boethius and sophia

20
Boethius and Sophia: Early Awakenings of the Archetypal Feminine in Philosophy  Historical an d Biographical Background Boethius was born during an age of transition: the Ancient World was dying and the Medieval Worl d had not yet be gun. Gregor y of Tou rs, who chron icles this era, writes of the decline of culture, literature, and philosophy in the lands of Gaul. He laments: “Woe to our times, because the study of letters is dying out among us and no man is capable of preserving in writing the doings of the  present.” (1) During this time it was in the East that philosophy and theology continued to develop into formative doctrine. Edmund Reiss explains: “Not only was the great literary and philosophical heritage of classical Greece fast becoming lost to the Latin West, but the Roman Church was increasingly at a lack in understanding and participating in the theological debates that proliferated during the 5 th and 6 th  centuries.” (2) The transformation of the social order, as barbarians took over the old Mediterranean culture and social structure, caused great changes to the Roman world. Under the reign of the Arian Ostrogoth king Theodoric, Italy did experience a period of peace and prosperity, but the military and political power now lay in the hands of the king and his Goth followers. Fortunately, Theodoric became a patron of the classical arts and under his rule, Boethius enjoyed access to educational institutions and libraries. Perhaps the principle importance of Boethius derives from the fact that he was the last of the Latin-speaking scholars of the ancient world to be well acquainted with Greek. Although the works of Jerome and Augustine abound in the echoes of Cicero, Virgil, and Plato, much classic philosophey and literature began to disappear in the West during the Merovingian Monarchy (the dynasty of the Frankish kings). After the demise of Boethius, the West was lacking in anyone with first-hand knowledge of Greek  philosophy until Aristotle’s works were rediscovered in the 12 th  century, largely from Arabic sources. Boethius was born into a family that had held many high offices of state during the 4 th and 5 th  centuries. He won the favor of King Theodoric and eventually became the head of civil service. I n 520, he was grante d the honorary title, Master of the Office s, which would probably be equivalent to a prime minister today. Four years later, he was dead, having been suspected of treachery by Theodoric and executed after a lengthy prison term. He was celebrated as a martyr after his torture and execution. It was in prison that he composed his most famous text, the Consolation of Philosophy, written without access to a library, which nonetheless abounds in reminiscences of classical texts in which his mind had been soaked since he was a child. It is generally believed that Boeth ius studied in Athens or Alexandria in his youth. Let us briefly examine his works.

Upload: rosamario

Post on 05-Jul-2018

217 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Boethius and Sophia

8/16/2019 Boethius and Sophia

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/boethius-and-sophia 1/20

Boethius and Sophia: Early Awakenings of the Archetypal Feminine in

Philosophy

 Historical and Biographical Background 

Boethius was born during an age of transition: the Ancient World was dying and theMedieval World had not yet begun. Gregory of Tours, who chronicles this era, writes of 

the decline of culture, literature, and philosophy in the lands of Gaul. He laments:

“Woe to our times, because the study of letters is dying out among us and no man iscapable of preserving in writing the doings of the present.” (1) During this time it was inthe East that philosophy and theology continued to develop into formative doctrine.

Edmund Reiss explains:

“Not only was the great literary and philosophical heritage of classical Greece fastbecoming lost to the Latin West, but the Roman Church was increasingly at a lack in

understanding and participating in the theological debates that proliferated during the 5th

and 6th centuries.” (2)

The transformation of the social order, as barbarians took over the old Mediterranean

culture and social structure, caused great changes to the Roman world. Under the reign of 

the Arian Ostrogoth king Theodoric, Italy did experience a period of peace and

prosperity, but the military and political power now lay in the hands of the king and his

Goth followers. Fortunately, Theodoric became a patron of the classical arts and under

his rule, Boethius enjoyed access to educational institutions and libraries.

Perhaps the principle importance of Boethius derives from the fact that he was the last of 

the Latin-speaking scholars of the ancient world to be well acquainted with Greek.Although the works of Jerome and Augustine abound in the echoes of Cicero, Virgil, and

Plato, much classic philosophey and literature began to disappear in the West during the

Merovingian Monarchy (the dynasty of the Frankish kings). After the demise of 

Boethius, the West was lacking in anyone with first-hand knowledge of Greek 

 philosophy until Aristotle’s works were rediscovered in the 12th  century, largely from

Arabic sources.

Boethius was born into a family that had held many high offices of state during the 4th

and 5th  centuries. He won the favor of King Theodoric and eventually became the head

of civil service. In 520, he was granted the honorary title, Master of the Offices, which

would probably be equivalent to a prime minister today. Four years later, he was dead,

having been suspected of treachery by Theodoric and executed after a lengthy prison

term. He was celebrated as a martyr after his torture and execution. It was in prison that

he composed his most famous text, the Consolation of Philosophy, written without access

to a library, which nonetheless abounds in reminiscences of classical texts in which his

mind had been soaked since he was a child. It is generally believed that Boethius studied

in Athens or Alexandria in his youth. Let us briefly examine his works.

Page 2: Boethius and Sophia

8/16/2019 Boethius and Sophia

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/boethius-and-sophia 2/20

In his early adult life, Boethius set out to translate into Latin all of the writings of Plato

and Aristotle, a task he was never able to complete due to his short life. Like Gregory of 

Tours, fearing the collapse of the Western Empire, he declared his fear “that many thingswhich are now known soon will not be.” (3) Boethius, it seems, had a salvage operationto perform: preserving a brilliant past for a dying civilization. He composed many

treatises of his own on astronomy, music, geometry and arithmetic, collectively known as

the quadrivium, or “the quadruple road to wisdom.” (4) Shortly before his imprisonment

he finished his famous dissertation on the Trinity which Thomas Aquinas wrote a

commentary on many centuries later.

Using an Aristotelian approach which would become common to the Latin Scholastic

Fathers, Boethius addressed the ecclesiastical doctrine of the Trinity and the nature of 

Christ in at least four treatises. Within the classic terminology of Aristotelian categories,

Boethius described the unity of God in terms of substance, and the three Divine Persons

in terms of relation, much like Gregory of Nyssa. Etienne Gilson has noted that:

“It is Boethius’ ‘De duabus naturis’, that is to say, in a treatise on the two natures inChrist, that there occurs that definition of the person that inspired the whole Middle

Ages…It was in order to know whether [he] had the right to apply it to God that…St.Thomas [Aquinas] examined and explored the definition of Boethius.” (5)

  In all of his works, whether, philosophical, scientific or theological, Boethius draws

from Platonic, Aristotlelian, and Neoplatonic sources. His primary influence for his work 

on the Trinity was Augustine, and therefore this work is highly Platonic. Like Plato,

Boethius writes with the mind of a poet, yet he is balanced by the rational conscience of 

Aristotle. In his discussions of Porphyry (the principle disciple of Plotinus) Boethius

launched the great medieval debate of the nominalists and the realists on the subject of 

universals. Plato had held that universals — the archetypes — had to be real, albeit they

were incorporeal. Aristotle proclaimed that universals were mental concepts(nominalism). Boethius attempted to reconcile the opposing positions by suggesting that

immaterial universals nonetheless subsist in matter.

Before the beginning of Theodoric’s reign, the communion between East and West hadbeen broken and it remained so for 35 years. Relations between the two churches had

been cool since the Emperor Zeno had issued the document known as Henotikon in 482.

