In CC research, pupils may seem to be using their everyday knowledge to explain

the world because the researcher’s purpose is to uncover ‘children’s explanations of the

world’. So for example, a question like ‘Can you see in a completely dark room?’ asked

of a student, is used by a researcher to make a claim about a student’s ‘private theory’

about how the world works. But of course, from the student’s perspective, this question

can be interpreted (perfectly reasonably) to call for a report of personal experience

(Macbeth 2000). Thus, researchers are led to see ‘gaps’ and ‘misconceptions’ where none

in fact exist

Page 35 of 43

Greiffenhagen, C. and W. Sherman (2008). Kuhn and conceptual change: on the analogy between conceptual changes in science and children. Science & Education 17 (1), 1-26.

7 Conclusion: What Happens in School Science?

In this paper we have argued that CC is mistaken to make what pupils learn in school

science analogous to Kuhn’s conceptual changes in the history of science. The main

reason for the inappropriateness of this analogy lies in the simple fact that school pupils

are not scientists. Kuhn’s conceptual schemes are tied to what scientists do (e.g.,

performing new experiments and calculations). However, school pupils are not engaged

in work in that sense, since they do not produce new explanations of the natural world.

Pupils are in school to learn what others have discovered. They might learn something

new for themselves (‘personal discovery’), but what they learn has been known for a long

time (i.e., is not a ‘scientific discovery’). That schools pupils are not engaged in ‘real’

scientific work is recognised both by teachers and pupils:

[…] while pupils may well acquire a taste of what it is to be a professional scientist, there is, in these data at least, no pretence that they are ‘real scientists’ engaged in real discovery. Indeed the distinction between themselves and ‘real scientists’ is quite explicitly stated by the teacher. (French 1989, pp.34-35)

In school science pupils witness and perform demonstrations in or about science, but they

don’t do science (cf., Macbeth 2000, p.237).

We want to point out that we are making a logical argument here, not a moral

one. Understandably, educators exhibit a strong preference for students to be engaged in

‘meaningful’ activities, and by extension, ‘meaningful’ learning. To these educators, our

comments above sound as if we are ‘against’ progressive school curricula, or if we are

against pedagogies meant to ‘empower’ students. Rather, what we are saying is that

accepting the thesis that human social life is contextually bound – as Kuhn argued for –

requires one to recognize that students and scientists are just not doing the same thing. No

curriculum or pedagogy can change this (logical) observation.

Page 36 of 43

Greiffenhagen, C. and W. Sherman (2008). Kuhn and conceptual change: on the analogy between conceptual changes in science and children. Science & Education 17 (1), 1-26.

Conceptual change for Kuhn occurs from a growing sense within the scientific

community that the existing tools are not adequate for dealing with new questions and

problems:

One aspect of the parallelism must already be apparent. Political revolutions are inaugurated by a growing sense, often restricted to a segment of the political community, that existing institutions have ceased adequately to meet the problems posed by an environment that they have in part created. (Kuhn 1996, p.92; our emphasis)

However, school science does not address problems of this kind in the lives of pupils

outside of and prior to school. What pupils learn in school science does not address

‘inadequacies’ in common sense. Although what pupils learn in school may change how

they look at the world and may enable them to do new things, it does seem misleading to

say that school education solves systemic ‘problems’ that pupils had prior to going to

school. That is to say, there are no ‘anomalies’ for pupils (as suggested by Posner et al.

1982, p.223) that science education will ‘resolve’. Pupils do not participate in school

science lessons with the anticipation that what they will learn might help them to solve

problems that they have been struggling with for some time. Their life outside school is

‘in order’ before and after instruction in school science – although they may as a result be

able to do new things. School science does not have new answers to old problems, but

poses new questions (just as school grammar does not teach you how to speak, but gives

you a new perspective on language). Science is very much an addition to, an expansion

of, and in important respects a transfiguration of everyday understandings, but not an

extensive refutation of them. Furthermore, current common-sense knowledge has already

an admixture of science ‘in it’. That is to say, our common-sense knowledge is different

from common-sense knowledge one hundred or two thousand years ago.

Page 37 of 43

Greiffenhagen, C. and W. Sherman (2008). Kuhn and conceptual change: on the analogy between conceptual changes in science and children. Science & Education 17 (1), 1-26.

