dorji wangchuk, “a relativity theory of the purity and validity of perception in indo-tibetan...

Upload: vidyutprabha

Post on 04-Jun-2018

214 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/13/2019 Dorji Wangchuk, A Relativity Theory of the Purity and Validity of Perception in Indo-Tibetan Buddhism. In Eli Fran

    1/27

    Dorji Wangchuk

    A Relativity Theory of the Purity and Validity of Perception in Indo-Tibetan Buddhism.

    In Eli Franco & Dagmar Eigner (eds.) 2009, Yogic Perception, Meditation and Altered States

    of Consciousness. Vienna: Verlag der sterreichischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, 215239.

  • 8/13/2019 Dorji Wangchuk, A Relativity Theory of the Purity and Validity of Perception in Indo-Tibetan Buddhism. In Eli Fran

    2/27

    D O R J I W A N G C H U K

    A Relativity Theory of the Purity and Validity ofPerception in Indo-Tibetan Buddhism*

    The mind is its own place, and in itselfCan make a heavn of hell, a hell of heavn.

    John Milton (16081674), Paradise Lost

    One devoid of self-cognitive mind that cognises true [reality],Would perceive even [pure] Buddha fields to be domains of baddestinations (e.g. hells).[For] one who realises the [true] reality of equality [taught by] theSupreme Vehicle,The very domains of bad destinations are domains of the Akaniha[and] Tuita [heavens].

    sGyu phrul le lhagand rDo rje gsang rgyud1

    1.INTRODUCTION

    On the whole, Tibetan Buddhist scholars have honestly striven toadhere to the doctrines of Indian Buddhism. But we do encounter fromtime to time philosophical theories and interpretations that are of purelyTibetan provenance. Most of them seem to be the product of an attemptto resolve conflicts and inconsistencies found in the heterogeneousIndian Buddhist scriptures and systems, which, as I have already tried toillustrate on the basis of the Buddha Nature theory, were dealt with indifferent ways.2No doubt differences in interpretations provoked heateddebates, but it is precisely these and similar doctrinal disputes that gave

    * I owe my thanks to Philip Pierce for kindly proofreading this article.1 sGyu phrul le lhag(p. 425.67) and rDo rje gsang rgyud(p. 332.34):

    yang dag shes pai rang rig blo med na ||bde gshegs zhing yang ngan song gnas su mthong ||theg mchog mnyam pai don nyid rtogs pa ni ||ngan song gnas nyid og min dga ldan gnas || .

    Note that the rDo rje gsang rgyuderroneously reads bla instead of blo in pda a.This verse is cited by Mi-pham in his Od gsal snying po(pp. 94.695.2), with thesGyu phrul rgyas panamed as his source. Instead of niinpdac, he has na.

    2 Wangchuk 2004.

  • 8/13/2019 Dorji Wangchuk, A Relativity Theory of the Purity and Validity of Perception in Indo-Tibetan Buddhism. In Eli Fran

    3/27

    216 DO R J I WA N G C H U K

    rise to fascinating philosophical ideas that are uniquely Tibetan. One ofthe most intriguing examples is the debate surrounding an Indo-TibetanBuddhist theory of knowledge, namely, on how beings of variousrealms and spiritual levels are said to perceive a common entity, forinstance, what is known to us humans as water. Some of the questionsthat Tibetan scholars have asked were whether what we call water existsat all as water, whether our perception of water is a valid cognition, orwhether it may be that water is not simply water after all but in fact pus(pya: rnag), as it is perceived by hungry ghosts (preta: yi dwags);nectar, as it is perceived by gods; a goddess, as it is perceived byyogins; or still something else. They also pondered upon such questionsas whether there is a common and shared object of perception, and if so,what it is, and which of the perceptionsif every sentient being of thesix realms perceives it differentlyis valid, and what the criteria ofperceptual validity are. Scholars from the four major schools of TibetanBuddhism (dGe-lugs, Sa-skya, bKa-brgyud, and rNying-ma) whoreflected upon these questions came to varying conclusions, which willbe discussed elsewhere. This paper seeks to introduce a relativity theory

    of the purity and validity of perception in Indo-Tibetan Buddhism, oneessentially the result of attempts made by some scholars of the rNying-ma (or the Ancient) School of Tibetan Buddhism to answer the abovequeries, having apparently drawn their inspiration from Indian Buddhistsources.

    The theory that I intend to present has revealed itself, as is oftenthe case, as more complex than initially assumed. Firstly, this theory ofperception does not concern an anthropocentric view of perception, andis not limited to human knowledge, but embraces the entire spectrum ofkarmically conditioned perceptions experienced by the six classes ofsentient beings, namely, gods, demigods, humans, animals, hungry

    ghosts, and beings in hell. Secondly, human beings for one may haveaccess to various dimensions of perception. For instance, based onkarmic influences, a man may perceive an entity x as waterassomething that can quench his thirstbut he may also be able tomeditatively enhance his perception and perceive x as a female beingcapable of arousing samdhic ecstasy in him. Thirdly, this theorypresupposes varying understandings of ontology, logic andepistemology (prama), gnoseology (i.e. the theory of jna, which inthe Buddhist context can be understood as higher epistemology), andsoteriologyin the varying Buddhist philosophical systemsand this

  • 8/13/2019 Dorji Wangchuk, A Relativity Theory of the Purity and Validity of Perception in Indo-Tibetan Buddhism. In Eli Fran

    4/27

    PU R I T Y A N D VA L I D I T Y O F PE R C E P T I O N 217

    makes the matter all the more complicated. Fourthly, there is a certainterminological constriction in having to express eastern thought inwestern languages, and one cannot always adopt or else try to getaround using western scientific or philosophical terms such asrelativity and relativism3without running risks of being misunder-stood.

    2.THE HISTORICAL AND DOCTRINAL SETTING

    Of the four periods of the history of Buddhist logic and epistemology(prama) in Tibet as proposed by Leonard W. J. van der Kuijp,4namely, Ancient (i.e. pre-Glang-dar-ma Period, that is, pre-9th century),Pre-Classical (beginning with Klu-mes Tshul-khrims-shes-rab in the10th century), Classical (beginning with Sa-skya Paita Kun-dga-rgyal-mtshan in the 12th century), and Post-Classical (beginning in the15th century), the Ancient Period witnessed the translation of only afew Indian works on Buddhist logic and epistemology.5One is likely toassume that beyond these few translations Tibetan scholars of the

    Ancient Period have really nothing to say or offer on matters pertainingto Buddhist logic and epistemology. Such an assumption wouldcertainly be justified if we were to think exclusively in terms ofcommentaries on pure Prama treatises belonging to the Dignga-Dharmakrti school of Buddhist logic and epistemology, but notnecessarily if we were to consider Buddhist theories of knowledge andtheir application in more general terms. For example, the theory of fourkinds of yukti (logical reasoning), namely, reasoning [based on theprinciple] of dependence (apekyukti: ltos pai rigs pa), reasoning[based on the principle of the ability of things to] cause effects(kryakaraayukti: bya ba byed pai rigs pa), reasoning that establishes

    3 I would like to thank John Taber for kindly acquainting me with MariaBaghramians monograph on relativism (Baghramian 2004). Unfortunately, it hasnot been possible to go into a discussion of whether my own employment of theterms relativity and relativism conforms to one or more of the numeroussemantic nuances and usages presented therein. I shall have to leave it up to readersfor themselves to judge if and to what extent the theory presented in this paper canbe described in those terms.

    4 van derKuijp1989: 89.5 For the Prama texts translated during the Ancient Period in Tibet, see Frauwallner

    1957.

  • 8/13/2019 Dorji Wangchuk, A Relativity Theory of the Purity and Validity of Perception in Indo-Tibetan Buddhism. In Eli Fran

    5/27

    218 DO R J I WA N G C H U K

    the tenability [of the other three types of reasoning] (upapattisdhana-yukti: thad pa sgrub pai rigs pa), and reasoning [based on the rule-boundedness] of reality [itself] (dharmatyukti:chos nyid kyi rigs pa), isparticularly interesting, for it existed in India prior to Dignga andDharmakrti, for the most part within the Maitreya-Asaga or Yogcratextual milieu. Some of the earliest sources of the fouryuktis may wellbe the rvakabhmi6 and Bodhisattvabhmi7 (and not the Sadhinir-mocanastra,8 in spite of its stra status). The four yuktis are eithermerely alluded to or discussed in greater detail in these and other Indianworks. In Tibet, the topic seems to have been quite popular from earlyon, as the commentaries on the Sadhinirmocanastra and the bKa

    yang dag pai tshad ma ascribed to the Tibetan King Khri-srong-lde-btsan9adequately demonstrate. One of the most detailed and systematicexplanations and applications of the four yuktis I have seen thus far,however, is that of the eleventh-century rNying-ma scholar Rong-zomChos-kyi-bzang-po (henceforth Rong-zom-pa),10 who evidently reliedon Candragomins Nyyasiddhyloka.11 Rong-zom-pas explanationsand applications of these fouryuktis are very useful, containing as they

    do intriguing deliberations on a number of ontological, epistemological,soteriological, and gnoseological issues.12Although the fouryuktis willnot be discussed in this article, it should be pointed out that earlyTibetan deliberations on theory of knowledge, including what I call therelativity theory of the purity and validity of perception, can best beunderstood at the backdrop of these fouryuktis.

