varieties of particularism

12
SOME VARIETIES OF PARTICULARISM* WALTER SINNOTT-ARMSTRONG ABSTRACT: Analytic particularism claims that judgments of moral wrongness are about particular acts rather than general principles. Metaphysical particularism claims that what makes true moral judgments true is not general principles but nonmoral properties of particular acts. Epistemological particularism claims that studying particular acts apart from general principles can justify beliefs in moral judgments. Methodological particularism claims that we will do better morally in everyday life if we look carefully at each particular decision as it arises and give up the search for a complete moral theory. This paper raises problems for each of these versions of particularism. Key words: ethics, moral philosophy, particularism, logical form, epistemology, metaphysics, moral methodology. Particularism is popular. It has been espoused recently by Jonathan Dancy (1993), John McDowell (1998), David McNaughton (1988), and many feminists, including Margaret Walker (1989). There are also honor- able ancestors from Sartre (1956) all the way back to Aristotle. 1 Still, recent particularists have developed the view more thoroughly than ever before. When a label applies to so many philosophers, it should not be surpris- ing to find that it covers many very different views. So the first step must be to define precisely what particularism claims. Scope The kind of particularism that interests me here is a theory about judg- ments, which include linguistic assertions as well as mental beliefs and thoughts. More specifically, particularism is about moral judgments rather than about aesthetic or prudential judgments. Even more specifically, it is © Metaphilosophy LLC and Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 1999. Published by Blackwell Publishers, 108 Cowley Road, Oxford OX4 1JF, UK and 350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148, USA METAPHILOSOPHY Vol. 30, Nos. 1/2, January/April 1999 0026–1068 1 * Versions of this paper and of the following papers by Bernard Gert and Jonathan Dancy were originally presented at the Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy, held in Boston, Massachusetts, USA, in August 1998. 1 Aristotle (1985): “When we are discussing actions, although general statements have a wider application, particular statements are closer to the truth.”

Upload: bp151

Post on 16-Nov-2015

4 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

DESCRIPTION

metaethics

TRANSCRIPT

  • SOME VARIETIES OF PARTICULARISM*

    WALTER SINNOTT-ARMSTRONG

    ABSTRACT: Analytic particularism claims that judgments of moral wrongnessare about particular acts rather than general principles. Metaphysical particularismclaims that what makes true moral judgments true is not general principles butnonmoral properties of particular acts. Epistemological particularism claims thatstudying particular acts apart from general principles can justify beliefs in moraljudgments. Methodological particularism claims that we will do better morally ineveryday life if we look carefully at each particular decision as it arises and giveup the search for a complete moral theory. This paper raises problems for each ofthese versions of particularism.

    Key words: ethics, moral philosophy, particularism, logical form, epistemology,metaphysics, moral methodology.

    Particularism is popular. It has been espoused recently by JonathanDancy (1993), John McDowell (1998), David McNaughton (1988), andmany feminists, including Margaret Walker (1989). There are also honor-able ancestors from Sartre (1956) all the way back to Aristotle.1 Still,recent particularists have developed the view more thoroughly than everbefore.

    When a label applies to so many philosophers, it should not be surpris-ing to find that it covers many very different views. So the first step mustbe to define precisely what particularism claims.

    Scope

    The kind of particularism that interests me here is a theory about judg-ments, which include linguistic assertions as well as mental beliefs andthoughts. More specifically, particularism is about moral judgments ratherthan about aesthetic or prudential judgments. Even more specifically, it is

    Metaphilosophy LLC and Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 1999. Published by BlackwellPublishers, 108 Cowley Road, Oxford OX4 1JF, UK and 350 Main Street, Malden,MA 02148, USAMETAPHILOSOPHYVol. 30, Nos. 1/2, January/April 199900261068

    1

    * Versions of this paper and of the following papers by Bernard Gert and JonathanDancy were originally presented at the Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy, held inBoston, Massachusetts, USA, in August 1998.

    1 Aristotle (1985): When we are discussing actions, although general statements havea wider application, particular statements are closer to the truth.

  • about moral judgments of actions.2 There are corresponding views aboutpeople, character traits, institutions, and so on, but the particularism thatconcerns me is about which actions are morally right or wrong, obligatoryor forbidden, good or bad, and so on.

