kroner primary of faith

Upload: claus-baro

Post on 09-Apr-2018

218 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    1/254

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    2/254

    234.2Kronerp-rimacy QJL

    234.2 K93p

    KeepYour Card inThis PocketBooks will be issued only on presentation of proper

    library cards.Unless labeled otherwise, books may be retainedlor two weeks. Borrowers finding books marked, de-laced or mutilated are expected to report same atlibrary desk; otherwise tibe last borrower will be heldresponsible for all imperfections discovered.The card holder is responsible for all books drawnon this card.

    Penalty for over-due books 2c a day plus cost ofnotices.

    Lost cards and change of residence must be re-ported promptly.

    Public LibraryKansas City, Mo.

    TEMEION KNVKt.0l*t CORP.

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    3/254

    KANSAS CITY, MO PUBLIC LIBRARY

    DFC

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    4/254

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    5/254

    THE PRIMACY OF FAITH

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    6/254

    THE MACMILLAN COMPANYNEW YOBK BOSTON CHICAGO

    DALLAS * ATLANTA 8AH FBANCI3COMACMILLAN AND CO., LIMITED

    LOBDQlf BOMBAT CALCUTTAMADBA8 MELBOUBNH

    THE MACMILLAN COMPANYOF CANADA, LIMITED

    TQBOHTO

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    7/254

    OF FAITH'

    byRICHARD KRONER

    Hew Yor{THE MACMILLAN COMPANY

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    8/254

    Copyright, 1943, byTHE MACMILLAN COMPANY.AH rights reserved no part of this book may bereproduced in any form without permission in writingfrom the publisher, except by a reviewer who wishesto quote brief passages in connection with a reviewwritten for inclusion in magazine or newspaper.

    First printinff.

    SET UP BY BROWN BROTHERS LINOTYPERSPRINTED IN THE WITH* STATES OP AMERICA

    BY THE FERRIS ERINTING COMPANY

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    9/254

    ToMICHAEL B. FOSTER M.A. (OXON.), PH.D. (KIEL)

    TUTOR OF CHRIST CHURCH, OXFORD

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    10/254

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    11/254

    PrefaceTHE FOLLOWING Gifford Lectures were delivered at theUniversity of St. Andrews in the academic year 1939-1940, not exactly in the form as they are published nowbut with the same content. I have enlarged their scope ofthought in some respects, and I have omitted some partsof the lectures as delivered.

    Circumstances, not connected with the lectures them-selves, have delayed publication. This delay certainly hassome disadvantages, since my inner development has pro-ceeded in the meantime. It has, I trust, proceeded alongthe lines which I was then pursuing. The delay has alsoone advantage : I have had the occasion to work out sometheses suggested in the lectures and to discourse aboutthem in the United States. Thus two other courses of lec-tures amplify and interpret the program that I outlinedat St. Andrews: The Bedell Lectures on The ReligiousFunction of Imagination^ and the Hewett Lectures onHowDo We Know God? 2 Together with these they forma kind of trilogy that might be entitled: The BoundaryLine between Philosophy and Religion. This was theoriginal title of the Gifiord Lectures.

    In the Bedell Lectures I dealt with the problem of reli-gious imagination, a problem too long neglected, Ithink; in the Hewett lectures I discussed the problem ofreligious knowledge, a very intricate problem,

    becausereligious knowledge deviates so obviously from all otherkinds of knowledge that even the question might be raised

    1 Published 1941 by Yale University Press.2 Published 1943 by Harper and Brothers.Vll

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    12/254

    viii PREFACEas to whether we are allowed to speak of knowledge atall; in the following lectures the problem of faith is inthe foreground, but the problems of religious imaginationand religious knowledge also are discussed. Indeed, faith,imagination and knowledge are so intimately combined inthe spiritual field that it is not easy to distinguish them.They are elements within one and the same living unity.The standpoint of the following treatise may be out-lined in advance. I try to show that a natural theologycannot be prohibited by dogmatics as Karl Earth wouldhave it; but also that a merely rational faith', as providedby Kant, is not tenable. Reason needs the supplement ofrevealed religion. In such a way thought and faith1 do notcontradict, but rather complement each other. In this rela-tionship faith has the primacy. It surpasses the power of^reason and completes its undertaking.I might call this standpoint a modern conservatism. Itdoes not inaugurate a new orthodoxy, but it shows thelegitimate right of a super-natural and even super-rationalfaith of that faith which was and is and I trust will everbe the basis and the source of our life.The tendency towards the humanization of religion is

    passing; it led finally to the dehumanization of man, andthus it refuted itself. Faith should neither be orthodoxnor heterodox; it should not be dogmatic at all. It shouldbe universal and individual at the same time, preservingthe ancient message but also reconciling it with the think-ing mind of today.

    I should like to express my sincere gratitude to theAdministration of the Gifford Foundation. The image ofbeautiful St. Andrews, the memories of many friendlyhours I enjoyed in the hospitable house of Professor Knoxand his wife, and the echo of many conversations and dis-cussions with the colleagues in the University, all this is

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    13/254

    PREFACE ixstill alive in me and will remain alive as long as I live. Ialso wish to thank Professor Monroe C. Beardsley ofYale University and the Reverend Dudley D. Zuver, whokindly revised the English of my manuscript.

    R. K.New York, January, 1943

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    14/254

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    15/254

    CONTENTSCHAPTER PAGE

    I. Biblical and Natural Theology iII. Kant's Critique of Natural Theology 24

    III. Kant's Doctrine of Rational Faith 46IV. The Nature of Evil 67V. The Mystery of Man 89VI. The Origin of Evil in the Will 112VII. The Idea of God and the Religious

    Imagination 133VIII. The Image of the Creator 151IX. The Origin of Evil and Original Sin 178X. The Primacy of Faith 198

    Index 223

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    16/254

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    17/254

    THE PRIMACY OF FAITH

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    18/254

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    19/254

    CHAPTER IBiblical and Natural Theology

    THE BIBLE shows us, with overwhelming power, that thenature of God is deeply hidden and that reason alone can-not disclose the divine mystery. Even to a man who can-not share the belief of the church or its dogmatic theologythe language of the Bible attests that truth' with con-vincing clarity. God is a hidden God. Thus the third com-mandment warns against abusing His holy name. We areforbidden to mention His name in a way that would leadus to believe we know His nature, or have dispelled themystery that covers it. We should never forget that weare speaking of His mystery when we are speaking ofHim, for He is His mystery.He who does not recognize this nature of God, may belearned, but he is more remote from the knowledge ofGod than the simple believer. Partial knowledge hasrobbed him of the capacity for religious awe. Actuallythose who deny God pretend to greater knowledge thanthe believer. To the believer the fundamental fact is thevast enigma of things divine. This fact makes him humble,and humility is the precondition and prerequisite of faith.Because God is a mystery we are forbidden to use Hisname in vain, which is to allege that we know His natureas we know the nature of other things. God is mystery;this is implied in the attribute of holiness. A thing fullyunderstandable cannot be holy, though of course a certainacquaintance is presupposed in calling God holy. But Hisholiness cannot be ascertained and tested in the way of

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    20/254

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    21/254

    BIBLICAL AND NATURAL THEOLOGY 3admits it to be, more profound than science can possiblybe itself. This point of view, axiomatic in former genera-tions, we must now recapture. It is not a deficiency thatmakes the Biblical language appear immature comparedwith' that of science; this contrast stems from the differ-ence between the entire purport and intention of religionand science. The scientist who thinks his own outlooksuperior to the Biblical shows only that he does notunderstand the essence of faith.

    Whereas science tries to discover the way in whichnature operates, religion appeals to the consciousness ofthe mystery that underlies nature and human life. Scienceand religion, from this point of view, are strictly opposedto each other. Science endeavors to diminish the realm ofthe unknown, religion stresses the fact that there is anunknowable ; that even the smallest and most unimportantthing is ultimately unknowable. Everything is embracedin universal mystery: the lowest and the highest, matteras well as mind, soul and spirit. This aspect of unknow-ability, of course, pertains only to one side of religion.There is another side also. Religion does not offer knowl-edge in the sense of scientific knowledge, but it does openan access to the unknowable and it does even offer a cer-tain knowledge of the all-embracing mystery: it teachesus to meet it with awe, with confidence, with hope, loveand faith. The Bible thus addresses man not as an isolatedintellect, but as a total personality possessing a moral willand centered in a feeling heart. Appealing to emotion andvolition, it necessarily appeals to reason and intellect also,for the heart and will are human precisely because theyare connected with', and influenced by, intellectual faculties.Thus the Scripture gives reasons for belief in God, andprovides us with a kind of knowledge. But this knowl-edge is neither scientific nor philosophic, strictly speaking;

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    22/254

    4 THE PRIMACY OF FAITHit is not conceptual and not rational. Rather it is imagina-tive. Compare the style of Biblical writers, even of thosewho are involved in theological thought like Paul, with'the style of scientific works, be they demonstrative orpredominantly descriptive, be they rational or empirical,critical or speculative. And the difference of style hints ata difference of purpose and purport. Religious knowledgeis not disinterested, it intends no objective truth; on thecontrary it stirs our conscience and touches our heart. Thisis the reason it is legitimately imaginative, not only occa-sionally using figurative speech or poetical metaphor,but rather imbued with imaginative elements in all its con-ceptions, in all its ideas, even and especially in the idea ofGod. Religion and science need not interfere with eachother. Their realms are wholly different. Science can neverproduce images in the religious sense, religion can neverproduce concepts instrumental in science and theoreticalknowledge. Religion cannot supersede scientific investiga-tion, but science also cannot replace religious imagination.A sharp boundary line divides 'these realms.

