truth%and%thesciences% - wordpress.com ·...

26
TRUTH AND THE SCIENCES Anjan Chakravartty Institute for the History and Philosophy of Science and Technology, and Department of Philosophy University of Toronto Abstract. Conceptions of truth in relation to the sciences vary extensively along two dimensions. The first concerns the applicability of the notion of truth to scientific knowledge, resulting in a number of contentions: that scientific knowledge is wholly, or in some important sense, independent of truth; that truth is, in some form, a proper aim of science; and that truths are, in fact, illuminated by means of scientific investigation. The second dimension concerns the particular theory of truth one might think applicable, and here one finds a variety of preferences, including: truth as coherence, especially suited to historicist and sociological approaches to science; truth as utility, described by pragmatist approaches to science; and truth via correspondence or truthmaking, especially in the context of various forms of “realism” in connection with scientific knowledge. In this essay, I travel along the first dimension in the direction of increasing commitment to the applicability of truth, and in each case explore the second dimension: how different views of scientific knowledge appeal, explicitly or implicitly, to different theories of truth. 1. Introduction What is the relationship of truth to the sciences? Ideally, as a prelude to answering this question, one might begin by specifying what, in this context, truth is generally thought to be. Unfortunately, however, though many philosophers of science believe that the concept of truth is important to a consideration of the practice and outcomes of scientific work, there is no consensus regarding which concept of truth, among the several philosophers have developed more generally, is most appropriate here. Indeed, there is no consensus even regarding the question of whether the concept is relevant to philosophical considerations of the sciences, and if so, how. In light of this diversity of opinion, perhaps not surprisingly, the task of getting to grips with the relationship of truth to the sciences is not entirely straightforward: it requires an examination of the different approaches to scientific investigation and knowledge that generate these different commitments. In this essay, I explore the many different ways in which concepts of truth have been brought to bear in connection with these different approaches. The various attitudes towards truth found in the philosophy of science have correlates in a number of what one might view as philosophically prereflective attitudes exemplified in everyday discussions and debates about science. The different philosophical approaches towards the sciences I have alluded to may thus be thought of as more careful or rigorous philosophical extensions of these everyday attitudes. By way of introduction, then, it may be helpful to enumerate these prereflective attitudes before digging into their philosophical counterparts. On the one hand,

Upload: phamdien

Post on 13-Oct-2018

235 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

TRUTH  AND  THE  SCIENCES    

Anjan  Chakravartty  Institute  for  the  History  and  Philosophy  of  Science  and  Technology,  and  Department  of  Philosophy  

University  of  Toronto      Abstract.  Conceptions  of  truth  in  relation  to  the  sciences  vary  extensively  along  two  dimensions.  The  first  concerns  the  applicability  of  the  notion  of  truth  to  scientific  knowledge,  resulting  in  a  number  of  contentions:  that  scientific  knowledge  is  wholly,  or  in  some  important  sense,  independent  of  truth;  that  truth  is,  in  some  form,  a  proper  aim  of  science;  and  that  truths  are,  in  fact,  illuminated  by  means  of  scientific  investigation.  The  second  dimension  concerns  the  particular  theory  of  truth  one  might  think  applicable,  and  here  one  finds  a  variety  of  preferences,  including:  truth  as  coherence,  especially  suited  to  historicist  and  sociological  approaches  to  science;  truth  as  utility,  described  by  pragmatist  approaches  to  science;  and  truth  via  correspondence  or  truth-­‐making,  especially  in  the  context  of  various  forms  of  “realism”  in  connection  with  scientific  knowledge.  In  this  essay,  I  travel  along  the  first  dimension  in  the  direction  of  increasing  commitment  to  the  applicability  of  truth,  and  in  each  case  explore  the  second  dimension:  how  different  views  of  scientific  knowledge  appeal,  explicitly  or  implicitly,  to  different  theories  of  truth.    

 

1.  Introduction  

 

  What  is  the  relationship  of  truth  to  the  sciences?  Ideally,  as  a  prelude  to  answering  this  

question,  one  might  begin  by  specifying  what,  in  this  context,  truth  is  generally  thought  to  be.  

Unfortunately,  however,  though  many  philosophers  of  science  believe  that  the  concept  of  truth  is  

important  to  a  consideration  of  the  practice  and  outcomes  of  scientific  work,  there  is  no  consensus  

regarding  which  concept  of  truth,  among  the  several  philosophers  have  developed  more  generally,  

is  most  appropriate  here.  Indeed,  there  is  no  consensus  even  regarding  the  question  of  whether  the  

concept  is  relevant  to  philosophical  considerations  of  the  sciences,  and  if  so,  how.  In  light  of  this  

diversity  of  opinion,  perhaps  not  surprisingly,  the  task  of  getting  to  grips  with  the  relationship  of  

truth  to  the  sciences  is  not  entirely  straightforward:  it  requires  an  examination  of  the  different  

approaches  to  scientific  investigation  and  knowledge  that  generate  these  different  commitments.  In  

this  essay,  I  explore  the  many  different  ways  in  which  concepts  of  truth  have  been  brought  to  bear  

in  connection  with  these  different  approaches.  

  The  various  attitudes  towards  truth  found  in  the  philosophy  of  science  have  correlates  in  a  

number  of  what  one  might  view  as  philosophically  pre-­‐reflective  attitudes  exemplified  in  everyday  

discussions  and  debates  about  science.  The  different  philosophical  approaches  towards  the  

sciences  I  have  alluded  to  may  thus  be  thought  of  as  more  careful  or  rigorous  philosophical  

extensions  of  these  everyday  attitudes.  By  way  of  introduction,  then,  it  may  be  helpful  to  enumerate  

these  pre-­‐reflective  attitudes  before  digging  into  their  philosophical  counterparts.  On  the  one  hand,  

Anjan  Chakravartty          Truth  and  the  Sciences  

  2  

there  are  more  or  less  “optimistic”  attitudes  regarding  the  connection  between  truth  and  the  

sciences  –  those  that  view  the  sciences  as  producing  truths  concerning  the  natural  and  social  

worlds  in  which  we  live,  or  as  arbiters  with  respect  to  such  truths,  or  at  the  very  least,  our  best  bets  

for  truth  production  and  arbitration.  On  the  other  hand,  there  are  more  or  less  “pessimistic”  

attitudes,  which  regard  the  connection  as  relatively  weak  or  in  some  cases,  illusory.  Let  us  consider  

this  range  of  possibilities,  briefly,  in  turn.  