    What unites particularists is their claim that such moral judgments are notand should not be based on general principles (or rules). But which kinds ofprinciples do they oppose? And what is the alternative to principles?

    Analytic Particularism

    Its very name suggests that particularism is the claim that all such moraljudgments are basically about particular actions. However, that claim isalmost incoherent. Davidson (1980a) has shown that action sentenceshave to be analyzed with quantifiers, and I have argued that deontic logicfalls into paradoxes unless judgments about obligations and what ought tobe done are analyzed with operators quantified on action sentences(Sinnott-Armstrong 1985). If so, even a very specific moral judgment thatSarah morally ought to paint Toms house on this Sunday afternoon at 3P.M. must be analyzed as the claim that there morally ought to exist someact by Sarah that is an act of painting Toms house and that occurs on thisSunday afternoon at 3 P.M. What she ought to do is some act of a kind. Soeven this very specific judgment is not about any particular act.3 Indeed,since every moral obligation can be fulfilled by more than one act, nomoral judgment is basically about only one particular act.

    Past-tense moral judgments might seem to be an exception. For exam-ple, the moral judgment Sarahs act of painting Toms house last Sundaywas morally obligatory seems to be about the particular act that Sarahdid. However, although Sarah did fulfill her obligation by means of oneparticular act, she could have fulfilled it by a slightly different act (say, bystarting a minute earlier or on a different side), so Sarah was not obligatedto do the particular act that she did. This variability can be represented byanalyzing this judgment as Sarah did an act of painting Toms house lastSunday, and Sarah was morally obligated to do some act of painting Tomshouse last Sunday. Such judgments are not basically about only oneparticular act. They are implicitly universal, and so can be seen as imply-ing a principle in a minimal way. Action theory and deontic logic alone areenough to refute any variety of particularism that claims otherwise.

    Metaphysical Particularism

    Particularists will complain that I have mischaracterized their position.Maybe I have. Maybe particularism is not about logical form. Instead, it

    2 WALTER SINNOTT-ARMSTRONG

    Metaphilosophy LLC and Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 1999

    2 See the quotation from Aristotle in note 1.3 Specificity contrasts with generality, but particularity contrasts with universalizabil-

    ity, as Hare (1963, 3840) pointed out.

  • might be about moral metaphysics (55, 74),4 and specifically about whatmakes some moral judgments true or about which properties make someacts morally right or wrong, good or bad, and so forth. The question isthen: What is it that makes Sarah morally obligated to paint Toms house?Particularists say that it is not general principles, but we still need to knowwhat they think it is instead.

    Particularists might not all agree, but Dancy claims that moral proper-ties result from nonmoral properties (7377). If so, then Sarahs act ofpainting Toms house has the moral property of being obligatory by virtueof having some nonmoral property, presumably the property of fulfillingher promise.

    This relation of resultance would entail moral principles, if the sameproperty that results in a moral obligation in Sarahs case also had to resultin a moral obligation in every other case. That is what particularists deny.They claim that the same nonmoral base properties result in differentmoral properties in different contexts. So particularists avoid moral prin-ciples by being contextualists, that is, by insisting that the relation ofresultance varies from context to context (11415).

    At one level, this contextualism is obvious. What makes it true thatSarah ought to paint Toms house is the fact that she promised to paintToms house. But that same fact does not make it true that Sarah ought topaint Toms house in a different context where Tom changed his mind andtold her not to paint his house. Moreover, if Sarah promises to paint Tomshouse tomorrow, but Toms house burns down today, then it is no longermorally obligatory for Sarah to paint Toms house tomorrow. Whether herpromise results in an obligation to paint Toms house tomorrow thusdepends on features of the context, such as whether Toms house burnsdown, whether he tells her not to paint it, and so on. Nobody should denyany of this.

    Dancy gives a string of examples like these. Within this string, heclaims, first, that I usually have a moral reason to return to you a book thatI borrowed from you, but if I discover that you stole the book from thelibrary, then I have no reason at all to return it to you. Second, that anaction is a lie is commonly a reason not to do it [but in a game that wouldbe spoiled without lying] it is a reason in favour. Third, pleasure isusually a reason that supports an activity, but pleasure at a wrong actioncompounds the wrong. Fourth, an action is usually worse for causingpain, but if someone deserves pain, the infliction of that pain can hardlybe diminished in value by the pain inflicted. Fifth, the fact that an actionis against the law is [usually] a reason against doing it, but [i]t mightalso be a reason for doing it, if this sort of behavior is not one that shouldbe regulated by law (6062).