So how would we characterise what happens in school science classrooms? In our

view what children are supposed to learn in school science is not a replacement, but

rather a specialisation of what they already know. School science could be said to

‘upgrade’ common-sense descriptions and explanations (Lynch & Macbeth 1998, pp.284-

286) rather than to ‘replace’ them. Thus, rather than adopting Kuhn’s (1957, pp.43-44)

way of speaking of the ‘re-education of common sense’ we would speak of the

continuing education of common sense in schools. School science starts with pupils’

experience of the world as a ‘way in’ to school science, i.e., as a way of seeing the new in

terms that pupils can recognize. Although at the end of a course in school science, some

pupils make be able to talk ‘scientifically’ and use scientific concepts correctly, this is not

how they start. This allows us to look at concepts in a new way:

Concepts lose their familiar ‘special’ estate, a substantially Platonic estate of types and formal relations. Their first work is found in ordinary, rather than disciplinary worlds. (Macbeth 2005, p.19)

School science creates a new, specialised ‘frame of reference’ (that does not stand in

conflict with the old one, but constitutes a new one). For example, ‘what goes up must

come down’ holds in most situations. What pupils learn in school science is that in the

very special situation of a very high acceleration (as in the case of rockets) it may not

hold. Similarly, it is true that our bodies do not have holes (except when we have been

shot). When pupils learn about atomic theory, they learn a different (but not

contradictory) way of looking at bodies, which now consist mainly of empty space, i.e.,

are full of holes. School science thus gives certain expressions (e.g., ‘hole’ or ‘earth’) a

new sense, which allows that new questions can be asked and new statements can be

made (using the old concepts). CC, exhibiting a form of scientism, thinks that school

science has to replace one frame of reference with another. Instead, in school science

Page 38 of 43

Greiffenhagen, C. and W. Sherman (2008). Kuhn and conceptual change: on the analogy between conceptual changes in science and children. Science & Education 17 (1), 1-26.

pupils learn additional frames of reference and learn how to coordinate between them. As

a consequence, understanding the relation between how we ordinarily speak of things and

how science speaks of, and conceives of, things is one of the fundamental challenges of

science teaching.

In our view, CC mystifies what goes on in school science classrooms to the extent

that it treats what pupils know as a set of proto-scientific, ontological beliefs. What pupils

have to learn in school science is difficult and it is worthwhile finding ways of helping

pupils with acquiring this new and difficult material. However, this is a pedagogical, not

an ontological, problem.

Acknowledgements

We would like to thank Wes Sharrock and two anonymous reviewers for helpful

comments and criticisms on an earlier version. Christian Greiffenhagen would like to

thank the British Academy for a Postdoctoral Fellowship to support work on this paper.

Page 39 of 43

Greiffenhagen, C. and W. Sherman (2008). Kuhn and conceptual change: on the analogy between conceptual changes in science and children. Science & Education 17 (1), 1-26.

1 For recent overviews of CC see Chi & Roscoe (2002), Duguit & Treagust (2003), and Leach &

Scott (2003).

2 The analogy is discussed, for example, in Gruber (1973), Cawthron & Rowell (1978), Hewson

(1981), Clement (1982), Siegel (1982), Posner et al. (1982), Driver (1983), Gibson (1985), Carey (1986),

Kitchener (1987), Vosniadou & Brewer (1987, 1992), Kitcher (1988), D. Kuhn (1989), Nersessian (1989),

Vosniadou & Ioannidis (1998), Garrison & Bentley (1990), Matthews (2000, 2003).

3 We acknowledge that the mechanism for conceptual change from informal to scientific ideas

about the world is contested (see Duit & Treagust 2003 for a review). Despite these differences, there

seems to be widespread agreement that everyday and scientific conceptions of the world are disparate

enough for learning in science to require some sort of psychological transition in pupils analogous to

Kuhn’s ‘paradigm shift’.

4 The position that scientific conceptions must replace ‘naïve’ or everyday conceptions has been

critiqued within the CC literature. For example, Driver et al. (1994) argue that scientific and everyday

conceptions probably operate in ‘parallel’ with one another in a student’s conceptual ecology. However,

this is not what we are saying in suggesting that scientific knowledge is an extension or refinement of

everyday knowledge. As we read arguments such as Driver et al.’s, we understand them to be talking about

scientific and everyday knowledge as two conflicting-but-equivalent entities, i.e., as having the same

purpose, whereas we want to suggest that the two are not sufficiently alike to be in conflict.

