another test of the theory of reference-dependent...

27
ANOTHER TEST OF THE THEORY OF REFERENCE-DEPENDENT PREFERENCES: THE TRADE-OFF BETWEEN MONEY AND TIME Bruno De Borger University of Antwerp, Belgium, [email protected] Mogens Fosgerau 1 Danish Transport Research Institute, Denmark, [email protected] 11 August 2006 Abstract We test the theory of reference-dependent preferences using binary choice stated preference data on the trade-offs between money and travel time. The model incorporates loss aversion, diminishing sensitivity and asymmetry between time and cost as well as between gains and losses. Evaluating different measures of time valuation, the empirical analysis first confirms the very large gap between estimates of willingness to pay and willingness to accept that is often reported in the literature. We then formulate and estimate an econometric model allowing for reference-dependent preferences. The implications of the theory are consistently accepted against more general alternatives, in tests of high statistical power. We find substantial evidence of loss aversion; we also find asymmetries between time and cost as well as between gains and losses. Finally, we show that the fraction of ´mistakes`, in the sense that participants are observed to sometimes select dominated options, systematically varies in a way consistent with the model of reference dependence. 1 Corresponding author. ©Association for European Transport and contributors 2006

Upload: others

Post on 28-Sep-2020

2 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: ANOTHER TEST OF THE THEORY OF REFERENCE-DEPENDENT ...web.mit.edu/11.951/OldFiles/oldstuff/albacete/Other_Documents/Eur… · ANOTHER TEST OF THE THEORY OF REFERENCE-DEPENDENT PREFERENCES:

ANOTHER TEST OF THE THEORY OF REFERENCE-DEPENDENT PREFERENCES:

THE TRADE-OFF BETWEEN MONEY AND TIME

Bruno De Borger

University of Antwerp, Belgium, [email protected]

Mogens Fosgerau1

Danish Transport Research Institute, Denmark, [email protected]

11 August 2006

Abstract

We test the theory of reference-dependent preferences using binary choice stated

preference data on the trade-offs between money and travel time. The model incorporates loss

aversion, diminishing sensitivity and asymmetry between time and cost as well as between gains

and losses. Evaluating different measures of time valuation, the empirical analysis first confirms the

very large gap between estimates of willingness to pay and willingness to accept that is often

reported in the literature. We then formulate and estimate an econometric model allowing for

reference-dependent preferences. The implications of the theory are consistently accepted against

more general alternatives, in tests of high statistical power. We find substantial evidence of loss

aversion; we also find asymmetries between time and cost as well as between gains and losses.

Finally, we show that the fraction of ´mistakes`, in the sense that participants are observed to

sometimes select dominated options, systematically varies in a way consistent with the model of

reference dependence.

1 Corresponding author.

©Association for European Transport and contributors 2006

Page 2: ANOTHER TEST OF THE THEORY OF REFERENCE-DEPENDENT ...web.mit.edu/11.951/OldFiles/oldstuff/albacete/Other_Documents/Eur… · ANOTHER TEST OF THE THEORY OF REFERENCE-DEPENDENT PREFERENCES:

1 Introduction

The purpose of the paper is to test the theory of reference-dependent preferences, using

binary choice stated preference data on the trade-offs between money and travel time. We formulate

a model of reference-dependence based on a linear reference-free utility function defined over

travel time and cost. Reference-dependence is captured by value functions centered at the reference.

The most general version of the model incorporates loss aversion and diminishing sensitivity, and it

captures asymmetry between time and cost as well as between gains and losses. We use this

theoretical setting to develop an econometric model that accounts for both observed and unobserved

individual heterogeneity through the individual-specific reference-free value of time. The model is

applied to a large data set with observations from more than 2000 individuals that were offered

repeated choices between alternatives, defined in terms of time and cost changes relative to the

reference. A range of models is estimated, incrementally allowing a more general specification of

the value functions. The results suggest that loss aversion plays an important role in explaining

responses. Moreover, we consistently fail to reject the null hypothesis of the reference-dependence

model against more general alternatives. Finally, we analyse data on choice situations where one

alternative dominates the other on both the cost and the time dimension. We show that the data on

dominated choices also show a clear pattern that to a large extent can be explained by loss aversion.

In their seminal paper, Tversky and Kahneman ( 1991) extend their earlier work

(Kahneman and Tversky ( 1979)) to conditions of risk-less choice. A fundamental ingredient of the

theory of reference-dependent preferences they develop is the value function, which has four

general features: (i) It is increasing; (ii) It is reference-dependent, meaning that individuals interpret

options in decision problems as gains or losses relative to a reference point; (iii) It exhibits loss

aversion: losses relative to the reference are valued more heavily than gains; (iv) It has diminishing

sensitivity: the marginal values decrease with size, both for losses and for gains. Reference-

dependence and loss aversion jointly imply that the slope of the indifference curve through a point

depends on the reference from which it is evaluated, and that kinks occur at the reference choice.

Loss aversion has two other straightforward implications. First, it implies status quo bias (the

opposite does not hold because of, e.g., transaction costs). Second, it implies that the same

difference between two options will count more if it is a difference between two disadvantages than

between two advantages, as compared to the reference state.

©Association for European Transport and contributors 2006

Page 3: ANOTHER TEST OF THE THEORY OF REFERENCE-DEPENDENT ...web.mit.edu/11.951/OldFiles/oldstuff/albacete/Other_Documents/Eur… · ANOTHER TEST OF THE THEORY OF REFERENCE-DEPENDENT PREFERENCES:

The theory has important economic implications and leads to directly testable predictions.

In an early application Samuelson and Zeckhauser ( 1988) provide evidence of status quo bias in

jobs, automobile colour, investment, and in the choice of medical plans by students. They also

suggest that loss aversion may operate differently on different dimensions of the choice problem.

Moreover, over the past decades, a substantial number of studies have used prospect theory to

explain the widely documented gap between willingness to pay (WTP) and willingness-to-accept

(WTA). The gap has been noted in stated as well as revealed choice situations, and it appears in very

different settings, including contingent valuation studies, laboratory experiments, public goods

experiments, etc.2. It is well known that in a Hicksian preference setting, as long as goods are

normal, it will be the case that WTP<WTA; the size of the difference depends on the magnitude of

income effects (see, e.g., Randall & Stoll 1980). Standard preferences also imply that WTP equals

the equivalent loss (EL), and WTA equals the equivalent gain (EG). However, the gap between WTP

and WTA that is found in experiments is often so large that it is difficult to explain in a standard

Hicksian setting3. Bateman et al. ( 1997) therefore use reference-dependent preferences to study the

systematic differences between the different concepts. They show that loss aversion immediately

implies WTA>WTP. Moreover, the two other measures (EL and EG) should be in between, but their

relative size cannot be determined a priori. The authors then set up a series of experiments that

allows testing the standard Hicksian theory versus a reference-dependent alternative, and they find

strong evidence in favour of the latter.

In this paper, we employ data from a binary choice experiment. Subjects in the

experiments were car drivers that had to choose between two alternatives, characterised by travel

time and travel cost. These alternatives were variations around a recent trip that was treated as the

reference4. Each binary choice implied a simple trade-off between travel time and travel cost. We

employ information on four types of choices. The first choice involves comparison of the reference

and an alternative which is faster but more expensive than the reference, a ‘willingness to pay’ type

2 See, among many others, Cummings et al. ( 1986) and Andreoni ( 1995) in the context of public goods evaluation, Kahneman, Knetsch and Thaler ( 1990), Benartzi and Thaler ( 1995) and Bateman et al. (1997) in a market exchange environment. 3 Horowitz and McConnell ( 2003) recently strongly suggest that, when the gap is large, the income effect is an implausible explanation. 4 There is an ongoing discussion concerning the determination of the reference point. A recent reference on this issue is Köszegi and Rabin ( 2006). They argue that in some applications it makes sense to assume that the reference is not the status quo of the current situation, but rather recent expectations about the outcome.