    Such examples do not, however, rule out moral principles. All they rule

    SOME VARIETIES OF PARTICULARISM 3

    Metaphilosophy LLC and Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 1999

    4All page references in the text are to Dancy (1993) unless otherwise noted.

  • out is overly simple moral principles. More complex principles will avoidsuch counterexamples. In Dancys first example, even if I have no reasonto return to you the stolen library book that I borrowed from you, one canstill hold a principle that I always have a moral reason to return to youyour property that I borrowed from you. Second, even if I have no reasonnot to lie in a game that requires lying, the players consented to play thegame, so one can still hold a principle that I always have a moral reasonnot to lie without consent. Third, even if pleasure at a wrong actioncompounds the wrong, one can still hold a principle that there is always amoral reason to cause innocent pleasure. Fourth, even if the value ofdeserved punishment is not diminished by the pain inflicted, one can stillhold a principle that there is always a moral reason not to inflict pain oninnocent people. Fifth, even if a law against an action is a reason to do thataction when the law is unjust (and breaking that law will shorten its lifewithout causing too much harm), one can still hold a principle that thereis always a moral reason not to break a just law. So such examples showthat principles should not be formulated too broadly, but they do not showthat no exceptionless principles should or could ever be formulated.

    Admittedly, these more complex principles include moral terms in theirexception clauses. We still need to specify when pleasures and people areinnocent, when laws are just, and so on. However, my point here is justthat such examples by themselves are not enough to show that these moralterms cannot be ultimately replaced by nonmoral terms or, hence, thatexceptionless principles are impossible.

    Of course, Dancy gives more than a few examples. He also claims thatthe resultance base and the relevant factors are naturally shapeless (76).This seems to mean that people who lack the resulting moral conceptcannot discern or see what is common to the items in the nonmoral resul-tance base that are classified together under the resulting moral concept(79) and also cannot discern the interrelationships of the various proper-ties (76). This claim would be falsified if one could formulate exception-less universal principles that go from the nonmoral resultance base (in theantecedent) to the moral properties (in the consequent). For example, ifthere is always some (possibly overridden) moral reason not to kill anyadult human, then someone who lacks the concept of a moral reason canstill see that all acts of killing adult humans get classified together. So thedenial of natural shape seems to be just another way of denying principles.

    These denials are analogous to Donald Davidsons anomalous monism(Davidson 1980b). Just as Davidson allows token identities but deniestype identities and bridging laws between the mental and the physical, soDancy allows token identities but no type identities or bridging lawsbetween the moral and its nonmoral base (116). This kind of view seemsas coherent in ethics as it is in the philosophy of mind, but such coherencealone is no reason to adopt such a view. Davidson gives an argument forviewing mental events in this way. Dancy owes us a similar argument to

    4 WALTER SINNOTT-ARMSTRONG

    Metaphilosophy LLC and Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 1999

  • show why the base for moral properties must be naturally shapeless. Ifound no such argument.

    Nonetheless, a challenge has been laid down. To meet this challenge,we need to show some shape in the principles that link the nonmoral basewith moral properties or facts. So I will suggest a simple outline. If Tomtells Sarah that she does not have to keep her promise, since he can findanother painter if she wants him to, then this cancels Sarahs reason topaint Toms house without giving her any reason to do anything to thecontrary. When a fact has this force, it is an underminer. In contrast, if Tomtells Sarah not to paint his house, this undermines her reason to paint hishouse and also gives her a reason not to paint his house. Such facts notonly cancel but reverse the force of the reason, so they can be calledreversers. Third, the fact that Sarah broke her leg removes her responsi-bility for not painting the house. When a fact has this force, it is an excuse.The fact that Sarahs daughter is very sick is a conflicting reason for Sarahto take her daughter to the hospital instead of painting Toms house. If thisnew reason overrides her reason to paint his house, it is an overrider.Overriders, underminers, reversers, and excuses are, then, all reasondefeaters.5

    This list of defeaters is hard to spell out in general and in detail. Onecomplication is that defeaters themselves can be defeated. If Sarahpromises to paint Toms house, and the house burns down, but Tom tellsSarah that he wants her to paint the ashes and rubble anyway, maybe thenshe does have a reason to paint it, so her reason is not undermined afterall. Maybe not. It is not obvious what to say about such odd cases. Thatmakes it hard to specify exactly when a fact counts as an underminer or,more generally, a defeater. Nonetheless, even if some are hard to classify,different kinds of facts can still be different kinds of defeaters becausethey have different effects on reasons.