Since Theodoric was an Arian, he took no interest in the theological distinctions that

separated Rome and the Byzantine world. The Henotikon was devoted to reconciling the

dogmatic differences which had evolved since the Council of Chaldedon in 451, and in

essence meant, “act of union”. This union, however, was actually forced, as Zeno

promulagated it without the approval of Rome. The  Henotikon  avoided any statementconcerning whether Christ had one or two natures, since Zeno was attempting to please

both Chalcedonians and non-Chalcedonians. In the end, the document failed to satisfy

either group. During the schism, the Pope condemned the Byzantine Patriarch Acacius

and had no interest in Byzantine political support. During this period Rome adhered

loyally to its new Gothic over-lords. However, those who were still interested in the unity

of the  churches, which no doubt included Boethius, “deplored this dissension”. (6)

Page 3: Boethius and Sophia

8/16/2019 Boethius and Sophia

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/boethius-and-sophia 3/20

Boethius, determined nonetheless to serve Theodoric loyally, inevitably recognized the

Arian Gothic regime as a bitter necessity in view of the general political and social

decline. Finally, after the healing of the schism, a new alliance between Rome and

Constantinople developed. This must have appeared threatening to Theodoric, who grew

increasingly concerned over the welfare of his fellow Arians in the East under the

Emperor Justin. When Catholics again saw the Byzantine emperor as their overlord, the

Goths began to be regarded as a hostile enemy of occupation, and heretics besides. In the

late ancient world, doctrinal disputes were often inseparable from politics, and no doubt

Boethius found himself in a disconcerting and ambivalent situation, as Edmund Reiss

explains:

 “Regardless of how effective Boethius may have been as transmitter of ancient learningor as clarifier of Christian doctrine, it was as Theodoric’s Master of the  Offices where he

could actively work to effect a meaningful unification of East and West, that he was able

to restore the prestige of Rome and achieve harmony within the Church…[However]anything he did to link Rome to the Empire would necessarily have been construed as

 being against the interests of the Goths…[and] of Theodoric, in particular.” (7)

During the tumultuous 6th  century, as the ancient world was dying, Boethius must have

been overwhelmed by the excess of evil in the world, of which he no doubt felt he was a

primary victim. He found himself accused of treason and awaiting execution, not long

after achieving the most prestigious honor that anyone of his generation was able to

accomplish. In the Consolation, Boethius says that forged letters and perjured testimony

were used against him, including the claim that he was seeking the assistance of spirits,

i.e., practicing magic. In reality, this may have been an allusion to the astrological

metaphors used in some of his Platonic dialogues. We do not know the exact accusations

against him. Von Campenhausen believes that Boethius was simply accused of wishing

to protect the Senate, then very unstable, on his own. (8)

After the fall of Boethius a dreadful sequence of events followed which fell as a dark 

shadow on the last years of the Gothic reign. The relationship between the Goths and the

Romans continued to deteriorate. Theodoric’s last years were marked by growingsuspicion and distrust, as the fragile union of Romans and Goths he had forged with such

care unraveled before him. After King Theodoric’s death the thirty years ‘struggle for Rome’ ensued; Roman culture and traditions began to slip away entirely. “Henceforth,there was no ancient aristocracy, no Roman state, no consuls, and no philosophy; the

Dark Ages were beginning.” (9)

It has been suggested that if Theodoric had followed the example of the King of the

Franks before him — King Clovis — whose sister Theodoric had married, he may havesuccessfully converted the Goths from Arianism to Catholicism or Orthodoxy and not

only would Italy probably have been spared the forthcoming horrors of war with the

Empire and the later conquest by the Lombards, but the program of Boethius to restore

classical culture may well have been successful. (10)

Page 4: Boethius and Sophia

8/16/2019 Boethius and Sophia

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/boethius-and-sophia 4/20

After Boethius died, his fellow senator, Cassiodorus documented his life and his works.

A foremost Boethian scholar, John Marenbon, tells us that in the Cassiodorean edition of 

Boethius’ work, the personification of the Wisdom -woman is depicted with “the traits of 

the biblical Wisdom, herself often identified with Christ.” (11) For several centuries,Sophia (which I will here refer to as Philosophia, or ‘Lady Philosophy’), was viewed as afigure upholding the Christian interpretation of the world. However, in the 10 th century,

the monk Bovo pointed out that there were elements in the Consolation ‘contrary toCatholic faith’ (12) and that Boethius may, in fact have been more influenced by thepagan philosophers than the Christian faith he explicitly defended in his other works.

  As the centuries progressed, and the Consolation  was printed and re-interpreted many

times over, the general consensus began to shift, then, from perceiving it as a Christian

text to a Platonic one. However, although it was most often thought to reflect the creed of 

Plato or Plotinus, it is nowhere glaringly incongruous with basic Christian values. We

will examine the problem of why a Christian writer would abandon his roots in a salvific

faith and to return to the cool reason of pagan philosophy later in this lecture.

In the Consolation, Boethius uses very little of his Aristotelain logic and relies on

Platonic dialogues, which through the archetypal image of Philosophia, restores to him

the recollection that the highest Good (the Platonic notion of God) is what ultimately

controls an unjust universe. The figure of Wisdom-Sophia invites him to withdraw into

the impregnable citadel of his soul and thus to find a harmony working within the secret

order of the world. Let us examine the five books of the Consolation and see how this

happens.

The Consolation of Lady Philosophy

The Consolation of Philosophy  consists of verse passages (poetry) alternating with

passages of prose. Like the Confessions of Augustine, the movement in the Consolationis from passion to reason, and from the personal to the universal. It became a great work 

of art, in other words, because the autobiographical elements of the narrative essentially

act as a springboard for the timeless tale of a soul lost in the confusion of a world which

has abandoned it. Philosophia, or Lady Wisdom, with whom the prisoner dialogues

throughout the treatise, acts as a kind of soul-doctor, implying that unhappiness is cured

by dispelling ignorance and illusion. The dialogue reveals the Stoic influence on

Boethius, for Lady Wisdom implies that despite the external conditions wherein one

find’s oneself, no real evil can be inflicted upon the soul: the only main evil was to fail todo the right thing. Therefore happiness must consist in attaining virtue which is

completely one’s own and does not derive from anyone else’s power. The conversation

between Boethius and Lady Philosophy proceeds from the initial lament over the prisoner’s immediate situation to the larger issues of alienation, mutability, value and

world order.

Initially we envision Boethius sitting alone in his cell, musing over his adversities.

Imprisoned and despairing, he suddenly receives a theophany, or vision of his former

teacher, Philosophia, who initially appears as a very imposing figure:“a woman of 

Page 5: Boethius and Sophia

8/16/2019 Boethius and Sophia

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/boethius-and-sophia 5/20

majestic countenance whose flashing eyes seemed wise beyond the ordinary wisdom of 

men.” (13) When she raised herself to her full height, “she penetrated heaven itself,

 beyond the vision of human eyes.” On her dress is woven the image of a ladder or stair,

which contain, at the bottom, the Greek letter  pi, and at the top, the Greek letter theta.