  Almost  everyone,  I  suspect,  would  agree  that  the  sciences  are  in  the  knowledge  production  

business  –  scientific  work  produces  theories,  models,  predictions,  and  explanations  which  are  

offered,  prima  facie,  as  candidates  for  knowledge.  The  optimism  and  pessimism  I  have  gestured  

towards  concern  the  extent  to  which  these  candidates  can  or  should  be  thought  of  in  terms  of  truth.  

Optimists  commonly  hold  that  our  best  scientific  theories  and  models  can  be  thought  of  as  yielding  

truths  regarding  their  subject  matter,  or  as  furnishing  descriptions  that  are,  over  time,  approaching  

the  truth  (in  a  sense  to  be  specified,  as  we  shall  see  in  sections  3  and  5).  This  is  the  implicit  attitude  

exemplified  in  everyday  contexts  in  which  scientists  are  presented  as  authorities  regarding  

everything  from  the  common  cold  to  genetic  manipulation  to  climate  change.  This  generally  

positive  view  of  the  connection  between  science  and  truth  has  its  most  pronounced  philosophical  

extension  in  varieties  of  “realism”  with  respect  to  scientific  knowledge.  Realists  of  different  sorts  

typically  defend  the  proposition  that  our  best  scientific  theories  provide  true  or  approximately  true  

descriptions  of  the  world,  but  in  different  ways:  some  defend  realism  rather  generally,  and  others  

only  with  respect  to  certain  classes  of  ontological  or  other  claims  which  they  assess  as  having  

greater  epistemic  warrant  than  others.  

  One  need  not  be  a  realist,  however,  in  order  to  adopt  a  positive  attitude  towards  the  

connection  between  science  and  truth.  A  certain  degree  of  pessimism  with  respect  to  truth  is  

compatible  with  a  degree  of  optimism.  There  are  those,  for  example,  who  are  somewhat  suspicious  

of  the  often  definitive-­‐  and  precise-­‐sounding  claims  of  scientists  –  particularly  in  connection  with  

things  very  far  removed  from  our  abilities  to  see  or  otherwise  register  information  in  the  absence  of  

elaborate  instrumentation.  Examples  of  such  things  may  include  the  very  small,  such  as  viruses  and  

subatomic  particles,  or  the  very  spatiotemporally  distant,  such  as  events  in  the  immediate  

aftermath  of  the  Big  Bang  or  those  leading  to  the  extinction  of  the  dinosaurs.  Some  sceptics  

nevertheless  hold  that  scientists  are  likely  on  to  something,  even  if  they  are  suspicious  about  their  

furthest  reaching  claims.  This  everyday  attitude  also  has  well  developed  philosophical  extensions.  A  

number  of  philosophical  positions,  including  certain  varieties  of  empiricism,  regard  the  sciences  as  

Anjan  Chakravartty          Truth  and  the  Sciences  

  3  

producing  truths,  but  of  a  restricted  subset  of  scientific  claims  comprising  descriptions  of  

observable  phenomena  (as  opposed  to  other,  less  directly  detectable  phenomena).  

  Of  course,  it  is  possible  to  be  even  more  strongly  sceptical.  One  might  doubt  that  the  

sciences  produce  truths  at  all,  or  that  while  they  might  do  so  on  occasion,  there  is  little  reason  to  

think  that  they  are  particularly  successful  in  this  regard.  Everyday  scepticism  about  the  veracity  of  

scientific  knowledge  has  its  source  in  a  multiplicity  of  motivations,  from  the  epistemological  to  the  

religious,  social,  and  political.  In  the  philosophy  of  science,  the  motivations  for  this  stronger  

sceptical  attitude  are  invariably  epistemological,  but  in  some  cases  these  views  do  have  important  

social  and  political  dimensions.  Some  who  ascribe  to  strongly  historicist  conceptions  of  knowledge  

doubt  that  truth  is  especially  relevant  to  an  assessment  or  understanding  of  scientific  knowledge.  

Social  constructivist  and  feminist  critiques  of  the  notion  of  truth  and  associated  concepts,  such  as  

objectivity,  engage  head-­‐on  with  the  socio-­‐political  implications  of  these  ideas,  thereby  injecting  a  

consideration  of  them  into  the  epistemology  of  science.  

  In  what  follows,  I  will  outline  the  range  of  views  that  have  emerged  in  the  philosophy  of  

science  regarding  the  notion  of  truth.  I  will  begin  in  section  2  with  views  that  ascribe  no  role,  or  a  

limited  role,  to  truth  in  connection  with  scientific  practice  and  knowledge.  The  primary  driver  of  

scepticism  about  the  role  of  truth  here  is  most  commonly  manifested  as  a  dissatisfaction  with  the  

correspondence  theory  of  truth,  according  to  which  truth  is  a  matter  of  corresponding,  in  the  right  

sort  of  way,  to  a  mind-­‐independent  reality.  (The  correspondence  theory  holds  that  a  belief  

(statement,  proposition,  etc.)  is  true  if  it  corresponds  to  the  way  this  reality  is,  or  to  the  facts  or  

states  of  affairs  that  make  it  up;  for  a  detailed  treatment  of  the  view  in  this  volume,  see  David.)  In  

some  of  these  cases,  an  account  of  truth  in  terms  of  coherence  –  that  is,  in  terms  of  the  consistency  

of  a  set  of  beliefs  (statements,  propositions,  etc.)  –  may  better  accord  with  the  relevant  approaches  

to  science.  (The  coherence  theory  holds  that  a  belief  is  true  if  it  is  part  of  a  coherent  system  of  

beliefs;  on  this  view,  see  Walker.)  In  section  3,  I  will  examine  positions  that  view  truth  in  some  form  

as  an  appropriate  aim  of  science,  and  in  section  4,  I  will  consider  the  even  stronger  commitment  to  

truth  adopted  by  positions  that  regard  it  not  merely  as  an  aim,  but  as  an  achievement  of  scientific  

investigation.  In  the  latter  case,  truth  is  generally  conceived  in  terms  of  some  sort  of  

correspondence,  or  truth-­‐making,  or  both.  