Page 40 of 43

Greiffenhagen, C. and W. Sherman (2008). Kuhn and conceptual change: on the analogy between conceptual changes in science and children. Science & Education 17 (1), 1-26.

References

Boden, M.A.: 1979, Piaget, Harvester Press, Brighton.

Butterfield, H.: 1931, The Whig Interpretation of History, Bell, London.

Carey, S.: 1986, ‘Cognitive Science and Science Education’, American Psychologist 41(10), 1123–1130.

Cawthron, E.R. & Rowell, J.A.: 1978, ‘Epistemology and Science Education’, Studies in Science Education 5, 31–59.

Chi, M.T.H. & Roscoe, R.D.: 2002, ‘The Processes and Challenges of Conceptual Change’, In M. Limón & L. Mason (eds.), Reconsidering Conceptual Change. Issues in Theory and Practice, Kluwer, Dordrecht, 3–27.

Clement, J.: 1982, ‘Students’ Preconception in Introductory Mechanics’, American Journal of Physics 50(1), 66–71.

Cook, J.: 1969, ‘Human Beings’, In P. Winch (ed.), Studies in the philosophy of Wittgenstein, Routledge & Kegan Paul, London, 117–151.

Coulter, J.: 1989, Mind in Action, Polity, Cambridge.

di Sessa, A.A.: 1982, ‘Unlearning Aristotelian Physics: A Study of Knowledge-based Learning’, Cognitive Science 6(1), 37–75.

Driver, R.: 1983, The Pupil as Scientist? Open University Press, Milton Keynes.

Driver, R., Asoko, H., Leach, J., Mortimer, E. & Scott, P.: 1994, ‘Constructing Scientific Knowledge in the Classroom’, Educational Researcher 23(7), 5–12.

Duit, R. & Treagust, D.F.: 2003, ‘Conceptual Change: A Powerful Framework for Improving Science Teaching and Learning’, International Journal of Science Education 25(16), 671–688.

Evans-Pritchard, E.E.: 1937, Witchcraft, Oracles and Magic among the Azande. Oxford, Clarendon Press.

French, J.: 1989, ‘Accomplishing Scientific Instruction’, In R. Millar (ed.), Doing Science: Images of Science in Science Education, Falmer, London, 10–37.

Garfinkel, H.: 1967, Studies in Ethnomethodology, Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs, NJ.

Garrison, J.W. & Bentley, M.L.: 1990, ‘Science Education, Conceptual Change and Breaking with Everyday Experience’, Studies in Philosophy and Education 10, 19–35.

Gibson, B.S.: 1985, ‘The Convergence of Kuhn and Cognitive Psychology’, New Ideas in Psychology 2(3), 211–221.

Gilbert, J.K., Osborne, R.J. & Fensham, P.J.: 1982, ‘Children’s Science and Its Consequence for Teaching’, Science Education 66(4), 623–633.

Gruber, H.: 1973, ‘Courage and Cognitive Growth in Children and Scientists’, In M. Schwebel & J. Raph (eds.), Piaget in the Classroom, Basic Books, New York, 73–105.

Hewson, P.W.: 1981, ‘A Conceptual Change Approach to Learning Science’, European Journal of Science Education 3(4), 383–396.

Hewson, P.W. & Hewson, M.G.: 1984, ‘The Role of Conceptual Conflict in Conceptual Change and the Design of Science Instruction’, Instructional Science 13(1), 1–13.

Kitcher, P.: 1988, ‘The Child as Parent of the Scientist’, Mind & Language 3(3), 217–228.

Page 41 of 43

Greiffenhagen, C. and W. Sherman (2008). Kuhn and conceptual change: on the analogy between conceptual changes in science and children. Science & Education 17 (1), 1-26.

Kitchener, R.F.: 1987, ‘Genetic Epistemology: Equilibration and the Rationality of Scientific Change’, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 18(3), 339–366.

Kuhn, D.: 1989, ‘Children and Adults as Intuitive Scientists’, Psychological Review 96(4), 674–689.

Kuhn, T.S.: 1957, The Copernican Revolution: Planetary Astronomy in the Development of Western Thought, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA.

Kuhn, T.S.: 1970a, ‘Logic of Discovery or Psychology of Research?’, In I. Lakatos & A. Musgrave (eds.), Criticism and The Growth of Knowledge, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1–23.