    6 rvakabhmi(pp. 236.10240.15).7 Bodhisattvabhmi(p. 293.1718).8 Sadhinirmocanastra X.7 (pp. 155158).9 See Steinkellner1989 and Powers2004:20, n. 43.

    10 dKon mchog grel(pp. 102.9103.15); mDo rgyas(pp. 308.22314.10); Theg tshul

    (pp. 487.20491.20); sNang ba lhar sgrub (pp. 560.6563.1). Mi-pham alsodiscussed the fouryuktis on a number of occasions; see, for example, his mKhas jug(pp. 296.3300.4), his commentary on Madhyamaklakra 65 (dBu ma rgyangrel, pp. 241.3249.2), mDo sde rgyan grel (pp. 667.2668.4), Shes rab ral griandShes rab ral grii mchan (pp. 790.1792.4), andsKad gnyis shan sbyar(pp. 235.6236.1). For the role Mi-pham envisioned for the four yuktis within the generalMahyna context, see his Legs bshad snang bai gter (p. 897.14). See alsoKapstein 2001: 317343.

    11 For a discussion of the authorship of theNyyasiddhyloka, see Steinkellner 1984.12 Rang byung ye shes (pp. 124.21125.22); dKon mchog grel (pp. 103.15109.9);

    sNang ba lhar sgrub (pp. 563.1567.6).

  • 8/13/2019 Dorji Wangchuk, A Relativity Theory of the Purity and Validity of Perception in Indo-Tibetan Buddhism. In Eli Fran

    6/27

    PU R I T Y A N D VA L I D I T Y O F PE R C E P T I O N 219

    It was, however, only in the nineteenth century that the rNying-ma school managed to colonise the field of classical Buddhist logicand epistemology, primarily thanks to the efforts of Mi-pham rNam-rgyal-rgya-mtsho (18461912),13who became an authority in the fieldin his tradition. One of Mi-phams most significant contributions totheories of knowledge is his systematisation of the theory of two kindsof means of conventional valid cognition (i.e. cognition that has theconventional as its object) (kun tu tha snyad pai tshad ma: svyava-hrikaprama),14 namely, one based on ordinary (lit. of this-side,i.e., this-worldly) perception (tshu rol mthong ba: arvgdarana/apara-darana)15 and the other based on pure perception (dag pai gzigs pa:*uddhadarana).16Mi-pham himself thought his theory to be a matterof great profundity (shin tu zab pai gnad) crucially relevant for bothtantric and non-tantric Buddhist systems. What can his motive forintroducing such a theory have been? Mi-pham was, like Tsong-kha-paBlo-bzang-grags-pa (13571419), a champion of the Prama andMadhyamaka systems, and he strongly believed in an intimate andnatural relationship between Dharmakrtis Prama and Ngrjunas

    13 The few Prama works by Mi-pham are: (a) Tshad ma rnam grel gyi gzhung gsalpor bshad pa legs bshad snang bai gter(MS,vol. 20, pp. 1901); (b) Tshad ma kunlas btus pai mchan grel rig [= rigs?] lam rab gsal snang ba(MS,vol. 8/h, pp.473619); (c) Tshad ma rigs pai gter mchan gyis grel pa phyogs las rnam parrgyal bai ru mtshon(MS,vol. 11/kha, pp. 549751); and (d) bsDus tshan rtsod rigssmra bai sgo byed(MS,vol. 27, pp. 285353). See the bsTan pai mdzes rgyan(pp.676.5677.2)a work of mKhan-po Kun-bzang-dpal-ldan, or in short Kun-dpal(18721943), which includes some additional Prama writings of Mi-pham, ofwhich the Tshad ma rnam grel gyi bsdus don nyi zlai phreng baseems particularlynoteworthy. For a discussion of Mi-phams theory of interpretation (as presented inhis Shes rab ral gri), see Kapstein 2001.

    14 The term svyavahrikaprama is attested in Prajkaramatis Bodhicary-

    vatrapajik (p. 180.25) and in Prajkaraguptas Pramavrttiklakra (e.g.pp. 3.14, 5.23, 226.8). Cf. Pramavrttiklakra (p. 487.28): svyavahrika

    pramam. Prajkaragupta also employs terms such as vyvahrikaprama(ibid.,p. 226.8) and svyavahrikapratyaka (ibid., p. 13.4). (I would like to thank EliFranco for drawing my attention to Prajkaraguptas work.) Note that Tibetansources also employ the expressions tha snyad dpyod pai tshad maand thasnyad(pai/kyi)tshad ma.

    15 Bodhicaryvatrapajik(p. 182.9, 13); Jackson 1987: 401, n. 103. Cf. Negi19932005:s.v. tshu rol mthong ba.

    16 Mi-pham, Od gsal snying po (pp. 82.184.5) and Shes rab ral gri (pp. 800.3801.4).

  • 8/13/2019 Dorji Wangchuk, A Relativity Theory of the Purity and Validity of Perception in Indo-Tibetan Buddhism. In Eli Fran

    7/27

    220 DO R J I WA N G C H U K

    Madhyamaka,17 or between the systems of the Two Krtis, namely,Dharmakrti and Candrakrti.18 Harmony between the doctrines ofDharmakrti and Candrakrti also meant for him harmony betweenYogcra and Madhyamaka, and so too between the Ngrjuna andMaitreya-Asaga traditions. The means of absolute valid cognition (i.e.cognition that has the absolute as its object) (don dam pai tshad ma:

    pramrthikaprama)19 emphasised by Ngrjuna and the svyava-hrikapramaemphasised by Dharmakrti are often referred to as thetwo means of valid cognition of the two kinds of reality (bden pa gnyiskyi tshad ma gnyis).20The explicit or implicit argumentanalogous toDharmakrtis argument for the number of pramasis that becausethere are two kinds of prameya, namely, conventional and absoluterealities, there must be two kinds ofprama, namely, svyavahrika-

    prama and pramrthikaprama.21 If something such as fire existson the conventional level, it must be attestable through svyavahri-kaprama for if it is not attestable through such a cognition, it cannotexist on the conventional level. Similarly, if there is an absolute realitysuch as emptiness, it must be attestable through pramrthikaprama,

    17 Mi-pham, dBu ma rgyan grel(p. 46.56): khyad par don dam pai tshad ma dpalldan klu yis ji ltar bzhed pa dang | tha snyad kyi tshad ma dpal chos kyi grags pas jiltar bzhed pa gnyis rags [= rigs]pai rgya mtsho chen por ro gcig tu bskyil zhing |.See also ibid. (p. 47.3): dbu tshad seng ge mjing bsnol.

    18 See the intermediate verses (bar skabs kyi tshigs su bcad pa) in the dBu ma rgyangrel(pp. 13.615.2).

    19 The term pramrthikaprama is attested, for example, in PrajkaraguptasPramavrttiklakra (p. 30.22; cited in Franco 1997: 50, n. 12). Cf. Prama-vrttiklakra (p. 67.1213): pramrthika pramam. Prajkaragupta alsoemploys the termpramrthikaprameya(ibid., p. 215.13). Note that Tibetan sourcesalso use the term don dam dpyod pai tshad ma.

    20 The terms tha snyad pa'i tshad maand don dam pa'i tshad maseem to go back tothe Pramavinicaya (p. 44.25): svyavahrikasya caitat pramasya rpamuktam | atrpi pare mh visavdayanti lokam iti | cintmaym eva tu prajmanulayanto vibhramavivekanirmalam anapyi pramrthikapramam abhimukh-kurvanti |; Tibetan translation (Vetter 1966: 100.2024): di ni kun tu tha snyad paitshad mai rang bzhin brjod pa yin te | di la yang pha rol rmongs pas jig rten slubar byed pai phyir ro || bsam pa las byung ba nyid kyi shes rab goms par byas pasrnam par khrul pas dben zhing dri ma med la log pa med pa don dam pai tshad mamngon sum du byed do ||. See also Mi-pham,Legs bshad snang bai gter(p. 553.1417).