  One  may  think  of  considerations  of  truth  in  connection  with  the  sciences  by  means  of  two  

analytical  dimensions:  the  first  concerning  the  degree  to  which  one  may  think  the  notion  is  

applicable  to  the  sciences;  and  the  second  concerning  the  precise  theory  of  truth  one  may  think  

applies.  I  will  consider,  in  turn,  views  that  are  increasingly  interested  in  truth,  and  for  each,  identify  

Anjan  Chakravartty          Truth  and  the  Sciences  

  4  

the  theory  or  theories  of  truth  that  are  most  appropriate.  In  section  5,  I  will  conclude  with  an  

overview  of  some  challenges  regarding  truth  to  emerge  in  recent  work,  particularly  in  connection  

with  scientific  realism,  the  most  truth-­‐indulgent  philosophy  of  science.  

 

2.  Truth  as  Orthogonal  to  Scientific  Knowledge  

 

2.1  Historicism  and  practice-­‐oriented  philosophy  of  science  

 

  Logical  positivism  (or  logical  empiricism),  the  founding  movement  of  the  philosophy  of  

science  as  a  recognizably  distinct  sub-­‐discipline  of  philosophy,  dominated  the  field  for  much  of  the  

twentieth  century.  In  the  1960s,  the  demise  of  positivism  was  hastened  by  a  historical  turn  in  the  

philosophy  of  science,  associated  with  authors  such  as  Thomas  Kuhn,  Paul  Feyerabend,  and  

Norwood  Russell  Hanson,  which  set  the  stage  for  many  of  the  issues  discussed  in  the  philosophy  of  

science  to  this  day.  In  particular,  Kuhn’s  extraordinarily  influential  book,  The  Structure  of  Scientific  

Revolutions,  played  a  large  role  in  establishing  a  form  of  historicism  about  scientific  knowledge,  and  

an  allied  (though  strictly  separable)  preoccupation  with  the  actual  practice  of  science  by  scientists,  

both  of  which  have  significant  consequences  for  thinking  about  truth.  I  will  take  Kuhn’s  views  as  

exemplary  in  this  regard  for  present  purposes,  though  it  is  important  to  note  that  in  a  number  of  

respects,  the  morals  I  will  draw  concerning  truth  apply  in  partially  overlapping  ways  to  some  of  his  

positivist  ancestors,  and  most  certainly  to  a  number  of  his  contemporaries.  

  The  underlying  commitment  of  the  approach  to  science  taken  in  the  historical  turn  was  to  

treat  the  history  of  the  sciences  and  their  constituent  practices  seriously  as  a  means  by  which  to  

investigate  the  nature  of  scientific  knowledge.  This  was  a  self-­‐conscious  attempt  at  descriptive  

philosophy  –  describing  the  nature  of  scientific  knowledge  as  it  is  actually  found  –  as  opposed  to  a  

normative  or  more  abstract  exercise  in  idealized  epistemological  speculation.  Kuhn  presented  the  

history  of  the  sciences  as  displaying  a  recurring  pattern  of  development:  periods  of  so-­‐called  

normal  science  punctuated  by  scientific  revolutions,  which  overturned  the  established  order  and  

thereby  laid  the  foundations  for  a  new  period  of  normal  science.  One  might  regard  classical  physics,  

for  example,  as  spanning  a  period  of  normal  science,  which  was  ultimately  replaced  by  relativistic  

and  quantum  physics,  which  in  part  constitute  the  normal  science  of  our  own  time.  The  key  

implications  for  truth  on  this  picture  derive  from  Kuhn’s  characterization  of  knowledge  on  either  

side  of  a  revolutionary  divide.  Two  different  periods  of  normal  science,  he  held,  are  

Anjan  Chakravartty          Truth  and  the  Sciences  

  5  

incommensurable  with  one  another,  and  indeed,  exemplify  a  phenomenon  that  is  now  commonly  

referred  to  as  world  change.  Let  us  consider  these  ideas,  briefly,  in  turn.1  

  Kuhn  held  that  each  period  of  normal  science  is  typified  by  a  shared  commitment  to  a  

‘disciplinary  matrix’  or  ‘paradigm’,  consisting  of  a  number  of  elements:  symbolic  generalizations  

(such  as  the  mathematical  formalism  of  scientific  laws);  metaphysical  beliefs  (for  instance,  the  

scholastic  commitment  to  the  existence  of  essential  natures);  values  (such  as  those  favouring  

certain  theoretical  virtues,  like  simplicity);  and  exemplars  (standard  problem  solving  algorithms  or  

techniques).  Scientific  theories  falling  under  the  rubric  of  different  paradigms  are  incommensurable  

with  one  another  –  a  metaphor  derived  from  the  origins  of  the  term  in  the  Greek  geometrical  

concept  of  having  ‘no  common  measure’.  If  two  theories  are  incommensurable  with  one  another,  

they  are  not  incomparable  per  se,  but  they  are  not  comparable  in  way  that  would  allow  one,  for  

example,  to  judge  that  one  is  true  and  the  other  false,  or  to  determine  that  one  is  closer  to  the  truth,  

relatively  speaking.  This  incommensurability  may  take  the  form  of  a  difference  in  methods  or  

standards  operative  in  science,  differences  in  perception  on  the  part  of  scientists  whose  

observations  are  differently  “theory  laden”,  and  most  importantly  for  Kuhn,  a  difference  in  the  very  

meanings  of  our  words.  This  semantic  incommensurability,  which  he  later  analyzed  in  terms  of  the  

failure  of  meaning  preserving  translation  (Kuhn  1983),  problematizes  assessments  of  truth  across  

paradigms.  