    In spite of this acknowledged difference of interest,intention, and method, these varieties of knowledge do notdwell in peace together. On the contrary a struggle hasraged between them since the beginning of Greek thought.In ancient times intellectual thought seemed to have over-come religious knowledge as represented by polytheisticbelief in the mythical gods. Greek philosophy held moreor less in contempt the images of the gods and strove tosupplant them by abstract knowledge. Aristotle was con-vinced that his theological insight was much more ade-quate to the nature of the divine than the religious beliefof his fellow countrymen. He was convinced that rationalthought was able to penetrate the essence of things, andtherefore the essence of the divine also* The mythical

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    23/254

    BIBLICAL AND NATURAL THEOLOGY 5form of religious knowledge, he says, is fit for "the per-suasion of the multitude and for legal and utilitarian ex-pediency." l According to him the true knowledge of Godis to be achieved by metaphysical inquiry and discourse.Aristotle became thus the founder of "natural theology."

    Greek thought preceded and initiated Christian theol-ogy. This historical fact proves that the human mind canfind a certain kind of knowledge of the divine through itsown resources, unsupported by, and even unaware of,other means. The similarity between certain doctrines ofGreek philosophy and Biblical views is so striking thatPhilo, Clement of Alexandria, and other theologians sawno explanation for it but to assume that Plato had beeninfluenced by the "barbarian philosophy." Later the con-geniality of Aristotle's natural theology and the Christianfaith generated their close alliance in the Middle Ages.But there is a profound difference between the Aristo-telian attitude towards faith and the attitude of theChristian thinkers. Aristotle could feel that thought wassuperior to the images of the mythical gods; that meta-physical discernment and argument could penetrate deeperinto the hidden nature of the deity than religious imagina-tion. Thus he could attain to a philosophic theology with-out any internal struggle between faith and thought.Mythological religion had no dogma and no doctrine ; itwas the pure product of an imagination nourished andenlarged from generation to generation by poets and^bythe poetical fancy of the Greek people. Greek religioncould not rival the acuteness and consistency of meta-physical considerations. And still in another respect phi-losophy was superior to folk, religion: it developedmorally higher conceptions of the deity. "Xenophanes hadboldly accused men of having attributed to the heavenly

    1 Met. 1074 b.

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    24/254

    6 THE PRIMACY OF FAITHones all that was disgraceful among men." 2 Plato's indig-nation on this score is well known.

    These historical data demonstrate that the boundaryline between revealed and natural theology involves anintricate problem, despite the fact that philosophy as ascience, and religion as based on revelation, have differentdomains and different jurisdictions. This difference isobvious. Philosophy is basically and essentially theoretical.It rests upon logical argumentation and conclusion, it aimsat doctrines, theories and systematic, methodical knowl-edge, while religion is related to life in its wholeness,especially to moral life, to conscience and conduct. Reli-gion, therefore, comprises the whole of life, not only asphilosophy does, by means of thought and concepts, butin the omnivorous fashion of life itself. Indeed, there isa religious aspect to every domain of life : there is aspecific religious morality, there are religious virtues, reli-gious obligations and actions; there is a religious art;there is a religious community, a religious law, a religiousright; there is a religious science; in short, the wholecosmos of human activity is imbued with the religiousspirit and controlled by religious authorities and tradi-tion. Nothing of this kind corresponds within the provinceof philosophy, although, especially in the ancient times,philosophy strove to take the place of religion and toorganize the whole of life. The difference between therealms of thought and faith, nevertheless, is unmistakableand inextinguishable.

    Philosophy teaches, religion preaches. Philosophy isalways the business of a single thinker, though he mayform a school; religion is the common concern of a com-munity though inaugurated by a founder. Philosophy has

    2 William Wallace, Gifford Lectures on Natural Theology and Ethics(ed. by Bdw. Caird, Oxford, 1898, p. 27).

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    25/254

    BIBLICAL AND NATURAL THEOLOGY 7no priests, no cult; religion has no logical methods, nosober investigations. To be sure, certain philosophicalschools have had a religious or semi-religious characterand authority like the Pythagoreans, the Stoics, the Neo-Platonists ; some philosophers seem akin to prophets andreligious leaders. Christianity, on the other hand, had itsown philosophers, professors, school systems, and method-ical teaching. There is obviously a certain rivalry betweenthe realms and their representatives. Philosophy is con-cerned with the ultimate meaning of life and reality; sois religion. The metaphysician is not a sober scientist, hehas no exact experiments, and his statements never enjoythe same validity and acceptance as those of the mathe-maticians and physicists. A certain analogy betweenSocrates and Jesus, despite the huge gulf that separatesthem, cannot be denied; there is a similarity, too, betweenthe writings of Plato where Socrates is the central figureand the Gospel. Philosophy and religion, though widelydiffering, are intimately connected; they even overlap insome respects and in some sectors.Thus peace between the rivals is not guaranteed fromthe outset; they resemble two nations with adjacent terri-tories. A boundary line divides them, but there is a bit ofdisputed country between them that continually threatenswar. This intermediate both-man's-land arouses perennialquarrels. Its name is "theology." Religion proposes toconstruct its own theology, philosophy does likewise. Tobe sure, they proceed from different bases though theymove to a common goal. This goal, a methodical andlogical science of God, is identical. Both religious andphilosophic, Biblical and natural, revelatory and rationaltheology represent different forms of the same science,namely theology. Therefore the task of relating them toeach other is urgent. In the Middle Ages they were united

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    26/254

    8 THE PRIMACY OF FAITHunder the sway of Christianity. Since the Renaissance theyhave been separated and their relation has never beenclear. This condition is becoming more and more scandal-ous. It mirrors the general gulf between religion andmodern culture, between life and thought which char-acterizes our age. Philosophy pays little attention to reli-gious theology, for religious theology claims specialsources of knowledge. Some attempts have been made tobridge the chasm between these antagonists, undertakenby religious theologians, but the task is still undone. Tooutline the nature of this task and to suggest a solutionis the purpose of these lectures. It is the same task whichconfronted men like Origen, Augustine, and the medievalthinkers, and which has been abandoned since the begin-ning of modern times without having been dischargedsatisfactorily. Modern science was believed to have founda new method. But the old task could not be taken overby science, nor by a philosophy which was based on scien-tific presuppositions or preoccupied with scientific prob-lems and views (using the word "scientific" in the nar-rower sense of the natural sciences).The conquest of philosophy by modern science caused

    all relations between philosophy and religion to becomedubious, and every attempt to reconcile them becamesuspect. Philosophy boasted that it was entirely free fromprejudices and could build up its theories on the samesolid ground as mathematics and mathematical physics,that is on empirical experience and rational conclusions.The modern outlook is exactly opposite to that of themedieval scholar. Whereas Anselm had said: "Credo utintelligam" 3 the modern thinker says : "We must aban-

    3 In substance this thesis of course is older than the word of Anselm.Augustine has similar phrases, e.g., "si non poUs intelllgtre, crude utintelligas" (Senno 118, i) ; cp. c. Acad. Ill, 43; de ord. II, 26; SolILI, 9; Horn. Ev. Joh. XXIX, 6.

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    27/254

    BIBLICAL AND NATURAL THEOLOGY 9don every belief before we begin to investigate nature.Only thus can objective knowledge arise." Belief impliesan assumption that is not verified by experiment and criti-cal observation. We must not admit such a hypotheticalelement in the field of philosophy since we do not admitit in that of science. This is the modern postulate. Thedifference in character between unwarranted assumptionand religious faith was no longer felt and conceded. Theneed to reconcile knowledge and faith was no longeracknowledged as affecting the standpoint and the outlookof philosophy.The sphere of science, based on sense experience andinference, on the one side, and, on the other, the sphereof religion based on revelation, seemed perfectly sepa-rated, an eternal peace between them seemed achieved.But this is only the outer impression which' deceives thespectator. It is not the inner truth of the state of modernman. Here in his inner life he is divided against himself.Intellect and heart are not in harmony with each other.Their sound order is disturbed. Man has to decidewhether he will trust the guide of science and scientificphilosophy or the guide of revealed religion. No clearrelation exists between these opposite poles. Has sciencethe primacy or has faith the primacy? This is the ques-tion.