©Association for European Transport and contributors 2006

Page 4: ANOTHER TEST OF THE THEORY OF REFERENCE-DEPENDENT ...web.mit.edu/11.951/OldFiles/oldstuff/albacete/Other_Documents/Eur… · ANOTHER TEST OF THE THEORY OF REFERENCE-DEPENDENT PREFERENCES:

of choice. The second is a ´willingness to accept` type choice; it involves the reference and a slower

but less expensive alternative. The third type is an equivalent gain type of choice. In this case, the

choice is between one alternative that is faster than the reference but with the same cost, and

another alternative that is cheaper than the reference but with the same driving time. Finally, the

fourth type, an equivalent loss type of choice, involves choosing between either a time or a cost

increase relative to the reference.

Our experiment has advantages and disadvantages compared to the experiments in

Bateman et al. ( 1997). Advantages are, first, that it involves the use of time. Time is fundamentally

important for everyone, and it can meaningfully be varied continuously, both up and down. Second,

unlike some of the earlier experiments (involving mugs or chocolates), the choices that we ask

subjects to make are similar to choices they face almost daily. Third, we have been able to gather a

very large database, so that our tests have considerable statistical power. Moreover, an advantage

we share with Bateman et al. (1997) is that the setup of the experiments, discussed in more detail

below, is highly likely to avoid some potential problems raised in the literature, such as large

income effects and strategic behaviour by participants. Finally, it has been argued that the size of

the gap between WTP-WTA may be related to the lack of training to deal with the choice

environment, the lack of familiarity with the choice task, lack of experience with the type of choices

to be made, etc. (see, e.g., Plott and Zeiler ( 2005), List ( 2004)). Since choices involving travel time

and cost are made on an almost daily basis, this hardly seems a problem for the setting of this paper.

Disadvantages of our experiments are, first, that we employ data on hypothetical choices.

This is necessary, since we are unable to endow subjects with time. For the same reason we cannot

ensure incentive-compatibility, and we are unable to move the reference to control for income

effects in the same way Bateman et al. (1997) do. However, on the use of hypothetical data we do

find support in Kahneman and Tversky ( 1979) who argue strongly in favour of this practice.5

Moreover, time is a private good so that our experiment is not vulnerable to the criticism raised by

Diamond and Hausman ( 1994) against contingent valuation.

5 “By default, the method of hypothetical choices emerges as the simplest procedure by which a large number of theoretical questions can be investigated. The use of the method relies on the assumption that people often know how they would behave in actual situations of choice, and on the further assumption that the subjects have no special reason to disguise their true preferences. If people are reasonably accurate in predicting their choices, the presence of common and systematic violations of expected utility theory in hypothetical problems provides presumptive evidence against that theory.” (Kahneman & Tversky 1979).

©Association for European Transport and contributors 2006

Page 5: ANOTHER TEST OF THE THEORY OF REFERENCE-DEPENDENT ...web.mit.edu/11.951/OldFiles/oldstuff/albacete/Other_Documents/Eur… · ANOTHER TEST OF THE THEORY OF REFERENCE-DEPENDENT PREFERENCES:

The contributions of this paper are easily summarized. We show the relevance of

reference-dependent preferences in modelling the trade-off between money and travel time, using

binary stated preference choice data involving the perfectly divisible goods ‘money’ and ‘time’. The

model incorporates loss aversion, diminishing sensitivity and asymmetry between time and cost as

well as between gains and losses. We first confirm the very large gap between WTP and WTA, by a

factor 4 to 6, for our data. Like Bateman et al. (1997), we find that the relations between the four

valuation measures WTP, WTA, EG and EL are in accordance with the theory of reference-

dependent preferences. Due to our large database, we are able to estimate the four measures with

very high precision, so that our test of the model has very high power against alternatives. We

consistently find support for reference-dependent preferences. Second, we find substantial evidence

of loss aversion; we also find asymmetries between time and cost as well as between gains and

losses. Third, we analyze the conditions that are required to recover the reference-free value of time

from the estimated trade-offs between money and travel time. Fourth, in the empirical

implementation, we utilise the fact that the choices in our data involve only time and cost to obtain

a more appropriate formulation than the conventional Random Utility Model (RUM). We are able

to formulate the model directly in terms of the preference-based value of time with errors that are

additive relative to the log of the time value. Finally, we show that reference-dependent preferences

also explain a substantial fraction of apparently irrational choices by participating subjects. In

particular, participants are observed to sometimes select dominated options. We show that the

fraction of such ´mistakes` systematically varies in a way consistent with the model of reference

dependence.

The structure of the paper is the following. In Section 2 we introduce the model of

reference-dependent preferences to analyze the trade offs between money and travel time. Section 3

describes the empirical application. We specify and estimate the empirical model, and we analyze

the implications for the trade offs between money and travel time, emphasizing the role of loss

aversion and asymmetries in the value functions. We further provide some supporting evidence for

reference dependent preferences based on dominated choices. Section 4 contains some concluding

remarks.

©Association for European Transport and contributors 2006

Page 6: ANOTHER TEST OF THE THEORY OF REFERENCE-DEPENDENT ...web.mit.edu/11.951/OldFiles/oldstuff/albacete/Other_Documents/Eur… · ANOTHER TEST OF THE THEORY OF REFERENCE-DEPENDENT PREFERENCES:

2 Methodology

2.1 Reference-dependent preferences

We consider reference-dependent gain-loss utility as a sum of value functions, as in

Tversky and Kahneman ( 1991). Denote a generic value function for a good by v(x), where x is the

deviation from the reference, such that v that is monotonously increasing, has v(0)=0, exhibits loss

aversion, i.e. v(x)<-v(-x), and diminishing sensitivity, xv’’(x)≤0.

We take preferences to be defined over two dimensions, travel cost (c) and travel time (t).

For any given alternative (c,t) denote deviations from a reference cost and time. We further assume

an individual specific reference-free value of travel time, denoted by w. Thus (c,wt) express the cost

and the time use on a comparable scale for each individual. An increase in both cost and time leads

to a utility loss, so we express reference-dependent gain-loss utility by

( )( ) ( ) ( )wtvcvtcu tc −+−=−− 0|, .

2.2 The choice framework

Consider binary choices between alternatives defined in terms of cost and time

differences, relative to a reference. We assume that choices are made by maximising reference-

dependent gain-loss utility. Four types of choice situations are depicted in Figure 1, where the axes

pass through the reference situation. The quadrants of Figure 1 define four different measures of the

trade off between money and time.

First, suppose the individual has to choose between the reference and an alternative which

is faster but more expensive than the reference. This is a ‘willingness to pay’ WTP-type of choice,

presented as a choice between the origin and a point in the upper left quadrant of Figure 1. A second

type of choice is of the WTA-type; it is the mirror image of the previous case, involving the

reference and a slower but less expensive alternative (see lower right quadrant). Third, there is a

choice between one alternative that is faster than the reference but with the same cost, and another

alternative that is cheaper than the reference but with the same driving time. This is an equivalent

gain (EG) type choice. Graphically, it is the choice between a point on the vertical axis and one on

the horizontal axis, see the lower left quadrant. Finally, the fourth choice situation is again the

mirror image of this (see the upper right quadrant). It is an equivalent loss (EL) type choice,

involving the choice between either a time increase or a cost increase relative to the reference.