  Kuhn’s  theory  of  meaning  is  a  species  of  meaning  holism,  or  meaning  contextualism:  it  

suggests  that  concepts  are  learned  in  groups,  such  as  those  constituting  the  sets  of  interconnected  

beliefs  composing  paradigms.  As  a  result,  when  some  of  these  concepts  change,  the  meanings  of  

terms  throughout  the  network  are  invariably  altered.  Thus,  the  term  ‘mass’  as  used  in  classical  

physics  simply  does  not  have  the  same  meaning  as  the  term  ‘mass’  as  used  in  relativistic  physics,  

and  to  suggest  that  one  theory’s  characterization  of  mass  is  closer  to  the  truth  is  importantly  

confused  –  it  is  to  equivocate  with  respect  to  two  very  different  concepts  which  cannot  be  

understood  except  from  within  the  paradigms  in  which  they  occur.  Indeed,  this  holism  or  

contextualism  is  so  pronounced  that  Kuhn  maintained  that  there  is  strong  sense  in  which,  after  a  

scientific  revolution,  scientists  live  in  a  different  world.  In  the  latter  stages  of  his  career  Kuhn  gave  a  

neo-­‐Kantian  gloss  to  this  notoriously  cryptic  remark.  One  may  think  of  different  paradigms  as  

different  lenses  one  must  employ  so  as  to  engage  in  and  indeed,  create  the  reality  of  scientific  

phenomena.  Perhaps  not  surprisingly,  this  is  a  challenging  idea  to  articulate  and  defend.  

                                                                                                                         

1  For  just  a  few  of  the  many  detailed  studies  of  these  topics,  see  Horwich  1993,  Hoyningen-­‐Huene  1993,  Sankey  1994,  and  Bird  2000.  

Anjan  Chakravartty          Truth  and  the  Sciences  

  6  

  The  pursuit  of  truth  plays  an  important  role,  on  this  picture,  during  normal  science.  Within  

the  scope  of  a  given  paradigm,  scientists  solve  problems  and  generate  facts  that  may  be  described  

in  terms  of  truth.  But  across  paradigms,  such  talk  becomes  incoherent.  One  cannot  judge  one  

scientific  theory  to  be  closer  to  the  truth  than  its  predecessor  if  the  very  comparison  is  rendered  

ineffectual  by  semantic  incommensurability.  And  if  one  takes  the  idea  of  world  change  seriously,  

the  problem  is  compounded,  for  there  is  no  paradigm-­‐transcendent,  God’s-­‐eye  point  of  view  from  

which  to  judge.  There  are  only  paradigmatic  judgements;  empirical  reality  is  in  part  structured  by  

our  paradigms.  One  might  adopt  a  coherence  theory  of  truth  with  respect  to  the  intra-­‐paradigmatic  

context,  since  knowledge  generated  within  a  paradigm  should  cohere  with  it.  This  will  not  suffice  to  

allow  for  anything  like  scientific  progress  across  paradigms,  however,  in  the  way  one  might  hope  

given  a  correspondence  theory  of  truth.  It  is  for  this  reason  that  those  moved  by  historicist  

approaches  to  scientific  knowledge  are  not  generally  interested  in  the  notion  of  truth.  It  is  of  limited  

applicability,  and  entirely  inapplicable  in  the  case  of  correspondence  truth.  Those  inspired  by  this  

approach  to  engage  primarily  with  descriptive  features  of  scientific  practice  have  also  often  found  

truth  to  be  an  unhelpful  or  irrelevant  concept.  

 

2.2  The  sociology  of  scientific  knowledge  

 

  Among  other  innovations,  the  historical  turn  in  the  philosophy  of  science  turned  a  spotlight  

on  the  social  context  of  the  sciences.  Descriptions  of  actual  scientific  practice  revealed  that  complex  

social  interactions  are  intimately  connected  to  the  generation  of  scientific  knowledge  –  from  the  

training  of  students  by  mentors,  to  the  collaborative  and  competitive  dynamics  of  the  hierarchies  of  

public  and  private  institutions  in  which  scientific  work  is  done,  to  the  role  of  economic,  political,  

and  other  factors  driving  research  by  funding  and  other  means,  and  so  on.  It  was  perhaps  

inevitable,  then,  that  in  the  wake  of  the  historical  turn  some  should  turn  to  sociology  as  a  means  of  

understanding  the  sciences.  The  sociology  of  scientific  knowledge  (SSK)  investigates  the  social  

contexts  of  the  sciences,  and  in  this  by  itself,  it  is  philosophically  neutral  with  respect  to  truth.  Just  

as  those  who  are  primarily  interested  in  descriptive  features  of  scientific  practice  might  find  the  

notion  of  truth  surplus  to  analytic  requirements,  those  primarily  interested  in  social  aspects  might  

do  likewise.  In  practice,  however,  most  accounts  of  science  inspired  by  SSK  have  significant  

philosophical  consequences.  Many  suggest  that  once  one  appreciates  the  role  that  social  factors  

play  in  generating  scientific  knowledge,  a  philosophical  commitment  to  some  form  of  social  

constructivism  is  inevitable,  and  this  once  again  problematizes  the  notion  of  correspondence  truth.  

Anjan  Chakravartty          Truth  and  the  Sciences  

  7  

  The  term  ‘social  construction’  is  used  somewhat  differently  by  different  authors,  but  let  us  

proceed  here  with  a  general  understanding  of  it,  according  to  which  it  applies  to  any  process  

wherein  what  counts  as  scientific  fact  (that  is,  a  claim  having  the  status  of  scientific  knowledge)  has  

been  shaped  and  determined  in  substantive  ways  by  social  factors,  and  in  which  different  social  

factors  (likely)  would  have  produced  facts  that  are  inconsistent  with  those  that  were  in  fact  

produced.  The  substantive  influences  of  the  social  on  the  scientific  are  of  course  numerous  