    Philosophy can and should contribute its resources tothe task of restoring and reconciling man with himselfagain. Religion has a legitimate right to interfere withphilosophy, when ultimate questions concerning the mean-ing of life and reality are raised, as religion or religioustheology should admit that philosophy is entitled and evenobliged to participate in the endeavor to fathom thedepths of deity. The calamitous chasm between theseparties should be filled by mutual good wilL Both have a

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    28/254

    jo THE PRIMACY OF FAITHcommon interest at stake, both the theologian and thephilosopher are actually persons involved in both religionand philosophy, because they are both feeling and think-ing beings. Philosophy must abstain from the attempt toreplace religion, or to deliver a theology which requiresno revelation, as the natural theology of the eighteenthcentury did. It has to forego the temptation to regard reli-gion as a lower form of metaphysical insight. Philosophyand religion are different paths to the same destination.Religion is superior in a certain sense, because God is amystery, and because the language of religion is betteradapted to the nature of this mystery than is the languageof philosophy. On the other hand, philosophy is superiorin respect to the rational side of theological method. Reli-gious theology, therefore, must cease regarding as con-temptible the share which philosophy can contribute tothe common task.When Lord Gifford, the founder of these lectures,wrote the regulations concerning their content andmethod, a generation existed which still believed in thepossibility of natural theology as a strictly natural science.This science, he says, should be treated "without refer-ence to or reliance upon any supposed special exceptionalor so-called miraculous revelation. I wish it consideredjust as astronomy or chemistry is." Times have changed.It is unlikely that a thinker today would strive to initiatea theology in the fashion and with the methods of chemis-try or astronomy. We feel again that God is a hiddenGod, and that the natural and the supernatural cannot betreated in the same manner. Even when we think it pos-sible to approach the divine by means of thought withoutrelying upon any religious source, we can no longer ignorethe gap between the physical and the metaphysical realms.It is no longer admissible to think of God in terms of

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    29/254

    BIBLICAL AND NATURAL THEOLOGY nnatural causality or substantiality. And, therefore, th'equestion whether any science or any human knowledgeabout God is possible at all can no longer be answered inthe affirmative without severe consideration and inquiry.Was Kant not right in forbidding such a science alto-gether? Is any philosopher entitled to return to naturaltheology after having studied Kant's criticism of allknowledge of the Supreme Being? And are not perhapsthose Christian theologians right who assert that there isno access to the divine mystery save through divine revela-tion?

    Natural theology is threatened by two powerful andallied foes, one of them undertaking to destroy it fromwithin by means of rational criticism, the other from with-out by means of faith and dogmatics. Critical or anti-metaphysical philosophy and anti-philosophical theologyunite in opposing all attempts of pure reason to inquireinto the mystery of God. Nevertheless the attempt mustbe renewed. Perhaps never before has it been so necessary,so urgent to renew it as today. For never before has thechasm between faith and secular culture widened so dan-gerously. The illness of our culture cannot be cured exceptby reconciling the sundered parts of the human mind andof human society. Philosophy must participate in this taskby showing that there is a bridge between faith and rea-son, that there is a natural theology in the sense of arational or speculative discipline which is in agreementwith Biblical theology. On the other hand, it does notsuffice to repeat the content of faith and to re-establishdogma without taking into consideration the judgmentof pure reason. Too many people have lost their confi-dence in tradition and no longer understand the truth ofrevealed religion unsupported by philosophical thought.Such a system of thought, it is true, can never supersede

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    30/254

    12 THE PRIMACY OF FAITHor generate faith ; but it can justify and reinforce the reli-gious outlook, it can disclose the inner alliance of faithand reason, of imaginative and abstract knowledge. Inthese lectures I shall first discuss this problem and its solu-tion within the philosophy of Kant. I should like to addsome remarks about the verdict on rational theology deliv-ered by the most rigorous modern representative of anexclusively scriptural standpoint, Karl Earth.

    It is a real merit of Karl Earth to have rediscoveredthe logical consistency and strength of reformed theology.The level of the discussion is elevated by his emphasison this classical virtue. The Barthian theology has sharp-ened the conscience of the philosopher trying to maintaina rational theology, and it has deepened the understand-ing of what revelation and the word of God mean. Butphilosophy should not be discouraged by the stern atti-tude of the dogmatic thinker and by his inexorable rejec-tion of all philosophic collaboration in the field of theo-logical knowledge. The dogmatic theologian is perfectlyright in defending the dominion of religious tradition. Hefails, however, to keep his claim legitimate when he beginsto contest the right of philosophy to deal with theologicalproblems in its own way. He transgresses the limit whichhe has himself laid when he judges about problems whichcan never arise as long as he remains on the ground ofbiblical revelation.

    Only he who believes in the necessity and in the possi-bility of uniting biblical and natural (or rational) the-ology is able and entitled to determine what contributioncan be given by philosophy to theology and where philos-ophy loses its power.4 Even if it be true that the Bible, as

    4 C Clemens Alexandrinus: "But if we are not to philosophize, whatthen? For no one can condemn a thing without first knowing it Conse-quently we must philosophize.'* (Stromata, Book VI, Chap. XVIII.)

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    31/254

    BIBLICAL AND NATURAL THEOLOGY 13the word of God, is the purest source of religious knowl-edge and the only genuine basis of faith, it does not followthat theological knowledge cannot be attained also bymeans of speculative thought. Biblical theology, keepingwithin the bounds of biblical revelation, cannot envisagethe scope of possible philosophic solutions in any field,not even in the field of speculative theology. The dog-matic theologian cannot inquire into the possibility ofapproaching the divine mystery by means of thought,because, as a dogmatic theologian, he has never exploredthe conditions and the limits of rational speculation. It isperfectly true that God, as He reveals Himself in theBible, cannot be met by such speculation. He is a person,and thought or reason cannot meet a person, even if itshould be possible to answer the question whether or notGod must be thought of as a person. But the problem con-cerning the relation of the different levels of religiousrevelation and rational speculation lies outside the pos-sible considerations and decisions of dogmatic theology.The biblical point of view does not forbid reasoningabout God, the world, and man. To be sure, the Bible doesnot permit any doubt as to the ability of man to reach ulti-mate truth. The Bible denies man's ability to solve allproblems by asserting that there is an impenetrable andinscrutable mystery. But the Bible does not say how farhuman understanding can penetrate this mystery. It hintsat the limit when it warns that God's thoughts are not ourthoughts or that we cannot see God face to face as long aswe live on earth. But this imaginative distinction is notconfined to the contrast of revelation and speculation; onthe contrary, it characterizes even revealed knowledge asinsufficient. If it is true that God has created man in hisimage, then we should be permitted to use the mentalpower which He has given to us in order to seek for traces

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    32/254

    14 THE FJRJLMACY

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    33/254

    BIBLICAL AND NATURAL THEOLOGY 15be answered. Thus, it is clear that dogmatic theology andspeculative philosophy, though they are striving after thesame ideal of truth in the same field of knowledge, never-theless have different standards of logical perfection.Dogmatic theology is neither able nor entitled to prejudicethe results of philosophic reflection. The difference ofprinciples and methods and of the spheres from whichthey issue makes the task of the unification of the twodifferent ways of theology hazardous and toilsome.

    Karl Earth denies categorically and "dogmatically"that there is any access to the mystery of God save theword of God Himself, as revealed in the Bible. God is aliving God, His will is a free will ; therefore the only wayof meeting Him is the way of hearing and obeying Hiscommandments. Man has no power to open the holyshrine of truth; God alone keeps the key. We have noadequate notion of God; God can never become the objectof any human science. If He could, man would be ableto "dispose" of God, whereas God instead disposes ofman. "An idea, made up with the claim to be the idea ofGod, is, not as an idea, but on account of this claim anidol. Even the idea of God as conceived by Plato, a reallypure idea which can almost fascinate by its purity, cannotbe exempted from this verdict." 5

    Is that verdict justified? Why does Plato fascinate KarlEarth as-he has fascinated so vast a number of Christiantheologians at all epochs in every country? Does not thisfascination suggest the point where the Platonic and theChristian knowledge of God coincide to a certain degree?If that holds good, how is it possible that purely humanknowledge can find a way to an idea of God consistentwith that which is revealed by God Himself? Neither

    s Die kirchliche Dogmatik, Bd. I, Halbbd. I, z. AufL, Munchen 1935,p. 412.

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    34/254

    16 THE PRIMACY OF FAITHreligious theology alone nor philosophical or natural the-ology alone can answer this question. On the other hand,the Christian theologian, as well as the worldly thinker,is urged to put this question, like Clement, the firstthinker, who tried to combine Greek philosophy andChristian faith.Of course, Karl Earth is perfectly right when he points

    out that despite the fascination emanating from the pla-tonic doctrine of the supreme idea of the Good, no ideawhatsoever can take the place of the living God. If we re-place the living God by a philosophic idea, we really deifyour idea, making it an idol. Such a deification has to beduly rejected not only by the dogmatist but by everyChristian thinker. On the other hand, the dogmatist iscompelled to speak of the mystery of God and to admitthat his knowledge of God is limited as is that of thephilosopher. Were either of them entitled to claim unre-stricted knowledge, he then could contest the right of theother to claim any knowledge of God at all, as Earth infact does. But neither Earth nor the philosopher canlegitimately claim exclusive right. Neither one can knowhow far knowledge can reach1 in this sublime field. It is asimpossible to imprison the divine in a dogmatic theologyas it is impossible to confine the highest Being within thelimits of a speculative metaphysics. We can and must ap-proach theological knowledge in two different ways, andwe do not know how these two ways are connected in thedivine itself, for we cannot carry either to completion.Both lead into the darkness of mystery.