    21 Such an argument is clearly inspired by Digngas Pramasamuccaya 1.2(Steinkellner 2005: 1) and Dharmakrtis Pramavrttika 3.1 (see the Prama-vrttiklakra, p. 169.1011).

  • 8/13/2019 Dorji Wangchuk, A Relativity Theory of the Purity and Validity of Perception in Indo-Tibetan Buddhism. In Eli Fran

    8/27

    PU R I T Y A N D VA L I D I T Y O F PE R C E P T I O N 221

    for reality that is not attestable through pramrthikapramais not anabsolute reality. However, Mi-pham also belongs to a tradition thatpostulates the indivisibility of the two truths. Accordingly, he posits thatultimately there is only one singleprameya,22and hence only one single

    prama, which he equates with self-occurring gnosis or with thegnosis of the Self-occurring One (i.e. the Buddha) (svayabhjna:rang byung gi ye shes). Tsong-kha-pa, when discussing, for example,

    Madhyamakvatra 6.71b, points out the consequence of denying theestablished Prama theories.23He, for his part, apparently feared that adenial of the Prama theories would lead to logical, ontological,epistemological, and ethical-moral indeterminism (or arbitrariness), oras Thubten Jinpa in his study of Tsong-kha-pas Madhyamakaphilosophy correctly points out, to epistemological scepticism,ontological nihilism, and moral relativism, all of which were forTsong-kha-pa different aspects of the same problem and equallyobjectionable.24Mi-pham, too, could not imagine a world where thereare no reliable criteria to differentiate between valid and invalidcognition. If a cognition were to be arbitrarily regarded as valid or

    invalid, how could one determine what is correct and incorrect, andwhat is right and wrong? He could thus in principle share Tsong-kha-pas concern.

    Mi-pham, however, had a concern of another kind, which wasobviously not shared or addressed by his fellow Tibetan scholars fromthe gSar-ma (New) schools. The established epistemologicalparadigm, which is perhaps common to most Tibetan Buddhist schools,must have appeared too narrow and inadequate to him, for it did not andcould not address or explain Buddhist doctrines which he thought wereof greater significance. Buddhist scriptures are full of allusions to theideas of supernatural or supramundane phenomena or perceptions that

    make no sense to the ordinary human understanding. For instance, injust a single atom there are said to exist Buddha fields numbering as

    22 For a similar idea, see Dharmakrtis Pramavrttika 3.53d (as cited in thePramavrttiklakra, p. 212.28): meyatv ekasvalakaam.

    23 Tsong-kha-pa, dGongs pa rab gsal (fol. 178b23): de ltar go ba dei don yin parbzung nas tshad mas grub pa la yid brtan med do zhes smra na ni | don di kho bosdi ltar rtogs so zhes pa gcig kyang gzhag tu med cing | tshad ma thams cad la skur

    pa debs pas na shin tu mi thad pao ||.24 Jinpa 2002: 34, 175.

  • 8/13/2019 Dorji Wangchuk, A Relativity Theory of the Purity and Validity of Perception in Indo-Tibetan Buddhism. In Eli Fran

    9/27

    222 DO R J I WA N G C H U K

    many as the total number of atoms. It is even explicitly stated thatneither has the size of the Buddha fields been contracted nor the size ofthe atom expanded. How is one to deal with such an idea? Onealternative would be to dismiss it as mere rhetoric. Most Buddhistscholars would not go for this alternative. Another alternative would beto explain it as a miracle demonstrated by the supernatural power of abuddha, which de factomeans that such a phenomenon or event is notattestable through any means of valid cognition. Some Tibetan scholarsmight accept this explanation. The problem with it, though, is theabsurd implications that it involves, particularly in a context where thesame entity x that appears to ordinary humans as water appears toyoginswho have fewer or no defilements or obscurations, whoundergo fewer or no sufferings, and are partially or totally released fromsasric bondageas something else. At least from a Buddhist point ofview, the supposition that our ordinary perceptions, obscured byintellectual-emotional defilements, pain, sufferings, and bondage, arevalid or true, whereas yogic perceptions free from intellectual-emotional defilements, pain, sufferings, and bondage, are invalid or

    false sounds quite absurd and supercilious. Mi-phams motive thusseems to have been to propose an upgraded and updated theory thatcould explain otherwise logically unexplainable phenomena,particularly the idea of pure appearances and pure perceptions(thematised in both tantric and non-tantric Mahyna scriptures).

    3.MI-PHAMS THEORY OF THE TWO KINDS OFSVYAVAHRIKAPRAMA

    Mi-pham argues that there must be two types of svyavahrikapram-a, for any phenomenon on the conventional level has two modes,

    namely, the mode of appearance (snang tshul) and the mode ofexistence (gnas tshul). A conventional entity x such as water mayappear to be impure, but it always exists in a pure state; in its absolutemode of existence, however, it is always characterised by emptiness(nyat: stong pa nyid).25He thus classifies means of valid cognitioninto two types: svyavahrikaprama and pramrthikaprama.Svyavahrikaprama is further divided into one based on ordinary

    25 Cf. the tables in Pettit 1999: 431434.

  • 8/13/2019 Dorji Wangchuk, A Relativity Theory of the Purity and Validity of Perception in Indo-Tibetan Buddhism. In Eli Fran

    10/27

    PU R I T Y A N D VA L I D I T Y O F PE R C E P T I O N 223

    perception (tshu rol mthong ba la brten pa kun tu tha snyad pai tshadma) and one based on pure perception (dag pai gzigs pa la brten pa kuntu tha snyad pai tshad ma). He distinguishes them on the basis of theircause (rgyu), nature (ngo bo), function (byed las), result (bras bu), andexample (dpe), as follows:

    Distinctions between the Two Types of Svyavahrikaprama

    Basis ofDistinction

    SvyavahrikapramaBased on Ordinary Perception(tshu rol mthong ba la brten

    pa kun tu tha snyad pai tshadma)

    SvyavahrikapramaBased on Pure Perception (dag

    pai gzigs pa la brten pa kun tutha snyad pai tshad ma)

    1. Cause(rgyu)

    Given rise to by dint of acorrect assessment of its lim-ited object, the [perceptible]phenomenon (rang yul choscan nyi tshe ba la tshul bzhinbrtags pai stobs las skyes pa)

    Acquired as an outcome of thecorrect appropriation of truereality [during meditative ab-sorption] (chos nyid ji lta batshul bzhin dmigs pai rjes lasthob pa)

    2. Nature(ngo bo)

    Cognition that is provisionallynon-deceptive in regard to its

    mere object (rang yul tsam lagnas skabs mi bslu bai rigpa)

    Discriminating insight of greatrange possessed by a subject

    [surveying] the full gamut [ofphenomena] (ji snyed pai yulcan rgya che bai shes rab)

    3. Function(byed las)

    Elimination of superimposi-tion [and depreciation] in re-gard to the objects of ordinaryperception (tshul [= tshu rol]mthong gi yul la sgro dogssel ba)

    Elimination of superimposition[and depreciation] in regard tothe [normally] inconceivable do-main (bsam gyis mi khyab paispyod yul la sgro dogs sel ba)

    4. Result(bras bu)

    Proceeding on after thepertinent object has beenexactly determined (skabs don

    yongs su bcad nas jug pa)

    Gnosis that cognises [phenom-ena] to the full extent (ji snyedmkhyen pai ye shes)

    5. Analogy(dpe)26 Human sight (mii mig) Celestial sight (lhai mig)

    Mi-pham presented these two types of svyavahrikaprama on atleast two occasions, namely, in his general commentary on the*Guhyagarbhatantra(a fundamental tantric scripture of the rNying-maschool) called Od gsal snying po, and in his work on hermeneutics

    26 Not counted separately by Mi-pham.

  • 8/13/2019 Dorji Wangchuk, A Relativity Theory of the Purity and Validity of Perception in Indo-Tibetan Buddhism. In Eli Fran

    11/27

    224 DO R J I WA N G C H U K

    called Shes rab ral gri, on which he also wrote an annotatedcommentary.27 One important question is how original Mi-pham wasand how much he owed to his Indian and Tibetan predecessors. As faras I can see, no one before him had proposed and explained two kindsof svyavahrikaprama. On the other hand, although the Sanskritterm for dag pa gzigs pai tshad ma(*uddhadaranaprama) has yetto be traced in Indian sources,28 the idea of pure perception(uddhapratyaka: dag pai mngon sum) is attested in the Hetuvidysection of the Yogcrabhmi29 as shown by Hjun Nagasaki in hisarticle Perception in Pre-Dignga Buddhist Texts,30where it is listedand explained as one of the four kinds of pratyaka, the other threebeing perception by means of corporeal sense faculties (rpndriya-

    pratyaka: dbang po gzugs can gyi mgnon sum), perception [in theform] of mental experience (manonubhavapratyaka: yid kyis myongbai mngon sum), and mundane perception (lokapratyaka: jig rten gyimngon sum). Nagasaki interprets uddhapratyaka in two ways: (a) asmanonubhavapratyaka and (b) as lokottarajna. One wonderswhether uddhapratyaka could have meant both pure mundane gnosis