She appears carrying a septre and books and she begins to chide him for his miserable

state of mind: “You have forgotten yourself a  little, but you will quickly be yourself 

again, when you recognize me.” He suffers from lethargic depression and she has cometo heal him. She tells him, “I am not so much disturbed by this prison as by your 

attitude,” and she proposes that he end his exile and return again to the mind’s native landthrough self-knowledge, which will reveal to him again the purpose of things and the

lawful ordering of the world.

Boethius continues to protest, however, giving an account of his public career and the

incidents leading to his present misery. He complains that the conduct of humans and

mutable fortune appear to stand outside the lawful pattern of divine love: “we wallowhere in the stormy sea of fortune.” She reminds him that her greatest disciples (such asSocrates) suffered at the hands of the wicked; but the wise are able to rise serenely above

good and bad fortune. She ends her discourse by explaining that he is confused because

 1, “you have forgotten who you are,”2, “you are ignorant of the purpose of things,” and

3. “you have forgotten how the world is governed.” In subsequent chapters of thisdiscourse, she will attempt to explain why this is so, and the remedy for his illness.

With Book Two, the nature of Fortune has morphed into a goddess, who turns her

unpredictable Wheel of Fate, which wreaks such havoc in men’s lives. C. S. Lewiscomments that here “we embark on that great apologia for Fortuna which impressed her 

figure so firmly on the imagination of succeeding ages.” (14) Lady Philosophy explains

that it is Fortuna’s nature to be changeable for, “she neither hears nor cares about the

tears of those in misery.” Everyone enters the world naked and is nourished by her inmany ways, and when the time comes, she again withdraws her favors. No one who has

ever known Fortune can ever trust her again, for she is capricious and her only certain

characteristic is her mutability.

 Boethius acknowledges that she is right and laments that the worst sorrow of the soul is

remembrance of lost joys. Philoso phia reminds him that a person’s life is a temporary

 pilgrimage and to pin one’s happiness on good fortune is the height of folly; for truehappiness is always found within. “Even if the gifts of Fortune were not momentary anduncertain, there is nothing a bout them that can ever really be made your own.” In thefinal analysis, Lady Philosophy argues that misfortune is actually more beneficial than

good fortune, for good fortune enslaves, but bad fortune frees from bondage by revealingthe fragile nature of earthly things. C. S. Lewis sees the Boethian legacy apparent here:

“His work here…in full harmony with the book of Job…is one of the most vigorousdefenses ever written against the view, common to vulgar pagans and vulgar Christians

alike…[which interpr et] variations of human prosperity as divine rewards or

 punishment.” (15)

Page 6: Boethius and Sophia

8/16/2019 Boethius and Sophia

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/boethius-and-sophia 6/20

In the next chapter, Book Three, Philosophia explains some of the greatest traps which

deceive us and lure us toward a fickle happiness: riches, honor, power, fame, bodily

pleasure. “Fix your gaze on the extent, the stability, the swift motion of the heavens, andstop admiring these base things,” she says. Her argument then explicitly points to theonly whole and perfect good: God. In the Consolation’s most famous poem, she invokesthe perfect Creator of the universe in song:

“O God, Maker of heaven and earth, who governs the world with eternal reason, you place all things in motion…you order the perfect parts in a perfect whole…you releasethe world-soul throughout the harmonious parts of the universe as your surrogate,

threefold in its operations, to give motion to all things…Burn off the fogs and clouds of earth and shine through in Thy splendor. For Thou art the serenity, the tranquil peace of 

virtuous men. The sight of Thee is beginning and end; one guide, leader, path and goal.”(pp.53-54, Green)

After having thus reminded the prisoner of what true happiness is, she offers a simple

deduction: “Since men become happy by acquiring happiness, and since happiness isdivinity itself , it follows that men become happy by acquiring divinity.” Althoughcouched in the verse of the classical Platonic metaphor of the lost soul returning to its

homeland, are there not also echoes in this assertion of that famous declaration of 

Athanatius: “Christ became man so that man may become god?” (16) It is here, in themiddle of Boethius’ great work that Lady Philosophy herself glorifies God, redefines the

 prisoner’s exile as a spiritual rather than a physical deprivation, and restores to Boethiusthe memory of the unimportance of worldly fortune when compared with a heavenly

destiny. Book Three ends with the story of Orpheus and Eurydice. Philosophia’s aim isthus to caution Boethius not to look back to the mutable world of Fortune.

Book Four begins with Boethius acknowledging the truth of Philosophia’s doctrine, butthen asks why there is evil in a world governed by an omnipotent God. Philosophia

replies that all is justice. The good are rewarded, just as the wicked are punished by the

mere fact of who and what they are. In addition, the wickedness of others can never

deprive the righteous of their glory. The wicked try to attain the good by ineffectual

means because they are blinded. Ultimately evil, since it is a negation of true being, will

suffer from a lack of existence itself. “Therefore, if you fix your attention on Providenceas the governor of all things, you will find that the evil which is thought to abound in the

world is really nonexistent.” Then Lady Philosophy compares the relationship of 

Providence to individual souls with spheres which orbit around a central point. By

following the wheel or sphere back to its center, the prisoner will no longer be tossed

about on its periphery, but will enjoy once again the freedom that increases when he findshimself at the stable center which is Providence. Here alone, and not in the tumultuous

moving spheres, subjected to Fate, will he again find happiness.

The concluding book of the Consolation  addresses the difficult problem of Divine

Providence and free will. Von Campenhauser calls this “the great theological theme of his century.” (17) For, if God sees all things and therefore knows my actions in advance,

Page 7: Boethius and Sophia

8/16/2019 Boethius and Sophia

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/boethius-and-sophia 7/20

how am I free to exert my own will? Lady Philosophy explains that reasoning about

divine foreknowledge and human freedom is a specifically human process, which

advances through distinct steps from premises to conclusions. It’s perspective isnecessarily partial and temporal. But pure Intelligence, which belongs to God alone,

coincides with  an eternally simple vision. God’s being and therefore, God’s eternity is

“the whole, perfect, and simultaneous possession of endless life.” Therefore “God sees as present those future things which result from free will.” By fusing the theme of perspective with that of time and eternity, Philosophia dissolves Boethius’ dilemma aboutdivine prescience and free will. The freedom of the human will remains inviolate and

continuously imposes upon us the obligation to ever strive for virtue.

In the final analysis, then, the point is not about the innocence of Boethius but about the

 justice of God and the unknown ways of God, finally affirming that everything which

occurs in God’s creation is for the best. In the Consolation, Boethius has given us an

exercise in interior existential psychotherapy, focusing on the human being’s search for meaning in a world of suffering. Indeed, Boethius suggests that meaning comes with

insight, which Lady Philosophy provides. Boethius’ illness is marked by the psychic splitbetween the various perspectives personified as the prisoner and Philosophia. The healing

of this split consists in the unification of these initially opposed viewpoints, the reflective

symbol of which is the unity of Divine Intelligence, which is the telos  that emerges in

Book Five.

Boethius’s Influence and the Understanding of the World-Soul in the Medieval Era

Translations of the Consolation  appeared in the ninth century by King Alfred, and

continued to appear in literature throughout Europe, including the poet Jean de Meun in

the 13th  century; Chaucer, in the 14th  century, Queen Elizabeth’s translation in the 16th

century, and various translations in the Byzantine world. Dante was so influenced by

Boethius that he placed him in Paradise, next to Augustine and Aquinas. (18) It has beennoted that in the twelfth-century, the influence of Boethius reached its peak. His works

became central to nearly every syllabus and he was a hallmark of the medieval schools.