    Karl Barth' defines dogmatics as "the rational endeavorto grasp the divine mystery." "The more serious," hesays, "this endeavor is, the more it will end in under-standing or conceiving the divine mystery as a mystery.Therefore it can be worth while to devote oneself to this

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    35/254

    BIBLICAL AND NATURAL THEOLOGY 17endeavor." 6 Precisely the same is true in the case ofphilosophical or natural theology. The word or term"mystery" indicates in both cases the same fact, that wecannot penetrate to the final end of knowledge. There issomething that God has not revealed and that cannot berevealed as long as we live on earth; and there is alsomuch that cannot be grasped by means of thought. It isjust this "something" which makes possible the duality ofrevelation and reason, of imaginative and notional knowl-edge, of positive and natural theology. Neither waynor form of knowledge is adequate in the last analysis.The inadequacy of each of them demands and permits thelegitimacy of the other. They supplement each other. Butwe cannot fully understand how, since we do not know thefinal end of either way, which is their common end. It isthis insight which reconciles them, although it is not pos-sible to unify them completely nor to derive the dualityfrom one and the same highest insight or principle.

    All these statements are based on one definite presuppo-sition, namely, that man has access to the divine mystery,not only through revelation, but also through his own un-derstanding and reason. Dogmatic theology cannot refutethis presupposition, as Karl Earth declares. Th'e divinemystery has two different aspects according to the twoforms of knowledge or approach. We can call them theaspect of personality, and the aspect of universality. Thedivine, as revealed or revealing Himself, is a living per-son ; as conceived in the realm of abstract knowledge, Heis universal truth. Or in other words : universal truth, asrevealed in the Bible, is God; God, as conceived in or byour understanding, is universal truth.

    But these definitions are not yet complete and perfect,though they are not erroneous ; they demand further in-

    6 I.e. p. 388.

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    36/254

    i8 THE PRIMACY OF FAITHvestigation and analysis. Barth has too low an idea ofwhat philosophy is and aims at doing, when he categori-cally rejects the claim of philosophy to deal with thedivine mystery. Reading his dogmatics, one has the defi-nite impression that he knows only the alternative betweenrevelation and the trivial consciousness of ordinary life.As a dogmatist, nay, as a Christian, he is right in dividingthe sacred from the profane, the eternal from the tem-poral, the spiritual from the rational, but this dichotomy isnot complete. If it is true that man can approach the divinemystery along the path of rational inquiry, then a par-ticular sphere of human activity, though profane in thehighest religious sense, is nevertheless not included in hisbifurcation. The profane sphere is not uniform; it con-tains various strata, lower and higher stages. The higheststage neighbors the sacred sphere

    and in the boundary lineboth spheres seem to overlap. May we say that religionleads from God to man, philosophy from man to God?Religion does not attain the rationality of philosophy,philosophy does not reach the personality of God. Butthere is a meeting point between the extremes. Could wetake our stand at this point, we should be able to reconcilethe antagonistic views of dogmatic and natural theology.In any case, the two opposite ways have one commonground: this is the mystery of the divine. But, unfortu-nately, the character of mystery allows us no footing;mystery affords no ground for an argument nor a premisethat can yield a train of deductions. On the contrary,mystery destroys all arguments, it deprives us of the solidground on which we, as thinkers, can stand. Both biblicaland natural theology confront ultimate problems they can-not solve and even contradictions they cannot evade. It isa contradiction in itself th'at knowledge should be rootedin mystery, The very phrase "knowledge of the divine

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    37/254

    BIBLICAL AND NATURAL THEOLOGY 19mystery" is baffling. How can mystery be the object ofknowledge ? Is it not by its very nature the unknowable ?Thus, do not knowledge and mystery exclude each other?

    It seems to be extremely difficult, if not completely im-possible, to find a language common to both kinds of the-ology, or to fix the point at which they would meet. TheChristian theologian cannot speak of the divine as thecontent of a conceptual idea, and the philosopher cannotspeak of God as revealed or revealing Himself in Scrip-ture. How then accomplish the task of reconciling theopponents or of reconciling ourselves in so far as we areat the same time both thinkers and believers, persons en-dowed with an autonomous intellect and children of God?How can we ever hope to unite knowledge and faith, if weare not even able to combine both in one and the samepersonal attitude? With what right can we assert thatnatural and inspired theology aim at the knowledge of thesame ultimate mystery, since we have no access to thismystery except the antagonistic ways of thought andfaith? The point where they would meet lies beyond thegrasp of both. On the other hand, it is the apex to whichboth are striving. The identity of our own self seems toguarantee this identity of the Ultimate. Although the Ulti-mate can never be completely encompassed by either the-ology, in so far as we can conceive of it as the Ultimate,we can be sure that it is one and the same, common toboth the theology of reason and the theology of reve-lation.The fact that each of us is one and the same person

    permits us and even commands us to assert that it is oneand the same divine mystery that confronts us in religionas well as in philosophy. This sameness is the reason reli-gious and philosophic language use one and the samecentral word to express their ultimate goal and concern,

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    38/254

    20 THE PRIMACY OF FAITHthe word: truth. And both know that ultimate truth ishidden, and that neither religious revelation nor meta-physical knowledge can ever contain the full and unre-stricted truth. It is just this immediate awareness whichunites and reconciles both approaches to the Ultimatewithout altering or lessening their differences. Thus thetheology of faith is bound not to render impossible thetheology of thought, while metaphysics is bound not toassert anything that could weaken or diminish the positionof revealed knowledge. Philosophy should be warnednever to forget that there is an ultimate mystery and thatrevelation is the form in which this mystery is brought tous in religion. If philosophy acknowledges the legitimacyof revelation and gives up the vain attempt to make itselfa substitute for it, the path1 to reconciliation is opened. Forit is the task of philosophy, not of religion,

    to bring aboutthis reconciliation, since there is a philosophy of religion,but not a corresponding department within religion. Phi-losophy, in other words, must understand religion, notreligion philosophy. Clemens Alexandrinus became a phi-losopher to do this very thing.Although philosophy must make religion the object of

    reflection, it must respect the line of demarcation betweenthe realms. Thus it must restrict itself. Indeed, it is theconsequence of a right appreciation of religion on the partof philosophy to draw the line which limits the preroga-tive of philosophic reflection. This was the intention ofthe criticism of Kant, and in this respect his standpoint Isa permanent contribution. It is the noblest task of philoso-phy to discover and to exhibit the ultimate mystery in allspheres of human experience ; it is not its task to supplantrevelation by speculation, be it ever so refined. Kant wasright m bridling the aspirations of metaphysics.

    Philosophy must to use an expression of Plato save

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    39/254

    BIBLICAL AND NATURAL THEOLOGY 21the ultimate mystery. It must trace all problems back tomystery. But philosophy is not entitled to violate the char-acter of this mystery by the attempt to transform it intoconceptual knowledge and so to deprive it of its nature.Philosophy does not come to an end: the nature of theUltimate as mystery forbids ultimate solutions. The man-ner in which Plato leads the reader of the dialogues onand on without ever coming to a definite and final desti-nation is consequently more philosophic than is the happyending of other systems. Philosophy not only begins butalso terminates in the feeling of wonder. This feeling isakin to religious awe, indeed it is the same feeling trans-ferred to another domain. Philosophy is the elaborateattempt of the thinking mind to approach the ultimate,all-embracing and all-penetrating mystery, called by theholy book God.Divine mystery is the universal mystery. Th'ere is noth-ing outside it, no being and no idea, no existence and noessence, nothing real and nothing ideal. This is the reasonwhy religion speaks of God as the Creator of the world,and even of Christ as begotten by God, and of the HolySpirit as having proceeded from God; and the reason whythe earliest fathers of the church insisted that even physi-cal matter is created by God, and that there is nothingwhatever that is not created by Him. It has often beensaid that Christianity is dualistic because of the duality ofCreator and creation, Eternity and temporal life, Spiritand flesh, Grace and nature, heaven and hell. That dual-ism is true, but it is only one aspect; in another AspectChristianity is thoroughly monistic, and this aspect isbasic. Christianity is monistic, because it teaches that Godoriginally is all in all, that He alone is the source ofeverything that is or can be, that this world is His, andthat the difference between those opposite sides is no final