    (uddhalaukikajna: dag pa jig rten pai ye shes) and non-conceptualgnosis (nirvikalpajna: rnam par mi rtog pai ye shes). In Tibetansources, the idea of means of pure valid cognition occurs primarily inthe context of what is called establishing the divinity of appearance(snang ba lhar sgrub pa), that is, establishing the supramundaneness ofthe very mundane, the divinity of the very earthlyaccording to Mi-pham, a uniquely rNying-ma concern, which stems from the eleventh-century rNying-ma scholar Rong-zom-pa, and is described by him asthe Lions Roar (seng gei nga ro) of this scholar.31Indeed Mi-phamstheory of pure svyavahrikaprama is clearly largely inspired by

    27 Od gsal snying po(pp. 82.184.5); Shes rab ral gri(pp. 800.3801.4).28 Compare the expression pramapariuddhasakalatattvaja in the Pramavrtti-

    klakra(p. 51.22).29 Hetuvidy(p. 340.213).30 Nagasaki 1991: 223225.31 Mi-pham,Nges shes sgron me (p. 103.45):

    snang kun rang bzhin lhar sgrub pa ||snga gyur ring lugs kho na ste ||kun mkhyen rong zom pai tai ||legs bshad seng gei nga ro yin ||.

    For an English translation, see Pettit 1999: 222.

  • 8/13/2019 Dorji Wangchuk, A Relativity Theory of the Purity and Validity of Perception in Indo-Tibetan Buddhism. In Eli Fran

    12/27

    PU R I T Y A N D VA L I D I T Y O F PE R C E P T I O N 225

    Rong-zom-pas writings, particularly those passages attempting toestablish the divinity of appearance.32

    4.RONG-ZOM-PA ON ONTOLOGY,EPISTEMOLOGY,SOTERIOLOGY,GNOSEOLOGY,AND THE INDIVIDUALITY OF PERSONS

    Undoubtedly Rong-zom-pas work on establishing the divinity ofappearances is unprecedented in the world of Indo-Tibetan Buddhism.He is said to have composed a set of seven works of varying size, whatone might call his heptalogy, on the establishment of the divinity ofappearances, of which only one is extant.33 The fundamental ideabehind the establishment of the divinity of appearances is thatphenomena, which appear to us in manifold ways, are in realityprimordially pure regardless of whether we perceive them as such ornot. One of Rong-zom-pas main arguments is that a dharma(phenol-menon) can hardly be impure if its dharmat (true reality) is pure,for there is an essential connection between dharma and dharmat.Both dharma and dharmat are thus pure, and hence also divine. For

    him, then, divinity means purity. Where could Rong-zom-pa have gotthis idea from? The proposition that all phenomena are completely pureis widespread in tantric and non-tantric Mahyna literature. Inparticular, it plays a dominant role in the *Guhyagarbhatantra, atradition to which Rong-zom-pa belonged, and wherein the so-called (a)external world or habitat (snod), comprising five elements, (b) itsinhabitants (bcud), made up of five psycho-physiological aggregates(phung po), and (c) mental continua (rgyud), a set of eight kinds ofmind (rnam par shes pa tshogs brgyad), are all said to be pure, thepurities of the external habitat (snod dag pa), its inhabitants (bcud dag

    pa), and the mental continua (rgyud dag pa) being referred to as three

    kinds of purity (dag pa rnam pa gsum).

    34

    The central philosophy of the*Guhyagarbhatantra is that all phenomena are in their conventionalitycharacterised by great purity (dag pa chen po) and in their absoluteness

    32 For Mi-phams own efforts to establish the divinity of appearance, see his Od gsalsnying po(pp. 77.297.1).

    33 See Rong-pa Me-dpungs list of Rong-zom-pas writings (Tho yig, p. 239.56):snang ba lha sgrub che phra bdun du grags pa la sogs pa dag yin te |. See alsoAlmogi 1997: 248249; 170171.

    34 Rong-zom-pa, dKon mchog grel(p. 184.16).

  • 8/13/2019 Dorji Wangchuk, A Relativity Theory of the Purity and Validity of Perception in Indo-Tibetan Buddhism. In Eli Fran

    13/27

    226 DO R J I WA N G C H U K

    by great equality (mnyam pa chen po), and that the two modes arecharacterised by great indivisibility (dbyer med pa chen po). One of themain devices employed to establish such propositions is the four kindsof reasoning referred to above.

    We may now set the theory proposed by Rong-zom-pa in thewider context of his assessment of the Mahyna doctrine. Broadlyspeaking, Mahyna Buddhism can be classified into tantric and non-tantric, although the borderline tends to be quite fluid or permeable.One generally assumes that non-tantric Mahyna is doctrinally moreconservative than tantric Mahyna. This is, however, not always thecase, inasmuch as some stras contain ideas that are more developedthan those found in certain tantras. This may help to explain why Rong-zom-pa occasionallyfor example, in his dKon mchog grelspeaks ofcommon (thun mong) and uncommon or special (thun mong ma yin pa)Mahyna. A distinction between the two is clearly made in accordancewith the degree of doctrinal conservatism. By special Mahyna, hemeans a school of Buddhist thought which postulates the idea of theindivisibility of the two kinds of truth (bden pa rnam pa gnyis dbyer

    med pa), that is, the idea that there is in reality one single truth, and thatits division into conventional and absolute is merely a device forenabling access to that single truth. This special Mahyna of Rong-zom-pa includes both tantric and non-tantric forms. To the group ofscriptures of the special Mahyna belong both stras, such as theVimalakrtinirdeastraandRatnaguasacayagth, and tantras, suchas the *Guhyagarbhatantra. According to him, the special Mahynais special for five reasons, which may be explicated as follows:35(a) It is special because it proposes a special kind of ontology.Specifically, the only viable ontological reality is what the author callsmere appearance (snang ba tsam), behind the facade of which there is

    nothing. Even this mere appearance may or may not enduredepending upon the presence or absence of necessary and sufficientcauses and conditions.(b) It is special because it proposes a special kind of soteriology.According to this special soteriological model, one sees and seeks asolution in the problem itself, nirva in sasra itself; release in

    35 dKon mchog grel (pp. 42.243.13). For a critical edition of the pertinent text and anEnglish translation, see Almogi 2006: 468470 (text), 319322 (translation).

  • 8/13/2019 Dorji Wangchuk, A Relativity Theory of the Purity and Validity of Perception in Indo-Tibetan Buddhism. In Eli Fran

    14/27

    PU R I T Y A N D VA L I D I T Y O F PE R C E P T I O N 227

    bondage itself. In other words, the very dukhasatya is seen as anirodhasatya; the very samudayasatya as a mrgasatya.(c) It is special because it proposes a special kind of gnoseology. Seeing(or, knowing) the gnosis through which release is attained (vimukti-

    jnadarana: rnam par grol bai ye shes mthong ba)36 is special,because this gnosis is not conceived as something that can be attained orgenerated at a certain stage, place, and time but as being immanent hereand now, for our ordinary minds and mental associates are by natureself-occurring gnosis (svayabhjna: rang byung gi ye shes).(d) It is special because it proposes a special kind of epistemology. Itoffers, that is, a unique theory of perception in regard to the scope andvalidity of the various human and non-human, yogic and non-yogicperceptions. This is one of the sources feeding into the relativity theoryof the purity and validity of perception. We shall return to it later.(e) I am not sure how best the fifth aspect of the special Mahyna canbe expressed. The author apparently alludes to a special spiritualproclivity or disposition within the person, namely, the uniqueness ofhis or her cognitive, conative, and emotive faculty which allows access

    to the so-called non-dual mode (gnyis su med pai tshul), clearlymeaning the indivisibility of the two kinds of truth referred to above.