©Association for European Transport and contributors 2006

Page 7: ANOTHER TEST OF THE THEORY OF REFERENCE-DEPENDENT ...web.mit.edu/11.951/OldFiles/oldstuff/albacete/Other_Documents/Eur… · ANOTHER TEST OF THE THEORY OF REFERENCE-DEPENDENT PREFERENCES:

time

cost

EG

EL

(WTP

WTA

Figure 1 The four quadrants

Now define cost and time in alternatives 1 and 2 by (c1,t1) and (c2,t2). We rearrange the

alternatives freely such that the first alternative is the faster and more expensive alternative, i.e.,

t1<t2 and c1>c2. We can then describe the four types of choices by time and cost differences relative

to the reference in the following way:

0,0,0:0,0,0:

0,0:0,0:

1221

2112

2211

2211

==>>==<<

<<====<<

tctcELtctcEG

tctcWTAtcctWTP

Indifference between the two alternatives occurs when:

( ) ( ) ( ) ( )2211 wtvcvwtvcv tctc −+−=−+− .

Note that the type of choice is defined by the signs of (c1,t1) and (c2,t2); recall that these

are differences relative to the reference. Now consider a certain time change with absolute value

t=t2-t1, where the sign depends on the type of choice. We can then empirically identify the

corresponding absolute value of the cost change that generates indifference between alternatives.

©Association for European Transport and contributors 2006

Page 8: ANOTHER TEST OF THE THEORY OF REFERENCE-DEPENDENT ...web.mit.edu/11.951/OldFiles/oldstuff/albacete/Other_Documents/Eur… · ANOTHER TEST OF THE THEORY OF REFERENCE-DEPENDENT PREFERENCES:

The sign of the cost change also depends on the type of choice. For each type of choice, the

indifference cost is defined implicitly as a function of t by:

( )( ) ( )( )( ) ( )( )( ) ( )

( )( ) ( ) 0000

=−=−−−=−+=+−

wtvtEGvwtvtELvwtvtWTAvwtvtWTPv

tc

tc

tc

tc

Using the properties of the value functions in these expressions it is then straightforward to derive

the following inequalities (also see Bateman et al. ( 1997)):

( ) ( ) ( )[ ] ( ) ( )[ ] ( )tWTAtELtEGtELtEGtWTP <≤< ,max,min

2.3 Constant loss aversion, linear utility

In this sub-section, we first consider the simple case where the value functions are linear,

except for a kink at the reference to generate constant loss aversion. The main purpose of this

exercise is, first, to show that assuming reference-dependent preferences imposes testable

restrictions on the relations between the different valuation measures and, second, to point at the

identification problem associated with recovering the reference-free value of time w. The specific

example we look at here has been considered by Tversky and Kahneman ( 1991, figure V). In this

case a generic value function can be defined by

( ) ( )ηα xSxex −=v (1)

where we have used the notation S(x) = x/|x| for the sign of x. Requiring that η>0 ensures that v is a

value function exhibiting loss aversion.

With the definition of v, as given in (1), it is easy to show that the four measures defined

above are give by:

( ) ( )( ) ( )

( ) ( )( ) ( ) ctcttt

ctcttt

ctcttt

ctcttt

ewtewtevtEG

ewtewtevtEL

ewtewtevtWTA

ewtewtevtWTP

c

c

c

c

ηηααηα

ηηααηα

ηηααηα

ηηααηα

+−−−−

−−+−

+−+−

−−−−−

==

=−−=

==

=−−=

1

1

1

1

(2)

©Association for European Transport and contributors 2006

Page 9: ANOTHER TEST OF THE THEORY OF REFERENCE-DEPENDENT ...web.mit.edu/11.951/OldFiles/oldstuff/albacete/Other_Documents/Eur… · ANOTHER TEST OF THE THEORY OF REFERENCE-DEPENDENT PREFERENCES:

Taking logs, equations (2) immediately imply:

( ) ( )( ) ( ) ( )( ) ( ) ctwttEGtELtWTAtWTP αα −+== loglog½log½ (3)

To see the implications of expressions (2)-(3) note that, using binary choice data on the

four types of choices, it is straightforward to estimate the four different valuation measures WTP,

WTA, EG, EL for different time changes relative to the reference. A general model can be estimated

that allows for different trade-offs in each quadrant; alternatively, a model can be estimated based

on reference dependent preferences as specified by the value functions (1). Equations (2) and (3)

then nicely illustrate two important implications of the theory of reference dependent preferences.

First, the first equality in (3) shows that reference dependence imposes testable restrictions on the

four valuation measures, providing a way to test the theory of reference-dependent gain-loss utility

against the general alternative. Second, however, expressions (2) and the second equation of (3)

also show that, under the assumptions of reference dependence, estimates of WTP, WTA, EG, EL do

not generally allow identification of the reference-free time value w. Of course, it follows from (2)

that if one is willing to assume ct αα = , we can estimate w in two equivalent ways. But without

assumptions on ct αα − , unfortunately, reference dependent preferences imply that knowledge of

the four measures WTP, WTA, EG, EL does not even provide information on the range of possible

values for the reference-free value of time w. The condition ctctct ηηααηη +≤−≤−− restricts

the time value to be bounded by the willingness to pay and the willingness to accept,

WTP(t)<wt<WTA(t). But equations (1) show, unfortunately, that it is possible to arrive at any value

for wt between WTP(t) and WTA(t). Without the constraint ctctct ηηααηη +≤−≤−− , reference

free time values can easily be greater than WTA or smaller that WTP.

To summarize, the simple example considered in this sub-section leads to two basic

messages that will also be relevant in the more general case discussed below. One is that the model

of reference-dependent preferences can be tested against the more general alternative. The other is

that without identifying restrictions recovering the reference-free time value may not be possible. In

the example presented above, the parameters ,t cη η are identified, the difference ct αα − is not.

©Association for European Transport and contributors 2006

Page 10: ANOTHER TEST OF THE THEORY OF REFERENCE-DEPENDENT ...web.mit.edu/11.951/OldFiles/oldstuff/albacete/Other_Documents/Eur… · ANOTHER TEST OF THE THEORY OF REFERENCE-DEPENDENT PREFERENCES:

2.4 General specification: introducing diminishing sensitivity

We now extend the formulation of the value functions to introduce the possibility of

diminishing sensitivity, allowing some curvature. Moreover, we will allow asymmetry between

gains and losses. We specify a generic value function as

( ) ( ) ( ) ( )xSxS xexSxv γβηα −−−= 1 (4)

A power function, as suggested here, is a common specification in empirical work. For example,

Stott ( 2006) points to the power function as the best empirical formulation for the value function.

Its interpretation is clear. Disregarding γ for a moment, the parameter η>0 ensures that the value

function exhibits loss aversion, while β≥0 measures the degree of diminishing sensitivity. The

parameter γ allows the diminishing sensitivity to be asymmetric for gains and losses. Note that

0== γβ reduces the model to the constant loss aversion - linear utility model of the previous

subsection.

Of course, to serve as a value function, the parameters β, γ and η must satisfy certain

restrictions. First, we require the value function to be monotonically increasing, i.e., v´(x)>0. This is

equivalent to β-1<γ<1-β. Second, diminishing sensitivity requires xv”(x)≤0, which boils down to

-β≤γ≤β. Third, we want the value function to exhibit loss aversion. For γ=0, the value function

exhibits loss aversion when η>0. When γ is non-zero, we have loss aversion when exp(-η/γ)<|x|, so

that loss aversion does not hold for small x.