    Even without being fully spelled out, this classification of defeatersshows what is wrong with Dancys argument against what he calls thedoctrine of universalizability. He states this doctrine in two parts:

    i. If we judge one action right, we must judge any other relevantly simi-lar action right.

    ii. An action is said to be relevantly similar if, roughly, it shares with thefirst action all the properties which were reasons why the first actionwas right. (57; cf. 80)

    This doctrine is said to fail in cases like that in which Sarah promises topaint Toms house. If everything else remains the same, but the house doesnot burn down, then the right thing for Sarah to do is paint Toms house.This is not the right thing to do when the house does burn down (if Tom

    SOME VARIETIES OF PARTICULARISM 5

    Metaphilosophy LLC and Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 1999

    5 This list extends my list in Sinnott-Armstrong 1988 (4143, 9394, 98101).

  • does not tell her to paint it anyway). Yet Sarahs reason to paint the houseis that she promised. The fact that the house did not burn down is not areason or even part of a reason for her to paint the house (81). Why not?Because not burning down is a background condition. Background condi-tions do not count as reasons any more than they count as causes. Just asthe absence of water is not a cause of a match lighting, so the house notburning down is not a reason to paint it (24, 66). This refutes (i) on theassumption that reasons are the only relevant features, as (ii) claims.

    A defender of universalizability is bound to respond that reasons arenot the only relevant features. Even if the fact that the house did not burndown is not a reason for Sarah to paint the house, it is still relevant inanother way, because it is the absence of an underminer. The relevance ofunderminers refutes (ii), since an action is not relevantly similar to anotheraction unless it is similar in all relevant respects, so it has to be similar notonly in the reasons for it but also in the underminers. Indeed, since alldefeaters as well as reasons are relevant, we need to rewrite the secondpart of universalizability like this:

    ii*. An action is relevantly similar if, roughly, it shares with the firstaction all the properties which were reasons why the first action wasright, as well as all the underminers, reversers, excuses, and overrid-ers.

    The revised doctrine of universalizability that combines (i) with (ii*) isnot subject to any of Dancys counterexamples. Moreover, (i) plus (ii*)seems closer to the views of traditional defenders of universalizability,such as Sidgwick and Hare, since they did not endorse Dancys (ii).

    In addition to saving universalizability, my classification of defeatersalso shows one way to qualify moral principles so as to avoid exceptions.Instead of saying that there is always a moral reason not to kill any adulthuman, just say that there is always a moral reason not to kill any adulthuman when there is no underminer, reverser, excuse, or overrider. Maybewe also ought to obey the law, keep our promises, avoid causing pain, andso on, as long as there is no underminer, reverser, excuse, or overrider.Such qualified principles are fully compatible with Dancys contextual-ism, since they allow the existence and force of reasons to vary with thecontext, which includes defeaters.

    Despite their context-sensitivity, these principles give some shape tothe resultance base. Principles with ceteris paribus clauses would not dothe trick, since such open-ended principles are almost empty without anyway to tell when the other things are equal (82). In contrast, the definitionsof underminers, reversers, excuses, and overriders place limits on excep-tions. If you demand more shape, I could subdivide, for example, bydistinguishing consequential overriders from deontological overriders,and so on. Much more could and should be done to explain the meta-physics and epistemology of various kinds of defeaters (96104).

    6 WALTER SINNOTT-ARMSTRONG

    Metaphilosophy LLC and Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 1999

  • Nonetheless, my simple list of defeaters at least points toward one way toformulate moral principles without exceptions.

    Dancy will complain that my definitions of defeaters refer to moralreasons, so principles whose antecedents refer to defeaters do not take usfrom purely nonmoral antecedents to moral consequents. What Dancyclaims is not shapelessness, but natural shapelessness, which is the claimthat the shape of the resultance base for moral reasons cannot be describedin purely natural or nonmoral terms (76). This challenge is hard to meet,because it seems to call for a general theory that uses only nonmoral termsto specify exactly which facts count as underminers, reversers, excuses,and overriders in all cases.