(consider,  for  example,  the  directions  and  methodologies  of  research  permitted,  encouraged,  and  

funded),  but  this  does  not  by  itself  establish  the  counterfactual  dimension  of  the  idea  of  social  

construction  –  the  notion  that  had  such  influences  been  otherwise,  one  would  have  ended  up  with  

facts  that  are  inconsistent  with  those  currently  accepted.  In  order  to  motivate  the  counterfactual,  

scholars  in  this  vein  have  typically  engaged  in  case  studies  of  scientific  work  which  aim  to  show  

how  contingent  decisions  in  the  workplace  are  both  determined  by  social  factors  and  could  have  

gone  otherwise,  resulting  in  different  and  potentially  conflicting  facts.  Additionally,  some  have  

offered  more  global  reasons  for  thinking  that  such  contingency  is  inevitable.  Chief  among  the  

proponents  of  the  latter  approach  are  supporters  of  the  so-­‐called  “Strong  Program”  in  SSK  (also  

known  as  the  “Edinburgh  School”).2  

  Two  of  the  central  tenets  of  the  Strong  Program  are  particularly  interesting  in  connection  

with  the  notion  of  truth.  The  first  is  the  idea  of  symmetry,  which  suggests  that  in  the  scientific  

domain  inter  alia,  beliefs  that  are  taken  to  be  true  are  on  a  par  with  those  taken  to  be  false  in  that  

both  have  the  same  causes,  and  thus  should  be  given  symmetrical  explanations.  This  stands  at  odds  

with  the  not  uncommon,  asymmetrical  practice  of  explaining  the  generation  of  true  beliefs  in  terms  

of  scientific  investigation  successfully  latching  on  to  some  facet  of  a  mind-­‐independent  world,  while  

explaining  false  beliefs  in  terms  of  something  going  wrong,  whether  it  be  instrument  malfunction,  

human  error,  corruption,  or  what  have  you.  Putting  all  scientific  belief  on  a  par  with  respect  to  their  

causes  opens  the  door  to  a  substantively  social  account  of  both  truth  and  falsehood.  A  second  tenet  

of  interest  is  the  idea  of  reflexivity,  which  suggests  that  the  claims  of  SSK  are  no  less  subject  to  

sociological  analysis  (including  the  symmetry  principle)  than  any  putatively  factual  claims.  This  

entails  a  wide-­‐ranging  commitment  to  relativism:  truth  and  falsehood  (even  with  respect  to  SSK)  

are  defined  only  in  the  context  of  a  social  community,  and  have  no  community-­‐transcendent  

                                                                                                                         

2  For  a  mature  statement  of  the  Strong  Program,  see  Barnes,  Bloor  &  Henry  1996.  For  a  sampling  of  different  approaches  to  social  constructivism,  see  Knorr-­‐Cetina  1981,  Pickering  1984,  Shapin  &  Schaffer  1985,  Latour  &  Woolgar  1986,  and  Collins  &  Pinch  1993.  

Anjan  Chakravartty          Truth  and  the  Sciences  

  8  

meaning.  As  with  many  relativist  positions,  there  is  ongoing  debate  as  to  whether  this  feature  of  the  

view  renders  it  self-­‐undermining.  

  Later  incarnations  of  the  Strong  Program  adopt  a  theory  of  language  acquisition,  meaning  

finitism,  which  also  has  profound  implications  for  truth.  Finitism  can  be  viewed  as  an  elaboration  of  

the  later  work  of  Kuhn,  and  especially  as  deriving  from  the  philosophy  of  the  later  Wittgenstein.  

Kuhn  emphasized  the  idea  that  one  learns  the  meanings  of  concepts  by  mastering  the  use  of  

exemplars  that  incorporate  them,  and  this  point  can  be  extended  to  training,  education,  and  

acculturation  more  broadly.  The  ensuing  claim  of  finitism  is  that  meanings  are  social  institutions  –  

the  meaning  of  a  term  is  simply  the  concatenation  of  ways  in  which  it  can  be  used  successfully  in  

communication  within  a  linguistic  community.  This  relegation  of  meaning  to  social  facts  can  be  

exploited  so  as  to  derive  a  forceful  case  for  the  idea  that  such  terms  need  have  no  fixed  or  

determinate  meanings  at  all.  For  on  this  view,  the  meaning  of  a  term  is  constituted  by  the  social  

acceptance  of  its  use,  and  this  is  something  that  can  change  subject  to  social  negotiation,  reflecting  

collective  decisions  about  how  to  go  on  using  language,  which  may  themselves  not  be  universally  

accepted.  This  once  again  appears  to  favour  coherence  as  an  analysis  of  truth  regarding  

propositions  entertained  within  a  scientific  community.  Whether  finitist  observations  regarding  

language  acquisition  successfully  entail  the  associated  view  of  meaning,  however,  is  certainly  

contestable.  

 

2.3  Feminist  critiques  of  science  

 

  Just  as  the  historical  turn  in  the  philosophy  of  science  suggested  and  facilitated  the  

emergence  of  SSK  and  the  development  of  a  number  of  forms  of  social  constructivism,  these  latter  

positions  facilitated  the  development  of  feminist  critiques  of  science,  often  in  conversation  with  

them.  There  is  significant  overlap  between  SSK  and  feminist  approaches  in  the  acknowledgement  of  

the  role  of  social  factors  as  determinants  of  scientific  fact,  but  feminist  scholars  have  extended  this  

analysis  in  more  specific  ways,  reflecting  their  more  specific  motivations.  Another  striking  

difference  is  the  near  universality  with  which  feminist  approaches  are  normative,  offering  

corrective  prescriptions  for  understanding  concepts  such  as  objectivity  and  knowledge  (not  to  

mention  proposals  for  reforming  scientific  practice  itself)  which,  as  we  shall  see  momentarily,  have  

implications  for  how  one  conceives  of  truth.  

  Several  prominent  positions  have  emerged  in  this  literature,  and  it  will  be  useful  to  mention  

them  in  passing.  Feminist  empiricism  emphasizes  the  possibility  of  warranted  scientific  belief  in  a  

Anjan  Chakravartty          Truth  and  the  Sciences  

  9  

communal  setting,  but  crucially,  only  where  biases  which  enter  into  research  –  stemming  from  

gender,  ethnicity,  socio-­‐economic  or  political  status,  and  so  on  –  are  transparent  and  appropriately  

considered.  Standpoint  theory  explores  the  contention  that  differences  in  gender,  ethnicity,  socio-­‐

economic  and  political  status,  etc.  define  perspectives  to  which  knowledge  is  inextricably  indexed.  