In addition, Consolation was one of the few books available for both lay persons and

scholars.

 One of the most influential commentaries on Boethius was written by William of 

Conches in the 12th century. He also wrote a commentary on Plato’s Timaeus, espousingthe classic Platonic doctrine that  Nous  (Intelligence) was above all the faculties of the

soul, and alone that which enables it to perceive the incorporeal. Plato’s doctrine of pre -

existence emphasizes the forgetfulness of the soul of her former home. The cosmology of 

the Neoplatonic world-view during this era posited a triple process of cognition. Thelowest was based on sense perception; the second was illumination in the individual soul

of forms or ideas in the World-Soul; and thirdly, through the intuition, which had as its

object, Nous, or Divine Mind. Above all these lay the Love and Knowledge of the One.

Anna Crabb identifies the central Platonic theme of Boethius’ Consolation:

Page 8: Boethius and Sophia

8/16/2019 Boethius and Sophia

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/boethius-and-sophia 8/20

“It is not just the material world in general, but actual imprisonment and exile, perhapseven physical chains and certainly physical death toward which he must learn

indifference in order to return to his former…state.” (19)

She notes that the stairs depicted upon Philosophia’s robe link the  pi and the theta  in a

motif of ascent; as the vicissitudes of politics and the sensible world are left behind,

attention turns toward contemplation of the pursuit of knowledge and enlightenment. (20)

William of Conches was perhaps the first commentator to note that the pi and theta on

Philosophia’s robe represent the realms of practice and theory — that is, knowledge which

is grounded in both the material world and its experiences (practice) and the spiritual

world and its metaphysical truth (theta). The ascent begins on the practical physical plane

and moves upward to ‘theoria’, the liminal realm of spirit. Pi and theta are the first letters

of the Greek words “Practical” and “Theoretical”, the two divisions of Philosophy. In theGreek numeral system, theta has a value of 9. It was believed to have been used in

classical Athens as an  abbreviation for the Greek “thanatos” or death; potsherds havebeen found with the letter theta  inscribed on them. It is believed they were used by the

ancient Athenians to vote for the death penalty. There is thus a double meaning of the

letter’s appearance on the top of Lady Philosophy’s dress, indicating that the soul mustpass through its portal to attain enlightenment (Divine Wisdom) in its home in the

afterlife.

In a Neoplatonic cosmology, a fragmentation of the primal unity and stability implies a

fall into alienation, much as in gnosticism. However, to late medieval Christian thinkers,

the visible universe was seen as a manifestation of God, who, consistent with Biblical

doctrine, made all things good. William of Conches wrote that “in the creation of things,

divine Power, Wisdom, and Goodness are beheld.” (21) These attributes, which arefundamental to Platonic cosmological thought, are perceived by William and diverse

other philosophers of this era as well, as an expression of the Trinity.

For William, the archetypal world was identified with the Word (Logos): “the divinewisdom which is called the archetypal world…immutable, eternal, pure, in which are

contained intelligible living creatures.” (22)

However, it is the World-Soul which is seen as the principle of harmony and movement

in life, the force which ensures the link between the intelligible and the sensible. For

William, this divine principle was the Holy Spirit, whose task it was to ensure the

“movement of life, and harmony of the all, uniting ‘individual’ and ‘divided’ nature— spirit and bodies —the same and the different…while remaining unique in itself.”(23) It

has been postulated by Tullio Gregory that the debate about the World-Soul in variousforms dominated the whole of 12 th century philosophy.

William, who was a pupil of Bernard of Chartres, went on to teach Platonism and

Christian theology in the schools of Paris. In his interpretation of Boethius, William

taught that like Augustine before him, when understood correctly, Platonic doctrine is in

accordance with basic Christian truth. William also alluded to the parallels with Lady

Page 9: Boethius and Sophia

8/16/2019 Boethius and Sophia

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/boethius-and-sophia 9/20

Philosophy and Biblical Wisdom. William’s treatises were peppered with Greek gods, but he used pagan mythology, like Boethius, as allegory: “the fictional garment…was

supposed to clothe profound moral doctrine.” (24) However, sometime around 1122, hewas warned by William of St. Thierry that his apparent identification of the Holy Spirit

with the World-Soul would lead to heresy.

It is probably that William’s speculations about the World-Soul, as well as his other

Platonic interpretations regarding cosmology and the natural sciences, were motivated by

a desire to discover the unifying principle that held the world together. Dorothy Elford

explains:

“The particular attraction of the world-soul as a cosmological principle was that,

stemming as it does directly from God, it could guarantee the relationship not only

 between different levels of existence but also between the world and its source.” (25)William, indeed much of the school of Chartres, found great inspiration in the concept of 

the World-soul, which joined the concrete world to the world of Ideas. The regular

motion of the world, evident in the sublime movement of the celestial spheres, revealed a

rational design. The world, as a vast living thing, was possessed of self-movement, and

this seemed to imply it has a soul. (26)

This is important for our discussion because this mediating role — i.e., the understanding

of the world-soul in numerous medieval Christian thinkers — is one which repeatedly

accrues to the function of Sophia in the continued evolution of sophiological thought.

Indeed, in the philosophical poetry of the later 12th  century, Nature becomes, like

Boethius’ Philosophia, a goddess, a manifestation of Wisdom. But in the medieval

Christian world, this would inevitably turn out to be problematic.

Peter Abelard and Hugh of St. Victor also wrote about the relationship between the

World-Soul and the Holy Spirit. In Hugh of St. Victor’s homily on Ecclesiastes, he talksabout the World-soul as a fiery spirit:

“we may— not inappropriately —take this ‘spirit’ to be the fiery force which, proceedingfrom the sun itself, infuses itself in all things, and permeating them all invisibly, animates

and moves them.” (27) Abelard identified the World-soul as a ‘beautiful figure of involucrum’, the allegorical veil for divine truth, in this case meaning the third person of the Holy Trinity. The Council of Sens condemned the thesis of Abelard that the Holy

Spirit is the World-soul, and William of St. Thierry, following his suppression of 

Abelard’s work, then openly pursued his attack on William of Conches. He characterizedWilliam as dangerously promoting a new theological understanding of the Trinity, and

rejecting the literary story of the creation of Eve from Adam’s rib as well.