    Nonetheless, even in the absence of any general theory, some casesseem clear. There is a moral reason not to kill a normal adult human (1)intentionally and on purpose when one suffers from no false belief,compulsion, or coercion, (2) when this person did not consent and did notcause death or disability or unusual pain to anyone, and (3) when thiskilling would not prevent any pain, disability, or death for anyone else.Clause (1) rules out any excuse, clause (2) rules out any underminer orreverser, and clause (3) rules out any overrider. Refinements are probablyneeded, but the basic idea should be clear: Somehow one can usenonmoral terms to describe facts that are sufficient (even if not necessary)to rule out any kind of defeater. This yields principles that go from purelynonmoral antecedents, like (1)(3), to moral consequents in some cases.That is enough to reveal some shape in part of the nonmoral resultancebase for moral properties. So that base is not all naturally shapeless.

    This move might seem to miss something, which suggests that the realissue is not shapelessness. The real issue is incompleteness. Even if theresultance base has some shape, it might not have shape in every corner.Dancy claims, we can give no sense to the idea that we might now havefinished the list of moral principles or of properties that can make a differ-ence sometimes (67). There might be other relevant kinds of factors inaddition to underminers, reversers, excuses, and overriders. And no matterhow long are our lists of facts within each category, there always might bemore underminers, reversers, excuses, and overriders that are not on ourlists. Consequently, it will be impossible to codify any moral maxim in away that will render it invulnerable to the vagaries of future situations(92).

    To assess these claims, we need to separate completeness in principlefrom completeness in practice. I found no argument by Dancy that evenbegins to show that the list of relevant factors cannot in principle becomplete. No set of examples can show that much. No uncontroversialview about the nature of morality implies incompleteness in principle. Sowhy believe it?

    Consider the dialectical situation: A generalist holds a theory with along list of defeaters shaped into groups. A particularist comes up and

    SOME VARIETIES OF PARTICULARISM 7

    Metaphilosophy LLC and Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 1999

  • claims, This example shows you need another item on your list. Ageneralist can always respond, No, it doesnt. Your moral judgment aboutthe example is incorrect. Alternatively, a generalist can respond, OK,Ill add another item to my list. A particularist can then come up withmore examples, but a generalist again has these two possible responses and so on. Some generalists might not be ingenious enough to figure outhow to redefine their principles or add to their list of defeaters. Or theymight just get frustrated and give up. But that does not show that it isimpossible in principle for generalists to keep adding qualifications anddefeaters until no more are needed. After all, such changes are neededonly to capture intuitions, and more complex theories might not conflictwith any strong intuitions. Maybe Dancys own intuitions are such that nolist could ever in principle completely capture his intuitions, but thatwould hardly show that completeness is impossible in principle for anyadequate moral theory.

    What about completeness in practice? Particularists seem to think thatno moral theory has gone very far toward listing all of the morally rele-vant factors. Maybe so, although utilitarians and possibly Gert (1999) willclaim that they have. Still, this does not show that completeness cannotever be attained in practice. Secular ethical theory is too young to feel sureabout this issue. So it is hard to see any reason to admit uncodifiabilityeven just in practice.

    Suppose Dancy is right, and complete codifiability is not attainable inpractice. What does that show? It shows limits on human abilities. It doesnot show anything about the metaphysical structure of moral reality unlessone assumes that there can be no more to morality than what everyoneknows already. Dancy never endorses or argues for any such assumption.The metaphysical version of particularism remains unsupported.

    Epistemological Particularism

    Incompleteness in practice still might seem to have implications for moralepistemology, specifically for whether or when we can be epistemicallyjustified in believing a moral claim. To be justified in believing that an actis morally wrong, we need to be justified in believing that no fact under-mines or overrides or reverses the moral reasons that make the act wrong.If we cannot in practice ever complete the list of relevant facts, then wecannot in practice ever be certain of any of our judgments about what ismorally wrong. We may still reach the conditional conclusion that, if thereare no defeaters, then the act is wrong. But if we cannot tell whether or notthere are defeaters, we cannot tell whether the act categorically is morallywrong. This seems to support Dancys claim that the moral relevance ofa property in a new case cannot be predicted from its relevance elsewhere(57; cf. 60).