Feminist  postmodernism  rejects  traditional  conceptions  of  universal  or  absolute  objectivity  or  

truth.3  Taken  together,  these  positions  offer  a  number  of  considerations  which  might  push  one  in  

the  direction  of  one  theory  of  truth  or  another,  or  indeed,  towards  a  rejection  of  any  substantive  

theory  at  all.  Foremost  among  these  are  considerations  of  objectivity  and  perspective.  Let  us  

examine  them  together,  as  they  are  interestingly  connected.  

  The  term  ‘objective’,  when  used  traditionally  in  connection  with  knowledge,  has  a  number  

of  stereotypical  connotations.  Most  important  in  this  context  are  connotations  of  disinterest  

(detachment,  lack  of  bias),  and  of  universality  (independence  of  any  particular  angle  of  approach  or  

perspective).  Knowledge  of  this  sort  arguably  comprises  propositions  that  are  candidates  for  

describing  a  mind-­‐independent  world,  and  thus,  is  consistent  with  a  correspondence  theory  of  

truth.  There  is  near  consensus  in  feminist  critiques  of  science  that  objectivity  in  the  sense  of  

disinterest  is  regularly  violated  in  science.  Case  studies  are  adduced  to  demonstrate  how  the  

presence  of,  for  instance,  androcentric  bias  exemplified  by  a  community  of  scientists  can  lead  to  the  

establishment  of  one  scientific  fact  at  the  expense  of  another,  mutually  inconsistent  possibility  (for  

example,  see  Longino  1990  for  detailed  accounts  of  two  cases:  one  concerning  explanations  of  the  

evolution  of  modern  human  biological  characteristics  in  paleoanthropology;  and  another  

concerning  the  influence  of  hormones  on  biological  characteristics  and  behaviour  in  

neuroendocrinology).  Many  also  reject  the  idea  of  objectivity  in  the  sense  of  universality  or  

perspective-­‐independence,  and  as  I  will  suggest,  it  is  this  latter  thesis  that  is  required  in  order  to  

problematize  the  notion  of  correspondence  truth.  

  Why  is  the  presence  of  bias  in  scientific  work  not  by  itself  sufficient  to  rule  out  

correspondence?  There  are  two  reasons  for  this.  One  is  that  the  presence  of  bias  may  not  be,  in  a  

given  case,  epistemically  significant.  That  is  to  say,  if  regardless  of  one’s  bias  one  would  have  

assessed  the  evidence  for  a  given  hypotheses  in  the  same  way,  one  might  thereby  end  up  with  true  

beliefs  concerning  that  hypothesis  in  the  correspondence  sense  quite  independently  of  one’s  bias.  

Of  course,  most  feminist  case  studies  are  not  of  this  sort  –  they  are  cases  in  which  bias  does  make  a  

difference.  A  second  reason  that  the  presence  of  bias  (taken  by  itself)  is  consistent  with  the  idea  of  

                                                                                                                         

3  For  a  sample  of  a  number  of  influential  versions  of  these  views,  see  Keller  1985,  Harding  1986,  Haraway  1988,  Longino  1990,  Alcoff  &  Potter  1993,  and  Nelson  &  Nelson  1996.  

Anjan  Chakravartty          Truth  and  the  Sciences  

  10  

correspondence  truth,  is  that  if  the  institutional  infrastructure  of  science  were  arranged  in  such  a  

way  as  to  make  epistemically  significant  bias  transparent,  then  it  should  be  possible  in  principle  to  

expose  such  bias  and  correct  for  it  where  necessary.  It  is  for  this  reason  that  many  feminist  

philosophers  of  science  advocate  for  institutional  structures  that  would  expose  sources  of  bias.  

Consider,  for  example,  the  idea  of  effective  peer  review,  where  “peers”  are  drawn  from  across  the  

space  of  possible  biases  exemplified  by  human  agents.  The  contention  that  in  many  and  perhaps  

most  domains,  the  sciences  do  not  yet  instantiate  such  structures,  is  one  motivation  for  the  

normative  character  of  most  feminist  critiques.  

  If  epistemically  significant  bias  is  a  fact  of  the  matter  about  much  contemporary  science,  

then  the  prospect  of  scientific  knowledge  of  a  mind-­‐independent  world  is  thereby  diminished  in  

practice  if  not  in  principle.  A  more  in-­‐principle  concern  emerges  from  the  idea  of  perspectives.  For  

just  as  the  Strong  Program  in  SSK  embraces  a  thoroughgoing  relativism,  where  truth  is  defined  only  

within  the  confines  of  a  context  and  not  universally,  some  standpoint  theory  and  certainly  all  

postmodernism  is  likewise  dismissive  of  the  idea  of  standpoint-­‐  or  perspective-­‐independent  truth.  

It  is  important  to  note  here,  however,  that  some  would  reject  this  implication.  Some  standpoint  

theorists,  reflecting  a  Marxist  inspiration,  claim  that  certain  perspectives  are  epistemically  

privileged  over  others  –  typically,  subjugated  perspectives  are  privileged  over  dominant  ones  as  

having  deeper  insight  into  the  subject  matter,  in  just  the  way  that  the  proletariat  might  have  deeper  

knowledge  of  human  potential  than  the  superficial  knowledge  possessed  by  those  in  positions  of  

power.  In  the  absence  of  such  epistemic  privilege,  however,  one  is  left  with  an  irreducibly  fractured  

picture  of  warranted  scientific  belief,  where  (at  best)  coherence  within  perspectives,  not  

correspondence  of  beliefs  from  across  perspectives,  might  serve  as  an  analysis  of  truth.  