    5.THE PHILOSOPHICAL-DOCTRINAL PRESUPPOSITIONS OF THE THEORY

    The theory of the purity and validity of perception proposed by Rong-zom-pa can perhaps be best understood against the backdrop of threekinds of presuppositions, namely, his concept of ontology, soteriology,and epistemology. I employ the term perception in the sense of theTibetan terms mthong ba(or gzigs pa) and snang ba. Tibetan mthong baseems to mean primarily the perception of an appearance and

    secondarily the perceived or perceptible appearance whereas snangbaseems to mean primarily perceived or perceptible appearance, andsecondarily perception of an appearance. A direct ontic-epistemiccorrespondence between appearance and perception is presupposed bymost Tibetan scholars, since only that which is ontologically possible isepistemically cognisable; and only that which appears is perceived orperceptible.

    36 Negi19932005:s.v.

  • 8/13/2019 Dorji Wangchuk, A Relativity Theory of the Purity and Validity of Perception in Indo-Tibetan Buddhism. In Eli Fran

    15/27

    228 DO R J I WA N G C H U K

    (a) The Ontological Presuppositions of the Theory

    One cannot talk about the theory of perception or knowledge if noknowable or perceptible is presupposed. Various Buddhist systems mayargue about the ontological status of the knowable, but I would assertthat within the Buddhist systems one tacitly assumes that there is a kindof reality, or nature to phenomena (whatever it may be) that is

    cognisable, timeless, and independent of being cognised and the personwho cognises it.37It is said that buddhas may come and go, but the truthremains as it is (yathbhtam), unaffected by its occasional rediscoveryor oblivion. This idea can be found in non-Mahyna sources (such asthe Sayuttanikya and Aguttaranikya), in non-tantric Mahynaliterature (such as the Lakvatrastra, Saddharmapuarkastra,and Jnloklakrastra), and tantric sources (such as theVairocanbhisabodhitantra).38 As we have just seen, for Rong-zom-pa, the only ontological reality is what he calls mere appearance(snang ba tsam). It is conceived of as being totally hollow, without anydefining characteristics whatsoever, rootless, bottomless, invariable, andsoteriologically neutral, and yet it is (i) the only viable basis forbondage and release, sasra and nirva;39 (ii) the basis of definingcharacteristics (mtshan gzhi), that is, the basis for assigning variousdefining characteristics (mtshan nyid sna tshogs),40(iii) the only viablepremise allowing for a dialogue between sentient beings of the sixrealms; yogins and non-yogins; experts and non-experts; (iv) the onlyviable shared object of independent perceptions.

    37 See Vetters remark in Bsteh2000: 48.38 For the universality of reality and its being independent of the appearance of a

    tathgatain both non-Mahyna and Mahyna sources, see Wangchuk2007: 4142, 78, n. 24.

    39 Rong-zom-pa, Theg tshul(p. 513.46): mdor na gzhi gcig la rnam par dag pai jigrten du snang ba dang | ma dag pai jig rten du snang ba ste | de la ma dag parsnang ba ni | bslad pas bsgribs pa yin no zheo ||; ibid. (p. 513.2022):snang ba denyid kyang byang grol dang ching ba gnyis gai rkyen du gyur bar mnyam pas |tshul gnyi ga ltar yang bsgrub du[= tu] rung bar snang ngo ||; ibid. (p. 522.45):snang ba la skyon med na sems can gang gis bslus te khor zhe na|.

    40 Rong-zom-pa, Theg tshul(p. 465.2024): snang ba tsam ni mkhas pa pai [= i] tanas blun mo [= po] ba glang rdzi yan chad gang yang rung ste | las kyi bsgo skal laspyod pa mthun par snang ba dang | yongs su dag pa dang ma dag pa la stsogs pasnang ba bye brag mthun pa rnams la snang ngo zhes bsgrub mi dgos te | mtshannyid sna tshogs rnam par jog pai mtshan [= mtshon?] gzhi yin no || mtshan nyid ni

    ji ltar snang ba de ltar bsgrub pa rdul phra mo tsam yang myed do ||.

  • 8/13/2019 Dorji Wangchuk, A Relativity Theory of the Purity and Validity of Perception in Indo-Tibetan Buddhism. In Eli Fran

    16/27

    PU R I T Y A N D VA L I D I T Y O F PE R C E P T I O N 229

    Why can a nondescript appearance appear as various specificappearances, such as pus, water, nectar, and so forth? Mi-phams mainargument is that where there is appearance-and-emptiness, everything ispossible, and where there is no appearance-and-emptiness, nothing ispossible.41Except for a slight modification in the wording, this is a clearreference to Mlamadhyamakakrik 24.14, according to whicheverything is possible for anything that exists in harmony withemptiness.42 According to Rong-zom-pa,43 appearances (snang ba)appear (snang) on account of (a) the power of delusion (khrul paidbang), (b) the power of self-cognition (rang rig pai dbang), and (c)the power of the non-origination of true reality (chos nyid skye ba med

    pai dbang). These three causes or factors of appearances (snang bairgyu/rkyen gsum) have been explained as follows: First, the power ofdelusion is for all practical purposes the diverse latent tendenciesimplanted in the layavijna (fundamental mind) by the deludedmind (khrul pai shes pa). Second, the power of self-cognition isexplained as the ability of the mind to cognise itself; that is, mind, beingalways self-cognitive, is not an inanimate entity (bem po) and offers no

    physical resistance (rdos can). If the mind were not self-cognitive ordevoid of any cognitive characteristics (shes rig gyi mtshan nyid dang

    41 Mi-pham,Nges shes sgron me(p. 101.45):des na rang gi lugs la ni ||snang stong ris su ma chad pai ||gzhi nyid cir yang ma grub pa ||gang snang kun la mnyam pai phyir ||dngos gcig sna tshogs par yang snang ||gang la snang stong rung ba na ||de la thams cad rung bar gyur ||gang la snang stong mi rung ba ||de la thams cad rung mi gyur ||.

    For an English translation, see Pettit 1999: 220221.42 Ngrjuna, Mlamadhyamakakrik 24.14 (cf. Vigrahavyvartan 70). See, forexample, the Tshig don mdzod(pp. 7.329.2), where Klong-chen-pa discusses sevenpositions on the universal basis (gzhi), alluding thereby to several rDzogs-chentantras. It is explained that the universal basis is neither (1) spontaneously present(lhun grub), (2) indeterminate (ma nges pa), (3) determinate (nges pa), (4) malleable(cir yang bsgyur du btub pa), (5) arbitrary (cir yang khas blang du btub pa), nor (6)manifold (sna tshogs), but (7) primordially pure (ka dag). The primordially pureuniversal basis is said to consist of the three inseparable qualities of emptiness,luminosity, and all-embracing compassion.

    43 Rang byung ye shes(pp. 120.16123.21).

  • 8/13/2019 Dorji Wangchuk, A Relativity Theory of the Purity and Validity of Perception in Indo-Tibetan Buddhism. In Eli Fran

    17/27

    230 DO R J I WA N G C H U K

    bral ba zhig), nothing would appear. Third, the power of the non-origination of true reality is also explained as the natural and intrinsicpurity (rang bzhin gyis rnam par dag pa / ngo bo nyid kyis rnam par dag

    pa) of all phenomena. Phenomena, not being anything (cir yang ma yinpa), can appear in any way (cir yang snang du rung ba), for they aredevoid of resistance (gegs med pa).

    Of the three factors of appearances, purity and the ability of themind to cognise itself are the dominant conditions for appearances ofboth pollution (saklea: kun nas nyon mongs pa) and purification(vyavadna: rnam par byang ba). The latent tendencies form thegeneral conditions for the appearance of both pollution and purification.Nonetheless, those appearances that are caused by negative latenttendencies (nag poi bag chags) are called deceptive (slu ba), untrue (mibden pa), fallacious (khrul pa), and unreliable (yid brtan du mi rungba), whereas those appearances that are caused by positive latenttendencies (dkar poi bag chags) are called non-deceptive (mi slu ba),true (bden pa), non-fallacious (ma khrul pa), and reliable (yid brtan durung ba). Although none of the appearances is ultimately true (yang dag

    par bden pa), the less deceptive ones are provisionally regarded as non-deceptive by the wise, for they are non-deceiving to the extent that theybring about salvation.

