bok christian - pataphyscs -- the poetics of an imaginary science

258
'PATAPHYSICS: THE POETICS OF AN IMAGINARY SCIENCE CHRISTIAN BOK A thesis submitted to the Faculty of Graduate Studies in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Graduate Programme in English York University North York, Ontario December 1997

Upload: grundum

Post on 30-Sep-2015

22 views

Category:

Documents


7 download

DESCRIPTION

Bok Christian - Pataphyscs -- The Poetics of an Imaginary Science

TRANSCRIPT

  • 'PATAPHYSICS: THE POETICS OF AN IMAGINARY SCIENCE

    CHRISTIAN BOK

    A thesis submitted to the Faculty of Graduate Studies in partial fulfillment of the requirements

    f o r t h e degree of

    Doctor of Philosophy

    Graduate Programme in English York University

    North Y o r k , Ontario

    December 1 9 9 7

  • National Library Bibliothque nationale du Canada

    Acquisitions and Acquisitions et Bibliographie Services services bibliographiques 395 Wellington Street 395. nie Wellington Ottawa ON K1A ON4 OttawaON K1AON4 Canada Canada

    The author has granted a non- exclusive licence allowing the National Library of Canada to reproduce, loan, distribute or sell copies of this thesis in rnicroform, paper or electronic formats.

    The author retains ownership of the copyright in this thesis. Neither the thesis nor substantial extracts fiom it may be printed or otherwise reproduced without the author's permission.

    L'auteur a accord une licence non exclusive permettant la Bibliothque nationale du Canada de reproduire, prter, distribuer ou vendre des copies de cette thse sous la forme de microfiche/film, de reproduction sur papier ou sur format lectronique.

    L'auteur conserve la proprit du droit d'auteur qui protge cette thse. Ni la thse ni des extraits substantiels de celle-ci ne doivent tre imprims ou autrement reproduits sans son autorisation.

    Canada

  • PATAPHYS ICS : THE FOETICS OF AN I M A G I N A R Y SCIENCE

    by C H R I S T I A N BOK

    a dissertation submitted to the Faculty of Graduate Studies of York University in partial fulfillrnent of the requirements for the degree of

    DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY

    O 1998 Permission has been granted to the LlBRARY OF YORK C;NIVERSITY to lend or seIl copies of this dissertation, to the NATIONAL L18RARY OF CANADA to microfilm this dissertation and to lend or sel1 copies of the film. and to UNIVERSITY MICROFILMS to publish an abstract of this dissertation. The author reserves other publication rights, and neither the dissertation nor extensive extracts from it may be printed or othenivise reproduced without the author's written permission.

  • ABSTRACT

    'Pata~hssics: The Poetics of an Imaainarv Science is a

    survey that attempts to describe a hypothetic philosophp-

    the avant-garde pseudo-science imagined by Alfred Jarry.

    'Pataphysics is a supplement to metaphysics, accenting it,

    then replacing it, in order to create a philosophic

    alternative, whose discipline can study cases, not of

    conception, but of exception: variance (anomalos), alliance

    (syzuaia), and deviance (clinamen). 'Pataphysics

    synthesizes the romantic schism between a literal,

    scientized discourse and a figural, poeticized discourse,

    and my thesis suggests that this revision of the signifier

    "science" by 'pataphysics is symptomatic of a postrnodern

    transition in science from a paradigm of absolutism to a

    paralogy of relativism. Structured as a descriptive

    explication, which emphasizes a theoretical perspective,

    this survey is divided into five chapters: the first

    chapter recounts the history of the conflict between science

    and poetry (in order to contextualize 'pataphysics within

    the metaphysical philosophies of the past); the second

    chapter examines the avant-garde pseudo-science of

    'pataphysics itself (in order to contextualize 'pataphysics

    within the anti-metaphysical meta-philosophies of the

    present); and finally, the last three chapters discuss the

    influence of 'pataphysics upon the poetics of its subsequent

  • successors (first, the Italian Futurists; second, the French

    Oulipians; and third, the Canadian "Pataphysicians). While

    mg thesis focuses upon theories of textual poetics rather

    than poetry itself (relyLng upon the kind o f Nietzschean

    sophistries that have come to characterize postmodern

    p h i l o s o p h y ) , my thesis does nevertheless trive to be as conceptually encyclopedic as 'pataphysics itself: instead

    of normalizing 'pataphysics within one theoretical

    perspective, this survey alludes intermittently to

    'pataphysical enterprises that constitute exceptions to such

    a genealogy of Jarryites. What is at stake is the status of

    poetry in a world of science. How might poetry reclaim its

    own viable truth? How might science benefit from its own

    poetic irony? For the postmodern condition, such questions

    have already opened up a novel space f o r speculative

    imagination; hence, this survey presents itself as a kind of

    primer for a future of possible reseerch.

  • PREFACE

    T h e Museum of J u r a s s i c T e c h n o l o ~ s i n Los A n g e l e s is a

    s t r a n g e g a l l e r y , where i n c r e d i b l e v e r i t i e s i n t e g r a t e s o

    p e r f e c t l y w i t h b e l i e v a b l e u n t r u t h s t h a t a v i s i t o r m a s n o t

    d e t e c t t h e p e c u l i a r s l i p p a g e f rom f a c t t o hoax. W i l s o n , t h e

    c u r a t o r , h a s r e b u i l t t h e Wunderkammern of m e d i e v a l a r c h i v e s ,

    p r e s e n t i n g c a b i n e t s and v i t r i n e s , f u l l of b i z a r r e c u r i o s a - -

    s p e c i m e n s : n o t o n l y of M s o t i s l u c i f u a u s (a b a t whose s o n a r -

    s y s t e m c a n be modulated t o create a p e r t u r e s t h r o u g h

    s u b s t a n t i v e b a r r i e r s ) , but o f Meaaloponera f o e t e n s (an a n t

    whose ne rve - sys tem c a n be c o n t r o l l e d by f u n g a l parasites f o r

    r e p l i c a t i v e p u r p o s e s ) . W i l s o n does n o t s i m p l y r e p e a t t h e

    grotesque s p e c t a c l e of R i p l e y , s i n c e t h e museum d o e s n o t

    p r e s e n t t h e t r u t h of the a b s u r d w i t h t h e command: b e l i e v e

    it o r n o t ! - - i n s t e a d , t h e museum p r e s e n t s t h e t r u t h as i t s e l f

    a b s u r d w i t h t h e q u e s t i o n : w h a t is it t o b e l i e v e o r not?

    Wesch le r o b s e r v e s t h a t "Wi l son h a s [ . . . ] p i t c h e d h i s

    museum a t t h e very i n t e r s e c t i o n o f t h e premodern and t h e

    pos tmodern" ( g o ) , i n s e r t i n g t h e v i s i t o r i n t o t h e i n t e r s t i c e be tween wondering-at a n d wondering-whetherl--a gap into

    which t h i s s u r v e y w i s h e s t o i n s e r t i ts own r e a d e r . What

    W i l s o n c a l l s " J u r a s s i c t echno logy ," w e might cal1 " J a r r y i t e

    ' p a t a p h y s i c s W - - a science of imaginary s o l u t i o n s , i n which

    the c r i t i c wishes not o n l y t o study, but also t o e v o k e ,

  • cases of exceptional singularity. Like Jarry (who wilfully

    occupies an ambiguous interzone between ratiocination and

    hallucination), Wilson hopes to imbricate the technical

    truth of modern science with the medieval magic of poetic

    wisdom. This survey, likewise, strives to indulge in s u c h a

    figura1 project, since it too proposes the potential existence of a, heretofore chimerical, science.

    'Pataphysics represents a supplement to metaphysics,

    accenting it, then replacing it, in order to create a

    philosophic alternative to rationalism. What Wilson has

    performed, Jarry has predicted: the disappearance of

    scientificity itself when reason is pushed to its own

    logical extreme. Such a 'pataphysical qualification of

    rational validity is symptomatic of a postmodern transition

    in science frorn absolutism to relativism, When even time

    itself fades away into spectacular uncertainty, the very

    idea that an historical technology might be called

    "jurassic" no longer seems wholly absurd (since w e can now

    imagine a futuristic apocalypse, in which cloning might

    allow a human tu coexist with a resurrected tyrannosaur--

    j u s t as cinema has cloned the image of an actual thespian

    and spliced it with the image of an unreal sauropod). 2

    'Pataphysics is speculative, waiting for its chance to

    happen, as if by accident, in a themepark of scientific

  • viii

    conception. Like the museum of Wilson, this thesis on Jarry

    attempts to scramble the jurassic sequence of history so that what is extinct in the past can be called forth again

    out of its context into the present where the idea of the

    past itself can in t u r n be made e ~ t i n c t . ~ For 'pataphysics,

    any science sufficiently retarded in progress must seem

    magical (but only after the fact), just as any science sufficiently advanced in progress must seem magical (but

    only before the fact)--and if 'pataphysics is itself

    thaumaturgic, it is so, not because of any ironic nostalgia

    for a prehistoric past, but only because of its oneiric

    prognosis for an ahistoric future. We see science itself

    vanish before the zero-degree of its own anti-science.

    Structured as a descriptive explication, which

    emphasizes a theoretical perspective, this survey argues

    that Jarry has provided an often neglected, but still

    important, influence upon the poetic legacy of this century

    (particularly the Italian Futurists, the French Oulipians,

    and the Canadian "Pataphysicians ) . Wbile my thes is focuses

    upon theories of textual poetics rather than poetry itself

    (relying upon the kind of Nietzschean sophistries that have

    corne to characterize the work of such French rebels as

    Baudrillard, Deleuze, Derrida, Serres, et al.), my thesis

    does nevertheless strive to be as conceptually encyclopedic

    as 'pataphysics itself: instead of normalizing 'pataphysics

  • within one thecretical perspective, this survey alludes

    intermittently to 'pataphysical enterprises that constitute

    exceptions to such a genealogy of Jarryites.