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    40/254

    22 THE PRIMACY OF FAITHone. At the end of time He will become again "all in all,"aa idea stressed by Origen. "For of Him, and throughHim, and to Him, are all things." Philosophy achieves itsbest when it tries to understand this monistic and thatdualistic outlook in its own way, and to explain how bothcan be aspects of the same ultimate reality.Karl Earth distinguishes "God in Himself" and "Godfor us," or the "eternal history of God" and "God's reve-lation as history," and frequently admits that the word ofGod, as revealed to us, is always mixed with worldly orhuman elements ; and that dogma has originated from theattempt to formulate biblical revelation in the terms ofcontemporary philosophy.7 Earth thus admits that whatwe know about God in dogmatic theology is always re-stricted by man's capacity to understand God. How canit be justifiable that contemporary philosophy has beenused for the purpose of dogmatics, if there is an irrecon-cilable cleavage between revelation and speculation, holyand profane theological knowledge? Only an inner rela-tionship between the two opponents, only an ultimatelycommon ground can explain and vindicate this fusion.As God's own revelation is necessarily adapted to man'scapacity, conversely man's speculation is necessarilyadapted to the character of the Ultimate as it appearsbefore the thinking mind. Both are determined by ulti-mate truth. Man has not arbitrarily invented or moldedthe possibilities of metaphysical speculation, he hasstamped his concepts in accordance with the exigenciesof the object of speculation, however problematical theseconcepts may be. We are not entitled to say that the Ulti-mate reveals itself in the medium of thought, for thisexpression vitiates the peculiar nature of revelation anddoes not characterize the real method of speculation; but,

    7 I.e. pp. 171 ff., 359, 399.

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    41/254

    BIBLICAL AND NATURAL THEOLOGY 23on the other hand, we must remain aware of the parallel-ism between natural and revealed theology. As dogmaand dogmatics are influenced by contemporary philoso-phy, so was philosophy influenced by contemporary the-ology, not only in the Middle Ages, but also in moderntimes, in Locke and Berkeley, in Descartes and Leibniz,in Kant and his successors.To be sure, natural theology underwent momentousalterations during its development from ancient times. Itwas severely criticized by Kant, and it seemed condemnedto death by his verdict. Is this doom final ? To answer thisquestion we must carefully examine the Critique of PureReason.

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    42/254

    CHAPTER IIKant's Critique of Natural Theology

    THE MEDIEVAL harmony between philosophy and religion,natural and sacred theology, reason and revelation, hasundergone two heavy attacks in modern times which haveradically disrupted it. The first attack was made fromthe side of religion, the second from the side of philoso-phy. Luther and Kant were the initiators respectively.They had the same target, they rejected purely intellec-tual or theoretical knowledge in the field of theology; or,in other words, they denied the validity of Greek thoughtin this field.1 Their arguments and even their motiveswere different, and so also the results they accomplished.Luther fought against human reason in general so far asit was not supported and inspired by the word of God.Kant strove against the primacy of theoretical speculationin the whole fabric of human valuations and propagated,instead, the primacy of practical or ethical reason. Theinterest of Luther was dictated by his belief in the activityof God alone; the interest of Kant by his critique of purereason. An immense gap separates these outlooks, the gapbetween two different ages. Luther was rooted in medi-eval ground, Kant was spokesman for the modern spirit.But this modern day begins already to decline. We nolonger believe so much in man as did the contemporariesof Kant. We begin to realize again that faith in the power

    1 Luther expressed strongly and often coarsely his animosity againstGreek philosophy and philosophy in general. "Philosophy," he writes as ayoung man, "is an old woman that stinks of Greece."

    24

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    43/254

    CRITIQUE OF NATURAL THEOLOGY 25of God is the basis even of man's own power and ofreason's achievements. Therefore we must stress oncemore the religious outlook, without cancelling the benefitsbequeathed by Kant. We must attain a new harmony be-tween religion and philosophy. This task cannot beachieved by going back to any former position, be it thatof Thomas Aquinas or Augustine. We must not forfeitthe advantages of Kant's. Critique.

    It is an astonishing paradox in the history of the Euro-pean mind that it was the Christian Church which propa-gated the ancient or pagan philosophy by resuming, first,Platonic and Neoplatonic schemes of thought, and thenrenewing the Aristotelian philosophy, while the succeed-ing modern epoch, which was in so many respects morepagan than Christian, rejected the ancient forms ofthought and created, step by step,

    a philosophy that wasborn out of the Christian conscience as rediscovered inProtestantism. This new philosophic movement reachedits summit and found its maturest interpreter in Kant.The key to the understanding of this paradox is the factthat Greek, and especially Aristotelian, thought, thoughtheological^ nevertheless is not originally Christian, whilemodern, and especially Kantian, thought, though nottheological, nevertheless is essentially Christian.

    It was protestant piety which abandoned the patternsof ancient philosophy and discovered a new method ofthought. The protestant faith protested not only againstcatholic faith but also against catholic theology and phi-losophy. The protest against catholic philosophy reachedits consummation in Kant's critique of natural theology,for this theology was an integral part of scholasticism.Scholasticism asserted the possibility of rational knowl-edge of God in agreement with the Christian faith. Itfollowed the dictum of Augustine: "Si sapientia Deus est,

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    44/254

    26 THE PRIMACY OF FAITHper quern fdcta sunt omnia, sicut divina auctoritas

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    45/254

    CRITIQUE OF NATURAL THEOLOGY 27and highest manifestations. Religious sects, descendedfrom philosophical systems or cults, were overpowered bythe growing Christian community. It was not until Kantthat the implications of this situation were realized in therealm of philosophic study. He was the first to under-stand by purely philosophic means why Christian faithhad been able to triumph over Greek philosophy, by show-ing the limit of pure reason in the realm of speculativetheology. He defeated speculation in its own strongholdand by its own methods : it is pure reason that criticisespure reason in Kant's Critique.

    Although philosophy was called the handmaiden oftheology throughout the Middle Ages, the real relationbetween speculative philosophy and Christian theologyduring those centuries is not accurately described by thatstatement; for though it is true that theology was themaster in the house of scholastic philosophy, this theologyitself was mastered by speculation and by categories de-rived from Greek thought.2 Aristotle and not the Gospelwas victorious in scholasticism. The philosophic develop-ment from Augustine to Thomas exhibits the ever-increas-ing adoption of thought elements originally and essentiallyforeign to the Christian faith, the growing self-estrange-ment of the basic attitude of prophetic religion. It marksa period of an ever-advancing secularization of theologi-cal thought. Luther, therefore, opposed scholasticism ashe opposed the whole tendency of that development. AndKant finally gave philosophy a new foundation with faithas its basis.

    2 I agree in principle with the intentions of Etienne Gilson as expoundedin Christianity and Philosophy (1939), but I do not agree with the thesisthat the medieval philosophy is the only right form of a "Christian philos-ophy." On the contrary, this philosophy, as based on the ancient categories,is not yet tinged by the Christian attitude towards reason as Kant'sphilosophy is.

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    46/254

    28 THE PRIMACY OF FAITHTo be sure, Kant's accomplishment should be qualified,

    because his criticism of rational theology did not imme-diately serve the Christian faith but instead a rationalfaith based on practical (moral) reason. And in this re-spect Kant's philosophic standpoint is more remote fromthe Christian faith than the scholastic system had been inspite of the latter's Aristotelian foundation. Confusingand interwoven are the historical motives and trends inthe development of European thought. A real Christianphilosophy, therefore, has not yet been written. One mustagree perfectly with Karl Earth when he says, that allendeavor to create a Christian philosophy has failed sofar, and that the thinkers who aimed at such a philosophyproduced "either a real and then no Christian or else aChristian and then no real philosophy." 3

    Kant's "critique of all theology,based upon speculative

    principles" intended to destroy forever all purely rationalknowledge of God. Kant shows that no extension of thecategories which make experience, and therefore science,in the empirical world possible, can be permitted in orderto attain knowledge of things beyond that world. We areable to explore causal relation in the world of sense, be-cause our intellect connects the sense data according tothe rule of temporal sequence. But in the field of thesupernatural, or the divine, no sense data are at our dis-posal and, therefore, no use of the rational rules or formsof connection is possible. Thus no rational knowledge ofGod, no natural theology can be achieved. If we try toattain knowledge of God by rational means, then weensnare ourselves in mere illusions. Kant expressed thisdoctrine in an extremely sceptical fashion; he vehementlydenied the right and the ability of reason to attain to anylegitimate knowledge of God.

    3 l.c. p. 4-

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    47/254

    CRITIQUE OF NATURAL THEOLOGY 29Kant derives the idea of God from the imperfection of

    all empirical knowledge. No empirical object can ever beperfectly known because we have no adequate intuitionof the sum total of all material conditions which deter-mine the reality of any entity in the empirical world. Ourempirical knowledge is always fragmentary and can neverbe complete. Even the idea of an end of our knowledgeis hypothetical because the very nature of infinity contra-dicts the possibility of such an end. Nevertheless ourreason is bound to conceive of the absolute perfection ofour knowledge as the practical goal of all our scientificstriving. We need the idea of the end of our striving asan ideal of reason. Kant calls this ideal "transcendental"because it transcends the horizon of the empirical world,and of empirical knowledge altogether.The transcendental ideal represents a problem never tobe solved by knowledge. It contains the positive determi-nations of all things real and possible, therefore it hasrightly been called the "ens realissimum" i.e., the mostreal thing. If we hypostatise and personify this ideal, ittakes the shape of a highest being or of the being of allbeings, in other words, of God. But this hypostasis andpersonification is in no way justified by reason. "In anysuch use of the transcendental idea we should, moreover,be overstepping the limits of its purpose and validity. Forreason, in employing it as a basis for the complete deter-mination of things, has used it only as the concept of allreality, without requiring that all this reality be objec-tively given and that it be itself an existing thing. Sucha thing is a mere fiction in which we combine and realisethe manifold of our idea in an ideal, as an individual'being. But we have no right to do this, nor even to assumethe possibility of such an hypothesis. Nor do any of theconsequences which flow from such an ideal have any bear-

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    48/254

    30 THE PRIMACY OF FAITHing upon the complete determination of things, or exercisein that regard the least influence. . . ." 4

    In accordance with this sceptical attitude Kant deniesthe validity of any proof of the existence of God by theo-retical means, or by means of speculation. All theseproofs are completely illusory, as Kant shows in detail.Even if we were rightly entitled to grasp the idea of Godin the way mentioned, we are not allowed to assert theexistence of the object of this idea. To assert that an indi-vidual being exists, demands the real or possible experi-ence of this being, the possibility of its appearance, andwe have no means of assuring such a possibility; on thecontrary, it is excluded through the very nature of the ideaor concept of this being. Reason alone, moreover, unsup-ported by intuition, cannot deduce the existence of any-thing, for existence is no rational predicate at all; it is apredicate that demands the context of a possible experi-ence to be attributed to an idea or to its object. Thetranscendental ideal is an ideal only, it is no real thing;this is as much as theoretical or speculative knowledge canaffirm.