    (b) The Soteriological Presuppositions of the Theory

    The main soteriological presupposition of the theory is that at least inprinciple anybody, at any given point in time and space, can gain fullaccess to true reality by means of meditative insight, and the correctcognition or insightful penetration of the truth has a soteriological orsalvific effect on the person who cognises or penetrates it. In other

    words, a person is liberated by gaining meditative insight into the truth.For most Buddhist scholars and mystics, it is the correct cognition oftrue reality, regardless of how it is defined by the various Buddhistsystems, that makes the spiritual or soteriological breakthroughpossible, and that the gnosis (jna: ye shes) of a buddha is by defini-tion direct valid cognition (prama: tshad ma). This notion of releaseupon seeing true reality is found in tantric sources such as the Cary-melpakapradpa,and also in non-tantric Mahyna sources such as the

  • 8/13/2019 Dorji Wangchuk, A Relativity Theory of the Purity and Validity of Perception in Indo-Tibetan Buddhism. In Eli Fran

    18/27

    PU R I T Y A N D VA L I D I T Y O F PE R C E P T I O N 231

    AbhisamaylakraandRatnagotravibhga.44According to Rong-zom-pa, release upon seeing true reality is an idea common to all Buddhistsystems,45 which implies that the actual spiritual breakthrough inBuddhism is intellectual and not emotional.46

    (c) The Epistemological Presuppositions of the Theory

    The basic epistemological assumption is that a variety of perceptions ofone and the same entity x is possible. If all sentient beings of the sixrealms (or yogins and non-yogins) were to perceive an entity or realityx in an identical way, there would be no need for a dialogue. Themain point of divergence among sentient beings of the six realms (oryogins and non-yogins) is the characteristics of a so-called mereappearance as it appears to various beings in various degrees ofimpurity and purity. Rong-zom-pa explains that (1) hungry ghostsperceive water as extremely impure (shin tu ma dag par snang); (2)human beings as somewhat impure (cung zad ma dag par snang), (3)individuals of the pure realms as pure (dag par snang), (4) yogins or

    vidydharas (knowledge bearers), who have command overphenomena, as extremely pure (shin tu dag par snang), and that (5)those who have exhausted all latent tendencies, clearly meaningbuddhas, are free from all appearances (snang ba thams cad dang bral),since for them all manifoldness has undergone complete cessation(spros pa thams cad yongs su zhi bar gyur). If all these perceptions wereequally valid or invalid, it would mean that there would be nothing thatone could call reality. If there were no such standard as the validity orinvalidity of perception, there would be no incentive for a dialogue.Rong-zom-pa thus rejects the arbitrariness of perceptual validity.

    6.THE THEORYRong-zom-pas position is that in general no perception isindependently valid or invalid. Depending on the varying degree of

    44 For several primary sources, see Wangchuk2007: 199200, n. 11.45 bDen gnyis jog tshul(p. 32.68): di ltar nyan thos kyi theg pa nas gzhi bzung nas |

    rdzogs pa chen poi mthar thug gi bar du | gang zhig yang dag pai don mthong narnam par grol lo zhes thun mong du grags pa yin la |.

    46 See also Wangchuk 2007: 4345, 199200.

  • 8/13/2019 Dorji Wangchuk, A Relativity Theory of the Purity and Validity of Perception in Indo-Tibetan Buddhism. In Eli Fran

    19/27

    232 DO R J I WA N G C H U K

    purity and impurity of perception, there is only a relative validity ofperception; that is, the human perception of appearance x as water ispure, and thus valid, when compared to the pretas perception of it aspus, but is impure when compared to the gods perception of it asnectar, and thus invalid. The most maculate and thus the most invalidperception of all is that of a hell-being, whereas the most immaculateand thus the most valid perception of all is that of one who is subject tono obscuration whatsoever. It is this theory that I call the relativitytheory of the purity and validity of perception, and it can be formulatedas: The validity of perception is directly proportional to the purity ofperception.47

    7.THE INDIAN BACKGROUND OF THE THEORY

    While Rong-zom-pa certainly deserves credit for suggesting that thedegree of purity of perception determines the degree of its validity, it isclear that he drew his inspiration from Indian sources, particularlyregarding the validity of yogic versus non-yogic perceptions. The idea

    that the perception of a person who has attained salvific release caninvalidate the perception of a person who is still bound can also befound in several Indian sources. For example, Candrakrti argued that anon-yogin who has no gnosis and is not released is not an authority, andthat if this were not the case, it would imply that such a person hasperceived true reality and eliminated ignorance, and this in turn would

    47 Rong-zom-pa, dKon mchog grel (p. 43.67): It should be known that if oneevaluates objectively, the purer these perceptions (snang ba), the truer (bden pa)[they are] (gzu boi blos gzhal na snang ba de dag kyang ji lta ji ltar dag pa de ltade ltar bden par shes par byao ||).Ibid. (p. 104.47): If these are evaluated with an

    objective mind, the purer the perceptions (mthong ba), the truer (bden pa) [they are],inasmuch as [the objects of valid perceptions] are objects [perceived by] the lordsamong those who have purified the obscurations (varaa: sgrib pa), and because[perceptions] are relatively (ltos te rnam par bzhag na) enduring and non-deceiving(brtan zhing mi bslu ba) (de rnams la gzu boi blos gzhal bar byas na | ji ltar ji ltarmthong ba dag pa de ltar de ltar bden pa yin te | sgrib pai dri ma dag pa rnams kyidbang po rnams kyi yul yin pai phyir dang | ltos te rnam par bzhag na brtan zhingmi bslu bai phyir ro ||).Ibid. (p. 105.23): if an objective assessment is made, as[stated] above, the [degree of] correctness corresponds to the [degree of] purity (gzu boi blos rnam par gzhag na | ji ltar dag pa ltar rig [= rigs]pa che ba ni snga mabzhin no ||).

  • 8/13/2019 Dorji Wangchuk, A Relativity Theory of the Purity and Validity of Perception in Indo-Tibetan Buddhism. In Eli Fran

    20/27

    PU R I T Y A N D VA L I D I T Y O F PE R C E P T I O N 233

    imply the redundancy of the spiritual paths of the noble ones (rya-mrga: phags pai lam).48That an undefiled cognition of a yogin caninvalidate the defiled cognition of a non-yogin and not vice versa hasbeen clearly stated by him in hisMadhyamakvatra:49

    The perception of eyes with a timira[disorder]Does not invalidate the perception [of eyes] without a timira[disorder].Similarly, a cognition that is devoid of immaculate gnosisDoes not invalidate an immaculate cognition.

    He also states that only the gnosis of a buddha, and not other types ofgnosis, given their limitation (ekadeatva: nyi tshe ba nyid), can be

    pratyaka.50 Veridical relativism is also suggested by ntideva in hisBodhicaryvatra 9.34ab. According to him, people (loka: jig rten)are of two kinds: ordinary people (prktako loka: jig rten phal pa)and people who are yogins (yogiloka: rnal byor jig rten). Theperception or knowledge (dh: blo) of the ordinary world can beinvalidated by that of theyogiloka, but not vice versa, as made explicitby Prajkaramati.51 A qualitative distinction is also made among theperceptions of the various yogins, with the perceptions of the moreadvanced yogins successively able to invalidate the perceptions of theless advanced yogins. Following this logic, buddhajna, or the

    yogipratyakaof a buddha, will certainly be assumed to be the supremecognition that can invalidate the perceptions of all yogins who have notyet attained Buddhahood.52 In particular, Majurmitras Bodhicitta-bhvanandBodhicittabhvannirdea (also attributed to him) seem tohave directly inspired Rong-zom-pa.53

    48 Candrakrti,Madhyamakvatra6.30.49 Madhyamakvatra6.27:

    mig ni rab rib can gyi dmigs pa yis ||

    rab rib med shes la gnod min ji ltar ||de bzhin dri med ye shes spangs pai blos ||dri med blo la gnod pa yod ma yin||.

    50 Madhyamakvatra 6.214.51 Bodhicaryvatrapajik(p. 158.11).52 Cf. Ngrjuna,Ratnval4.91.53 Bodhicittabhvan(P, fols. 2b73a2; D, fol. 2b13; S, vol. 33, pp. 810.18811.5);

    Bodhicittabhvannirdea (P, fol. 59a5b5; D, fol. 48a17; S, vol. 33, pp. 188.20189.20). See particularly the latter(P, fol. 59a8; D, fol. 48a3; S, vol. 33, p. 189.67):sems can gyis mthong ba rnams ni khrul pa yin par mngon no ||; ibid. (P, fol. 59b5;D, fol. 48a7; S, vol. 33, p. 189.1820): de ltar sems can gyismthong ba rnams ni rig

  • 8/13/2019 Dorji Wangchuk, A Relativity Theory of the Purity and Validity of Perception in Indo-Tibetan Buddhism. In Eli Fran

    21/27

    234 DO R J I WA N G C H U K

    8.CONCLUDING REMARKS

    We have seen that the only feasible ontology for Rong-zom-pa is mereappearance, which is rootless, unrestricted, invariable, soteriologicallyneutral, and yet the only viable basis for sasra and nirva.Strikingly, for him, mere appearance, like a mirage, operates inaccordance with the principle of dependent origination (rten cing brel

    bar byung ba:prattyasamutpda). Depending on the presence orabsence of causes and conditions, it may appear or disappear. What hedoes seem to posit is the sphere in which the mere appearance operates,namely, the dharmadhtu, the sphere of reality itself, just as he positsthe space in which mirages appear or disappear. According to hisepistemology, a mere appearance may be perceived as extremelyimpure, somewhat impure, pure, extremely pure, or not perceived at all,and the degree of the purity of perception determines the degree of itsvalidity. Here the person by whom mere appearance is not perceived atall is a buddha, whose gnosis (if it exists at all)54 represents the upperlimit of the perceptual scale. Just as a mirage is an optical illusion andthe perception of it a perceptual delusion, a mere appearance is anillusion, and the perception of it, no matter how pure or impure,ultimately a mere delusion. A buddha, being free from all delusions,perceives no illusions. Not perceiving an optical illusion such as amirage in the open air may be designated as seeing space. Similarly, notperceiving any mere appearance in the dharmadhtu, the sphere ofreality, is clearly designated as perceiving the dharmadhtu.