 It appeared that the concept of the Platonic World-Soul was too pantheistic to be

integrated into Christian metaphysics. Pantheism was a heresy, which numerous other

writers from the Paris schoool were also accused of promoting, (28) and even extended to

a ban on the teaching the works of Aristotle, which were eventually condemned as well:

“Neither the books of Aristotle, on natural philosophy nor the commentaries shall be read

Page 10: Boethius and Sophia

8/16/2019 Boethius and Sophia

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/boethius-and-sophia 10/20

at Paris publicly or secretely and we forbid this under penalty of excommunication…”(ibid,) In any case, William, who did not want to become embroiled in dogmatic

theological controversies, abandoned his study of theology and turned his attention to the

study of nature. His major work, “Philosophy of the World,” written in 1125, isremarkable for its conception of nature as an instrument of divine operation, whose order

guarantees the constancy of things: “The work of nature is to bring forth like things f rom

like through seeds or offshoots, for nature is an energy inherent in things and making like

from like.” (29) When he withdrew his attention from theological matters, Williamasserted his independence of patristic authority, by proclaiming that it was not necessary

to invoke the omnipotence of God as an explanation of natural phenomenon. Rather, God

empowers nature to produce effects and therefore one should seek the cause of those

effects in nature. For example, although God could perfectly well make it something else,

an acorn invariably develops into an oak tree. These speculations are found in William of 

Consches’ Dragmaticon (30)

Marie-Dominique Chenu has observed that “the Christian contemplating the world is tornby a double attraction: to attain God through the world, the order of which reveals its

creator, or to renounce the world, from which God is radically distinct.” (31) In an erainitiated by Boethius and enormously influenced by him, the tension was resolved in

favor of the first option. Scholars who followed Boethius (William of Conches, Hugh of 

St. Victor, Alan of Lille) proposed the view of a homogeneous, non-hierarchal cosmos,

where nature itself acquired a spiritual significance. Matter was no longer the opposing

principle which it had so readily appeared to be for the earlier Christian interpretation of 

the Timaeus. There was dignity and divinity in nature, for what God had created “wasgood.” Chenu notes that “many…nourished by the Consolation of Philosophy…used thissupreme intelligible Reality to explain the sense-perceptible world and not merely to

mount toward Being that is self-existent and divorced from the world.” (32) To affirm theunity of spirit and matter depended ultimately on the ability of the human spirit to know

both, i.e., to apprehend in nature a knowledge of the universal, which participated indivinity. For Hugh of St. Victor, contemplation requires the use of the intellect, and is not

confined to mystical experience. Contemplation on the sensible world brings “an easy

and clearsighted penetration of the soul into that which is seen.” (33)

 To know nature is to understand the self; and a study of nature would lead to a view of 

natural law as a standard for the regulation of the social and moral order. The symbolic

emphasis of the  pi and theta on Lady Philosophy’s robe, in representing both the realmsof practice and theory, remind the prisoner (and through him, us) that the stairs of 

spiritual ascent begin here, that is, with knowledge grounded in physical experience. In

the balanced synergy of Boethius’ Aristotelian and Platonic perspectives, we glimpse his

remarkable ability to combine the realms of spirit and matter; and because Boethius hadbestowed to the natural sciences their state of autonomy, William of Conches and others

in succeeding generations could conclude that the world was a holistic and organic

ensemble, created in and through Beauty.

Boethius’ Philosophy: Christian or Pagan?

Page 11: Boethius and Sophia

8/16/2019 Boethius and Sophia

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/boethius-and-sophia 11/20

It has often been noted that what is missing in the Consolation is any explicit reference to

the Bible. The manner in which Lady Philosophy herself is commended by Boethius is in

presenting her arguments: she sticks to philosophy and does not employ revelation. In

his exile and his contemplation of death, Boethius makes no mention of the Incarnation

or the doctrine of grace — that which most Christians would find most meaningful. The

Boethian doctrine of redemption appears to be the “ascent of the unaided individual bymeans of philosophical introspection and meditation.” (34) The opinion of both

Chadwick and von Campenhausen is that Consolation was composed by a Christian and

a Platonist, but it is not a Christian work.

 Scholars have argued about whether Boethius’ last work is Platonic or Christian for centuries. The single reference to the World-soul, right at the center of the work, during

the prayer in Book 3, caused, as we have seen, great confusion to many of the later

medieval commentators on the text. This reference aside, the most evident Platonic

theme in the Consolation appears to be the general interpretation that imperfections of the

world are allowed for the purpose of facilitating the return of the soul to its origin. (35) In

a Neoplatonic cosmology, a fragmentation of the primal unity and stability implies a fall

into alienation. Any system of thought based on emanation theory tends to produce

continuously inferior beings as part of the outflow from the point of origin., e.g.,the Deity

of Plotinus was absolutely transcendent and ineffable; it is from a hierarchy of powers,

such as Nous, World-Soul, Nature, etc. that multiplicity of finite things emanates.

However, for the early Fathers, if by ‘origin’ is meant a return to a pre -existent primal

unity with the One, it is inconsistent with Christian revelation. This is, in fact, the

principle heresy of Origen. Life is an evolutionary process of movement into the life of 

God made possible through the Incarnation. Christian life now, and in eternity (as in

Gregory Nyssa), moves forward into a fuller maturity, because every antithesis to life has

been overcome by Christ. There is nothing of this in the Consolation. Yet, Boethius,

although resting upon Plato and Aristotle, adapts their principles to a universe governedby a personal, caring God. It was precisely in an era which we often refer to as the ‘agesof faith’ that the appeal of Boethius’ work was most strongly felt.

In his earlier treatises on the Trinity and on the Nestorian problem, Boethius had already

engaged in doctrinal disputes. Perhaps his statement of faith in several earlier works

stood in no need of repetition. Indeed, at the end of his treatise on the Trinity, he says it is

simply an apologetic in defense of an article “which stands by itself on the firmfoundation of faith.” (36)

Victor Watts believes there is little in the Consolation that is contrary to Christianity. He

points out that although much of his thought conforms to Neoplatonism, Boethiushowever, “talks not of a supreme essence but of God: and he does not fill the gapbetween God and  his world by any elaborate series of ‘graded abstractions’. Boethius’God is a personal God, a God to whom one can and should pray.” (37) In addition,although Boethius mentions Plato and Aristotle in the Consolation, he never specifically

names any of the Neoplatonic philosophers who lived after Christ. Henry Chadwick 

Page 12: Boethius and Sophia

8/16/2019 Boethius and Sophia

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/boethius-and-sophia 12/20

agrees that the “mythological jungle of pagan gnosticism” which characterizes the later books of Proclus is discarded by Boethius.

 Chadwick feels, however, that Boethius was very careful in how he constructed the

Consolation, for “this cycle of original being, emergence to otherness, and then reversionto identity is latent in the structure of the Consolation itself. Hence it is no accident

that…he can state an exclusively Neoplatonic doctr ine of redemption, which is

nevertheless capable of being read in a Christian sense with the minimum of force to the

text…Boethius is unlikely to have achieved this by chance or without careful thought.”(38)

Robert McMahon feels that since Boethius was a Christian, he simply used those aspects

of Platonism consistent in Christian teaching; and there is little of Plato in the

Consolation that is not already found in Augustine. McMahon points out that “return tothe Origin may have a Neoplatonist ring to it, but for Augustine, it was [also] a

 profoundly biblical and ecclesial reality. Within the ‘Confessions’ he treated Neoplatonism as an incomplete Christianity” made complete only in the Bible. (39)

Etienne Gilson has made it clear that the Christian tradition’s influence on Boethius was amost compelling factor in the way he develops his philosophy in the Consolation. What

Gilson calls Christian philosophy is: “every philosophy which, although keeping the twoorders formally distinct, nevertheless considers the Christian revelation as an

indispensable auxiliary to reason.” (40)

For Gilson, the elegance of Christianity lies in the fact that it is both a richly developed

epistomology, as well as an efficacious way of salvation. Today, we generally do not

think of philosophy as having a direct connection to salvation, because we consider

philosophy as belonging more to the sphere of science; however, for Boethius and the

medieval world which followed him, even Platonic and Aristotelian philosophy,“although essentially science, was not merely a science but a [way of] life.” (41) TheGreek Stoics even adopted a distinctive type of dress similar to a priest or monk.