    Recounting the transition from 'pataphysics to

    "pataphysics (from the single apostrophe of France to the

    double apostrophe of Canada), this survey reflects the

    influence of Jarry upon my own poetic career (in particular:

    my 'pataphysical encyclopedia, ~r~stalloara~hu). Inspired

    by the etymology of the word "crystallography," such a work

    represents an act of lucid writinq, which uses the language

    of geological science to misread the poetics of rhetorical

    language. Such lucid writing is not concerned with the

    transparent transmission of a message (so that, ironically,

    the poetry is often "opaque");' instead, lucid writing is

    simply concerned with the exploratory reflexivity of its o w n

    pattern (in a manner reminiscent of lucid dreaminq). The

    capricious philosophg of 'pataphysics is itself an oneiric

    science aware of its own status as a dream.

    'Pataphysics reveals that science is not as "lucid" as

    once thought, since science must often ignore the arbitrary,

    if not whimsical, status of its own axioms. Like the work

    of some 'pataphysicians (particularly the Oulipians), who

    make a spectacle of such epistemic formality by writing

    texts according to an absurd, but strict, rule of machinic

  • artifice, this survey also expresses its own extreme of

    nomic rigor ( in this case, grammatical parallelism ) : each

    sentence develops a chiastic symmetry as balanced as the

    contrast in physics between meta and pata. The a r b i t r a r y

    character of such a constraint does not simply constitute a

    stylistic frivolity, but strives 'pataphysically (if not

    allegorically) to dramatize a scientific perversion: that

    the universe is itself an a r b i t r a r y formality, whose rules

    have created a science that can in turn discuss such rules.

    'Pataphysics valorizes the exception to each r u l e in

    order to subvert the procrustean constraints of science.

    While this survey may do little to change the mind of a

    customary scientist (who must ignore the 'pataphysical

    peculiarity of science itself in order to avoid the c h a r g e

    of crackpot delusion), my survey may nevertheless convince

    poets to qualify their own ludditic attitude toward science.

    Such poets might recognize that, if poetry cannot oppose

    science by becoming its antonyrnic extreme, perhaps poetry

    can oppose science by becoming its hyperbolic extrerne, using

    reason aqainst itself 'pataphysically in order to subvert

    not only pedantic theories of noetic truth, but also

    romantic theories of poetic genius. Such poets might learn

    to embrace the absurd nature of sophistic reasoning in order

    to dispute the power of both the real and the true.

  • Vaneigem, however, warns us that, because of this

    sophistry, "Joe Soap intellectuals, [']pataphysicians[ . . . f i -

    bandwagon after bandwagon works out its own version of the

    credo quia absurdum est: you [do notJ believe in it, but

    you do it anyway" (178) so that, as a result, " [ 'plata-

    physics[ . . . ] leads us with many a twist and turn to the last graveyards" (126). While such charges of nihilistic

    conformism do apply to the work of some 'pataphysicians

    (particularly Sandomir and Shattuck), such misgivings do not

    take into account that, like Nietzsche, Jarry does

    radicalize philosophy, lampooning pedagogic authority, in

    order to foment a spirit o f permanent rebellion, be it anti-

    bourgeois or anti-philistine.' My thesis argues that this

    apparent strategy of "indifference" in 'pataphysics merely

    serves to satirize t h e impartiality of sciexe i t s e l f .

    'Pataphysics refuses to conform to any academic

    standard: hence, this survey cannot demonstrate that it has

    learned the lessons of its t o p i c without also negotiating a

    virtually untenable ambiguity between the noetic mandate of

    scholarship and the poetic license of 'pataphysics itself.

    Since no literary history has ever traced in detail the

    unorthodox genealogy of this avant-garde pseudo-science, 1

    hope that my survey might in effect o f f e r a Wunderkammern of

    literary teratism, cataloguing the scientific exceptions to

    the given n o m s of poetry in order to create an absurd

  • museum of " jurassic" machines. J u s t as the anachronism of an iron tool from before the Ice Age might d i s r u p t our sense

    of temporal security, so a l s o might such an archive of

    anomaly r e c o n t e x t u a l i z e the g iven canon of modern poetry.

    Let u s imagine a fu ture for such an impossible philosophy.

  • x i i i

    Notes to Preface

    l~eschler observes that , because the M ~ o t i s

    lucifuaus is a hoax, while the Meaaloponera foetens is a

    fact, "[tlhe Jurassic infects its visitor with doubts--

    little curlicues of misgiving--that proceed to infest

    all[ . . . ] other dealings with the Culturally Sacrosanct" (40).

    2 ~ h e Jurassic Park of Crichton, for example,

    dramatizes a 'pataphysical domain, in which a science of

    operative risks (chaotic mathematics) indicts a science of

    irnperative tasks (genetic engineering) for practising

    "thintelligence' ( 2 8 4 ) - - a clever truth with wanton power.

    '~urassic technology demolishes the rnernory of the

    museum so that the museum can no longer function properly as

    a mausoleum for what has otherwise been forgotten: there,

    we do n o t remember what e x i s t s in the past so much as

    remember that the past itself does not exist.

    - ' ~ r ~ s t a l l o ~ r a ~ h y strives to achieve a state of

    "birefrigence," offering two perspectives at the same time

    from the focal point of a single lens, if not from the acute

    angle of a poetic word: in other words, lucid writing does

    not transmit so much as diffract a given meaning.

  • x i v

    'vaneigeln must admit that , when active rather than

    passive, such nihilism does evoke revolutionary sensi-

    bilities: "Nietzsche's[ ...] i r o n y L . 1 , Jarry's Umour[ ...]-- these are some of the impulses[ ...] investing human con- sciousness with[ . . . ]a true reversa1 of perspective" ( 177 ) .

  • TABLE OF CONTENTS

    Abstract

    Preface

    Science and Poetry: The Poetics of the Ur in 'Pataphysics

    Millenial 'Pataphysics: The Poetics of an Imaginary Science

    Italian Futurism: A 'Pataphysics of Machinic Exception

    French Oulipianism: A 'Pataphysics of Mathetic Exception

    Canadian " Pataphysics : A 'Pataphysics of Mnemonic Exception

    Texts Cited

    iv - v

    vi - xiv

  • 1

    Science and Poetrs: The Differend of the Ur in 'Pata~hvsics

    nNon cum vacaveris, ~atavhssicandum est."

    (Jarry 1965:39 )

    "[TJhe encyclopaedia said: For one of these

    pnostics, the visible universe was aQ

    i l l u s i o n or (more ~recisels) a sophism." (Borges 1983: 8 )

    "The debt that ['Ipataphysics owes to sophism

    cannot be overstated." (Bernstein 1994:105)

    Quasi-Healities

    Borges in T l h , Uqbar , Orbis Tertius imagines an

    allegory about the seductions of s imulation. A secret cabal

    of rebel artists has conspired to replace the a c t u a l w o r l d ,

    piece by piece, with a virtual world, so that the inertia of

    a true history vanishes, phase by phase, into the amnesia of

    a false memory. The irony is that this conspiracy meets

    with no resistance: lq[a]lmost immediately, reality yielded

    on more than one account" for "[tlhe t r u t h is that it longed

    to yield" (1983:22)--to disappear into its own phantasms.

    Al1 things embrace the weirdness of this astonishing event

  • and ignore the piousness of al1 admonishing truth. The

    event foments a revolution in philosophy--a shift away from

    the nomic study of what is veritable t o a ludic study of

    what is possible, as if "every philosophy is by definition a

    dialectical game, a Philosophie des Als Ob" ( 1 4 ) .

    Borges imagines a reality where to imagine a reality

    can cause a reality t o e x i s t ex nihilo. Each memory of an

    object conjures the miracle of an h d n , the replica of a replica; and yet, " [s] tranger and more pure than any h r h

    is, at times, the u" (an ectype without prototype), "the

    object produced through suggest ion, educed by hope" (1983: 18) .' Like the t ih i s ta s who believe that

    "metaphysics is a branch of fantastic literature" ( 1 4 ) , the narrator of this fantasy pretends to believe in such an

    imaginary philosophy, quoting fictitious references to it i n

    gazettes and treatises. His alternative to metaphysics is

    itself an ur because his dream of i t has indeed corne true,

    not only in his story but also in our world. We too fulfill

    this apocalyptic conspiracy by creating, for ourselves, a

    world where fantasy has more reality than reality itself.

    Postmodernism in fact defines itself in terms of such a

    catastrophe. Philosophy has everywhere begun to threaten

    the constraints of both the real and the true in order t o

  • practice an anti-philosophp-what Jarry might call by the

    name of '~ataahssics, the science of imaginary solutions and

    arbitrary exceptions ( 1 9 6 5 : 1 9 2 ) . Jarry suggests through 'pataphysics that reality does not exist, except as the

    interpretive projection of a phenomenal perspective-which

    is to say that reality is never as it is, but is always es

    if it is. Reality is quasi, pseudo: it is more virtual

    than actual; it is real only to the degree to which i t can

    seem to be real and only for so long as it can be made to

    stay real. Science for such a reality has increasingly

    become what Vaihinger might call a "philosophy of as if"

    (xvii), w i l f u l l y mistaking possibilities for veritabilities.

    Baudrillard observes that, for the "[']Pataphysics of

    the year 2000," history has accelerated past the escape

    velocity for reality, moving from the centrifuga1 gravity of

    the real into the centripetal celerity of the void

    (1994a:l). Events occur in the nullspace of simulation,

    where "[al11 metaphysical tension has been disaipated,

    yielding- a 'pataphysical ambiancet' (1990: 71 ) . Things succumb to relativity, complexity, and uncertainty, shifting

    from an absolute state of determinism to a dissolute field

    of indeterminism. The science of 'pataphysics responds to

    these sbsurdities with a genre of science fiction that shows

    science itself to be a fiction. It nsrrates not what is,

  • but what miaht have become. It i n h a b i t s t he t e n s e of t he

    f u t u r e p e r f e c t , o f the post modo--a paradoxical t e m p o r a l i t y ,

    i n which what h a s yet to happen has already t a k e n place.