    Kant's verdict against all speculative theology is relent-less. "Our understanding is in no way fitted" for it.5 Kantdiscloses the abysmal depth of human ignorance in thisfield of knowledge.6 There is a boundary line between ourmental faculty of understanding on the one hand, andreligion, on the other hand, between reason and faith.Reason can never transcend this line. Kant criticises

    4 Cr. of P.R., B 608 (A 580).3 l.c. B 664. (A 636).6 In a footnote to the chapter on the transcendental Ideal Kant speaks

    of the great value of discoveries concerning our ignorance. "The observa-tions and calculations of astronomers have taught us much that is wonder-ful j but the most important lesson that they have taught us has been byrevealing the abyss of our ignorance, which otherwise we could neverhave conceived to be so great. . . ." (Cr. of P.R., B 603.)

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    49/254

    CRITIQUE OF NATURAL THEOLOGY 31reason, as he says in the preface to the second edition, "inorder to make room for faith." His scepticism in no wayextends to religion, it concerns our human knowledge only.It is a scepticism directed against theorizing about God,by no means against our belief in the existence of God.Kant sharply separates theoretical knowledge and reli-gious belief. Belief is, as Kant's doctrine of rational faithdefines it, the attitude of practical or moral, not the atti-tude of theoretical or speculative, reason. To save and todefend faith against all possible scepticism, Kant smashesall arrogant knowledge in the field which sensation andperception can never reach.

    "Pure" reason is purely negative. It can criticise itselfbut it cannot produce any real knowledge. The religioussource of Kant's attitude is Protestantism. Luther's doc-trine that faith, and faith alone, can constitute man's re-lationship to God has found an adequate philosophic allyand its expression in Kant's Critique. While medievalCatholicism had brought about a system in which natureand grace, world and God, reason and revelation, were in-tegral parts, supplementing each other, so that the wholewas in perfect equilibrium in spite of the gap between theparts, Protestantism stressed the fact of tfie gap. Whilethe catholic system reconciled the oppositions by meansof a hierarchy which mediated between the lowest andthe highest spheres in accordance with the neoplatonictype of philosophy, Protestantism emphasized the missionof God's word and of Christ as the only mediator be-tween God and man, and thus generated the Kantian typeof philosophy. v

    Protestantism rediscovered the paradoxical characterof the Christian creed, and opposed it to the orthodoxcharacter of the scholastic system. The fact was empha-sized anew, that the Gospel is called a stumbling block

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    50/254

    32 THE PRIMACY OF FAITHand foolishness. Instead of the rational reconcilation be-tween revelation and speculation effected by Thomism,Protestantism restated the impossibility of reconcilingreason with the nature of God's mystery.7 In Kant'sTranscendental Dialectic this new (and old) religiousoutlook is reflected. Unavoidable antinomies, naturalparalogisms, fatal illusions bar the way to the throne ofthe Highest for human understanding. Reason must ca-pitulate to faith. Christian dialectic, as it appears in theparables of Jesus or in utterances of Paul, has not only thesame implication as Kant's dialectic, but is also akin to itin spirit. Both point to the divine mystery which cannotbe revealed without contradiction, and which thereforetranscends the rational sphere.Of course there is an important difference between theparadox of faith and the anti-dogmatic content of Kant'sphilosophy. Both agree in restricting human understand-ing, but while faith uses the paradox to express a truththat transcends its limits, Kant uses criticism to a purelynegative end, at least for the possibility of human knowl-edge. There is no "dialectical method" whereby positivetruth may be discovered. Kant does not exalt the "law ofcontradiction" in order to express truth as Hegel does.Kant does not establish a philosophic "paradox." On thecontrary, he believes that he can explain why humanunderstanding necessarily comes to contradictions, and inwhat way the contradictions are to be solved, namely, byrestriction of our knowledge.

    Is Kant's verdict a final one? Has his Critique anni-hilated speculative theology for all time? Does his nega-tive attitude bind us still? Is no reconciliation possible

    7 This character of Protestantism has been pronounced with a newvigor in our days by Karl Barth, Reinhold Niebuhr, Paul Tillich andother theologians.

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    51/254

    CRITIQUE OF NATURAL THEOLOGY 33between speculation and faith? Is it true, that all naturaltheology, from Aristotle to Hegel, from Clement toThomas, was based on logical fallacies? Is the gap be-tween reason and faith as deep and abrupt as Kantasserts ? These questions we must discuss in order to re-constitute natural theology on a new basis.Two items must be taken into consideration for thispurpose. First, the relationship between theoretical (orspeculative) and moral (or practical) reason and knowl-edge; second, the concept of existence as used by Kantwith regard to the transcendental ideal, and rejected byhim. The first item cannot be considered in full untilKant's doctrine of the primacy of practical reason and ofrational faith has been developed in the next lecture. Onepoint, however, may be mentioned here. The completeseparation of mental faculties or of different phases of hu-man reason is, though old in substance, more emphasizedand developed by Kant than ever before. Of course, thedivision of problems into theoretical and practical hasbeen classical since Aristotle. But Aristotle's metaphysicsis far from being purely theoretical in the sense of Kant.On the contrary, Aristotle's doctrine concerning the exist-ence and the nature of God combines precisely the func-tions of both theoretical and practical reason, or the view-points of logic, physics, and ethics. God is not only purespeculative reason ; as the prime mover of the world, he isalso the highest good. It is true, God's actuality is, ac-cording to Aristotle, the actuality not of the will, but ofthought, and he is good in the highest degree, b'ecausehe is this actuality in the highest degree. "It is throughthinking that its value belongs to it." 8 On the other hand,"God thinks of that which is most divine and precious."The highest good which is represented by this actuality is

    8 Met 1074 b. Transl. by W. D. Ross, Oxford, 1928.

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    52/254

    34 THE PRIMACY OF FAITHthe theoretical and moral order of the world, or theworld's unity. In this respect he is the mover of bothnature and the moral world, without being moved, as theobject of desire and of thought; as this object he is desirednot arbitrarily, but because he is "in itself desirable," andaccordingly the best in every regard.9

    It is difficult if not impossible to compare Kant withAristotle without analyzing all the terms which both use,and it cannot be the task of this lecture to engage in suchan analysis. But it can be maintained that Aristotle is farfrom thinking of God in the fashion criticised by Kant. Theconcept of God as designed by Aristotle is not the conceptof all reality hypostatised and personified in an individualbeing; it is rather the concept of the thinking mind, freedfrom all restrictions which characterise the human mind.It is not the concept of a thing that is personified; it isthat of a person who is nothing but a thinking mind. Aris-totle emphasizes the actuality or the act of thought, inwhich God thinks the unchangeable, immovable, eternaltruth1 , the full truth, all truth. God is this truth, he is whathe thinks, and he thinks what he is. Truth is thus theactuality of thought. It is not really a thing, it is life, asAristotle says. These determinations are not contained inKant's concept of the transcendental ideal. Kant is notreflecting on the act and activity of thought when hecriticises the speculative theology of the ens realissimum,

    9 Met. 1072 a. Aristotle proclaims a kind of supremacy of thought overdesire, and so a kind of supremacy of theoretical over practical activity,but this doctrine does not imply a primacy of theoretical over practicalreason, instead it means the primacy of reason over desire. "Thought," asapplied to the knowledge of God and to God's nature is, according toAristotle, not "theoretical" in the sense Kant uses the term, it is rathertheoretical and practical as well. God is the highest good and the highesttruth at the same time. Aristotle's theology is the result of the combinationof metaphysics and ethics; both become one and the same "thought" inGod.