In the remainder of this section, we use specification (4) for the value functions to analyze

binary choices over cost and time. As before, let us define cost and time in alternatives 1 and 2 by

(c1,t1) and (c2,t2), where both dimensions are measured relative to the reference. Moreover, we

arrange the two alternatives such that t1<t2 and c1>c2. With this setting, the slow alternative 2 will

be selected if it yields higher (reference-dependent) utility than alternative 1. Noting that the value

functions were specified such that x>0 corresponds to an improvement as compared to the

reference, alternative 2 will be selected when:

)(12

)(2

)(12

)(2

)(11

)(1

)(11

)(1

2222

1111

)()(

)()(tStScScS

tStScScS

ttttcccc

ttttcccc

wtetScecS

wtetScecSγβηαγβηα

γβηαγβηα

+−++−+

+−++−+

−−<

−− (5)

©Association for European Transport and contributors 2006

Page 11: ANOTHER TEST OF THE THEORY OF REFERENCE-DEPENDENT ...web.mit.edu/11.951/OldFiles/oldstuff/albacete/Other_Documents/Eur… · ANOTHER TEST OF THE THEORY OF REFERENCE-DEPENDENT PREFERENCES:

In the choice situations considered, one cost variable and one time variable is always

zero. Therefore, we can simplify the inequality in (5) by substituting with 2121 , tttccc +=+= and

further reduce the terms that are zero in each of the four types of choices. For example, for a WTP-

type choice, the slow alternative will be chosen when:

0)()( )(1)()(1)( <− +−++−+ tStScScS ttttcccc wtetScecS γβηαγβηα−

Similarly, for a WTA-type of choice, the slow alternative will be chosen when:

)(1)()(1)( )()(0 tStScScS ttttcccc wtetScecS γβηαγβηα +−++−+ −−<

Finally, under EG and EL type of choices the slow alternative will be chosen when, respectively:

)(1)()(1)( )()( cScStStS cccctttt cecSwtetS γβηαγβηα +−++−+ −<−

and

)(1)()(1)( )()( tStScScS ttttcccc wtetScecS γβηαγβηα +−++−+ −<−

Using our definitions of time and cost changes, note that in all four cases the slow

alternative is selected if:

)(1)(

)(1)()(1

tStS

cScStS

tttt

cccc

tt

te

cew γβηα

γβηαγβ

+−+

+−++− < (6)

Taking logs, this amounts to the condition:

[ ] [ ] [ ] ttSccStScSwtS ttcctctctt ln)(1ln)(1)()(ln)(1 γβγβηηααγβ +−−+−+−+−<+− (7)

As in the linear case of sub-section 2.3, the parameter difference cα - tα is not identified.

Knowledge of the functions WTP(t), WTA(t), EL(t) and EG(t) is sufficient to identify the remaining

©Association for European Transport and contributors 2006

Page 12: ANOTHER TEST OF THE THEORY OF REFERENCE-DEPENDENT ...web.mit.edu/11.951/OldFiles/oldstuff/albacete/Other_Documents/Eur… · ANOTHER TEST OF THE THEORY OF REFERENCE-DEPENDENT PREFERENCES:

parameters.6 There is, however, an important difference between the linear and the general case. To

see this, assume that βt and βc are different, and that γt and γc are different from zero. Now consider

a change of the monetary unit. This will change ln|c| and ln w by the same constant. However, in

the inequality (7), ln w is multiplied by [1-βt+γtS(t)], which will be different from the parameter [1-

βc+γcS(c))] multiplying ln|c|. A change in the monetary unit will then be absorbed into tc αα − , ηc

and ηt. A change in the time unit will not have a similar effect on parameters, since ln w and ln|t|

are multiplied by the same parameter. The fact that the parameters depend on the choice of

monetary unit is unavoidable, when we apply different nonlinear value functions to cost and time.

Fortunately, however, the interesting economic implications are determined by the relative values of

the parameters (e.g., cη versus tη ), and not so much by their individual values.

2.5 Econometric model specification

In this subsection we formulate the econometric model, which is a descendant of the

model in Cameron and James ( 1987). We use a log-linear formulation for the individual specific

reference-free value of time whereby

0ln w z uδ δ σ= + +

is inserted into inequality (7). To ease on notation, we do not include subscripts to denote that ln w

is individual specific. In the expression for ln w, δ0 is a constant, δz captures the effect of observed

heterogeneity while σu captures unobserved heterogeneity through a standard normal random

variable u and standard deviation σ. We also introduce random error terms µεi, where µ is the scale

of the errors and the εi are iid. standard logistic error terms for a sequence of choices i by the same

individual.7 Since the scale of the model is not identified, we conveniently normalise the coefficient

6 The slope parameters β and γ are identified from the derivatives of the four valuation measures with respect to t. Then the η’s are identified using inequality (7). 7 The formulation in WTP space rather than in indirect utility space is supported by Fosgerau ( 2005) for very similar data. The use of the normal distribution for u is supported by Fosgerau ( 2006), at least when the mean of w is not the object of interest. We shall find below that the parameters of interest are not much affected by the representation of heterogeneity, so that we did not try to relax the distributional assumptions. (For more on relaxed distributional assumptions, see Fosgerau & Bierlaire 2005;Fosgerau & Nielsen 2005;Honoré & Lewbel 2002).

©Association for European Transport and contributors 2006

Page 13: ANOTHER TEST OF THE THEORY OF REFERENCE-DEPENDENT ...web.mit.edu/11.951/OldFiles/oldstuff/albacete/Other_Documents/Eur… · ANOTHER TEST OF THE THEORY OF REFERENCE-DEPENDENT PREFERENCES:

of ln|c| to 1. The model to be estimated is then easily described. The dependent variable indicates

whether the slow alternative is chosen in choice situation i. That is, whether

[ ][ ]

[ ] [ ] iiittiiccticitc

itt

ttSccStScS

uztS

µεγβγβηηαα

σδδγβ

++−−+−+−+−

<+++−

ln)(1ln)(1)()(

)(1 0

We normalise this expression by dividing through with 1-βt. Factoring out, the model to be

estimated can be written:

p0 + p1z + p2u + p3S(ti) + p4S(ti)z + p2p5S(ti)u + ln|ti| + p5S(ti)ln|ti|

<

p6S(ci) + p7ln|ci| + p8S(ci)ln|ci| + p9εi

Under the assumptions of our model of reference dependent preferences, the parameters estimated

in this expression are defined as follows:

tt

c

t

c

t

c

t

t

t

t

t

tt

t

ct

pppp

ppp

ppp

βµ

βγ

ββ

βη

βγ

βδγ

βηδγ

σδβαα

δ

−=

−=

−−

=−

=

−=

−=

−+

=

==−−

+=

1,

1,

11

,1

,1

,1

,1

,,1

9876

540

3

2100

In line with our earlier remarks, it is clear from these expressions that not all the parameters of the

value functions and the reference-free value of time are identified. However, many of the relevant

economic effects can be identified from these estimates, see below.

3 Empirical application

3.1 Data

We employ data from a large-scale survey of car drivers (Fosgerau, Hjort, & Vincent

Lyk-Jensen 2006). Interviews were conducted over the internet or face-to-face in a computer

©Association for European Transport and contributors 2006

Page 14: ANOTHER TEST OF THE THEORY OF REFERENCE-DEPENDENT ...web.mit.edu/11.951/OldFiles/oldstuff/albacete/Other_Documents/Eur… · ANOTHER TEST OF THE THEORY OF REFERENCE-DEPENDENT PREFERENCES:

assisted personal interview. All subjects in the experiment had to choose between two alternatives,

described by travel time and travel cost. This is similar to choices that car drivers make routinely

every day. So, in the transport literature, the validity of such data is generally thought to be high,

even though choices are hypothetical, and subjects do not receive actual mugs or chocolate.