Furthermore, Gilson stresses that in a Christian universe nothing ever happens save in the

name of a rational order, that is, nothing happens by chance. Lady Philosophy explains

we can define chance as:

 “an unexpected event brought about by a concurrence of causes which had other purposes in view. These causes come together because of that order which proceeds

from inevitable connection of things, the order which flows from the source which is

Providence and which disposes all things, each in its proper time and place.”

Gilson acknowledges the debt to the Platonists in Boethius and the overwhelming

importance of the philosophical element in everything he wrote, including his theological

tractates; however, this is “precisely the reason why he is rightly considered as one of thefounders of scholasticism.” (42) Edward Grant’s opinion is that Gilson relys on the

‘handmaiden’ approach, which goes back to Clement of Alexandria, where “philosophyis the handmaid of theology” (43)  In the final analysis, I find myself agreeing with Joel

Page 13: Boethius and Sophia

8/16/2019 Boethius and Sophia

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/boethius-and-sophia 13/20

Relihan: ‘We cannot say that it is not Christian because it is not a catechism.” (44)Boethius is much too complex a writer; and, as Relihan points out, if it in any way

resembles the genre of Wisdom literature “which gains its religious dimensions by itsplacement in the religious context of the canons of Scripture, Consolation co-ops secular

traditions for religious purposes.” (ibid)

If this is so, in what way is the Wisdom tradition evident in this, the last work of an

exiled prisoner?

 Lady Philosophy and the Wisdom Literature

Are there themes in the Wisdom literature that emerge in the Consolation? Certainly, it is

a hallmark of the Wisdom Literature that our everyday experiences in life become a path

to our understanding of God. Chadwick believes the Consolation  is an essay in natural

theology apart from revelation (45) And surely the Wisdom tradition sees the splendor of 

creation as a motive for praising God. (Wis 13; Sir 42: 14-43; Ps. 8; Job 38) Emergent

themes in the Wisdom texts are the beauty and order of the universe, a call for the people

of God to discern God’s purpose in the world, and a declaration that those who co-

operate with God by following God’s wisdom are in conformity with the order of creation and those who choose the path of folly will end in ruin, for rejecting the way of 

Wisdom leads to a return of the primeval chaos. The book of Job belongs to the Wisdom

tradition and a detailed comparison with Job and Boethius has been made by Ann Astell

(46) Astell sees the development of providential themes in the Consolation through Lady

Philosophy’s insistence of the human inability to envision the world from a divine

viewpoint. She believes that Lady Philosophy’s “final exortation to humble prayer”encouraged medieval readers to supply what Boethius, revered as a Christian martyr, had

omitted by not referring in a more overt manner to the Job story. When Aquinas, on the

other hand, wrote his commentary on Job, he explicitly linked it to the Consolation.Boethius however, does appear to paraphrase Job 1:21 in Consolation, Book 2, Prose 2,

when Lady Philosophy says that “nature brought you forth from your mother’swomb…naked and devoid of everything.”

We noticed earlier that C.S Lewis also sees a clear Job theme in the Consolation. Job’sstory, like the prisoner of Boethius, is an account of an innocent human being who

initially questions the meaning of his suffering and who must earn a hard-won wisdom as

he comes to understand that the mutable world must always succumb to the majesty and

mystery of a God beyond comprehension. The stories do not explain why God chose to

design the world in the way that it is; rather the heroic pilgrim is only made aware of the

incommensurability of human and divine knowing. The conclusion of the Consolation isthe theodicity of the Job story. Both must admit to the inadequacies of the categories of 

thought and accept the transcendence of God. As Astell comments, “’wisdom’ loses itspragmatic, prudential associations and becomes instead the Pauline foolishness that

rejoices in the cross.” (1 Cor. 1: 18-23) (47) Joel Reilan stresses that there are other

allusions (48) to the Wisdom Literature besides the comparison with the Job story, one

Page 14: Boethius and Sophia

8/16/2019 Boethius and Sophia

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/boethius-and-sophia 14/20

that comes from the Wisdom of Solomon, which indeed personifies Lady Wisdom a

number of times.

And so we must ask, Who is the Wisdom Woman in the Consolation? Is the lady a

literary device, a philosophical abstraction, or a personification of the goddess: in

essence, a revelation? Kathyrn Lunch has noted that the visionary nature of the poetry of 

Boethius has not been given the clarification it demands or deserves, (49), which may be

a problem that characterizes the analysis of the Wisdom tradition since the genesis of 

exegetical commentaries. For now, we must simply wonder: why does the prisoner

awaiting execution turn to Lady Philosophy? Why a goddess? For it is Philosophia who

acts as the minister and healer of the soul, not Christ; it is she who bends over the

suffering disciple to soothe and strengthen him. Reilan clearly identifies a key factor

which emerges here: “it shows that the ability to know who one is, is strictly in the

 province of anima, not ratio…” (50) For it is the anima which opens the soul to dreams

and visions, not reason. Lynch stresses that “for Philosophy’s disciple…insight occurs asa matter of  sight, revelation, or showing  (italics mine); spiritual healing became a

 precisely embodied event…For Boethius…a personal need— a need that went beyond

any previous writer’s to bring both human psychological reality and earthly experience inaccord with grace — played a great part in the vision experience.” (51).

 Visionary experiences are — like pilgrimages — liminal or marginal in nature, experiences

“betwixt and between” what is familiar. Liminality, from the Latin, ‘limen’ means athreshold  and is always a quality of consciousness that implies that which is numinous in

archetypal psychology. In this interpretation, the prisoner’s initial epiphany is archetypalin nature, having its precedent in literature of an earlier Hellenistic era (with which

Boethius would have been very familiar) — such as the vision of Isis in the

Metamorphoses of 2nd  century Platonist Apuleius, or the vision (the “showing”) whichaccompanied the Eleusinian Mysteries. The description of Philosophia at the beginning of 

the text is painted in visionary language, e.g., her dreamlike changes in size andappearance, her burning eyes or her combination of youth with great age. Marenbon feels

that her numinous appearance fits into a “tradition of divine manifestations” whichstretch as far back as Homer. (52)

Yet, as the goddess-like image of Lady Philosophy develops in the story, she is revealed,

not as a figure inspiring the awe one normally associates with a classic epiphany event in

religious literature (compare the ‘epopteia’, or visual culmination of the Eleusinian

Mysteries, with the classic visions of the medieval mystics), but rather as a psychopomp.

Frederick Brenk has rightly noted, that during the era of Middle Platonism, a vision, even

a direct intellectual vision of God was problematic. For “in the philosophical eschatology

of Plato, God [the demiurge] or gods are the guides or mystagogues, or fellowvisionaries, but not worthy as the object of visions itself.” (53) Rather, when Platospeaks of a vision, it is directed toward the transcendent Idea of the Good or Beautiful,

ie., the initial Form. Later, in Plutarch, a human being’s intellect ( Nous) is also one’sdaimon or guardian spirit, to which we must attend, if we are at all to benefit from our

sojourn on the earth. In Plutarch’s Isis and Osiris, we begin to see an identification of the

Good with the Supreme God, the vision of which is the soul’s goal and purpose. The

Page 15: Boethius and Sophia

8/16/2019 Boethius and Sophia

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/boethius-and-sophia 15/20

significant contribution of Plutarch, as Brenk notes, is not only that herein lies the telos,

i.e., the vision of God, but “the object of love [is] itself capable of returning love.” (54)

God’s creation is enough for God; however, the mystery of our world is that God createscreatures out of love.