    ABBREVIATIONS AND BIBLIOGRAPHY

    Almogi 1997 Orna Almogi, The Life and Works of Rong-zom Paita.MA thesis. Hamburg: University of Hamburg, 1997.

    Almogi2006 Id., Rong-zom-pas Discourses on Traditional Buddho-logy: A Study of the Development of the Concept ofBuddhahood with Special Reference to the ControversySurrounding the Existence of Gnosis (ye shes: jna) atthe Stage of a Buddha. Doctoral Dissertation. Hamburg:University of Hamburg, 2006.

    [= rigs] pas kyang khrul par [ba D] mngon zhing | sangs rgyas kyi lung las kyangkhrul pa yin par gsungs so ||.

    54 On the Indian and Tibetan controversies on whether a buddha possesses gnosis(jna: ye shes), see Almogi 2006.

  • 8/13/2019 Dorji Wangchuk, A Relativity Theory of the Purity and Validity of Perception in Indo-Tibetan Buddhism. In Eli Fran

    22/27

    PU R I T Y A N D VA L I D I T Y O F PE R C E P T I O N 235

    Baghramian2004 Maria Baghramian, Relativism. London and New York:Routledge, 2004.

    bDen gnyis jog tshul Rong-zom Chos-kyi-bzang-po, Grub mtha so soi bdengnyis kyi jog tshul. InRS, vol. 2, pp. 2934.

    Bodhicaryvatrapajik P. L. Vaidya, ed.,Bodhicaryvatra of ntideva with theCommentary Pajik of Prajkaramati. BuddhistSanskrit Texts 12. Darbhanga: The Mithila Institute,1960.

    Bodhicittabhvan Majurmitra, Bodhicittabhvan. P 3418; D 2591; S1497, vol. 33.

    Bodhicittabhvannirdea Id. (ascribed), Bodhicittabhvandvdarthanirdea. P3405; D, 2578; S 1484, vol. 33.

    Bodhisattvabhmi Unrai Wogihara, ed., Bodhisattvabhmi: A Statement ofWhole Course of the Bodhisattva (being fifteenth sectionof Yogcrabhmi). 193036. Reprint: Tokyo: SankiboBuddhist Book Store, 1971.

    bsTan pai mdzes rgyan mKhan-po Kun-bzang-dpal-ldan, Gangs rii khrod kyismra bai seng ge gcig pu jam mgon mi pham rgyamtshoi rnam thar snying po bsdus pa dang gsung rab kyidkar chag snga gyur bstan pai mdzes rgyan . InMS,vol.8/h, pp. 621731.

    Bsteh2000 Andreas Bsteh, ed., Der Buddhismus als Anfrage anchristliche Theologie und Philosophie. Mdling: VerlagSt. Gabriel, 2000.

    D The sDe-dge Edition of the bsTan-gyur. Nos. accordingto: Hakuju Ui et al., ed., A Complete Catalogue of theTibetan Buddhist Canons (Bka-gyur and Bstan-gyur).Sendai: Thoku Imperial University, 1934.

    dBu ma rgyan grel Mi-pham rNam-rgyal-rgya-mtsho, dBu ma rgyan gyirnam bshad jam dbyangs bla ma dgyes pai zhal lung . In

    MS, vol. 13/nga, pp. 1359.dGongs pa rab gsal Tsong-kha-pa Blo-bzang-grags-pa, bsTan bcos chen po

    dbu ma la jug pai rnam bshad dgongs pa rab gsal. InThe Collected Works (gsung bum) of the Incomparable

    Lord Tsong-kha-pa Blo-bzang-grags-pa, vol. ma, fols.

    1a303a. sKu-bum-byams-pa-gling-par-khang, n.d.dKon mchog grel Rong-zom Chos-kyi-bzang-po, rGyud rgyal gsang ba

    snying po dkon cog grel. InRS, vol. 1, pp. 31250.Franco 1997 Eli Franco, Dharmakrti on Compassion and Rebirth.

    WSTB 38. Vienna: Arbeitskreis fr tibetische undbuddhistische Studien Universitt Wien, 1997.

    Frauwallner 1957 E. Frauwallner, Zu den Buddhistischen Texten in derZeit khri-srong-lde-btsans. WZKS1, pp. 95103.

    Hetuvidy Jagadshwar Pandeya, ed., Baudhhcrya Asaga ktaYogcrabhmistra me Hetuvidy. In Homage

  • 8/13/2019 Dorji Wangchuk, A Relativity Theory of the Purity and Validity of Perception in Indo-Tibetan Buddhism. In Eli Fran

    23/27

    236 DO R J I WA N G C H U K

    Jagadish Kashyap, ed. P. N. Ojha. Nalanda: Siri NavaNalanda Mahavihara, 1986, pp. 315349.

    Jackson 1987 David Jackson, The Entrance Gate for the Wise (SectionIII): Sa-skya Paita on Indian and Tibetan Traditions ofPrama and Philosophical Debate. 2 vols. WSTB 17.Vienna: Arbeitskreis fr tibetische und buddhistischeStudien, Universitt Wien, 1987.

    Jinpa 2002 Thubten Jinpa, Self, Reality and Reason in Tibetan

    Philosophy: Tsongkhapas Quest for the Middle Way.London & New York: Routledge Curzon, 2002.

    Kapstein 2001 Matthew T. Kapstein, Mi-phams Theory ofInterpretation. In Reasons Traces: Identity and

    Interpretation in Indian and Tibetan Buddhist Thought.Studies in Indian and Tibetan Buddhism. Boston: WisdomPublications, 2001, pp. 317343.

    van derKuijp1989 Leonard W. J. van der Kuijp,An Introduction to Gtsang-nag-pas Tshad-ma rnam-par nges-pai i-ka legs-bshadbsdus-pa: An Ancient Commentary on DharmakrtisPramavinicaya, Otani University Collection No.13971. Otani University Tibetan Works Series 2. Kyoto:Rinsen Book Co., 1989.

    Legs bshad snang bai gter Mi-pham rNam-rgyal-rgya-mtsho, Tshad ma rnam grelgyi gzhung gsal por bshad pa legs bshad snang bai gter.InMS, vol. 20.

    Madhyamakvatra Louis de La Valle Poussin, ed.,Madhyamakvatra parCandrakrti. Traduction tibtaine. Bibliotheca Buddhica9. St. Petersburg: Imprimerie de lAcadmie impriale dessciences, 1912.

    mDo rgyas Rong-zom Chos-kyi-bzang-po,Dam tshig mdo rgyas chenmo. InRS, vol. 2, pp. 241389.

    mDo sde rgyan grel Mi-pham rNam-rgyal-rgya-mtsho, Theg pa chen po mdosdei rgyan gyi dgongs don rnam par bshad pa thegmchog bdud rtsii dga ston. InMS, vol. 2/a, pp. 1760.

    mKhas jug Id., mKhas pai tshul la jug pai sgo zhes bya bai bstanbcos. InMS, vol. 22, pp. 1327.

    MS Jam mgon ju mi pham rgya mtshoi gsung bum rgyas pasde dge dgon chen par ma. The Expanded Redaction of theComplete Works of Ju Mi-pham. Reconstructed andreproduced from the surviving prints at the order of H. H.Dilgo Chhentse Rimpoche. Paro: Lama Ngodrup &Sherab Drimey, 19841993.

    Mlamadhyamakakrik Jan William de Jong, ed., Mlamadhyamakakrik ofNgrjuna. Madras: Adyar, 1977.