    The U r of S c i e n c e

    Jarry claims t h a t ' pa t aphys i c s studies "the universe

    supplementary to this one," b u t n o t s i m p l y an adjunct

    reality s o much as an e r s a t z r e a l i t y , "a universe which can

    bel . . . ] envisaged i n the place o f t h e t r a d i t i o n a l one" 1 9 6 5 : 1 3 1 ) S u c h a supplement i s always more s u b s t i t u t i v e t h a n augmentative, r e p l a c i n g r e a l i t y i n s t e a d o f accent i n g

    r e a l i t y , and ironically t h e science t h a t studies auch a

    supplement i s i t s e l f a supplement. I t is " t h e science of

    t h a t which is superinduced upon metaphysicsl' as both an

    excess and a r e d r e s s , "extending as far beyond metaphysics

    as the latter e x t e n d s beyond physics" ( 131 ) . A n a u x i l i a r y

    substitute that compensates for a lack i n philosophy even as

    it impregnates the form of philosophy, such a science

    simulates knowledge , p e r p e t r a t i n g a hoax, really and truly ,

    b u t only t o r e v e a l t h e hoax of bo th t h e real and the t r u e .

    Jarry performs humorously on behalf of l i t e r a t u r e what

    Nietzsche performs seriously on behalf of philosophy. Both

    t h i n k e r s in effect attempt to dream up a gay s c i e n c e , whose

  • 5

    joie d e v ivre thrives wherever the tyranny of truth has

    increased our esteem for the lie and wherever the tyranny of

    reason has increased our esteem for the mad. Both thinkers

    lay the groundwork f o r an anti-philosophy, whose spirit of

    ref orm bas corne to characterize such alternatives to

    metaphysics as the grammatology of Derrida, the

    schizanalysis of Deleuze, or the homeorrhetics of Serres.

    Al1 such anti-metaphysical meta-philosophies argue that

    anomalies extrinsic to a system remain secretly i n t r i n s i c to

    such a system. The most credible of truths always e v o l v e s

    rom the most incredible of errors. The praxis o f science

    always involves the parspraxis of p o e t r y .

    'Pataphysics, " t h e science of the particular" (131),

    does not, therefore, study the rules governing the general

    recurrence o f a periodic incident ( t h e ex~ected case) so much as study the garnes governing the special occurrence of

    a sporadic accident (the excepted case). 'Pataphysics not

    only studies exception, but has itself become an exception--

    dismissed and neglected despite its influence and relevance .

    Jarry has not only inspired t h e a b s u r d i t y o f nearly every

    modern avant-garde, but has also p r e d i c t e d the absurdity of

    nearly al1 modern techno-science. No history, however, has

    ever traced in detail this unorthodox genealogy, even though

    contemporary philosophy has begun to shift its emphasis from

  • 6

    the metaphysical to the anti-metaphysical-a trend that only

    a few critics (Dufresne, McCaffery, etc.) have dared to

    descr ibe as 'pataphysical in nature.

    'Pataphysics b a s ultimately determined the horizon of

    thought f o r any encounter between philosophy and literature,

    but criticism has lasgely ignored this important principle

    of the postmodern condition. What irony: 'pataphysics has

    replaced metaphysics so slowly and subtly that, once

    noticed, the transition seems at once sudden and abrupt.

    This survey therefore intends to redress the surprise of

    such smnesia by revising the history o f both science and

    poetry i n o r d e r t o br ing 'pataphysics to bear upon

    'pataphysics itself. Such revision, of course, faces

    obstacles, not the least of which is the fact that

    'pataphysics is imaginary. No such discipline exists. What

    then is there to study? What museums can house its rel ies?

    What codexes can record its axioms? Such a science may be

    no more than an =--a l a s t hope that has yet to corne true.

    'Pataphysics does not pretend to unify its parts into a

    system or to ratify its ploys into an agenda. Such a cesual

    science has no theory, no method ( even though Jarry has since i n s p i r e d writers t o c r e a t e t h e College o f

    'Pataphysics, aspects of which allude to a fictional

  • -

    i

    archive, the Grand Academy of Lagado). Such a casual

    science also has no manual, no primer (even though Jarry has

    since inspired critics to study the Elements of

    'Pataphysics, excerpts of which appear in a fictional

    almanac, the Exploits of Doctor Faustroll). Like the

    abridged treatise on T l b , the incomplete handbook of Jarry

    compels its readers to finish the job of converting the fake image of a virtual science into a real thing in the actual

    universe. Even t h i s survey may not explain t h e existence of

    'pataphysics so much as conjure 'pataphysics i n t o existence.

    Jarry implies that such a s c i e n c e can be written only

    with an invisible ink, "sulphate of quinine," whose words

    remain unseen u n t i l read in the dark under the "infrared

    rays of a spectrum whose other colors [are] locked in an

    opaque box" ( 1 9 1 - 1 9 2 ) . Such a science cannot be seen except under a l i g h t t h a t cannot be seen in a place that cannot be

    s e e n . Such a science exists paradoxically in an eigenstate

    o f indeterminate potentiality (like the cat of Schrodinger--

    both there and n o t there at the same time). Not philosophy,

    but philosophastry, such a science at first appears

    scandalous and superfluous because it delights in the

    eclectic and the esoteric. It encourages a promiscuous

    economy of indiscriminate exchanges, playfully conjugating paradoxes in order to make possible an absolute expenditure

  • of thought without any absolute investiture in thought .

    'Pataphysics thus heralds apocalyptically what

    Baudrillard cal l s a "casual form of writing to match the

    casual &&ementialitg of our ageW--a spiralling commentary

    upon "the Grande Gidouille of History" (1994e:17). This

    survey attempts to practice such a writing of h i s t o r y in t h e

    belief that theory must explore as much as it must explain.

    To do o therwise is t o reduce t h e science of ' p a t a p h y s i c s to

    another species of hermeneutics: just a way to resd, not a

    way to live. To write against metaphysics, with its good

    sense and its good taste, is not to s h i r k the duties of the

    c r i t i c , but to wager their values against the demand for

    change. If we are to take 'pataphysics seriously, are we

    not obliged to be exceptional? If this survey t h r e a t e n s to

    meander, is this not because it imitates the vortices of a

    pidouille in order to maintain an element of s u r p r i s e ?

    Surprise b r e a k s the promise o f the expected: it is the

    exception t h a t disturbs the suspense of what we know must

    happen next. Hence, this survey offers the following

    itinerary about things to corne in the hope that we might

    later be surprised by the unexpected. This survey begins by

    tracing the h i s t o r y of the conflict between science and

    poetry in order t o contextualize 'pataphysics within the

  • four phases of such dispute (the animatismic, the

    mechanismic, the oraanismic, and the cvborganismicl. The

    survey then discusses 'pataphysics itself, defining three

    declensions of exception (the anomalos, the s y z s a i a , and the

    clinamen), in order to show the diverse parallels not only

    between the work of Jarry and Nietzsche, but also to relate

    such work to the diverse projects of such contemporary philosophers as Baudrillard, Derrida, Deleuze, and Serres.

    Subsequently, the survey traces the influence of Jarry

    on three cases of avant-garde pseudo-science (the Italian

    Futurists, the French Oulipians, and the Canadian

    "Pataphysicians). Each movement revises a prior schema

    about the structure of exception in order to disrupt the

    norrnalization of the 'pataphysical: for the Futurists,

    exception results from the collision of machines; for the

    Oulipians, exception results from the constraint of

    programs; and for the "Pataphysicians, exception results

    from the corruption of mernories. Like these movements, this

    survey also tries to avoid the normalization of the

    'pataphysical, doing so by alluding intermittently to

    'pataphysical enterprises that do not refer to the tradition

    of Jarry, but nevertheless represent some of the exceptions

    to the genealogy that this survey posits.

  • 10

    Exceptions, after all, can resort to an assortment of

    modalities: variance (anomalos), alliance (sszvgia), or

    deviance (clinamen). The anomalos finds a way to d i f f e r

    from e v e r y other thing in a system that values the norm of

    equivalence; t h e s v z s a i a finds a way to e q u a t e t h i n g s to

    each other in a system that values the norm of d i f f e r e n c e ;

    and the clinamen finds a way to to detour around things in a

    system that values t h e fate of contrivance. Al1 three modes

    of exception do inform t h i s s u r v e y on 'pataphysics so that,

    if its style r i s k s everything to d i s r u p t , to confuse, and to

    digress, it does so not for any lack of forma1 rigour, but

    for the sake of a crucial thesis. Can a ludic theory of

    'pataphysics be fairly judged by the nomic values of

    metaphysics if 'pataphysics criticizes metaphysics itself?

    Are we not obliged to consider the problem of this question?

    ' Pataphysics , strangely enough, has two parallel

    histories that act out opposite strategies for criticizing

    such a scientific metaphysics: first, the irrationalism of

    the Symbolists, the Dadaists, and the Surrealists (al1 of

    whom argue for a poetic emancipation from science); second,

    the surrationalism of the Futurists, the Oulipians, and the

    "Pataphysicians (al1 of whom argue for a poetic

    appropriation of science). Jarry has influenced both

    strategies despite their opposition. The Futurists attack

  • the Symbolists, for example, just as the Oulipians attack

    the Surrealists. Both cases of conflict pit the pragmatic

    formalism of postrnodernity against the aesthetic mysticism

    of rnodernity. What is at stake is the status of poetry in a

    world of science. How rnight poetry reclaim its own viable

    truth? Hou might science benefit from its own poetic irony?