Surely, then, the telos of the Consolation is to urge the prisoner to seek, not wisdom, but

the highest Good. “As an exhortatio to philosophy, the Consolation is really an exhortatio

to God.” (55) Edmund Reiss has seen in the Consolation not only comparisons to several

other Neoplatonic treatises, including those by Plutarch and Iamblichus, but also, a

culmination of all of Boethius’ earlier work. “While earlier studies may have led to anunderstanding of logic, the study of philosophy leads, as the Soliloquies of Augustine, to

the revelation of the nature of divinity. “ (56) Brenk has theorized that we rarely see any

of the philosophers of the Middle Platonic era unambiguously referring to a vision of God

as the telos  of the soul because of the gap between the First and Second God (ie., the

Demiurge) (57) And Boethius certainly knew Plotinus, who said, “For one should beholdthe source of the illumination.” This is the “veritable telos of the soul”. (58)

  Lady Philosophy seems to be reticent about explaining in detail the operation of the

world; she says, rather, “I shall limit my discussion of the divine judgment to a few things

which human reason can comprehend.” In book Four, she even says she is not a god (or goddess, depending on the translation). (Book 4, Prose 6) If Philosophia is not a goddess

or a lesser kind of god, an inferior kind of wisdom, then what is the point of her

revelation?

In Gilson’s classic History of Christian Philosophy in the Middle Ages he notes the case

“where Boethius says of the Sovereign Good that it ‘reacheth from end to end mightilyand ordereth all things sweetly.’” (59) Here Gilson believes the quote is undeniably acitation from Wisdom 8:1, which was frequently quoted by Augustine. (60) Reilan muses

that if Philosophia clearly demonstrates that God is the highest Good and governs allthings [sweetly!] then “we must infer” that Boethius was indeed influenced by theWisdom text. This then is where the prisoner “begins to see the possibility of theseamless integration of philosophy and revelation.” (61)

 Although the books of Proverbs and Qoheleth offer instruction on living life in

moderation and acceptance of old age, loss of health and possessions, and death, as part

of the process of cyclical cosmic change, the Wisdom of Solomon  confidently proclaims

God’s vindication for the just, beyond the horizon of mortal life and cyclical nature. This

text — which the post-Reformation church accepts only as apocryphal — was written in a

Hellenistic atmosphere, and also seems to accept the Platonic notion of the immortality of 

the soul. Here, the Spirit of God is a feminine vitalizing principle, almost like the World-soul of the Platonists, which is immanent  in the universe.

Boethius would most certainly have been aware that the apocryphal Wisdom of Solomon,

often simply called the  Liber Sapientia  (The Book of Wisdom) personified Divine

Wisdom as feminine, consistent with both the Greek and the Latin translations of the

word, (ie., “sophia” and “sapientia”) Perhaps here, as Relihan notes, Boethius has “given

Page 16: Boethius and Sophia

8/16/2019 Boethius and Sophia

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/boethius-and-sophia 16/20

us his own version of Wisdom.” (62) In other words, it  is possible that Boethius saw

Sophia as an accepted personification within the Christian tradition; therefore he felt — ina very subtle way to be sure — he could use her in his own epic drama. For Kathryn

Lynch, however, the tradition which Boethius would draw upon to speak in visionary

language was the tradition of Neoplatonic dream theory. In particular, the dream image

 provides an appropriate structure for the medieval era “because of its liminal character,its ability to combine the realms of spirit and matter into a single experiential

 phenomenon.” (63)

We have examined many viewpoints of Boethius’ main work, circling around the centraltheme of the personification of Sophia. In conclusion, we can say that Boethius

synthesized the Platonic and Aristotelian elements of his Greek culture, and in doing so,

made a valuable contribution to the evolving philosophy of the medieval era. This is

important for the study of modern sophiology for a couple of reasons. What is most

obvious is that Lady Philosophy’s  principle task in sustaining the marriage of the divine

order and natural circumstance was to help convince her prisoner of the basic integrity of 

the world, despite the fickleness of fate. She does this by gradually making him conscious

of the ways in which Divine Providence was revealed in and through the physical world.

As we have seen, as medieval commentaries of Boethius’ Consolation  emerge, they

would display a belief in the interpenetration of spiritual and physical realms, which even

included the possibility of knowing spirit through matter, particularly evident in the work 

of William of Conches. Nature, in the metaphysics of the schools of 12th century Chartres

was not merely an allegory but an active force which presided at the birth of things and

sustained their continued evolution. In light of the deep influence of Aristotle on the

Scholastic fathers, Gilson poses an intriguing question. “How came it” Gilson asks, “that, having followed the Platonic tradition for so long, the Christian thinkers gradually

yielded to the growing influence of Aristotle, and….finally defined the soul as a  form of 

the body?” [rather than the other way around]. In other words, as Lynch also indicates,

there is a reversal from balancing Plato with Aristotle in Boethius.

The second reason Lady Philosophy is an important contribution to the development of 

our theme is that she becomes the numinous Mediator, a role Sophia seems to play

wherever and whenever she appears. Gilson acknowledges that, although Boethius does

not seek support directly from Scripture in the Consolation, it is because it is Lady

Philosophy who is speaking. (64) If the wisdom she embodies must necessarily be pagan

for Boethius, it is because divine mediation in the form of a goddess is not an unnatural

association in pagan’ philosophy. It is, as we have seen, a genre of allegory— and one

which frequently includes an analysis of the World-soul — which is woven throughout

numerous Platonic medieval texts.

Marenbon following Klingner, says that although Lady Philosophy is imagined by

Boethius to have “come down from the pole on high” (65), she acts only as anintermediary. For Friedrich Klingner (66), who concludes that the Consolation is a sacred

dialogue, Lady Philosophy is an angel, leading him step by step back toward the

remembrance of God. However, unlike the divine mediation which has been

appropriated to Mary in numerous Christian Fathers, or the feminine Holy (Mother)

Page 17: Boethius and Sophia

8/16/2019 Boethius and Sophia

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/boethius-and-sophia 17/20

Spirit in the very early Church, by the time of the Western medieval world, it was heresy

to associate the World-soul (anima mundi) with the Holy Spirit. The Latin “spiritus”, in

any event, is no longer associated with the Hebrew “ruach” or the Greek “pneuma”; isnow a masculine Spirit, rather than a feminine Breath of God. Lady Philosophy may be

the  persona  of the ‘anima mundi’   but she is certainly not Christ or the Holy Spirit,

although she appears to embody some aspects of divine Wisdom.

The true Christian philosopher (or philosopher-mystic, as this is where our future studies

lead us) it seems, would necessarily have to reject all pantheistic elements from his or her

vision of Wisdom, or else leave her in the realm of pagan allegory. This is precisely what

happens in Henry Suso’s vision of Sophia, where Divine Wisdom becomes , once again,

Christ. In this case, however, the figure who appears as Christ must undergo a gender

reversal, as we will see in the next lecture.