Moreover, having travel time as an attribute in the experiment is particularly useful since travel time

meaningfully can be varied continuously both up and down.

All choices were designed relative to a recent actual trip subjects had made. We use

observations with trip durations greater than 10 minutes, since for shorter durations it is hard to

generate meaningful faster alternatives. We interpret the recent trip as the reference situation and

generate choice situations by varying travel time and cost around the reference. Four types of choice

situations were presented, as described in section 2.2. The reference travel time and cost appears in

all choice situations such that the subjects are continuously reminded about the reference situation.

Each subject was presented with eight non-dominated choice situations. Our data contain 16566

observations of such choices from 2132 individuals. Subjects were furthermore presented with a

dominated choice situation, where one alternative was both faster and cheaper than the other. The

quadrant for this choice situation was also random. The data contain 2062 such observations from

2057 individuals. These data on dominated choices are analysed in section 3.3 below.

The eight choice situations were generated in the following way. First, eight choices were

assigned to quadrants at random: two to each quadrant in random sequence. Second, two absolute

travel time differences were drawn from a set, depending on the reference travel time, in such a way

that respondents with short reference trips were only offered small time differences. Thus there is

no asymmetry in the size of the time differences up and down. Both travel time differences were

applied to the two situations assigned to each of the four quadrants. Third, eight trade-off values of

time were drawn at random from the interval [2-200] Danish Crowns (DKK) per hour, using

stratification to ensure that all subjects were presented with both low and high values. The absolute

cost difference was then found for each choice situation by multiplying the absolute time difference

by the trade-off value of time. Fourth, the sign of the cost and time differences relative to the

reference were determined from the quadrant. The differences were added to the reference to get the

numbers that were presented to respondents on screen. Travel costs were rounded to the nearest 0.5

DKK.8

8 In some cases, rounding caused the cost difference to be zero. These observations are omitted from the analysis.

©Association for European Transport and contributors 2006

Page 15: ANOTHER TEST OF THE THEORY OF REFERENCE-DEPENDENT ...web.mit.edu/11.951/OldFiles/oldstuff/albacete/Other_Documents/Eur… · ANOTHER TEST OF THE THEORY OF REFERENCE-DEPENDENT PREFERENCES:

Finally, it should be noticed that alternatives differ only with respect to time and cost, so

that issues such as heterogeneous preferences for various transport modes play no role. Some

summary information regarding the data set is given in Tables 1 and 2. Table 1 shows some

descriptive statistics regarding trip characteristics and the time and cost differences presented in the

experiment. Note that the mean fraction of the commuting time that is due to congestion alone is

fairly small (9%). Table 2 shows statistics regarding the socio-economic characteristics used in the

models to control for observed heterogeneity. In the interview, subjects stated their personal gross

annual income, grouped into intervals of 100,000 DKK up to 1 million DKK. We have computed

net annual income by applying national tax rates to interval midpoints. The progressive Danish tax

system implies a difference in income elasticities with respect to gross and net income of 26 %. We

note that our subjects tend to be richer and older than the national average.

Table 1. Summary statistics, trip characteristics

Variable Mean Min MaxCost difference, DKK9 8.79 0.5 200 Time difference, minutes 9.27 3 60 Reference cost, DKK 58.4 1 850 Reference time, minutes 49.2 11 240 Share of time due to congestion 0.09 0 0.7

9 1 Euro ≈ 7.5 DKK.

©Association for European Transport and contributors 2006

Page 16: ANOTHER TEST OF THE THEORY OF REFERENCE-DEPENDENT ...web.mit.edu/11.951/OldFiles/oldstuff/albacete/Other_Documents/Eur… · ANOTHER TEST OF THE THEORY OF REFERENCE-DEPENDENT PREFERENCES:

Table 2 Summary statistics, socio-economic characteristics

Variable Mean Min Max Net annual income, DKK 178617 42882 469959Lowest income group, dummy 0.07 0 1 Missing income info, dummy 0.07 0 1 Female, dummy 0.41 0 1 Age 50.4 16 89 Greater Copenhagen area dummy 0.19 0 1 Employer pays, dummy 0.06 0 1 Student, dummy 0.05 0 1 Internet interview, dummy 0.66 0 1 Family type: couple w/ children, dummy 0.33 0 1 Family type: single w/ children, dummy 0.04 0 1 Family type: single no children, dummy 0.15 0 1 Family type: other, dummy 0.01 0 1

3.2 Estimation results

We estimate a series of models, gradually allowing for more general value functions (loss

aversion, diminishing sensitivity, asymmetries). Each of the models occurs in two versions, an

unrestricted version (denoted M1, M2, etc.) and a restricted version (denoted M1R, M2R, etc). The

former unrestricted models allow for a different constant term for each quadrant. The restricted

models impose the constraints on the η’s implied by the theoretical model of reference dependent

preferences. The restricted models are nested within the corresponding unrestricted models, so that

a standard likelihood ratio test can be used to test the restriction. To describe the models in more

detail, consider Table 3 below. It sketches the overall plan of the estimation strategy. It includes the

different models estimated, indicating for each model the parameters to be estimated in the

restricted version of the corresponding model. The unrestricted models are not included in the table

to save space. As previously indicated, the unrestricted models have, for all models considered,

separate constants per quadrant.

An overview is easily given. Model M0 contains just a common constant for all

quadrants; it is just presented for purposes of comparison. Then a series of models is estimated in

which the restricted versions impose constant loss aversion. Model M1 estimates four separate

©Association for European Transport and contributors 2006

Page 17: ANOTHER TEST OF THE THEORY OF REFERENCE-DEPENDENT ...web.mit.edu/11.951/OldFiles/oldstuff/albacete/Other_Documents/Eur… · ANOTHER TEST OF THE THEORY OF REFERENCE-DEPENDENT PREFERENCES:

constants, one for each quadrant, while M1R has a general constant in addition to the loss aversion

parameters ηc and ηt. To be precise, model M1R assumes the slow alternative is chosen if

ln ( ) ( ) ln lnc t i c i t i iw S c S t c t iα α η η< − + − + − + µε

where neither observed nor unobserved heterogeneity is allowed for. This implies 0ln w δ= , so that

the estimated parameters are given by 0 , , ,t c c tδ α α η η µ+ − .

Models M2 and M2R introduce random unobserved heterogeneity. Next, several models

add observed heterogeneity. Whereas M3a and M3Ra only include income variables to control for

observed heterogeneity, models M3b and M3Rb have a much larger set of controls (see the

descriptive statistics in Tables 1 and 2). For reasons discussed below, models M4 and M4R again

drop the controls but, importantly, they introduce diminishing sensitivity through the β parameters.

Finally, M5 and M5R allow for asymmetry in curvature via the γ’s.