    Surrationalism, for example, responds to such questions

    not only by using the forms of poetry to criticize the myths

    of science (its pedantic theories of expressive truth), but

    also by using the forms of science to criticize the myths of

    poetry (its romantic theories of expressive genius).

    Surrationalism has accented this conflict between science

    and poetry in three different ways. The Futurists inflect

    the machinic intensities of technological forms; the

    Oulipians inflect the mathetic intensities of numerological

    forms; and the "Pataphysicians inflect the mnemonic

    intensities of palaeological forms. This survey focuses

    largely upon these three surrational movements not only

    because -they have better expressed the original intentions

    of 'pataphysics, but also because they have received less

    critical attention from theoreticians.

    Surrationalism is t h u s j u s t as exceptional as it is 'pataphysical, defining a regime for the avant-garde, not

  • only in poetry, but also in s c i e n c e . Bachelard suggests

    that al1 scientific radicalisrn begins with "an e ~ o c h e , a

    placing of reality between parentheses" (28) so that science

    might systematically explore an otherwise impossible

    hypothesis: "it is in this area of dialectical

    surrationalism that the scientific mind dreams" (32). Every

    question about what if leads to a science of as if. No

    longer limited by one case of nature, science can propose

    many modes of reason: for example, the non-Euclidean

    geometry of Riemann or the non-Boolean algebra of Korzybski.

    We see science interrogate itself in order to relativize

    itself. It can no longer t a k e its reality for g r a n t e d , but

    must account for its history: the reason of its reason.

    Baudrillard suggests that, while metaphysics is the

    anti of simulation (opposing fantasy with ever more

    r e a l i t y ) , 'pataphysics is the ante of simulation (opposing fantasy with ever more fantasy) : "only a 1 ' l~ata~hvsics of simulacra c a n remove us rom the[. ..lstrategy of simulation

    and the impasse of death i n which it imprisons us," and

    "[t]his supreme ruse of the system[. . . ] , only a superior ruse can stop" (1994b:153-154). Metaphysics is a supreme

    ruse because it makes us believe in the true; 'pataphysics

    is a superior ruse because it lets us pretend to be untrue.

    Truth implodes upon itself and reveals an aporia at its

  • 13

    centre - - the "[dlead point[ ...] where every system crosses this subtle limit of[ .,.] contradiction [....]and enters live into non-contradictionw--the ecstasy of thought: "[hlere

    begins a ['lpataphysics of systems" (1990:14).

    The Ur of Historv

    Beginnings: let us digress for a moment; let us begin

    with a swerve. Ubu, the "Professor of ['lpataphysics,"

    steps on stage at the turn of t h e century in order to

    announce "a branch of science which we have invented and for

    which a crying need is generally experienced" ( 1 9 6 5 : 2 6 - 2 7 ) . An imaginary science thus makes its debut in a millenary

    instant, appearing at the transition from a romantic era to

    a modernist era, when metaphysics has totalized, but not yet

    optimized, its power to speak the truth. If poetry has

    failed to oppose science by being its antonymic extreme,

    then perhaps poetry c m attempt to oppose science by being

    i ts hyperbolic extreme. A n absurd science t h a t might

    dissect contradictions, has itself enacted contradictions.

    It has simultaneously affirmed and negated, not only its

    belief in, but also its doubts about, the values of reason.

    Science has historically legitimated itself by

    practicing a contemvtus historia. Theories in the past that

  • d i f f e r from theories in the present must forfeit t h e i r

    validity. History becomes nothing more than what Canguilhem

    might cal1 le ~ a s s d d k ~ s s s d ( 27 ) , a museum of error, where

    time can cause any concept to becorne as quaint as a

    metaphor . 2 Whenever science d e i g n s to think its h i s t o r y , it

    narrates a transition from the falsity of poetry to the

    verity of science, even though history s e e s science, not as

    the progress to truth, but as the congress of truth--a

    quorum of dispute, where the right to speak the truth is

    itself a t s t a k e . The surrationalism of 'pataphysics might

    pursue this line of reasoning in order to suggest that in

    fact science replaces its errors not w i t h other errata, but

    with other errors, each one more subtle than t h e last one.

    Science errs when it s e e s its history as a consecutive

    process of both accumulation and amelioration. When t r a c i n g

    the history o f the term " p h y s i c a l , " from the d iscourse of

    A r i s t o t l e (phsikos), through the discourse of Bacon

    (phvsica), to the discourse of Heisenberg (phusics), science

    often presumes not only that each discourse is the nascent

    form o f t h e next discourse, but also that each discourse is

    a variant form of the same discourse: scientie. The word 11 science," however, does not designate the coherent progress

    of one rational practice, but instead signifies an unstable

    array of logical tactics, whose local, synergistic conflict

  • can invoke, provoke, and revoke a global, syllogistic

    program: deduction through dialectics (for Aristotle);

    jnduction through empiricism (for Bacon); and abduction

    through statistics (for Heisenberg).

    'Pataphysics reveals that, like poetry, science has an

    avant-garde with its own history of dissent. What Deleuze

    and Guattari might cal1 the roval sciences of efficient

    productivity have historically repressed and exploited the

    nomad sciences of expedient adaptability ( 1987: 3 6 2 ) A royal science is a standardized rnetaphysics: it is deployed

    by the state throughout a clathrate, Cartesian space,

    putting truth to work on behalf of solid, instrumental

    imperatives (law and order). A nomad science is a

    bastardized metaphysics: it is deployed against the state

    throughout an aggregate, Riemannian space, putting truth &

    risk on behalf of fluid, experimental operatives (trial and

    error). Such scientific economies are contrastive, but not

    exclusive. They transect at many points acrose many scales,

    each one immanent in the other, like a postponed potential.

    Royal sciences value the renovation of what Kuhn calls

    a paradiam (1970:10), a nomic language-game that must

    systematically (im)prove its own consistency and efficiency

    by solving problems, yevokinfi anomsly for the sake of what

  • 1 6

    is normal and known.' Nomad sciences, however, value the

    innovation of what tyotard calls a p a r a l o ~ ~ ( 1 9 8 4 : 6 0 ) , a ludic language-game that must systematically (ap)prove its

    own inconsistency and inefficiency by convolving problems,

    invokinq anomaly for the sake of what is abnormal and

    unknown. These two economies do not oppose each other so

    much as enfold each other. They inflect opposite values of

    intent within a composite system of truth. A failure in one

    language-game played according to one set of rules always

    determines the rules of success for a new language-game

    played according to a new set of rules.

    'Pataphysics no doubt d e f i n e s t h e rubric for this kind

    of nomadic paralogy. Itinerant and sophistic, a l1 such

    surrationalism reveals that science, like poetry, changes

    only when it deploys what Shklovsky might cal1 a tactic of

    ostranenie, of estrangement (12). Scientific revolutions

    may be nothing more than metaphoric revolutions, in which

    autotelic novelties foreground the dramatization of a system

    in order to undermine the autornatization of its reason.

    Paradigm shifts reveal t h a t every axiology secretly involves

    a reductio ad absurdum--the anomaly of an irresistible, but

    inadmissible, theorem. The aporia of such a system arises

    paradoxically from the rigour of its logic--as if its

    success also means its failure. The sudden triumph of

  • ' p a t a p h y s i c s t h u s does not imply t h e utter defeat of

    m e t a p h y s i c s so much as the pyrrhic v i c t o r y of m e t a p h y s i c s .

    Lyotard o b s e r v e s that , because science creates a method

    by which t o c o r r e c t t h e errors that it detec ts i n its

    method, science is "a process of delegitimation f u e l e d by

    the demand for legitimation itself" ( 1 9 8 4 : 3 9 ) . I n t e r d i c t i o n by a paradigm agains t c o n t r a d i c t i o n i n the parad igm causes

    the paradigm t o e x c l u d e , as e x t r i n s i c from i t , a paralogy

    i n t r i n s i c t o i t : " science--by c o n c e r n i n g itself w i t h such

    t h i n g s as u n d e c i d a b 1 e s l . J - - i s theorizing i t s own evolution

    as[ . . . ] p a r a d o x i c a l " ( 6 0 ) . Ironically, t h e system that yearns t o v a l i d a t e i t s e l f , o n l y l e a r n s t o invalidate i t s e l f .

    No l o n g e r d o e s science r a t i o n a l i z e i t s t r u t h so much as

    relativize i ts t r u t h . W e adopt "a model of l e g i t i m a t i o n

    t h a t has nothing t o d o w i t h maximized p e r f o r m a n c e " ( 6 0 ) , but r a t h e r implies "a model of an 'open s y s t e m , ' i n which a

    statement becomes relevant if it ' g e n e r a t e s ideas'" ( 6 4 ) .

    Science g r a p h s a r h i z o m a t i c f l o w c h a r t of stratif ied

    t r a j e c t o r i e s , an agonis t i c forcef i e l d of d i v e r s i f i e d c a t a s t r o p h e s , some o f which c o l l i d e w i t h each other, some of

    which c o l l u d e w i t h each other, al1 of which o p e r a t e together

    s i m u l t a n e o u s l y i n fits and s tarts at asynchronous rates of

    incornmensurate change. Science is a complex tissue of

  • hybrid tensions, its metaphors not only reflectinq each

    other, but also refracting each other. They facilitate

    changes to aa economy of exchanges by accentuating al1 the

    unforeseen instabilities in scientific signification. Like

    poetry, science is a bricolage of figures, an assemblage of

    devices, none of which fit together perfectly--but unlike

    poetry, science must nevertheless subject its tropes to a system, whose imperatives of both verity and reality

    normally forbid any willing suspension o f disbelief.