End-Notes

1. Quoted in Let, Ferdinand.  The End of the Ancient World and the Beginnings of the

 Middle Ages. NY: Harper and Row, 1961. p. 371.

2. Reiss, Edmund. Boethius, Boston: Twayne Pub. 1982. p. 4.

3. quoted in Oxford History of the Classical World . Boardman, John, et al. NY: Oxford

University Press. 1986. p. 811.

4. quoted in Gilson , Etienne. History of Christian Philosophy in the Middle Ages. NY:

Random House. 1954, p 97.5. Gilson, Etienne. The Spirit of Medieval Philosophy. Trans by A.H.C. Downes.

London: University of Notre dame Press. 1936, p. 204.

6. von Campenhausen, Hans. Men Who Shaped the Church. NY: Harper & Row. 1964

pp. 290-294.

7. Reiss, Edmund, Boethius. Twayne’s World Author Series. Boston: TwaynePublishers: Duke University. 1982. pp.77- 78.

8.  Men Who Shaped, p. 300.

9. ibid.,p. 299.

10. see Reiss, p. 78. Here he is paraphrasing Pierre Riche, Education and Culture in the

 Barbarian west, Sixth through Eighth Centuries, Trans. J Contreni. Columbia: University

of south Carolina Press, 1976.11. Marenbon, John. Boethius, Oxford University Press 2003. p. 174.

12. ibid.

13. The following quotations from Consolation are taken from: Green, Richard. The

Consolation of Philosophy: Boethius. Pearson Pub. 1962.

14. Lewis, C.S. Discarded Image, p. 81.

15. Discarded, p. 82.

Page 18: Boethius and Sophia

8/16/2019 Boethius and Sophia

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/boethius-and-sophia 18/20

16. I have not seen anyone else who has noticed the analysis comparing this text with the

Greek Christian theology of salvation except for Jaroslav Pelikan, see  Mary Through the

Centuries, Yale University Press, 1998. p. 105.

17. Men Who Shaped , p. 311.

18. Marenbon, 2003, p. 180.

19. “ Literary Design in the De Consolatione Philosophiae, Anna Crabb in Boethius, His

Life, Thought and Influence. Ed by Margaret Gibson. Oxford, England: Basil Blackwell ,

1981. p242 (pp237-274.

20. ibid, pp. 243-44.

21. quoted in, “Philosophy, cosmology and the Twelfth-century Renaissance” Winthrop

Wetherbee, in Peter Dronke ed,  A History of Twelfth-Century Western Philosophy,

Cambridge University Press. 1988, p.25.

22. quoted in ibid, From “The Platonic Inheritance, Tullio Gregory, in Dronke, A History

of Twelfth-Century Western Philosophy. 1988, p. 61.

23. ibid, p. 68. See also Gregory, Tullio,  Anima Mundi: La Filosofia Di Gu Glielmo Di

Conches E La Scuola Di Chartres) G. C. Sansoni 1955.

24. Aspects of Medieval French and English Tradition of the De Consolatione

Philosophiae, in Margaret Gibson, Boethius, ibid, p. 315.

25. Elford, Dorothy. “William of Conches.” In Dronke, 1988, p. 327.26. see, Chenu, M D , Nature, Man and Society in the Twelfth Century. Edited and trans.

By Jerome Taylor and Lester Little. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. 1968, pages

18-24.

27. from Pergit spiritus, Hugh of St. Victor; quoted in Michael Lapidge “The Stoic

Inheritance” in Dronke, 1988, p. 109 pp 308-327.

28. Other prominent voices which were condemned at the Fourth Lateran Council in

1215 included Amaury of Bebe and David of Dinant, and John Scotus Eriugena. See

Haren, Michael. The Western Intellectual Tradition from Antiquity to the Thirteenth

Century. Toronto: University of Toronto Press. p. 147.

29. William of Conches Glossa in Timaeum, quoted in Chenu, Nature, pl 41.30. see Tina Stiefel, The Intellectual Revolution in Twelfth-century Europe. NY: St.

Martin’s Press. 1985, esp. pp 79, 91-92.

31. Chenu, Marie-Dominique. Nature, Man and Society in Twelfth Century: Essays on

 New Theological Perspectives in the Latin West . Ed and Trans: J Taylor & L.K. Little

(Chicago. 1968)

32. ibid, p. 97.

33 Hugh of St. Victor De Modo Dicendi et Meditandi, 8; quoted in Eco, Umberto. Art

and Beauty in the Middle Ages. Trans by Hugh Bredin. New Haven: Yale University

Press, 1986. p 10.

34.Victor Watts, trans. Boethius. Penguin Books 1999, p. xxxiii.

35. As Watts, explains: “…the ascent of the soul is not simply a process of education; itis also one of remembering: and the Platonic basis of the Consolation is seen again in the

reference to this doctrine of anamnesis, or recollection…” Watts, trans. Boethius, p.

xxvi.

36. in deTrinitate, quoted in Reiss, Boethius, p. 61

37. p. xxxii

Page 19: Boethius and Sophia

8/16/2019 Boethius and Sophia

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/boethius-and-sophia 19/20

38. Chadwick, Henry. Boethius: The Consolations of Music, Logic, Theology and 

Philosophy. Oxford ; Clarendon Press, 1981, pp 221-222

39. p. 102 in, Understanding the Medieval Meditative Ascent: Augustine, Boethius,

Anselm, and Dante” Robert McMahon. Washington DC: Catholic University of AmericaPress. 2006

40. Gilson, The Spirit of Medieval Philosophy. Trans. A.H.C. Downes. London:

University of Notre Dame Press 1936.

p. 37.

41.ibid. p. 28.

42. History of Christian, p. 106.

43. Grant, Edward. God and Reason in the Middle Ages. Cambridge Univ. Press 2001,

p.32.

44. Relihan, Joel. The Prisoner's Philosophy. Life and Death in Boethius's Consolation.

Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 2007p.129.

45. Boethius, p. 251

46. Astell, Ann. Job, Boethius, and Epic Truth. Ithaca and London: Cornell University

Press. 1994.

47. Astell, p. 13

48. Relihan, p. 128

49. Lynch,Kathryn. The High Medieval Dream Vision: Poetry, Philosophy, and Literary

Form Stanford University Press. 1988

50 ibid p 110

51. ibid.p54.

52. Boethius, 2003, p 153

53. Brenk, S.J.Frederick. In, “Darkly Beyond the Glass: Middle P latonism and the Vision

of the Soul” In Platonism in Late Antiquity pp. 39-60, Ed by Stephen Gersh & Charles

Kannengresser. Indiana: University of Notre Dame Press. 1992

54. ibid, p. 54

55. Boethius, Edmund Reiss, Twayne Pub. Boston. 1982, p. 13956. ibid, p 139

57. Darkly, p. 60.

58 quoted in Darkly, pp 59-60

59. Gilson, History of Christian Philosophy in the Middle Ages. Random House, 1955.

60.ibid p. 102.

61 p. 28

62. Prisoner’s Philosophy, p. 128

63. High Medieval, page 56

64. Historyp.102.

65. Boethius, Oxford Univ Press, 2003. p 154

66. Klingner, F. De Boethii, Consolatione Philosophiae. 2 Unveranderte Auflage. Zurich/ Dublin 1966

Page 20: Boethius and Sophia

8/16/2019 Boethius and Sophia

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/boethius-and-sophia 20/20