 

3.  Truth  as  an  Aim  of  Science  

 

3.1  The  ideal  end  of  inquiry  

 

  Having  canvassed  some  reasons  for  dismissing  the  relevance  of  correspondence  

conceptions  of  truth  in  the  context  of  the  sciences  (in  some  cases,  in  favour  of  a  notion  of  

coherence),  or  for  dispensing  with  concerns  about  truth  altogether,  let  us  turn  now  to  views  in  

which  truth  is  offered  explicitly  as  a  goal  of  scientific  investigation.  One  of  the  most  influential  

themes  to  emerge  in  the  philosophy  of  science  in  this  regard  represents  scientific  inquiry  as  

converging,  ultimately,  on  the  truth.  The  idea  of  convergence  has  two  features  of  particular  

Anjan  Chakravartty          Truth  and  the  Sciences  

  11  

relevance  here.  One  is  that  convergence  is  something  that  can  be  realized  by  a  process  –  in  this  case,  

the  development  of  scientific  knowledge  –  quite  independently  of  whether  the  goal  itself  is  ever  

realized.  (Consider  the  analogy  of  a  mathematical  limit  that  can  be  approached  but  never  quite  

realized,  accept  at  infinity.)  Another  feature  of  interest  here  is  the  broad  compatibility  of  the  notion  

of  convergence  with  different  views  of  science.  Some  scientific  realists,  for  example,  whom  we  will  

consider  in  section  4,  hold  that  scientific  knowledge  is  converging  on  truths  in  the  correspondence  

sense.  But  one  need  not  be  a  realist  of  this  or  any  other  sort  to  think  that  truth  is  the  ultimate  aim  of  

science.  

  An  important  case  in  point  of  non-­‐realist  endorsement  of  convergence  is  associated  with  the  

pragmatist  tradition  in  philosophy.  The  terminology  can  easily  mislead  here,  since  some  self-­‐

avowed  pragmatists  also  refer  to  themselves  as  realists,  but  as  we  shall  see,  their  realism  is  

generally  not  what  goes  by  the  name  ‘scientific  realism’  more  specifically.  One  way  of  generating  

the  distinction,  conveniently  for  present  purposes,  is  to  pay  attention  to  the  theories  of  truth  

typically  endorsed  by  these  camps.  While  scientific  realists  generally  opt  for  some  version  of  the  

correspondence  theory  –  or  if  they  dislike  classical  accounts  of  truth,  some  version  of  truth-­‐maker  

theory  –  pragmatists  generally  do  not.  (This  is  a  traditional  characterization  of  pragmatism;  for  a  

more  nuanced  treatment,  see  Misak  in  this  volume.)  In  order  to  appreciate  the  pragmatist’s  

conception  of  convergence,  let  us  digress  momentarily  to  consider  her  connected  notions  of  

meaning,  and  truth.4  

  As  is  the  case  in  any  grand  philosophical  movement,  not  all  participants  share  precisely  the  

same  view,  but  one  tenet  shared  by  many  if  not  all  pragmatists  is  a  commitment  to  a  criterion  of  

meaning,  whereby  the  content  of  a  proposition  is  given,  as  C.  S.  Peirce  put  it  in  his  essay  ‘How  to  

Make  Our  Ideas  Clear’,  by  clarifying  its  ‘practical  consequences’.  Such  consequences  are  to  be  

understood  in  terms  of  human  experience;  that  is,  as  having  implications  for  actual  or  possible  

empirical  observations.  In  the  context  of  the  sciences,  this  concerns  everything  from  successful  

prediction,  retrodiction,  and  communication,  to  heuristic  use  and  problem  solving,  where  

theoretical  claims  are  employed  as  a  basis  for  action.  In  the  work  of  William  James  in  particular,  this  

analysis  of  meaning  was  parlayed  into  a  theory  of  truth,  according  to  which  positive  utility  of  the  

sort  indicated  by  useful  practical  consequences  is  the  marker  of  truth.  Given  the  fallible  nature  of  

scientific  knowledge,  however,  the  application  of  this  concept  is  conceived  of  by  many  pragmatists  

as  something  of  an  ideal:  truth  is  whatever  it  is  that  will  be  agreed  upon  in  scientific  investigation  in  

                                                                                                                         

4  Here  I  will  focus  on  some  general  pragmatist  principles  drawn  primarily  from  James  1979/1907  and  Peirce  1998/1992,  though  readily  recognizable  in  the  work  of  many  who  have  identified  with  pragmatism  since.  

Anjan  Chakravartty          Truth  and  the  Sciences  

  12  

the  ideal  limit  of  inquiry.  For  both  Peirce  and  James,  the  truth  in  this  sense  exhausts  our  conception  

of  reality,  which  is  made  by  us,  not  mind-­‐independent.  Peirce  in  particular  held  that  through  a  

process  analogous  to  evolution,  scientific  methods  will  converge  on  a  particular  body  of  knowledge.  

In  this  way,  truth  may  be  conceived  as  the  ultimate  aim  of  science.  

  The  evolutionary  analogy  here  is  an  evocative  one,  but  its  appropriateness  in  the  context  of  

scientific  knowledge  may  be  questioned  in  a  number  of  ways,  including  some  we  have  already  

considered.  If  strongly  historicist  readings  of  scientific  knowledge  are  compelling,  for  example,  then  

the  very  idea  of  convergence  is  problematic,  since  in  this  case  it  is  difficult  to  understand  what  it  

could  mean  for  scientific  theories  across  different  periods  of  history  to  be  moving  in  any  particular  

direction.  Indeed,  Kuhn  himself  was  attracted  to  an  evolutionary  picture  of  the  development  of  

scientific  knowledge,  but  of  a  rather  different  sort.  On  our  modern  understanding  of  the  analogue  –  

evolution  by  natural  selection  –  there  is  no  sense  in  which  the  adaptations  of  organisms  are  

“moving”  in  the  direction  of  anything  resembling  a  definitive  ideal.  Adaptations  in  the  biological  

case  are  more  or  less  optimal  only  relative  to  particular  conditions  of  existence  represented  by  

particular  ecological  settings,  and  the  same  sort  of  thing  (mutatis  mutandis)  might  be  thought  true  

of  knowledge  in  historical  settings.  It  is  for  this  reason  that  many  regard  the  evolutionary  analogy  

as  properly  suggesting  only  a  notion  of  progress  from  a  particular  state  of  knowledge,  as  opposed  to  

progress  towards  an  ideal,  and  without  the  latter,  there  can  be  no  convergence.  Similar  appraisals  

can  be  generated  from  the  point  of  view  of  some  social  constructivist  and  feminist  positions,  and  

these  are  contested,  as  we  shall  see,  by  some  varieties  of  realism,  which  like  pragmatism  subscribe  

to  the  idea  of  convergence.  