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    53/254

    CRITIQUE OF NATURAL THEOLOGY 35or of all reality as itself an individual thing. Pure reasonas criticised by Kant is thus a special type of reason, butnot reason unqualified.This deficiency in Kant's treatment of speculative the-ology is connected with the second problem that shouldbe taken into consideration, namely with the concept ofexistence as a predicate of the ens realissimum. Kant issurely right in insisting on the impossibility of positing theexistence of an individual being by means of thought only.But he goes too far when he deals with the transcendentalideal as an ideal of human reason only, as if no kind ofobjective reality could be attributed to it. It may be truethat we have no objective intuition to fill the idea of theens realissimum^ and that even this idea in itself, i.e., itsconnotation, is questionable; nevertheless it cannot bedenied or doubted that something must needs corre-spond to this problematic idea, something that not onlybelongs to the human mind or reason, but to the natureof being itself. The necessity which forces upon us theidea of the highest being is not a psychological one, it is alogical or ontological necessity. We may not know any-thing about the nature of the object of this idea, nay, wemay even be obliged to admit that the content of the ideais "hypothetical" or problematic, nevertheless the idea isobjectively necessary, for we know that truth about em-pirical objects cannot be fully obtained without that de-termination which is assumed to be contained in the objectof this idea.

    In other and simpler words : if it is not true that some-thing exists which corresponds to the object of the prob-lematic idea, then nothing at all can exist. If we call thissomething "God," then we can conclude that the existenceof "God" is the necessary condition of 'the existence ofeverything that exists. Reason must appeal to "God" as

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    54/254

    36 THE PRIMACY OF FAITHthe highest instance of all knowledge, simply because thename of God represents the highest goal of all knowl-edge: the goal of truth. The idea of truth is the pointwhere epistemological and ontological thought convergeand mingle.To be sure, if we reserve the concept "existence" to in-dividual things and beings only, then we must admit thatreason cannot grant the existence of God as the object ofthe transcendental idea. God cannot be thought of as anindividual. But is this impossibility a lack of insight on thepart of reason or thought? Is it not, on the contrary, areal insight that God is not to be known as an object ofexperience; that He is not on the same level as a stone, aplant or an animal, not even at the level of the heavenlybodies which Aristotle and even Origen put in Hisvicinity? If Kant had denied the existence of God in thisrestricted sense only, then he would obviously have beenright. But he was not right in regarding the impossibilityof thinking of God in this fashion as a deficiency of reason.It is not a deficiency of the human mind that it cannotperceive God like other empirical things, for God doesnot belong to that order.

    Is Kant then right in saying that there is no objective,theoretical knowledge of God at all? He would be right,if he confined the meaning of objective, theoretical knowl-edge to the scientific realm alone. Such a determinationwould not exclude a knowledge of God which, though notobjective, nevertheless would be theoretical in the samesense in which the Critique itself is theoretical. TheCritique does not contain objective scientific knowledge orknowledge of the objective world, but rather knowledgeof knowledge or self-knowledge of knowledge. Is not per-haps the knowledge of God, if there be such, akin to thisself-knowledge? If that should prove correct, then it

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    55/254

    CRITIQUE OF NATURAL THEOLOGY 37would follow that Kant had not destroyed speculativetheology altogether. He destroyed a special kind ofrational theology, the kind which dealt with God in thesame way as science deals with matter and natural powers,as if God were a thing like other things in space and time.He destroyed that kind of theology which proceeded byanalogy with the natural sciences. And thus he destroyedthe natural theology founded by Aristotle and maintainedby all his followers. For Aristotle, although he recog-nized God as a thinking spirit, nevertheless determinedthe concept of the divine, not by means of self-reflection,but instead by means of objective knowledge and infer-ence : God is the prime mover of the world, He is a thinglike all other things, belonging to the same world ofobjects as natural things, though possessed of a specialessence. All successors of Aristotle in the Middle Agesheld to this standpoint in principle; Leibniz, indeed, wasstill following his model. Kant was the first to expose theradical failure of all these attempts.At the same time it must be remarked that neither Aris-totle nor his successors and followers were so blind as notto see the difference between God and finite things inthe world. They saw this difference but they did not suc-ceed in clarifying it sufficiently. In spite of this insufficiencysome insights gained by them are not to be neglected, andKant was surely wrong in annihilating all speculative the-ology because of that mistake which he rightly discovered.He was wrong in identifying all possible speculative the-ology with the type of a science of God which he criticisedbecause it was built up by analogy with the natural sci-ences. Kant was able to separate physics and metaphysicsradically because he discovered the peculiar co-operationof sensation and intellect in the realm of the naturalsciences.

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    56/254

    38 THE PRIMACY OF FAITHAristotle was "speculative" even in the field of physics

    as he was "empirical" in the field of metaphysics. He didnot fully realize the gap between philosophic and empiri-cal, metaphysical and physical knowledge. It is character-istic that his metaphysics contains a theory of the physicaluniverse regarding the solar system, while his physics dealswith the metaphysical problem of space and time. Hismetaphysics is as physical as his physics is metaphysical,if we use the terms in the modern fashion. Kant, onthe other hand, was so eager to analyze scientific knowl-edge that the very concept of knowledge blended with thespecial kind required by science. Consequently he feltobliged to deny the legitimacy of all rational knowledge ofGod altogether, not acknowledging that speculative the-ology at all times was more, or was something else thanmerely a branch of science in the sense inquired into bythe Critique of Pure Reason.Now a most serious and grave question arises : is anyother speculative theology possible if reason avoids theway in which Aristotle and all his followers have pro-ceeded? Is it possible to retain the Aristotelian type oftheology after having purified and purged it of those ele-ments which can no longer be retained? The mere refer-ence to the knowledge validated by Kant's Critique itself(to the reflective knowledge of knowledge) cannot suffice.This knowledge, though surely not scientific (that is, notempirical in the sense of the natural sciences), is notspeculative (that is, not metaphysical in the Aristoteliansense of theology) either. It has human knowledge as itssubject matter, not God. It is a metaphyslc of knowledgeor an epistemology and not a metaphysic of being or anontology. Is it possible to graft this kind of epistemologi-cal knowledge upon the subject matter of theology? Isthere any inner connection between the activity of our own

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    57/254

    CRITIQUE OF NATURAL THEOLOGY 39understanding and the concept of God? Is there anyaccess to God through knowledge from the standpoint ofepistemological self-knowledge ?At first sight it seems as if this question should be an-swered in the negative. What a difference between ourown way of acquiring knowledge concerning the objects asthey appear in space and time, i.e., our empirical knowl-edge as analyzed and justified by the Critique, and Godas we know Him in the Bible! How is it possible to con-struct a bridge over this chasm? Is it possible at all? Theactivity of our own understanding in building up empiricalknowledge can be experienced in a certain way. It is,though no empirical object (in the sense of the naturalsciences), nevertheless an object of reflective experience,moreover of an experience which is concerned indirectlywith empirical objects. God, on the contrary, does notbelong to the realm of this inner experience. Should Aris-totle's determination of God as "thought of thought*'prove true, even then a speculative theology based on theself-reflection of the human understanding is not possible.The human self and the self of God cannot be inquiredinto by means of the same method. There is no possiblereflection on the self of God from the standpoint of man.Even if it were true that the nature of God is, as Aris-totle asserts, an everlasting activity of self-knowledge,this self-knowledge could never become our own self-knowledge I

    If there were, on the other hand, no connection be-tween our empirical knowledge and the idea of God, thenKant would never have spoken at all of this matter inhis metaphysic of knowledge. He would never have criti-cised speculative theology, if a close connection did notexist between our empirical cognition and the idea of God.Indeed, there exists such a coherence between them. The

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    58/254

    40 THE PRIMACY OF FAITHtranscendental ideal as introduced by Kant means noth-ing but the ideal of all empirical cognition; it means'the idea of an absolute completion and perfection ofknowledge, or the ideal of perfect truth. Kant rejects theknowledge of God on the ground that this ideal can neverbe achieved by means of objective knowledge. He is rightin this respect. But he forgets that the ideal of perfecttruth transcends the limit of objective knowledge in anycase, that it is not the limit of the human mind which for-bids an objective knowledge of God but rather the natureof God who is no object and cannot become the objecteven of the most perfect objective knowledge! Kant doesnot realize that the ideal of an absolute completion of allempirical (scientific) knowledge leads beyond the entiresphere of all empirical objects; or in other words, thatthis ideal concerns not so much the completion of allempirical knowledge alone but the completion of the meta-physic of knowledge (of self-reflection or self-knowledge)as well. He forgets that, if there is any knowledge of Godat all, this knowledge must be constructed by analogy withself-reflection, since God is no object but a self. Kant wasmisled by the fact that all speculative theology before histime had been constructed as an objective knowledge, thatis, as the knowledge of an object, though of the highestand perfect object; of a thing, though of the most realthing.There is still another reason why the belief in thepossibility of an objective knowledge of God had beenmaintained so long before Kant, and why even Kant him-self did not envisage any other possibility : the existenceof a kind of experience of God which is, though differentfrom, nevertheless akin to, our empirical experience ofnature. I refer to religious experience. Aristotle could be-lieve that it is possible to transform religious knowledge

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    59/254

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    60/254

    42 THE PRIMACY OF FAITHthis knowledge was religious as well as philosophic, re-vealed as well as natural, that is, rational.