    I do not disagree if all Dancy means is that our prediction cannot be

    8 WALTER SINNOTT-ARMSTRONG

    Metaphilosophy LLC and Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 1999

  • certain. Dancy suggests this weak position when he says, for example,we must be careful to retain the sense that considerations may not befunctioning here as they have previously done, and so not allow ourselvesto be driven too easily to fit what we say here to what we have said onother occasions (63; my emphasis). If may means might for all weknow and hence refers to epistemic uncertainty, then this quotation callsfor recognizing fallibility. We should all answer that call.

    After all, almost no predictions are certain. Even physicists cannot becertain that there are no forces that science has not discovered. And evenif we had a complete list of moral defeaters in hand, we still could not becertain that our list is complete, so we could not be certain of uncondi-tional moral judgments. So lets give up the quest for certainty, as Deweynamed it. We can still use a theory with a well-worked-out list of defeatersto get some justification for our moral beliefs.

    This justification can be adequate and even strong. If we get a list thatfits every case that either we or our critics can come up with, and if weand they have tried long and hard to find flaws in the theory, then we havestrong reason to believe that the list is complete, even if we admit that wecannot be certain. Maybe few peoples moral beliefs are justified in thisway, but it still seems possible, or at least Dancy has not shown other-wise.

    Methodological Particularism

    Some particularists will claim that I have misunderstood them yet again.Maybe I have. Maybe they are making a different point about moralmethodology, namely, that we should not search for a set of principles(56). I take this as a piece of practical advice in living our everyday morallives. Even if we could justify our moral beliefs by basing them on generaltheories, why should we want that kind of justification? We might dobetter morally if we quit looking for a complete theory and just look care-fully at each particular decision as it arises.

    This suspicion of theory might be based on several observations. First,in cases where the correct moral judgment is obvious, theories do not andshould not increase our confidence in a moral belief. Second, any univer-sal generalization is less likely to be true than the cases on which it isbased. Third, incomplete theories sometimes lead us to overlook relevantfacts (64). Just as too much aesthetic theory can blind a viewer to theaesthetic quality of a painting, poem, or song, so too much moral theorycan blind an agent to the moral quality of an act. These are all serious chal-lenges to the practical usefulness of general moral theories. They all needto be met. But I will not try to meet them here, since that would require afull-scale moral epistemology and methodology.

    Here I will just ask: What is the alternative method if we cannot cite anyuniversal moral principle? It seems that particularists can only appeal to

    SOME VARIETIES OF PARTICULARISM 9

    Metaphilosophy LLC and Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 1999

  • bare direct intuition of a particular case. This creates a variety of practicalproblems.

    An intrapersonal problem arises when someone studies a case in depthbut still does not see whether or not an act is morally wrong. Moral prin-ciples can be useful in some such cases for some people to help themdecide what to believe about what they should do.

    The most serious problems are interpersonal. Suppose Ken believesthat same-sex marriage is unnatural and morally wrong, so it should notbe recognized by law. John disagrees on all counts, but he is a particular-ist. What can John say to Ken? He can say, Look again or Think moreabout it or You would see if you were more sensitive and reliable or hadbetter training or just Trust me. But this will hardly impress Ken, whocould say the same to John with the same grounds (compare 8990).Moreover, Johns encounter with Ken will give John some reason to doubthis own moral judgment. Our vision becomes questionable when otherssee what we do not see. Our moral judgment seems to be subject to thesame tests of intersubjective agreement. John might be right even if every-one else agrees with Ken, but disagreement gives John some reason todoubt that he is right.

    Such doubts can be counteracted in two ways. John might cite a moralprinciple that no act is morally wrong when it has or lacks a certaingeneral feature. But John cannot cite any such first-order reason if heremains a particularist. Particularists can cite moral principles if a moralprinciple amounts [only] to a reminder of the sort of importance that aproperty can have in suitable circumstances (67; Dancys emphasis). Butthat kind of principle cannot be used against Ken, who may respond thatthe property of being same-sex has significance in the case of marriage,regardless of what significance it can have or lack in other situations.