    Science and p o e t r y have shared a common history,

    undergoing four phases of distinct change (the anirnatismic,

    the mechanismic, the organismic, and the cyborganismic);

    nevertheless, the two disciplines h a v e not evolved in tandem

    or in s y n c h . Foucault observes, for example, that science

    and poetry have evolved opposite relations to the authorial

    function (1977:125-126): science moves toward anonymity;

    poetry moves toward eponymity. The absence of the author in

    science serves a n allotelic interest (justifying itself for the sake-of a finality outside of its own language), while

    the presence of the author in poetry serves an autotelic

    interest (justifying itself for the sake of a finality inside of its own language). Whenever science gains the

    anonymous power to speak the t r u t h about things, poetry

    seeks an eponymous refuge in the space of its own words.

  • Allotelic interests have always regarded autotelic

    interests as a waste of time, particularly in a capitalist

    economy where only the most effective arsenal of productive

    tactics can prevail. 1s it any wonder then that, for such

    imperial cynicism, science and poetry function within a

    relation, not of genre , but of power? The waxing influence

    of science has always implied the waning re levance of

    poetry--as if science must capitalize upon the competition

    for truth in order to monopolize the legitimation of truth.

    The science of 'pataphysics, however, expresses on behalf of

    poetry what the metaphysics of science represses in itself:

    its own basis in signs, their errors and biases--the

    ideology of metaphor. The autotelic aspect of science (its

    ludic surrationalism) always threatens to radicalize the

    allotelic agenda of science ( i t s nomic rationalism).

    Althusser argues that, although ideology always

    involves a denegation of itself so thst subjects produced by

    it cannot recognize themselves within it, the allotelic

    anonymity of science means that the clarity of its language

    can nevertheless negate ideology, yet successfully remain

    impartial: "ideology has no outside (for itself), but at

    the same tirne[ ...] it is nothina but outside (for science [ . . . ] ) " (175). Barthes disagrees, however, arguing that

    science is never neutral. Instead, science interpellates

  • its subject as an absence--a vanishing point, projected

    within ideology as though beyond ideology: "the scho lar

    excludes himself i n a concern for objectivity; yet what is

    excluded i s never anything but the 'person'[...], not the

    subject; moreover, this subject is filled[..,]with the very

    exclusion it[ ...] imposes upon its person" (8).

    Barthes suggests that science d i f f e r s from poetry, not

    because of any disparity between them in format, content,

    method, or intent, but becase of a d i s p a r i t y between them

    in status-a prestige of pedagogy ( 3 ) . Whereas poetry h a s

    always offered an egalitarian regime, destabilizing the

    s i g n i f i e r within a generalized economy of polysemic

    enunciation, science has only offered a totalitarian regime,

    stabilizing the si~nified within a r e s t r i c t e d economy of

    monosemic enunciation. For Barthes, s c i e n c e must begin to

    acknowledge i t s ideological investments, radicalizing i t s e l f

    by poeticizing i t s e l f . If ideology is the unreal

    conciliation of a real contradiction, is it not fair to Say

    that ideology is i t s e l f an imaginary solution--and therefore

    'pataphysical? If metaphysics must study the ontology of

    t ruth , must not 'pataphysics study the ideology of power?

    Ultimately, the conflict between science and poetry

    concerns this power to speak the truth, and this power has

  • undergone four phases of epistemic transition: the

    animatismic phase, whose truth involves interpreting signs

    through an a c t of exegesis; the mechanismic phase, whose

    truth involves disquisiting signs through an ect of

    mathesis; the oraanismic phase, whose truth involves

    implementing signs through an act of anamnesis; and the

    cvbornanismic phase, whose truth involves deregulating signs

    through an act of catamnesis. The life sciences, for

    example, have progressed from the biomaav of animatism,

    through the biotaxu of mechanism, through the biolo~v of

    organism, to the bionics of cyborganism. Each phase

    involves not only a different definition of science and

    poetry, but also a different opposition between t h e m .

    During the animatismic phase, when papal academies

    divide discourse scholastically into modes of textualization

    and numeralization (trivium and suadrivium), knowledge is

    rarefied largely because of its insufficient supply. During

    the mechanismic phase, when royal academies divide discourse

    aristocratically into modes of investigation and

    dissemination, knowledge is rarefied largely because of its

    unspecialized market. During the organismic phase, when

    state academies divide discourse democratically into modes

    of ratiocination and acculturation (scientia and humanitas),

    knowledge is rarefied because of its specialized labour.

  • 2 2

    And during the cyborganismic phase, when state academies

    divide discourse plutocratically into modes of totalization

    and optimization, knowledge is r a r e f i e d largely because of

    its overabundant supply*

    The Animatismic Phase

    Foucault observes that , bef ore empiricism, "divinatio

    and eruditio are both part of the same hermeneutics"

    (1973:34). Medieval trestises on natural history establish

    no criterion for the condition of relevance, s i n c e such

    treatises merely compile leaenda, collecting together

    haphazardly al1 the randorn lore about a sample topic in

    order to document the complex heraldry of its textual

    spectrum: "none of these forms of discourse is required to

    justify its d a i m to be e x p r e s s i n g a truth before it is

    interpreted; a l 1 that is required of it is the possibility

    of talking about it" (40). Science in its snimstismic phase

    s e e s that signs e x i s t long b e f o r e being known: they are

    written-into things by nature, and they extinguish the

    distance between things in order to reveal the synchronie

    continuum of their secret order.

    Reality for the animatismic phase is a stable orrery

    t h a t r e v o l v e s around a central fulcrum. Knowing such a

  • reality involves an exegetic function, reading signs,

    interpreting them, rearranging them within an anagram that

    permutes al1 their modes of sympathy and antipathy. Such an

    anatomy o f forms distributes signs aesthetically throughout

    a nomad regime in which al1 things must conform to an order

    of both resemblance and concordance. Even the difference

    between the reasoning of science and t h e imagining o f poetry

    does not yet exist because no paradigm provides a consensus

    for such verities. Each text has equal truthfulness. Each

    myth can convey what Vico might cal1 a "poetic wisdom"

    (110), whose truth owes its power t o an error that demands

    belief in a "credible impossibilityt' (120)--an as if that

    can provide the premise in the future for a nuovo scienza. 4

    Poetic wisdom simply monopolizes the totality of both

    the subject and the o b j e c t , leaving no space f o r modern science to speak the truth for itself except as an act of

    deviance within such a norm. Poetic wisdom cannot recognize

    any disparity between the subjective affect of imagining and

    the objective effect of reasoning. Alchemy, for example

    r e s o r t s t o such poetic wisdom in order to imagine a lapis

    philoso~horum that can produce a coniuntia o ~ ~ o s i t o r u m ,

    harmonizing the disputes among al1 such elements. Truth

    becomes a r i t u a l of scenes in which al1 things can change

    their images into each other. The transitive category for

  • 2 4

    l e a d becoming gold transmutes i n t o a redemptive allegory

    about body becoming soul. The lapis ~ h i l o s o ~ h o r u m is a

    t h i n g unlike any o t h e r , but i t makes t h i n g s so that they are

    l i k e everything else. Tt is the metaphor for al1 metaphor.

    Donne practices the poetic wisdom of such a s c e n i c

    ritual when he d e l i b e r a t e l y misunderstands t h e difference

    between the s c i e n c e of alchemy and his p o e t r y of c o n c e i t s ,

    i n v i t i n g h i s reader, " A s f i r e these drossie Rymes to

    p u r i f i e , / O r as E l i x i r , t o change them t o g o l d " since such a

    reader is "that A l c h i m i s t which alwaies had/ W i t , whose one

    spark could make good th ings of bad" ( 2 9 4 ) . Alchemy becomes a metaphor that can undergo a process o f alchemy itself.

    The device of t h e conceit r e f l e c t s an alchernical rnarriage o f

    antongrnical extremes so t h a t , f o r example, the idea of love

    can be equated w i t h any m o t i f , no matter how absurd, b e i t a

    drafting compass or a drinking i n s e c t . The lapis of

    alchemy, like the lexis of poe try , reveals t h a t the figura1

    is merely the alembic for t h e l i t era l . The noble metal of

    truth arlses from t h e ignoble filth of e r r o r . 5

    Vico claims that just as modern science shows t h a t "man becomes al1 things by understanding (homo intelliaendo fit

    ornnia)," so a l s o does p o e t i c wisdom show tbat "man becomes al1 t h i n g s by not understanding[...)(bomo non intelliaendo

  • 25

    fit omnia)" (130). To understand on behalf of truth is to

    be reactive, accepting the world of the as is, but to

    misunderstand on behalf of error is to be creative,

    inventing the world of the as if. To be an alchemist is to

    practice an aesthetic that acts as a lapis ~hiloso~horum,

    transmuting the errors of alchemy (a nomad science) into the

    truths of chemistry (a royal science), but ironically, this

    change requires that science and poetry shift from an order

    where they are unified to an order where they are divided.

    A literal stone that philosophers must diligently seek

    embodies a figura1 power that they must eventually deny.

    Foucault argues that, during such a transition, the

    "tautological world of resemblance n o w finds itself

    dissociated and, as it were, split down the middle"

    (1973:58). For Donne, such a dissociation of sensibility

    implies the failure of alchemy to reconcile the imminent

    conflict between the subjective affect of imagining and the

    objective effect of reasoning: "new philosophy cals al1 in

    doubt" so that "The Sun is lost, and th'earth, and no man's

    wit/ Can well direct him, where to looke for it" (335).

    The old, geocentric order of elemental synthesis regards the

    conceit as the integrel epitome of al1 similes, but the new,

    heliocentric order of empirical analysis regards the conceit

    as the marginal extreme of al1 follies.' N o t until the

  • advent of 'pataphysics does the conceit, the s y n t h e s i s of

    opposites, regain its status as a device of poetic wisdom.