Table 3: Model plan

Variable Parameter M0R M1R M2R M3R M4R M5R 1

t

ctpβααδ

−−

+=100

ct ααδ

−+0

ct ααδ

−+0

ct ααδ

−+0

ct ααδ

−+0

t

ct

βαα

δ

−−

+1

0

t

ct

βαα

δ

−−

1

0

+

z δ=1p δ u σ=2p σ σ σ σ S(t)

t

ttpβηδγ

−+

=1

03

tη tη tη

t

t

βη−1

t

tt

βηδγ

−+

10

S(t)z

t

tpβδγ

−=

14

p2S(t)u

+ S(t)ln|t| t

tpβ

γ−

=15

t

t

βγ−1

ln|t| 1 1 1 1 1 1 < S(c)

t

cpβ

η−

=16

cη cη cη

t

c

βη−1

t

c

βη−1

ln|c|

t

cpββ

−−

=11

7

t

c

ββ

−−

11

t

c

ββ

−−

11

S(c)ln|c|

t

cpβ

γ−

=18

t

c

βγ−1

ε t

pβµ−

=19

µ µ µ

tβµ−1

µ−1

©Association for European Transport and contributors 2006

Page 18: ANOTHER TEST OF THE THEORY OF REFERENCE-DEPENDENT ...web.mit.edu/11.951/OldFiles/oldstuff/albacete/Other_Documents/Eur… · ANOTHER TEST OF THE THEORY OF REFERENCE-DEPENDENT PREFERENCES:

All models are estimated in Biogeme (Bierlaire 2003;Bierlaire 2005). The estimation

results are presented in Table 4. In what follows we report the most noteworthy findings. First, note

that the estimated unrestricted constants per quadrant (see model M1) are very significant and very

different from one another; more importantly, they imply the relative sizes for the WTP, WTA, EG

and EL that would be predicted by the theory of reference-dependence (Bateman et al. (1997); also

see Section 2 above). More in particular, we derive the following values for the four measures from

the estimated model: WTP=8.9, WTA=38.2, EG=14.6, EL=24.9, implying WTP<EG<EL<WTA.

Moreover, the difference between willingness to pay and willingness to accept is large, and highly

unlikely to be due to the experimental setup or the presence of income effects; it amounts to a factor

of more than four. Also note that the extension of M1 over M0, which just contains a common

constant, results in a very large improvement to the likelihood.

Model M1R imposes the restriction on the constants implied by the theory, as indicated in

Table 3. The constant p0 and the two parameters p3 and p6, relating respectively to time and cost

gains/losses, correspond to the case of constant loss aversion with linear utility. Note that the

parameters p3 and p6 yield estimates of tη and cη , respectively. Both are positive, as expected, in

this and all following models. Since t cη η> , we find evidence that drivers are more loss averse in

the time dimension than in the cost dimension. Importantly, the likelihood indicates that the

restriction implied by M1R, relative to M1, is easily accepted. This is not a light test, considering

that the constants by quadrant in M1 were highly significant and very different. These results

strongly indicate the presence of loss aversion.

The models M2 and M2R extend M1 and M1R by allowing for unobserved heterogeneity.

The parameter p2 measures the standard deviation of a mean zero normal distribution which is

added to the constants. Thus ln w is normal with mean given by the constants. The extension with

unobserved heterogeneity results in a very large improvement of the likelihood. The restriction from

M2 to M2R is again easily accepted.

The next models introduce observed heterogeneity. First, models M3a and M3Ra just

incorporate income variables: log income is included together with dummies for low income and

missing income information. As could be expected, accounting for this type of heterogeneity

reduces the estimated standard deviation of the unobserved heterogeneity captured in p2. The

income variables are generally very significant. Note that the parameter z_inc = 1.37 can be

©Association for European Transport and contributors 2006

Page 19: ANOTHER TEST OF THE THEORY OF REFERENCE-DEPENDENT ...web.mit.edu/11.951/OldFiles/oldstuff/albacete/Other_Documents/Eur… · ANOTHER TEST OF THE THEORY OF REFERENCE-DEPENDENT PREFERENCES:

interpreted as the estimated income elasticity of the reference-free value of time. The restricted

model R is again easily accepted against the unrestricted alternative. Next, models M3b and M3Rb

extend on the previous ones by including a more elaborate list of controls for observed

heterogeneity. The parameter estimates for these are not shown, but are available on request. The

estimated income elasticity is now lower, because some of the added independent variables

correlate with income. The restriction R implied by the theory is again easily accepted. We

moreover note that the inclusion of lots of observed heterogeneity reduces the estimated standard

deviation of the unobserved heterogeneity even more.

We observe that the parameters p3 and p6 , and also the four constants for the quadrants,

are hardly affected by the inclusion of both observed and unobserved heterogeneity. This could be

expected, since individual heterogeneity has the same effect in all types of choice situations. Given

this observation, and since observed heterogeneity is not our main concern in this paper, we drop

the variables for observed heterogeneity from the remainder of the models below.

Models M4 and M4R introduce possible diminishing sensitivity. The parameter

711

c

t

p ββ

−=

− implicitly measures the ratio of diminishing sensitivities in the cost and time

dimensions. The resulting improvement in likelihood relative to models M2 and M2R is large,

given that just one extra parameter has been allowed for. Importantly, p7 is greater than zero, as

implied by the theory. Moreover, it is less than 1, which in turn implies that βc>βt. The economic

meaning is that the value function for cost bends more than the value function for time. This is

equivalent to all the valuation measures increasing with the size of the time difference, a common

empirical finding (see, e.g., Bates & Whelan 2001;Cantillo, Heydecker, & de Dios Ortuzar

2006;Hultkrantz & Mortazavi 2001). Again, the restriction from M4 to M4R is easily accepted.

Finally, note that the standard deviation of the unobserved heterogeneity term now has decreased a

lot, even though the variables for observed heterogeneity have been omitted. This shows that the

random coefficient also captured some of the nonlinearity, which is now captured by p7. The loss

aversion parameters p3 and p6 are also affected (but see section 2).

The last set of models, M5 and M5R, introduce the parameters p5 and p8 to capture

asymmetries in the curvature of the value functions. These parameters are significantly different

from zero and positive, as expected. We find that 5 8p p< , which implies that t cγ γ< . Introduction

of the asymmetry parameters causes the loss aversion parameters to decrease. Moreover, we find

that p8<p7 , implying that γc<1-βc , and p5<1 , implying that γt<1-βt. As we have seen in section

©Association for European Transport and contributors 2006

Page 20: ANOTHER TEST OF THE THEORY OF REFERENCE-DEPENDENT ...web.mit.edu/11.951/OldFiles/oldstuff/albacete/Other_Documents/Eur… · ANOTHER TEST OF THE THEORY OF REFERENCE-DEPENDENT PREFERENCES:

2.4, this is required for the value functions to be monotonous; our estimates thus confirm this

requirement.

In summary, the previous results are systematically consistent with reference-dependence

of the form predicted by the model. The parameter p7 is less than one, indicating that βc and βt are

different (and at least one of them is not zero). Finally, the estimates regarding tγ and γc conform to

the theoretical requirements.

To conclude this subsection, we have performed a small series of split sample

experiments, in which we have split the sample according to sex, income above/below the median

and age above/below the median. Model M5R has then been estimated for each sub-sample. We do

not show these results but briefly report on the main findings. In all cases, the distribution of the

value of time differs significantly. For sex, there is no significant difference in the parameters

representing the value functions. For income, the high income group appears to be more time loss

averse. The largest differences are found when the sample is split according to age, where the older

group is significantly more loss averse for both time and cost. This finding agrees with Johnson,

Gächter and Herrman ( 2006).

3.3 Dominated choice situations

As stated above, each subject was presented with a dominated choice situation in which

one alternative was both cheaper and faster than the other. Under standard Hicksian reference-free

preferences, selecting the dominated alternative is clearly irrational, and we would expect the share

of “mistakes”, i.e. choice of the dominated alternative, to be largest for small differences of c and t.

Moreover, we would not expect the share of mistakes to differ across the four types of choices.

Under reference-dependence, we would similarly expect more mistakes for small differences of c

and t, but we would expect to find differences across quadrants. Observations of such mistakes are

rarely analysed, so this is a useful outside check on the theory of reference-dependence.

The dominated choice situations are labelled as shown in Figure 2. Under the standard

preference model, all subjects would be expected to choose the fast and cheap alternative (to the

South-West in the figure). The only way the dominated alternative can be chosen is by mistake.