Kuhn, T.S.: 1970b. ‘Reflections on my Critics’, In I. Lakatos & A. Musgrave (eds.), Criticism and The Growth of Knowledge, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 231–278.

Kuhn, T.S.: 1977 [1959], ‘The Essential Tension: Tradition and Innovation in Scientific Research’, In T. S. Kuhn, The Essential Tension: Selected Studies in Scientific Tradition and Change, University of Chicago Press, Chicago, 1977, 225–239. Originally published 1959 in C.W. Taylor (ed.), The Third (1959) University of Utah Research Conference on the Identification of Scientific Talent, University of Utah Press, Salt Lake City.

Kuhn, T.S.: 1977 [1964], ‘A Function for Thought Experiments’, In T.S. Kuhn, The Essential Tension: Selected Studies in Scientific Tradition and Change, University of Chicago Press, Chicago, 1977, 240–265. Originally published 1964 in L’aventure de la science, Mélanges Alexandre Koyré, Hermann, Paris.

Kuhn, T.S.: 1977 [1971], ‘Concepts of Cause in the Development of Physics’, In T.S. Kuhn, The Essential Tension: Selected Studies in Scientific Tradition and Change, 21–30. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Originally published 1971 as ‘Les notions de causalité dans le developpement de la physique’ in Edudes d’épistémologie génétique 25.

Kuhn, T.S.: 1977 [1974], ‘Second Thoughts on Paradigms’, In T.S. Kuhn, The Essential Tension: Selected Studies in Scientific Tradition and Change, University of Chicago Press, Chicago, 1977, 293–319. Originally published 1974 in F. Suppe (ed.), The Structure of Scientific Theories, University of Illinois Press, Urbana.

Kuhn, T.S.: 1989a, ‘Possible Worlds in History of Science’, In S. Allén (ed.), Possible Worlds in Humanities, Arts and Sciences, Walter de Gruyter, Berlin, 9–32.

Kuhn, T.S.: 1989, ‘Speaker’s Reply’, In S. Allén (ed.), Possible Worlds in Humanities, Arts and Sciences, Walter de Gruyter, Berlin, 49–51.

Kuhn, T.S.: 1990, ‘The Road Since Structure’, In PSA 1990, Volume 2, 3–13.

Kuhn, T.S.: 1996, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (third editon), University of Chicago Press, Chicago.

Lakatos, I. & A. Musgrave (eds.): 1970, Criticism and The Growth of Knowledge. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

Leach, J. & Scott, P.: 2003, ‘Individual and Sociocultural Views of Learning in Science Education’, Science & Education 12(1), 91–113.

Levine, A.T.: 2000, ‘Which ways is up? Thomas S. Kuhn’s Analogy to Conceptual Development in Childhood’, Science & Education 9(1/2), 107–122.

Loving, C.C. & Cobern, W.W.: 2000, ‘Invoking Thomas Kuhn: What Citation Analysis Reveals about Science Education’, Science & Education 9(1/2), 187–206.

Page 42 of 43

Greiffenhagen, C. and W. Sherman (2008). Kuhn and conceptual change: on the analogy between conceptual changes in science and children. Science & Education 17 (1), 1-26.

Lynch, M. & Macbeth, D.H.: 1998, ‘Demonstrating Physics Lessons’, In J.G. Greeno & S.V. Goldman (eds.), Thinking Practices in Mathematics and Science Learning, Lawrence Erlbaum, Mahwah, NJ, 269–297.

Macbeth, D.H.: 2000, ‘On an Actual Apparatus for Conceptual Change’, Science Education 84(2), 228–264.

Macbeth, D.H.: 2005, ‘Respecifying Concepts: The Case of Classroom Research,’ Paper presented at the annual meeting of the American Educational Research Association (AERA), Montreal, April 2005.

Matthews, M.R.: 2000, ‘Editorial’, Science & Education 9(1/2), 1–10.

Matthews, M.R.: 2003, ‘Thomas Kuhn’s Impact on Science Education: What Lessons Can Be Learned?’, Science Education 88(1), 90–118.

Maxwell, G. & Feigl, H.: 1961, ‘Why Ordinary Language Needs Reforming’, Journal of Philosophy 58(18), 488–498.

McCloskey, M.: 1983, ‘Naive Theories of Motion’, In D. Gentner & A.L. Stevens (eds.), Mental Models, Lawrence Erlbaum, Hillsdale, NJ, 299–324.