    Nagasaki 1991 Hjun Nagasaki, Perception in Pre-Dignga BuddhistTexts. In Studies in the Buddhist EpistemologicalTradition: Proceedings of the Second International

  • 8/13/2019 Dorji Wangchuk, A Relativity Theory of the Purity and Validity of Perception in Indo-Tibetan Buddhism. In Eli Fran

    24/27

    PU R I T Y A N D VA L I D I T Y O F PE R C E P T I O N 237

    Dharmakrti Conference, Vienna, June 1116, 1989, ed.Ernst Steinkellner. Vienna: Verlag der sterreichischenAkademie der Wissenschaften, 1991, pp. 221225.

    Negi19932005 J. S. Negi et al., Tibetan-Sanskrit Dictionary. 16 vols.Dictionary Unit. Sarnath: Central Institute of HigherTibetan Studies, 19932005.

    Nges shes sgron me Mi-pham rNam-rgyal-rgya-mtsho,Nges shes rin po cheisgron me. InMS, vol. 9/shr, pp. 71123.

    Od gsal snying po Mi-pham rNam-rgyal-rgya-mtsho, gSang grel phyogs bcumun sel gyi spyi don od gsal snying po . In MS, vol. 19,pp. 1271.

    P The Peking Edition of the bsTan-gyur. Nos. according to:Daisetz T. Suzuki, ed., The Tibetan Tripitaka. PekingEdition: Catalogue & Index. Reduced-size Edition.Kyoto: Rinsen Book Co., 1985.

    Pettit 1999 John W. Pettit, Miphams Beacon of Certainty:Illuminating the View of Dzogchen, the Great Perfection.Boston: Wisdom Publications, 1999.

    Powers2004 John Powers,Hermeneutics and Tradition in the Sadhi-nirmocana-stra. Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 2004.

    Pramavrttiklakra Rhula Sktyyana, ed. Pramavrttikabhshyam or

    Vrtiklakra of Prajkaragupta (Being a commen-tary on Dharmakrtis Pramavrtikam). Patna: KashiPrasad Jayaswal Research Institute, 1953.

    Pramavinicaya Ernst Steinkellner, ed., Dharmakrtis Pramavinicaya.Chapters 1 and 2. Vienna: Austrian Academy of SciencesPress, 2007.

    Rang byung ye shes Rong-zom-pa Chos-kyi-bzang-po, Rong zom chos bzanggis mdzad pai rang byung ye shes chen poi bras bu rol

    pai dkyil khor du blta bai yi ge. InRS, vol. 2, pp. 111130.

    Ratnval Michael Hahn, ed., Ngrjunas Ratnval. Vol. 1: TheBasic Texts (Sanskrit, Tibetan, Chinese). Indica et Tibetica1. Bonn: Indica et Tibetica Verlag, 1982.

    rDo rje gsang rgyud rDo rje gsang bai snying po rtsa bai rgyud de kho na

    nyid nges pa. In rNying ma rgyud bum [mTshams-bragEdition], vol. 22/za, pp. 322480. Thimphu: NationalLibrary of Bhutan, 1982.

    RS Rong zom chos bzang gi gsung bum. 2 vols. Chengdu: Si-khron-mi-rigs-dpe-skrun-khang, 1999.

    S bsTan gyur (dpe bsdur ma). Sichuan: Krung-goi-bod-kyi-shes-rig-dpe-skrun-khang, 19942005.

    Sadhinirmocanastra tienne Lamotte, ed. & tr., Sadhinirmocanastra: LExplication des mystres. Texte tibtain dit et traduit.Louvain / Paris: Bureau du Recueil, 1935.

  • 8/13/2019 Dorji Wangchuk, A Relativity Theory of the Purity and Validity of Perception in Indo-Tibetan Buddhism. In Eli Fran

    25/27

    238 DO R J I WA N G C H U K

    sGyu phrul le lhag sGyu phrul le lhag. In rNying ma rgyud bum[mTshams-brag Edition], vol. 20/wa, pp. 417580. Thimphu:National Library of Bhutan, 1982.

    Shes rab ral gri Mi-pham rNam-rgyal-rgya-mtsho, Don rnam par nges pashes rab ral gri. See Shes rab ral grii mchan.

    Shes rab ral grii mchan Id.,Don rnam par nges pa shes rab ral gri mchan bcas. InMS, vol. 4/pa, pp. 787820.

    sKad gnyis shan sbyar Id., sKad gnyis shan sbyar rab gsal nor bui me long. In

    MS, vol. 26, pp. 1598.sNang ba lhar sgrub Rong-zom Chos-kyi-bzang-po, gSang sngags rdo rje theg

    pai tshul las snang ba lhar bsgrub pa rong zom chosbzang gis mdzad pa. InRS, vol. 1, pp. 559568.

    rvakabhmi rvakabhmi Study Group, ed., rvakabhmi: RevisedSanskrit Text and Japanese Translation. The FirstChapter. Taish University Sg Bukky KenkyjoSeries 4. The Institute for Comprehensive Studies ofBuddhism, TaishUniversity. Tokyo: The Sankibo Press,1998.

    Steinkellner1984 Ernst Steinkellner, Miszellen zur Erkenntnis-theoretischen-logischen Schule des Buddhismus: IV.Candragomin, der Autor des Nyyasiddhyloka. WZKS

    28, 1984, pp. 177178.Steinkellner1989 Id., Who is Bya chub rdzu phrul? Tibetan and non-Tibetan Commentaries on the Sadhinirmocanastra- ASurvey of the literature. Berliner Indologische Studien4/5, ed. Institut fr Indische Philologie und Kunst-geschichte der Freien Universitt Berlin. Reinbek: Dr.Inge Wezler Verlag fr Orientalistische Fachpublika-tionen, 1989, pp. 229251.

    Steinkellner 2005 Ernst Steinkellner, Digngas Pramasamuccaya,Chapter 1: A hypothetical reconstruction of the Sanskrittext with the help of the two Tibetan translations on thebasis of the hitherto known Sanskrit fragments and thelinguistic materials gained from Jinendrabuddhis k.www.oeaw.ac.at/ias/Mat/dignaga_PS_1.pdf (April 2005).

    Steinkellner 2007 Ernst Steinkellner, ed., Dharmakrtis Pramavinicaya.Chapters 1 and 2. Vienna: Austrian Academy of SciencesPress, 2007.

    Theg tshul Rong-zom Chos-kyi-bzang-po, Theg pa chen poi tshul lajug pa zhes bya bai bstan bcos. In RS, vol. 2, pp. 415555.

    Tho yig Rong-pa Me-dpung, rJe dharma bha dras mdzad paichos kyi rnam grangs kyi tho yig. In RS, vol. 2, pp. 233239.

    Tshig don mdzod Klong-chen-rab-byams-pa Dri-med-od-zer, gSang babla na med pa od gsal rdo rje snying poi gnas gsum gsal

  • 8/13/2019 Dorji Wangchuk, A Relativity Theory of the Purity and Validity of Perception in Indo-Tibetan Buddhism. In Eli Fran

    26/27

    PU R I T Y A N D VA L I D I T Y O F PE R C E P T I O N 239

    bar byed pai tshig don rin po chei mdzod. In mDzodbdun. Gangtok: Dodrup Chen Rinpoche, n.d. Reprint:Thimphu: National Library of Bhutan, n.d., vol. nya.

    Vetter 1966 Tilmann Vetter, Dharmakrtis Pramavinicaya, 1.Kapitel: Pratyakam. Einleitung, Text der tibetischenbersetzung, Sanskritfragmente, deutsche bersetzung.Vienna: Hermann Bhlaus Nachf., Kommissionsverlagder sterreichischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, 1966.

    Vigrahavyvartan Kamaleswar Bhattacharya, E.H. Johnson, and ArnoldKunst, ed. & tr., The Dialectical Method of Ngrjuna:Vigrahavyvartan. Fourth Edition (Revised andEnlarged): Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1998.

    Wangchuk 2004 Dorji Wangchuk, The ri-ma Interpretations of theTathgatagarbha Theory. WZKS 48, 2004 [appeared in2005], pp. 171213.

    Wangchuk2007 Id., The Resolve to Become a Buddha: A Study of theBodhicitta Concept in Indo-Tibetan Buddhism. StudiaPhilologica Buddhica Monograph Series 23. Tokyo: TheInternational Institute for Buddhist Studies, 2007.

    WSTB Wiener Studien zur Tibetologie und BuddhismuskundeWZKS Wiener Zeitschrift fr die Kunde Sdasiens

  • 8/13/2019 Dorji Wangchuk, A Relativity Theory of the Purity and Validity of Perception in Indo-Tibetan Buddhism. In Eli Fran

    27/27

    240 DO R J I WA N G C H U K