    The Mechanismic Phase

    Bacon observes that , before empiricism, "systems are

    but so many stage plays, representing worlds of their own

    creation after an unreal and scenic fashion" ( 1 9 6 0 : 4 9 ) . Natural history must revoke these "Idols of the ~heater"

    ( 4 9 ) , replacing the theatrical world of scenes (the as if) with the empirical world of senses (the as is), but this

    change risks an aporia since this new mode of investigation

    only ratifies a new mode of dramatization--the petit r&i t

    of an experiment in which an event must restage itself again

    and again under the auspice of control. Epistemic errors

    are now simply traced to linguistic abuses. Science in its

    mechanismic phase sees t h a t signs e x i s t only by being known:

    they are written ont0 things by culture, and they

    distinguish the distance between t h i n g s i n order to invent

    the synchronie continuum of their proper order.

    Reality for the mechanismic phase is a stable clock

    t h a t operates within a static regimen. Knowing such a

    r e a l i t y involves a mathetic function, testing signs,

    disquisiting them, regimenting them within a diagram that

  • 27

    d i s p l a y s a l 1 t h e i r modes o f i d e n t i t y and a l t e r i t y . Such a

    taxonomy o f forms d i s t r i b u t e s signs i n c r e m e n t a l l y throughout

    a royal regime in which al1 t h i n g s must depend upon an o r d e r

    o f both equivalence and d i f f e r e n c e . The evidence of

    s c i e n c e , not the eminence of p o e t r y , provides a consensus

    for t h e v e r i t i e s of a paradigm. A l 1 t e x t s have their

    t r u t h f u l n e s s at stake. Al1 t e x t s must legitimate their

    s o u r c e s . The t r u t h of science fulfills such a r e q u i s i t e by

    favourably gauging its power over the object a g a i n s t t h e d i v i n e power of n a t u r e . The t r u t h o f science t h u s aligns

    i t s cause, i t s a r c h e , w i t h t h e power of a noumenal origin.

    Modern science s i m p l y c o l o n i z e s the a l t e r i t y of t h e

    o b j e c t , l e a v i n g no space f o r poetic wisdom t o speak t h e t r u t h about nature except through an act of alliance with

    s u c h a norm. Poetic wisdom must adopt t h e v a l u e s of modern

    s c i e n c e i n o r d e r t o s t a t e any objective v e r i t i e s . Sprat,

    for example, argues t h a t , poet i c a l l y " T r u t h 1s n e v e r so

    w d l e x p r e s ' d or a m p l i f y ' d , as by those Ornaments which are

    Truie1 and Real i n t hemse lves " ( 4 1 4 ) . Truth is t h e b e s t ornament because it has the least ornament--which is t o say

    t h a t s c i e n c e i s the best poetry because it has t h e least

    poetry. The i r o n y here is t h a t verse must l e a r n i ts r u l e s

    of metaphor from a genre t h a t r u l e s out metaphor. The sage

    o f s c i e n c e a c t u a l l y becomes the muse of poetry (hence t h e

  • numerous elegies to scientists, particularly N e w t o n , despite

    the fact that science follows a principle of antipoeisis). 7

    Newton berates poetry for its "ingenius nonsense" (Bush

    40) even though Glover portrays him as the paragon of

    poetry: "O might'st thou, ORPHEUS, now again revive,/ And

    NEWTON should inform thy list'ning ear" ([Pemberton 231).

    Poetry indulges in scientific sycophancy, largely because

    the gravity of force in the Princi~ia lends itself to the

    idea of a poetic sublime just as the levity of light in the Opticks lends itself to the idea of a poetic beauty. 8

    Glover writes that "Newton demands the muse" ( [ 1 4 ] ) , but soon Thomson w o n d e r s : "How shall the Muse, then, grasp the

    mighty theme," particularly "when but a f e w / Of the deep-

    studying race can stretch their minds/ To w h a t he knew"

    (1853:337). Science has unveiled so many universal

    mysteries that, ironically, it threatens to become a poetry

    of truth more sublime than the t r u t h of poetry itself.

    Poetry makes an effort to dispute this omniscience of

    science (its will to power), as Swift does, for example, but

    poetry cannot dispute the conscience of science (its will to

    truth). While science ascends to a state of greater

    complexity, becoming more abstract, theoretic, and

    autocratic, poetry descends through science to a state of

  • 29

    greater simplicity, becoming more concrete, pragmatic, and

    democratic. To keep Pace with science, poetry must shift

    its focus from the sublime in the natural physics of Newton

    to the poetic beauty in the natural history of Linnaeus.

    As Aikin avers, the updated images of natural history must

    replace the outdated tropes of poetry since "no th ing can be

    really beautiful which has not truth for its basis" (25).

    To fulfill a didactic mandate, poetry must learn its truth

    directly from the mineral, the vegetal, and the bestial. 9

    Darwin, the p o e t i c savant, follows such advice to t h e

    letter when he explains the botanical taxonomy of Linnaeus

    by equating modes of floral procreation with modes of s o c i a l

    flirtation: " t h e general design[ ...] is to i n l i s t Imagination under t h e banner of Science; and to l e a d her

    votaries from t h e l o o s e r analogies, which dress[ . . . ] p oetry,

    to the stricter ones, which form[ . . . lphilosophy" ( 1791 :v) . Poetic pleasure submits to noetic pedagogy. The catalogue

    of flowers, the antholonv, so to speak, is merely the

    flowery ornament for the summary document of its scientific

    marginalia. The poetry acts as a mere note for the notes

    themselves--a pretense to plant the seeds of interest so

    that the reader might in turn disseminate this information.

    The poetry literally is a botanic garden, in which

    germinates the romantic metaphor that poetry is organic.

  • The Oraanismic Phase

    Coleridge observes that, after empiricism, the botanic

    mode1 of science does inform a poetry of organic unity, but

    contrary to Darwin, t h i s poetic pleasure does not submit to

    noetic pedagogy: "[a] poem[ ...] is opposed tof. ..]science, by proposing for its immediate object pleasure, not truth"

    (164). Wordsworth qualifies this statement by arguing that

    "the knowledge of both the Poet and the Man of science is

    pleasure" ( 4 5 6 ) , but while poetry i s an e c s t a t i c search for an intimate truth, science is a monastic search for an

    ultimate truth--one whose discourse values an empiricism of

    the senses at the expense of their sensualism. Science in

    its organismic phase s e e s that signs evolve by being known:

    they are written across events by culture, and they

    distinguish the interval between events in order to direct

    the diachronic continuum of their normal order.

    Reality for the organismic phase is a simple engine

    that generates a stable dynarnic. Knowing such a reality

    involves an anemnestic function, working signs, implementing

    them, redeploying them within a program that displays al1

    their modes of function and relation. Such an economy of

    forms distributes its signs pragmatically thoughout a royal

    regime in which al1 things must depend upon an order of both

  • 3 1

    productivity and applicability. Not only the evidence of

    science, but also the progress of science, provides a

    consensus for the verities of a paradigm. Al1 texts have

    their usefulness at stake. A l 1 texts must legitimate their

    intents. The truth of science fuifills such a requisite by

    favourably gauging i L s power over the subject against the

    humane power of culture. The truth of science t h u s aligns

    its effect, its telos, with the power of a noumenal motive.

    Modern science simply colonizes the identity of the

    subject, leaving no space for poetic wisdom to speak the

    truth about culture except through an act of defiance

    against such a norm. Poetic wisdom must evict the values of

    modern science in order to state any subjective verities. Hence, Keats condemns Newton for the "cold philosophy" that

    must "Conquer al1 mysteries by rule and line" (226) just as

    Blake condemns Newton for the "Reasonings like vast

    Serpents" that must hang their "iron scourges over Albion"

    (16). Such reasoning that allegedly discredits imagining

    only creates an undead truth, an Ur-Frankenstein that, for

    Wordsworth, must await a poetic rebirth: "the Poet will

    lend his divine spirit to aid in the transfiguration" when

    "science, thus familiarized to men, shall be ready to put

    on, as it were, a form of flesh and blood" ( 4 5 6 ) .Io

  • 32

    Wordsworth claims t h a t "[ t lhe r e m o t e s t discoveries of the C h e m i s t , t h e B o t a n i s t , o r M i n e r a l o g i s t , will be as

    p r o p e r o b j e c t s o f t h e ~ o e t ' s art[. . . ] i f the t i m e should ever corne when t h e s e things s h a l l be f ami l i a s to us" ( 4 5 6 ) , but in t h e meantime, this differend has no t e r m s f o r c o n s e n s u s .

    Poetry i n d u l g e s i n s c i e n t i f i c c o n t r o v e r s y , largely because

    the schisrn be tween r e a s o n i n g and i m a g i n i n g has begun t o

    reflect t h e anomie of p o e t i c labour. For Huxley, such

    l a b o u r c a n n o t compete w i t h t h e c a p i t a l v a l u e s o f u t i l i t y

    ( 1 9 4 8 : 4 9 ) - - t h u s p o e t r y must warrant a Benthamite r e j e c t i o n - - but for Arnold, such labour d o e s reflect upon t h e communal

    values o f l i b e r t y (1889:llZ)--which is to s a y , the reasoning

    of s c i e n c e can t e a c h w h a t is real and t r u e , but o n l y t h e

    i m a g i n i n g o f poetry can t e a c h what is f i n e and j u s t .