Nersessian, N.J.: 1989, ‘Conceptual Change in Science and in Science Education’, Synthese 80(1), 163–183.

Osborne, R.J.: 1980, ‘Some Aspects of Students’ Views of the World’, Research in Science Education 10, 11–18.

Piaget, J.: 1930, The Child’s Conception of Physical Causality, Routledge, London.

Piaget, J.: 1970, Genetic Epistemology, Columbia University Press, New York.

Popper, K.R.: 1970. ‘Against “Normal Science”’, In I. Lakatos & A. Musgrave (eds.), Criticism and The Growth of Knowledge, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 51–58.

Posner, G.J., Strike, K.A., Hewson, P.W. & Gertzog, W.A.: 1982, ‘Accommodation of a Scientific Conception: Toward a Theory of Conceptual Change’, Science Education 66(2), 211–227.

Reiner, M., Chi, M.T.H. & Resnick, L.B.: 1988, ‘Naive Materialistic Belief: An Underlying Epistemological Commitment’, In Proceedings of the Tenth Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society (August 17–19, 1988, Montreal, Canada), Lawrence Erlbaum, NJ, 544–551.

Resnick, L.B.: 1983, ‘Mathematics and Science Learning: A New Conception’, Science 220(4596), 477–478.

Rotman, B.: 1977, Jean Piaget: Psychologist of the Real, Harvester Press, Hassocks.

Ryle, G.: 1954a, ‘The World of Science and the Everyday World’, In G. Ryle, Dilemmas, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 68-81.

Ryle, G.: 1954b, ‘Technical and Untechnical Concepts’, In G. Ryle, Dilemmas, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 82–92.

Schütz, A.: 1962a, ‘Common-sense and Scientific Interpretation of Human Action’, In A. Schütz, Collected Papers I: Studies in Social Theory, Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague, 3–47.

Schütz, A.: 1962b, ‘On Multiple Realities’, In A. Schütz, Collected Papers I: Studies in Social Theory, Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague, 207–259.

Shanker, S.G.: 2004, ‘The Roots of Mindblindness’, Theory & Psychology 14(5), 685–703.

Page 43 of 43

Greiffenhagen, C. and W. Sherman (2008). Kuhn and conceptual change: on the analogy between conceptual changes in science and children. Science & Education 17 (1), 1-26.

Sharrock, W.W. & Anderson, D.C.: 1982, ‘The Persistent Evasion of Technical Issues in Media Studies’, Sociology 16(1), 108–115.

Sharrock, W.W. & Read, R.: 2002, Kuhn: Philosopher of Scientific Revolution. Polity, Oxford.

Siegel, H.: 1982, ‘On the Parallel between Piagetian Cognitive Development and the History of Science’, Philosophy of the Social Sciences 12(4), 375–386.

Vosniadou, S.: 1989, ‘On the Nature of Children’s Naive Knowledge’, In Proceedings of the Eleventh Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society (August 16–19, 1989, Ann Arbor, Michigan), Lawrence Erlbaum, NJ, 404–411.

Vosniadou, S. & Brewer, W.F.: 1987, ‘Theories of Knowledge Restructuring in Development’, Review of Educational Research 57(1), 51–67.

Vosniadou, S. & Brewer, W.F.: 1992, ‘Mental Models of the Earth: A Study of Conceptual Change in Childhood’, Cognitive Psychology 24(4), 535–585.

Vosniadou, S. & Ioannides, C.: 1998, ‘From Conceptual Development to Science Education: A Psychological Point of View’, International Journal of Science Education 20(10), 1213–1230.

Winch, P.: 1964, ‘Understanding a Primitive Society’, American Philosophical Quarterly 1, 304–324.

Wittgenstein, L.: 1953, Philosophical Investigations (Translated by G.E.M. Anscombe), Oxford, Basil Blackwell.

Wittgenstein, L.: 1979, ‘Remarks on Frazer’s “Golden Bough”’, In C.G. Luckhardt (ed.), Wittgenstein: Sources and Perspectives, Harvester Press, Hassocks, 61–81.

Woodfield, A.: 1987, ‘On the Very Idea of Acquiring a Concept’, In J. Russell (ed.), Philosophical Perspectives on Developmental Psychology, Basil Blackwell, Oxford, 17–30.

Wolpert, L.: 1992, The Unnatural Nature of Science, Farber and Farber, London.