©Association for European Transport and contributors 2006

Page 21: ANOTHER TEST OF THE THEORY OF REFERENCE-DEPENDENT ...web.mit.edu/11.951/OldFiles/oldstuff/albacete/Other_Documents/Eur… · ANOTHER TEST OF THE THEORY OF REFERENCE-DEPENDENT PREFERENCES:

time

cost

EG

EL

(WTP

WTA

Figure 2: Labelling of dominated choice situations

As it turns out, 11.5% of subjects choose the “wrong” dominated alternative. Table 5

summarises the data for the dominated choice situations. A striking finding is that there are indeed

large differences by quadrant. Independence is rejected in this table with overwhelming

significance. Under reference-dependence, we would expect most mistakes in the EG-quadrant as

the dominated alternative is equal to the reference in both the cost and the time dimension.

Similarly, we would expect least mistakes in the EL- quadrant, since the dominating alternative is

then equal to the reference. Both relationships are clearly evident from the table. For the WTP and

WTA-quadrants we expect the number of “wrong” choices to be in between, as both alternatives in

these choice situations match the reference on one dimension. If the loss aversion parameter for

time is greater than that for cost (ηt>ηc), as found above (at least in the linear models where this

inference can be made), we would expect to find more mistakes in the WTP-quadrant than in the

WTA-quadrant. These expectations are also matched by the data. So at a first glance, the predictions

of reference-dependence are closely supported by the data, also for the dominated choice situations.

Table 5. Dominated choice situations

NO. CHOOSING ALTERNATIVE EL EG WTA WTP TOTAL Dominant 444 365 547 469 1825 Dominated 20 75 51 91 237

Share of mistakes 4.3% 17.0% 8.5% 16.3% 11.5% Reference-dependence -ηt-ηc +ηt+ηc -ηt+ηc +ηt-ηc

©Association for European Transport and contributors 2006

Page 22: ANOTHER TEST OF THE THEORY OF REFERENCE-DEPENDENT ...web.mit.edu/11.951/OldFiles/oldstuff/albacete/Other_Documents/Eur… · ANOTHER TEST OF THE THEORY OF REFERENCE-DEPENDENT PREFERENCES:

In order to substantiate this conclusion, we estimated a series of binary logit models. We

let the dependent variable be 1 if the dominated alternative is chosen and 0 otherwise. The

estimation results are summarised in Table 6. The first model, denoted as D0, is specified just with

a constant, such that the share of mistakes is predicted to be constant over quadrants. Model D1

specifies constants by quadrant to allow the share of mistakes to differ by quadrant. The estimation

results show that this improves the estimated log likelihood; the differences between quadrants are

indeed strongly significant. Model D1R imposes the same restriction on the constants as in section

3.2. The loss aversion terms are positive as expected and time loss aversion is larger than cost loss

aversion; this was also found for the non-dominated choice situations. The decrease in log-

likelihood from model D1 to model D1R of 2.3 is small and indicates (almost) acceptance of the

restriction at the standard 5% level.

Models D2 and D2R are similar to models D1 and D1R, but now the differences in cost

and time between alternatives are used as controls. These variables are jointly significant and

negative, indicating that the share of mistakes decreases as the cost and time differences become

larger. The restriction from model D2 to D2R is again just significant at the 5% level, indicating

that the pattern across quadrants is largely as expected under reference-dependence. The loss

aversion terms are unaffected. In conclusion we find that the pattern of mistakes across the four

quadrants matches the predictions from the reference-dependence model quite closely.

©Association for European Transport and contributors 2006

Page 23: ANOTHER TEST OF THE THEORY OF REFERENCE-DEPENDENT ...web.mit.edu/11.951/OldFiles/oldstuff/albacete/Other_Documents/Eur… · ANOTHER TEST OF THE THEORY OF REFERENCE-DEPENDENT PREFERENCES:

Table 6. Model summary - dominated choices

Model D0 D1 D1R D2 D2R Log likelihood -735.5 -706.2 -708.5 -702.5 -704.6 Constant -2.041

(-29.6) -2.132 (-28.4)

-1.976 (-18.9)

Constant EG

-2.373 (-16.2)

-2.239 (-13.8)

Constant EL

-1.640 (-14.3)

-1.475 (-10.8)

Constant WTA

-1.582 (-12.5)

-1.416 (-9.5)

Constant WTP

-3.100 (-13.6)

-2.951 (-12.3)

Loss aversion cost, ηc

0.129 (1.8)

0.127 (1.8)

Loss aversion time bias, ηt

0.528 (7.0)

0.540 (7.1)

Cost difference

-0.014 (-1.6)

-0.014 (-1.6)

Time difference

-0.004 (-0.4)

-0.005 (-0.4)

Dof 1 4 3 6 5 LR-test 0.000 0.032 0.025 0.040 vs. D0 D1 D1 D2

4 Concluding remarks

In this paper, we have tested a model of reference-dependent preferences to explain

individuals´ valuation of travel time. Using data from a large scale binary choice experiment, where

each choice implied a simple trade-off between travel time and travel cost, we estimate four types

of valuation measures: willingness to pay, willingness to accept, equivalent gain and equivalent

loss. We confirm the findings of Bateman et al. ( 1997) on the relationship between these four

measures. They are not only very different but they conform to the relationship predicted by the

model of reference dependent preferences. Empirically, the implications of the theory are

consistently accepted against more general alternatives in tests of considerable statistical power.

Reference-dependence is furthermore able to explain the pattern of mistakes across different types

of choices.

©Association for European Transport and contributors 2006

Page 24: ANOTHER TEST OF THE THEORY OF REFERENCE-DEPENDENT ...web.mit.edu/11.951/OldFiles/oldstuff/albacete/Other_Documents/Eur… · ANOTHER TEST OF THE THEORY OF REFERENCE-DEPENDENT PREFERENCES:

The analysis of this paper also raises a number of issues that deserve further research. For

example, it appears that under reference-dependent preferences the reference-free value of time is

not generally identified, unless some strong assumptions on the preference parameters (e.g., if all

value functions are the same) are imposed. This is a worrying finding. In a nutshell, we find

empirical support for a theory that assumes a reference-free value of time but does not allow us to

identify it in general. A way out of this dilemma may be to note that we have assumed that the

reference-free value of time is constant for each individual. Relaxing this assumption can yield the

degrees of freedom necessary to be able, empirically, to accept an assumption that the value

functions are identical across dimensions such that the reference-free value of time may be

identifiable after all. This is a subject for further research. Finally, under our experimental design it

is not possible to identify the degrees of diminishing sensitivity for time and cost separately.

Expanding the experimental design to include choice situations off the reference allows

identification of the degrees of diminishing sensitivity. This will be a very relevant exercise, since

at the moment we are unable to determine whether the assumption of diminishing sensitivity holds

empirically.