    Schlegel writes that p o e t r y must redeem science in the

    b e l i e f that "al1 art should become science and al1 science

    art" ( 1 5 7 ) . Poetry must become a genre of therapeutic knowledge , c r e a t i n g pseudo-statements t h a t can, according t o

    Richards, d e t a c h the untruth of poetry from belief and yet

    retain the b e a u t y of such untruth in order to r e f i n e belief

    i t s e l f ( 6 1 ) . Newtonian cosmology has discredited the p o e t i c o b j e c t just as Darwinian e v o l u t i o n has discredited t h e p o e t i c sub ject ; t h e r e f o r e , poetry must henceforth resort to

    the as if of an imaginary solution in order to speak i t s own

  • t ru th . Poetry must ascend through science to a state of

    greater complexity, becoming more abstract, theoretic, and

    autocratie. Poetry must transform its scientific

    radicalism, shifting its critique from an opposition

    (external to science) to a subversion (interna1 to science).

    'Pataphysics thus arises j u s t before modernism begins to wring its hands about the enigma of what Snow calls "the

    Two Cultures" ( 2 ) . Huxley argues that, despite their dispute, the two cultures resemble each other most when the

    noetic clarity of reasoning and the poetic opacity of

    imagining approach t h e sublimity of the ineffable (1963:14).

    What is sublime in t h e pseudo of poetry can, according to

    Richards, return reasoning and irnagining to an equilibrium

    t h a t resembles the tension of forces in a cloud of magnets

    (15-18) .ll Such an equation of antonyms revives the conceit

    as a sublime device not of alchernical marriage, but of

    scientific synthesis; hence, Eliot can equate poetry with a

    platinum catalyst that f u s e s oxygen and sulphur w i t h o u t

    changing-itself: " [ i l t is in this depersonalization that art may be said to approach the condition of science" (7). 12

    The Csbor~anismic P h a s e

    B a r t h e s observes that, after modernism, science can no

  • 34

    longer stabilize its object within an allotelic economy of

    monosemic reference, but must, like poetry, criticize its

    method within an autotelic economy of polysemic existence:

    "science speeks itself; literature writes itself[...]: it

    is not the same body, and hence the same desire, which is

    behind the one and the other" (5); nevertheless, "science

    will becorne literature, insofar as literature [ . . . ] is

    alreadyr. ..]sciencew (IO), only when science can see that

    its own truth exists not outside of language, but only

    because of language. Science in its cyborganismic phase

    sees that signs evolve beyond being known: they are written

    as events by culture, and they extinguish the interval

    between events in order to create the synchronic

    discontinuum of their random order,

    Reality for the cyborganismic phase is a complex matrix

    that cornputes a mobile dynamic. Knowing such a reality

    involves a catamnestic function, playing signs,

    deregulating them, recombining them within a hologram that

    displays-al1 their modes of seduction and simulation. Such

    a synonymy of forms distributes its signs excrementally

    throughout a nomad regime in which al1 things must depend

    upon an order of virtuosity and virtuality. Al1 texts have

    their artfulness at stake. Al1 texts must legitimate not

    only their reasons (be they in the origin or in the result),

  • 35

    but the reason for these reasons. The truth of science can

    no longer fulfill s u c h a r e q u i s i t e by favourably gauging its

    power against t h e metaphysics of e i t h e r an arche or a telos,

    but only against the 'pataphysics of an exceptional

    phenornenon-be it an aporia, a c h i s s m , or a swerve*

    Modern science simply mono.polizes the totality of both

    the subject and the object, leaving no space for poetic

    wisdom t o speak t h e t r u t h for i t s e l f except as an act of

    deviance within such a norm. Modern s c i e n c e can no longer

    stabilize the disparity between the subjective affect of

    imagining and the objective effect of reasoning. The advent

    of 'patsphysics signals the f i r s t attempts to subvert this

    agenda from within its own limits. The science of

    'pataphysics inspires a literary tradition that has i n t u r n

    begun t o regard i tse l f as s response to science with an

    outcome to be studied by a science, be it formalist,

    structural, semiologic , or c y b e r n e t i c . l3 The ' pataphysical

    fundamentsls of surrationalism have in turn provided the

    aesthetic parallel for the dialectic sophistry of almost al1

    anti-metaphysical meta-philosophies.

    Baudrillard s u g g e s t s that, "a century after J a r r y , but

    in a cool universe w i t h o u t irony, and without 'pataphysical

    acid," science has so inflated the fund of information that

  • 36

    the excesses of such metastasis evoke the flidouille of Ubu:

    "['p]ataphysics or metaphysics, this pregnancyr . . . ] is one of the strangest signs[ ...] of this spectral environment where each ce11 ( e a c h function, e a c h structure), is left with the possibility, as in cancer, [...]of multiplying indefinitely"

    (1990:28). Science is a tautological extravagance, for

    which Ubu, "a figure of genius, r e p l e t e with that which has

    absorbed everything, transgressed everything, [... Iradiates in t h e void like an imaginary solution" (71). Science now

    f u n c t i o n s i n what Jarry might cal1 an economy of phvnance

    (1969:43), expending w i t h o u t investing, producing pschitt or

    merdre--an ironic eponym f o r "excess" w i t h an e x c e s s l e t t er .

    Baudrillard suggests that, for such an economy o f

    science, the threat of the unrea l haunts every system o f

    verity s i n c e t h e methods of physics can no longer confirm

    whether or not reality itself is a fsntasy: "[sJuch would

    be the [']pataphysics[ ...] that lies i n w a i t for al1 physics at its inadmissible limitstt (1990:85). Has not physics

    already started to resemble a s c i e n c e of imaginary

    solutions, what with its particle zoo of new paradoxes (the

    amphibolies of psrticles, the metaleptics of causality)? Do

    we not see a h i n t of 'pataphysics in the strsngeness gf

    anti-matter, black-holes, and time-travel (the theories of

    which have already fomented philosophical apprehensions

  • 37

    about the existence of existence itself)? In the face of

    such scientific absurdities, poetry has responded by

    portraying itsel f as a literalized experiment .

    Prigogine and Stengers observe that, for such an

    episteme, "science occupies a peculiar position, that of a

    poetical interrogation of nature, in the etymological sense

    that the poet is a 'makerY--active," inventing the world

    post facto while observing the world a priori (301).

    Science has finally achieved the hyperbole of its own

    "death," so t o speak, disappearing into a condition of

    tautologic metalepsis, paradoxically becoming both the cause

    and effect of its own virtual reality. Science has begun to

    fulfill the simulacral precession that, for Baudrillard,

    defines the 'pataphysics of a postmodern philosophy. As

    Genosko suggests, "[i]t is surely a ['Jpataphysical accident

    that death is for Baudrillard the very[. . .]gesture which

    pushes the tautologies of the system over the edge, with a

    b e l l y laugh of symbolic proportions" ( 116).

    Pseudo-Sciences

    Feyerabend argues t h a t , f o r science t o progress, the

    nomic t ru th of the as is must induce an escape to the ludic

    space of an as i f : " w e need a dream-world in order to

  • discover t h e f eatures of the real world[ . . . Iwhich may

    actually be just another dream-world" (32). Science in such

    a Traumwelt adopts not the terrorism of unified theories,

    but the anarchism of ramified theories--"[t]he only

    principle t h a t does not inhibit progress is: ansthina noes"

    (23). Such a principle does not encode a laissez-faire

    economy (whose Darwinian cornpetition requires that a royal

    science discard the truth of a defunct concept as either

    extinct or deviant); instead, such a principle tries to

    entice a savoir-faire economy (whose Lucretian arbitration

    requires that a nomad science bracket the truth of a defunct

    concept as either dormant or defiant), 15

    'Pataphysics dramatizes this principle of Feyerabend by

    arguing t h a t , however obsolete or indiscrete any theory

    might at first appesr, every theory has the potential to

    improve knowledge in s a m e way. Just as biodiversity can

    make an ecology more adaptable, so also can dilettantism

    make an episteme more versatile. The process of science

    muet lea-rn to place its defunct concepts into a kind of

    suspended animation that preserves them for the millenary

    reverie of an imaginary science. The truth diverges

    throughout many truths, inducing the sophisms of dissent,

    novelty, and paradox: "given any rule(...]for science,

    there are always circumstances when it is advisable not on ly

  • 39

    to ignore the rule, but to adopt its opposite" (23) in order

    "to make the weaker case the stronnerl...land t h e r e b v to

    sustain the motion of the whole" (30).

    'Pataphysics thus behaves as if it is a Philosophie des

    Als Ob. Vaihinger observes that the phrase "as if"

    constitutes a "comparative apperception" (91), juxtaposing

    two concepts somewhere in t h e interzone between the

    virtuality of a figura1 relation and the a c t u a l i t y of a

    literal equation. Neither rhetorical nor theoretical, the

    as if constitutes a paradox of contingency, since reference

    is made to an impossibility, but from t h i s impossibility an

    inference is made: "reality[ . . . ] is com~ared with something whose[. ..]unreality is at the same time admitted" (98). The

    as if posits the possible consequences of an impossible

    inconsequence. The as if is simply the irnaginary solution

    tu the question what i f . 1s not this question a deliberate

    misreading that shows the real and the true to be quasi and

    pseudo--free, that is, to be something else?

    'Pataphysics s u g g e s t s that metaphysics forgets that

    this operative conditional (as if) is not an imperative

    conditional (if t h e n ) ; nevertheless, the latter relation always resides unheard between the two words of the former

    relation. The if t h e n revokes t h e suspension of disbelief

  • 4 0

    in the as if so t h a t the event must be treated as it would

    be treated i f it were as is. The slightness of t h i s

    difference between the as i f and the if then thus marks t h e

    slightness of the difference between t r u t h and power. The

    science of 'pataphysics explores t h e s e conditionals i n order

    to see what might happen if science is treated as poetry and

    vice versa, the philosopher studying the exceptional ( b e i t t h e anomalos, t h e s u z ~ ~ i a , or t h e clinameq) i n order to make

    t h e weaker case, t h e stronger--almost as i f to s a y t h a t

    ultimately such a case might be as true as ang from Tlon.