    Dancy might respond that a particularist can use arguments from anal-ogy as long as they are seen as providing enlightenment, not coercion(65). However, this cannot help if Ken sees the analogy but is not enlight-ened. Moreover, this gives no explanation of why analogies are moreuseful with morality than with colors. One cannot argue that Kens neigh-bors house is red, so Kens house must be red; but one can argue thatKens neighbor has a reason not to lie (without consent, etc.), so Ken alsohas a reason not to lie (without consent, etc.). It is the peculiar force ofanalogies in moral reasoning that a particularist cannot explain or admit.

    The remaining possibility is to cite circumstances under which a moraljudgment is reliable (that is, probably true). But how could a particularistformulate such a second-order reason to believe in his own reliability?Dancy says, the person on whom we can rely . . . is someone who gets itright case by case (64); so, to show that he is reliable, John might citepast cases where he got it right. But Ken could simply question whetherJohn really did get it right in those cases, at least whenever they are rele-vant to same-sex marriage. John could not show that he was right in those

    10 WALTER SINNOTT-ARMSTRONG

    Metaphilosophy LLC and Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 1999

  • past cases any more than in the present case. So John and Ken are left withno good reason to believe that John is a reliable detector of moral wrong-ness (or its absence) in these kinds of circumstances. A particularist mightbe a reliable detector, but being reliable is not much use if one has noreason to believe that one is reliable and no way to show others that oneis reliable. That is what a particularist lacks.

    And that is what generality is supposed to add. If John could citegeneral principles, or if he could draw an analogy with interracialmarriage, for example, then he would have some way to check his ownintuition and to show others that he is reliable. His audience might be toobullheaded to accept his reasons, but at least he would have a reason togive. In contrast, without analogies or principles, all a particularist has tooffer is bare intuition.

    Particularists often respond that universal principles, analogies, and theo-ries really cannot achieve these goals any better than particularism. Maybenot. But the failure of general theories does not show that particularism isdefensible. If moral theory, analogy, and principle really get us nothing, thenthe conclusion should be moral skepticism, not moral particularism.

    This conclusion is not to be despised. Indeed, I have argued for alimited version of moral skepticism (Sinnott-Armstrong 1996). But mygoal here is not to argue for any skepticism. My main goals here havebeen, first, to distinguish different versions of particularism, so thatDancy can tell us which is his view (or, if his view is none of the above,what his view is). My second goal has been to raise problems for thesevarious views so that Dancy can try to defend the ones he does believein.

    Department of PhilosophyDartmouth CollegeHanover, NH [email protected]

    References

    Aristotle. (1985). Nicomachean Ethics. Translated by Terence Irwin.Indianapolis, Ind.: Hackett Publishing Company.

    Dancy, Jonathan. (1993). Moral Reasons. Oxford: Blackwell.Davidson, Donald. (1980a). The Logical Form of Action Sentences.

    Reprinted in Essays on Actions and Events, 10548. New York: OxfordUniversity Press.

    . (1980b). Mental Events. Reprinted in Essays on Actions andEvents, 20725. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Gert, Bernard. (1999). Morally Relevant Features. Metaphilosophy, thisissue.

    SOME VARIETIES OF PARTICULARISM 11

    Metaphilosophy LLC and Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 1999

  • Hare, R. M. (1963). Freedom and Reason. New York: Oxford UniversityPress.

    McDowell, John. (1998). Mind, Value, and Reality. Cambridge: HarvardUniversity Press.

    McNaughton, David. (1988). Moral Vision. Oxford: Blackwell.Sartre, Jean-Paul. (1956). Existentialism Is a Humanism. Translated by

    Philip Mairet. Reprinted in Existentialism from Dostoevsky to Sartre,edited by Walter Kaufmann. New York: Meridan Books.

    Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter. (1985). A Solution to Forresters Paradox ofGentle Murder. Journal of Philosophy, 82, 16268.

    . (1988). Moral Dilemmas. Oxford: Blackwell.. (1996). Moral Skepticism and Justification. In Moral

    Knowledge? New Readings in Moral Epistemology, edited by WalterSinnott-Armstrong and Mark Timmons, 348. New York: OxfordUniversity Press.

    Walker, Margaret. (1989). Moral Understandings: AlternativeEpistemologies for a Feminist Ethics. Hypatia, 4, 1528.

    12 WALTER SINNOTT-ARMSTRONG

    Metaphilosophy LLC and Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 1999