    Kant, on the other hand, wanted to restrict knowledgeto "make room for faith." Thus he tried to destroy naturaltheology forever. And he was possessed of the convictionthat all knowledge of God is illusory. He failed thereforeto recognize the deep chasm between the empirical knowl-edge of nature, which he deemed valid, and the rationalknowledge of God which he held illegitimate. The trainof his argumentation can be rendered in the followingsyllogism :

    God is the Supreme Being.The knowledge of real beings requires empirical perception.There is no empirical perception of the Supreme Being.No knowledge of God is possible.This syllogism is quite correct. But Kant is blind to thefact that the knowledge denied by this syllogism would bean empirical knowledge of God, and that such an empiri-cal knowledge if we exclude religious experience andrevealed knowledge is not even to be desired ! Kant doesnot see that the reason why an empirical knowledge ofGod is denied to man should not be sought in man's re-straint, that is, in the restriction of his finite intellect, butrather in the nature of the Infinite Spirit. Not man alone,but no intellect whatsoever can know God or should wantto know God empirically, because God by His very natureis not an empirical object, but the ens realissimum, theIdeal of Reason, the supreme Self. In other words: notman's intellect, not the finite intellect, but rather intellectqua intellect cannot know the living God.

    Should knowledge of God be possible in theoreticalscience, this science would have to be super-empirical or,as Kant uses the term, speculative. God cannot be re-

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    61/254

    CRITIQUE OF NATURAL THEOLOGY 43garded as just another kind of object; He is rather theSupreme Being because He is no object at all, but insteadthe highest, the perfect subject: Infinite Spirit. This truthis not achieved in the Critique of Pure Reason, although itis its necessary conclusion. In his later works, especially inthe Critique of Judgement, Kant worked his way to it.There he conceived of the divine intellect as the perfectintellect which is no longer separated from intuition andtherefore no intellect at all in the human sense. Rather itis a creative spirit. The restrictions of the human intellect,Kant then stated, do not consist in the lack of an empiricalintuition or perception of the Supreme Being, but in thelack of intellectual, super-empirical intuition. The divinespirit is now characterized as possessing a productive in-tuition in himself, or as producing knowledge out of hisown creativity without requiring support from sensationor from corresponding superhuman perception. Manwould understand the divine spirit only if he could pro-duce the knowledge of God in the same way.Kant thus approves of a certain philosophical knowl-edge of God. Indeed, he corroborates and even augmentsthe first entirely repudiated and refuted natural theologyat the end of his career ! He elevates the idea of God overthe level of an ens realissimum, of an all-embracing object,of a thing-in-itself ; he acknowledges that this highest idealof reason is nothing short of the perfect knowing subject,the ideal self of knowledge. He realizes, in other words,that natural theology corresponds not to empirical science,but to reflection on empirical science and on the knowingsubject. God must be conceived, not as an object that wecannot perceive, but as a self that we cannot actualize inourselves because it transcends the limit of human sub-jectivity and the conditions of human activity. The knowl-edge of God is no knowledge of an object, it is God's

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    62/254

    44 THE PRIMACY OF FAITHknowledge of Himself so that He Himself is the only normand the very archetype of truth. This idea reapproachesthe concept of the Aristotelian god. His successors wereencouraged by this idea to venture a new revival of meta-physics on the basis prepared by the criticism of Kant.

    I should like to draw some conclusions important forthe discussions I will pursue in these lectures. God, in sofar as pure reason can attain to a knowledge of Him, isnot an object, not even the sum total of all objects; He israther the all-embracing subject or the ideal self. But Heis not only the self of perfect knowledge, He is also theperfect will; He is creative in both respects, and thereforeno longer a knowing intellect or an acting will in thehuman sense. But we do not know of any other intellector will by experience, and therefore the idea of the divineintellect and the divine will remains problematic; it re-mains the content of a problem, the solution of which isdenied to us. Natural theology is the science of this prob-lematic idea. Though the idea is problematic, it is none-theless of the greatest importance, since it closes the sys-tem of thought not by giving final answers but by showingthe necessity of revelation. Faith supplements what is lack-ing in the field of reason. Revelation delivers what experi-ence lacks, not in the form of another empirical datum asthe theological empiricists would claim (thus destroyingthe fruit of Kant's criticism), but instead in the form ofan experience that is appropriate to the mystical nature ofthe Ultimate.

    Kant did not succeed in appraising the true function ofthe religiously inspired imagination or prophetic con-sciousness because he was and remained throughout hislife a child of the age of reason. He never overcame theprejudices of this age in spite of his discovery of the limitof reason, and in spite of his program to deny knowledge

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    63/254

    CRITIQUE OF NATURAL THEOLOGY 45in order to make room for faith. He persisted on theone hand, in the rejection of all natural theology but, onthe other hand, he did not attain to a just appreciation offaith and revelation, of inspiration and imagination in thereligious realm. These attitudes are connected in a specificway. Since Kant was a representative of the age of reasonhe tried to find a rational road to God. He believed hehad found this road on the plane and within the limitsof moral reason. Thus a moral faith or the "faith of amoralist" ensued from his premises and took the place oftrue religion as well as of natural theology.

    It will be our task to rehabilitate both true religionand true philosophic theology without relapsing into theerrors of former standpoints, be they theistic or deistic,Platonic or Aristotelian, empiristic or rationalistic. Wemust carry through the original program of the philoso-phy of Kant: we must establish the primacy of faith bymeans of philosophical reflection*

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    64/254

    CHAPTER IIIKanfs Doctrine of Rational Faith

    KANT'S CRITIQUE of speculative theology is not his lastword on the problem of the relation of man and God, be-tween philosophy and religion, reason and faith. The mostimportant doctrine concerning this subject is not containedin the Critique of Pure Reason, but in the Critique ofPractical Reason and in Kant's later works. The negativeattitude toward knowledge of God is no longer main-tained in these later books. Kant goes on to admit thatthere is a kind of natural religion which even the criticalstandpoint cannot deny. To be sure, Kant qualifies thenature of this religion in a way which excludes almost allknowledge from it. The right attitude toward God, Kantteaches, is not theoretical, it is practical ; it is an attitudeof the moral will, not of the thinking intellect ; of a faithbased upon a practical need, not upon speculative reasons.uln the whole faculty of reason it is the practical reasononly that can help us to pass beyond the world of sense,and give us knowledge of a supernatural order and con-nection. . . ." *

    This knowledge, however, is a strictly practical one,and ucannot be extended further than is necessary forpure practical purposes." It is in no sense a speculative ormetaphysical knowledge; it contains nothing about thenature of its object. Out of practical ideas "we can formno conception that would help to the knowledge of the

    1 Kanfs Critique of Practical Reason, tr. by Th. K. Abbott, $d ed.,London, 1883, P- 2 -

    46

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    65/254

    KANT'S DOCTRINE OF RATIONAL FAITH 47object"; they ftcan never be used for a theory of super-natural beings, so that on this side they are quite in-capable of being the foundation of a speculative knowl-edge, and their use is limited simply to the practice of themoral law." 2

    This famous doctrine proclaiming the "primacy of thepractical reason" is even more significant with respect toKant's protestant outlook than is the refutation of allspeculative theology. As Luther stressed the primacy offaith against any objective guarantee on the part of man,so Kant defended the primacy of faith against any objec-tive knowledge of God. Of course, Luther and Kant donot mean the same thing when they speak of faith. Luthermeans belief in the word of God as revealed in Scripture,especially in the Gospel; Kant means rational faith. Butdespite this difference, which must be examined carefully,there is common ground for both Luther and Kant tostand on. Both mean by faith a relation of man to God,not founded on objective facts but rather on our con-science; both mean a practical relation, i.e., a relationwhich concerns primarily man's will in its moral aspect;both mean, therefore, something that affects a person as aperson and not something that would satisfy the humanintellect or reason in general.

    This is expressed by Kant when he says that the beliefin God is a belief for "the pure practical purpose" of pro-moting morality, that this belief is based upon the con-sciousness of duty, and that, therefore, the validity of thisbelief cannot be separated from a personal moral atti-tude toward life and reality. ". . . Admitting that thepure moral law inexorably binds every man as a command(not as a rule of prudence) , the righteous man may say: Imil that there be a God, . . . ; I firmly abide by this, and

    3 l.c, p. 235.

  • 8/7/2019 kroner primary of faith

    66/254

    48 THE PRIMACY OF FAITHwill not let this faith be taken from me; for in this in-stance alone my interest, because I must not relax any-thing of it, inevitably determines my judgement. . . ." 3It is an interest of mine in so far as I am a moral personstriving after moral ideals. It is a subjective personalinterest; but it is not a merely personal, i.e., a selfish in-terest, rather an interest of morality, i.e., of moral reason.This interest, not a theoretical insight or a proof of anyother intellectual surety determines my judgment. I, as a"righteous man," involved in moral duties, believe in God.The requirement of reason in this case is of a personalkind, it depends, as Kant says, on a Subjective conditionof reason," Kant's doctrine of moral belief in God thusappears to be the first step in the doctrine of Kierkegaardthat not thought but the existent thinker alone can berelated to God; that not a philosophic system but theliving man alone, the sinner and he who repents, can judgeabout the existence of God; that the standpoint of thebelieving man, therefore, must always