©Association for European Transport and contributors 2006

Page 25: ANOTHER TEST OF THE THEORY OF REFERENCE-DEPENDENT ...web.mit.edu/11.951/OldFiles/oldstuff/albacete/Other_Documents/Eur… · ANOTHER TEST OF THE THEORY OF REFERENCE-DEPENDENT PREFERENCES:

Table 4 Estimation results Model M0 M1 M1R M2 M2R M3a M3Ra M3b M3Rb M4 M4R M5 M5RLoglike -10555.3 -10302.4 -10302.7 -9097.5 -9098.0 -8998.0 -8998.5 -8840.1 -8840.6 -9014.2 -9014.7 -9001.9 -9002.4p0 -1.16 -1.16 0.00 -1.17 0.00 -2.54 0.00 -3.71 0.00 -1.35 -1.34 T -39.2 -39.9 -26.5 -18.7 -6.5 -46.0 -45.9p2 1.66 1.66 1.56 1.56 1.40 1.40 1.01 1.01 1.00 1.00T 31.2 31.2 30.8 30.8 29.9 29.9 25.1 25.1 25.2 25.2p3 0.50 0.50 0.50 0.50 0.31 0.24T 18.2 21.6 21.6 21.6 19.4 7.0p5 0.03 0.035T 2.37 2.4p6 0.23 0.24 0.24 0.24 0.15 0.09T 9.2 11.1 11.1 11.2 10.7 4.7p7 0.70 0.70 0.70 0.70T 45.5 45.5 45.6 45.6p8 0.04 0.044T 4.37 4.3p_eg -1.41 -1.41 -2.79 -3.95 -1.50 -1.48 T -26.4 -24.3 -19.6 -6.9 -41.1 -30.39p_el -0.88 -0.88 -2.26 -3.42 -1.17 -1.18 T -18.2 -16.1 -16.3 -6.0 -31.4 -23.55p_wta -0.45 -0.45 -1.82 -2.99 -0.90 -1.03 T -9.6 -8.3 -13.5 -5.2 -22.5 -20.46p_wtp -1.91 -1.93 -3.30 -4.47 -1.82 -1.68T -30.6 -30.0 -22.4 -7.8 -46.4 -32.50z_inc 1.37 1.37 0.59 0.59 T 11.9 11.9 4.9 4.9z_lowinc 0.84 0.84 0.36 0.36T 3.7 3.7 1.7 1.7z_missinc 1.03 1.03 0.65 0.65T 5.12 5.12 3.5 3.5p9 0.67 0.69 0.69 0.98 0.98 0.98 0.98 0.98 0.98 1.58 1.58 1.58 1.58t wrt. 1 17 15.5 15.5 0.8 0.9 0.9 0.9 0.9 0.8 10.6 10.6 10.7 10.7

©Association for European Transport and contributors 2006

Page 26: ANOTHER TEST OF THE THEORY OF REFERENCE-DEPENDENT ...web.mit.edu/11.951/OldFiles/oldstuff/albacete/Other_Documents/Eur… · ANOTHER TEST OF THE THEORY OF REFERENCE-DEPENDENT PREFERENCES:

References

Andreoni, J. 1995, "Warm-glow versus cold-prickle: The effects of positive and negative framing on cooperation in experiments", Quarterly Journal of Economics, vol. 110, pp. 1-21.

Bateman, I., Munro, A., Rhodes, B., Starmer, C., & Sugden, R. 1997, "A Test of the Theory of Reference-Dependent Preferences", The Quarterly Journal of Economics, vol. 112, no. 2, pp. 479-505.

Bates, J. & Whelan, G. 2001, "Size and sign of Time Savings", ITS Working Paper no. 561.

Bierlaire, M. 2003, BIOGEME: a free package for the estimation of discrete choice models, Proceedings of the 3rd Swiss Transport Research Conference, Monte Verità, Ascona, Switzerland.

Bierlaire, M. 2005, "An introduction to Biogeme", www.epfl.ch/biogeme.

Cameron, T. A. & James, M. D. 1987, "Efficient Estimation Methods for "Closed-Ended" Contingent Valuation Surveys", Review of Economics and Statistics, vol. 69, no. 2, pp. 269-276.

Cantillo, V., Heydecker, B., & de Dios Ortuzar, J. 2006, "A discrete choice model incorporating thresholds for perception in attribute values", Transportation Research Part B: Methodological, vol. 40, no. 9, pp. 807-825.

Cummings, R. G., Brookshire, D., & Schulze, W. D. 1986, Valuing environmental goods Rowman and Allanheld, Totowa, NJ.

Diamond, P. A. & Hausman, J. A. 1994, "Contingent Valuation: Is Some Number Better than No Number?", Journal of Economic Perspectives, vol. 8, no. 4, pp. 45-64.

Fosgerau, M. 2005, "Specification of a model to measure the value of travel time savings", European Transport Conference.

Fosgerau, M. 2006, "Investigating the distribution of the value of travel time savings", Transportation Research Part B: Methodological, vol. 40, no. 8, pp. 688-707.

Fosgerau, M. & Bierlaire, M. 2005, "A practical test for the choice of mixing distribution in discrete choice models", IATBR Conference 2006.

Fosgerau, M., Hjort, K., & Vincent Lyk-Jensen, S. 2006, The Danish Value of Time Study - Results for Experiment 1 www.dtf.dk.

Fosgerau, M. & Nielsen, S. F. 2005, "Deconvoluting preferences and errors: a semi-nonparametric model for binomial data", Econometric Society European Meeting 2006.

Honoré, B. E. & Lewbel, A. 2002, "Semiparametric binary choice panel data models without strictly exogenous regressors", Econometrica, vol. 70, no. 5, pp. 2053-2063.

©Association for European Transport and contributors 2006

Page 27: ANOTHER TEST OF THE THEORY OF REFERENCE-DEPENDENT ...web.mit.edu/11.951/OldFiles/oldstuff/albacete/Other_Documents/Eur… · ANOTHER TEST OF THE THEORY OF REFERENCE-DEPENDENT PREFERENCES:

©Association for European Transport and contributors 2006

Horowitz, J. K. & McConnell, K. E. 2003, "Willingness to accept, willingness to pay and the income effect", Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization, vol. 51, no. 4, pp. 537-545.

Hultkrantz, L. & Mortazavi, R. 2001, "Anomalies in the Value of Travel-Time Changes", Journal of Transport Economics and Policy, vol. 35, no. 2, pp. 285-300.

Johnson, E. J., Gächter, S., & Herrman, A. 2006, "Exploring the Nature of Loss Aversion", IZA DP, vol. 2015.

Kahneman, D., Knetsch, J. L., & Thaler, R. 1990, "Experimental Tests of the Endowment Effect and the Coase Theorem", Journal of Political Economy, vol. 98, no. 6, pp. 1325-1348.

Kahneman, D. & Tversky, A. 1979, "Prospect Theory: An Analysis of Decision under Risk", Econometrica, vol. 47, no. 2, pp. 263-292.

Köszegi, B. & Rabin, M. 2006, "A model of reference-dependent preferences", The Quarterly Journal of Economics, vol. Forthcoming.

List, J. A. 2004, "Neoclassical Theory Versus Prospect Theory: Evidence from the Marketplace", Econometrica, vol. 72, no. 2, pp. 615-625.

Plott, C. R. & Zeiler, K. 2005, "The Willingness to Pay–Willingness to Accept Gap, the "Endowment Effect," Subject Misconceptions, and Experimental Procedures for Eliciting Valuations", The American Economic Review, vol. 95, no. 3, pp. 530-545.

Randall, A. & Stoll, J. R. 1980, "Consumer's Surplus in Commodity Space", American Economic Review, vol. 70, no. 3, pp. 449-455.

Samuelson, W. & Zeckhauser, R. 1988, "Status quo bias in decision making", Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, vol. 1, pp. 7-59.

Shlomo Benartzi & Richard H.Thaler 1995, "Myopic Loss Aversion and the Equity Premium Puzzle", Quarterly Journal of Economics, vol. 110, no. 1, pp. 73-92.

Stott, H. P. 2006, "Cumulative prospect theory's functional menagerie", Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, vol. 32, no. 2, pp. 101-130.

Tversky, A. & Kahneman, D. 1991, "Loss Aversion in Riskless Choice: A Reference-Dependent Model", The Quarterly Journal of Economics, vol. 106, no. 4, pp. 1039-1061.