  • Notes to Chanter 1

    is of course an i r o n i c signifier w i t h two

    meanings that c o n t r a d i c t each other. Its real usage as an

    a d j e c t i v e i n German refers t o a n o r i g i n a r y mode1 f o r imaginary c o p i e s , b u t its u n r e a l usage as a s u b s t a n t i v e i n

    T l h e s e r e f e r s to imaginary copies wi t h o u t any originary

    model. The ur thus embodies a paradox o f s i m u l a t i o n , whose

    s t r u c t u r e impl ies t h a t , a t the origin, no o r i g i n e x i s t s , but

    t h e dream of an o r i g i n . No longer does t h e causa l vector

    from t h e r ea l t o i t s copy make sense s i n c e the fantasy of

    t h e u_r d o e s not r e p l i c a t e , so much as o r i g i n a t e , r e a l i t y .

    ' ~ a n ~ u i l h e r n observes t h e t " t h e history of s c i e n c e

    i s t h e h i s t o r y of a n abject[. ..]that is a h i s t o r y and [that] has a h i s t o r y , whereas sc ience is the s c i e n c e of an o b j e c t -

    t h a t is n o t a history [and] t h a t has a h i s t o r y " ( 2 5 - 2 6 ) . Science ignores its history because s c i e n c e i n its history

    is no longer s c i e n c e * F o r s c i e n c e , t r u t h is p r e s c i e n t ,

    always t-here b e f o r e t h e fact of its revelation; for h i s t o r y ,

    t r u t h is expedient, only there a f t e r the fact of i ts

    production. The h i s t o r y of t r u t h shows t h a t a persistent

    concept does n o t n e c e s s a r i l y imply its c o n s i s t e n t meaning.

  • 42

    '~uhn writes that "a paradigi is a criterion for

    choosing problems that, while the paradigm is t a k e n for

    granted, can be assumed to have solutions" (1970:37). It is

    a Weltanschauung with three discursive functions: first, it

    ratifies interdictions in order to define what it makes

    perceivable and thereby improve its accuracy; second, it

    verifies predictions in order to align the perceivable with

    the conceivable and thereby improve its efficacy; and third,

    it pacifies contradictions in order to define what it makes

    conceivable and thereby improve its adequacy.

    '~uovo scienza is a poetic wisdom that might

    study poetic wisdom (and thus such a science almost appears

    to preempt 'pataphysics itself). Vico, like Jarry, believes

    that, because nature is an inhuman creation, we can never

    know its truth; but unlike Jarry, Vico believes that,

    because culture is a human creation, we can know its truth.

    Jarry argues that al1 truth, be it natural or cultural, is

    still an opaque mirage, never to be known. Every science,

    for him; is a poetic wisdom if only because it rnust commit

    at leest one error--the error of belief in truth itself,

  • onne ne suggests t h a t al1 "this worlds genrall sicknesse" ( 336) might paradoxicslly cleanse impurity itsel f

    and thus "purifie/ A l l , by a true religious Alchimy" (334).

    Metaphysics involves a christological transmutation that

    purifies a supernal truth of al1 its errors; however,

    'pataphysics involves an anti-christological transmutation

    that purifies an infernal error of al1 its truth (as if

    t r u t h itself is the filth)-ohence, Ubu in the heraldic

    allegory of Caesar Antichrist performs a reverse alchemy, in

    which to rise above sin i s to fa11 from grace.

    '~allyn observes t h a t , for Copernicus and Kepler,

    " t h e world is the work of a divine poietes," and "what they

    aim to reveal through their own poetics is thus

    t r u l y [ . . . ] t h e poetic structure of the world" (20). Donne feels snxiety about such a p o e t i c cosmos even though its

    system is more aesthetic than empirical, not verified and

    rectified so much as symmetrized and harmonized. The

    problem is that such a view radically displaces humanity,

    propelling us into a regressive infinitude, a sublime

    extreme without limit, be it atomic or cosmic in scale.

  • 44

    '~homson eulogizes Newton: "The heavens are al1

    hi6 own; from the w i l d rule/ O f whirling v o r t i c e s and

    circling s ~ h e r e s , / To t h e i r first great simplicity

    restored," and "Even Light i t s e l f [ . . . ] / Shone undiscover'd, till his brighter rnind/ Untwis ted al1 the shining robe of

    day" (1853:336). Akenside, likewise, eulogizes Newton:

    "The lamp of science through the jealous maze/ Of Nature

    g u i d e s , when haply you reveal/ Her secret honours: [...)/ The beauteous l a w s of l i g h t , the central powers/ That wheel

    the pensile p l a n e t s round t h e year" ( 1825: 51-52 ) .

    orce ce and light a c q u i r e aesthetic currency i n an industry that must versify t h e theory by Newton i n order t o

    d e i f y the memory of N e w t o n . F o r poets influenced by the

    sublime of the P r i n c i ~ i a , see William Powell Jones: The

    R h e t o r i c of Science: A Studs o f Scientific Ideas and

    Irna~ery in Ei~hteenth-Centurv Enalish Poetrv (Berkeley:

    U n i v e r s i t y o f California, 1 9 6 6 ) . For poets in f luenced by the beauty of the Opticks, see Marjorie Nicholson: Newton Pemands -the Muse: Newton's 'Opticks' and the Ei~hteenth

    Centurs Poets (Hamden: Archon, 1 9 4 6 ) .

  • 45

    ' ~ i k i n p o s i t s a didact ic hierarchy a s c e n d i n g f rom

    t h e m i n e r a l t o the animal, so t h a t zoology l e n d s i t s e l f best

    t o p o e t r y , l a r g e l y because beasts most closely resemble

    humans and thus p r o v i d e a larges repertoire of p e d a g o g i c a l

    similes ( 3 4 ) . A ik in thus contradicts himself: he argues that poetry must use s c i e n c e t o reject t h e past o f culture and d e p i c t n a t u r e d i r e c t l y , b u t then h e argues that p o e t r y

    must use s c i e n c e t o reject a par t of nature and depict c u l t u r e i n d i r e c t l y . Poetry must imitate a facet of t h e

    n a t u r a l t h a t most imitates t h e realm of the c u l t u r a l .

    l0wordsworth posits a dualist paradox when he

    deploys this animatismic t r o p o l o g y - f o r although science is

    an i n a n i m a t e body of knowledge, it has no flesh, no corpus ,

    and is thus a body w i t h o u t a body, yet this i n s e n s a t e ,

    i ncorporea l form of knowledge is not a s o u l , because i t has

    no breath, no animus, and is thus a s o u l w i t h o u t a s o u l .

    Science, l i k e t h e Monster in Frankenstein, is a morbid

    f i g u r e for the c o r r u p t i o n of s i m u l a t i o n . Shelley i m p l i e s

    t h a t s c i e n c e , n o t poetry, i s t h e replica of an error t h a t

    threatens t o r e p l a c e t h e t r u t h of t h e o r i g i n .

  • 46

    l lFtichards argues that poetic wisdom is s brownian

    movement: "Suppose that[ ...] w e carry an a r rangement o f msny magnet ic n e e d l e s , l a r g e and small, swung so t h a t they

    i n f l u e n c e one a n o t h e r , some a b l e o n l y t o swing h o r i z o n t a l l y ,

    others v e r t i c a l l y , others hung freely[.. .. ] Each new

    d i s e q u i l i b r i u m f ...] co r r e sponds to a need ; and the wagglings which ensue as t h e system rearranges i t s e l f are our

    responses[ ....] Sometimes the poem is itseif t h e i n f l u e n c e which disturbs us, sometimes it is merely the means by which

    an already existing disturbance can r i g h t i t ~ e l f . ' ~ (15-18)

    12~liot argues that p o e t i c wisdom i s a chernical

    r e a c t i o n : "When the two gases[ . ..]are mixed i n t h e p r e s e n c e

    of a f i l a m e n t o f platinum, they form s u l p h u r o u s acid. T h i s

    combinat ion t a k e s p l a c e only i f the p l a t i n u m is p r e s e n t ;

    nevertheless t h e newly formed acid c o n t a i n s no trace of

    platinum, and t h e p l a t i n u m itself is a p p a r e n t l y u n a f f e c t e d ;

    has remained i n e r t , neutral, and unchanged. The mind o f t h e

    poet i s the shred of p l a t i n u m [ . ...] [Tlhe more p e r f e c t the ar t i s t , - t h e more completely separate i n him w i l l be t h e man

    who suf fers and t h e mind which creates" ( 7-8 ) .

  • " ~ a u l s o n has provided one of the most

    theoretically comprehensive surveys of such sciences when he

    plots the epistemic transition from the organismic paradigm

    of literature to the cyborganisrnic paralogy of information:

    "[ais science disqualifies the medium through which we have experienced and spoken the world, language and culture as we

    have known them are swept away at an astonishing rate" so

    that, " [ i l f we want to preserve something of our subjectivityl ... 1, then we must open Our texts to the

    n e w [ , . . ]noises of science" ( 5 2 ) .

    "~audrillard implies that , as a " [ ' plataphysician

    at twenty" (l996a:83), he derives much of his irony from a

    scientific vocabulary--particularly when he indulges in his

    own hyperbole of molecular metaphors, be they quantum,

    fractal, genetic, etc. Genosko remarks that, for

    Baudrillard, such language does not evoke the rhetorical

    equivalent of scientific legitimation; instead, the nomad

    value of these modifiers rises in indirect relation to their

    absence -of meaning: they constitute a "science fiction

    practised in the service of the symbolic" (106).

  • 48

    15~eyerabend writes: "NO idea is ever examined in

    a l1 its ramifications and no view is ever given al1 the

    chances [thst] it deserves" ( 4 9 ) for "[tlheories are abandoned and superseded by more fashionable accounts long

    before they have had an opportunity to show their virtues"

    (40). Voodoo, for example, offers science an insight into

    (heretofore unknown) aspects of pharmac