 

3.2  Constructive  empiricism  and  one  formulation  of  realism  

 

  The  pragmatist  notion  of  truth  in  the  ideal  limit  of  inquiry  is  an  example  of  one  manner  of  

thinking  about  truth  as  an  aim  of  science.  I  have  described  this  manner  above  in  terms  of  

conceptions  of  the  ultimate  aim  of  scientific  investigation.  One  might  think  of  truth  as  a  goal,  

however,  in  rather  different  terms,  as  a  proximate  aim.  That  is  to  say,  one  might  think  that  the  

sciences  aim  at  the  truth  in  the  present,  not  merely  as  an  imagined  outcome  in  a  limit.  Indeed,  it  is  

possible  to  hold  that  truth  is  both  a  proximate  and  an  ultimate  aim  of  science  in  precisely  these  

senses  –  that  by  aiming  at  truth  in  the  present,  one  might  thereby  realize  it  in  the  limit  of  inquiry,  

whether  this  limit  is  held  to  be  an  idealization  (as  suggested  by  Peirce),  or  something  one  might  

think  is  achievable  in  a  finite  time,  or  even  now  with  respect  to  some  scientific  facts,  as  many  (if  not  

Anjan  Chakravartty          Truth  and  the  Sciences  

  13  

all)  realists  contend.  This  combination  of  proximate  and  ultimate  aims  would  seem  to  be  consistent  

with  any  position  that  takes  scientific  knowledge  to  be  converging  on  the  truth,  in  some  way,  shape,  

or  form.  Having  considered  one  version  of  the  idea  that  science  aims  at  truth  in  the  limit,  let  us  turn  

to  the  idea  that  it  aims  at  truth  in  the  here  and  now.  

  Bas  van  Fraassen  (1980)  has  been  influential  in  suggesting  that  different  views  of  the  nature  

of  scientific  knowledge  can  be  described  in  terms  of  how  they  view  the  proximate  aim  of  science.  

This,  I  submit,  is  a  tricky  business,  for  it  is  unclear  why  any  view  of  scientific  knowledge  should  take  

it  to  have  any  one  particular  or  primary  aim,  given  the  many  candidates  that  seem  to  be  

transparently  evident  in  scientific  practice.  Based  on  the  activities  of  scientists,  one  might  plausibly  

contend  that  the  sciences  aim  to  describe,  to  predict,  to  explain,  and  much  more  besides.  Given  this  

plethora  of  aims,  a  question  arises  as  to  what  philosophical  argument  could  establish  the  primacy  of  

any  one  in  particular.  One  possibility  here  would  be  to  argue  that  some  particular,  over-­‐arching,  

epistemic  aim  makes  good  sense  of  scientific  practice  and  its  various  other  aims,  by  accounting  for  

the  latter  aims  as  subsidiary  to  the  former.  Pronouncements  regarding  “the  (proximate)  aim  of  

science”  issuing  from  philosophical  accounts  of  scientific  knowledge  generally  do  not  engage  in  

such  argument,  however,  and  for  this  reason,  any  claim  of  this  sort  must  be  viewed  as  harbouring  a  

significant  promissory  note.  

  Van  Fraassen  offers  a  characterization  of  scientific  knowledge  in  terms  of  aims  on  behalf  of  

two  positions:  his  own  view,  which  he  calls  ‘constructive  empiricism’;  and  the  view  with  which  he  

contrasts  it,  scientific  realism.  The  constructive  empiricist  holds  that  the  aim  of  science  is  empirical  

adequacy,  where  this  is  defined  in  the  following  way:  ‘a  theory  is  empirically  adequate  exactly  if  

what  it  says  about  the  observable  things  and  events  in  the  world,  is  true’  (1980,  p.  12).5  In  contrast,  

realism  is  described  as  the  view  according  to  which  the  aim  of  science  is  truth  simpliciter  –  not  

merely  regarding  scientific  claims  about  observable  things  and  events,  but  also  regarding  claims  

about  unobservable  things  and  events.  In  both  cases,  truth  may  be  understood  in  a  correspondence  

sense,  and  the  distinction  between  the  observable  and  the  unobservable  is  drawn  in  terms  of  

human  sensory  capabilities.  Whatever  is  detectable  by  the  unaided  senses  (such  as  planets,  alpacas,  

and  metals)  is  observable,  and  whatever  is  not  so  detectable  (such  as  dark  matter,  genes,  and  

                                                                                                                         

5  This  definition  suffices  for  present  purposes,  but  it  is  worth  noting  that  van  Fraassen  goes  on  to  define  empirical  adequacy  again  in  more  technical  terms:  a  theory  is  empirically  adequate  if  the  observable  content  of  scientific  investigation  –  ‘the  structures  which  can  be  described  in  experimental  and  measurement  reports’  (1980,  p.  64)  –  are  isomorphic  to  empirical  substructures  of  some  model  or  models  of  the  theory,  where  a  model  is  understood  to  be  any  structure  of  which  the  axioms  and  theorems  associated  with  the  theory  are  true.  The  relevant  empirical  substructures  can  then  be  taken  to  represent  observable  things  and  events.  

Anjan  Chakravartty          Truth  and  the  Sciences  

  14  

neutrons)  is  unobservable.  While  this  particular  opposition  regarding  the  putative  aim  of  science  

has  attracted  significant  attention,  one  could  no  doubt  imagine  other  possible  epistemological  

stances  with  respect  to  scientific  knowledge,  each  defined  by  a  different  proposal  for  the  principal  

aim  of  scientific  investigation.  

  There  is  arguably  good  reason,  however,  to  be  dissatisfied  with  this  strategy  for  defining  

epistemological  positions  such  as  constructive  empiricism  and  scientific  realism.  To  define  an  

epistemological  position  purely  aspirationally  –  that  is,  in  terms  of  aims  –  may  strike  one  as  too  

weak.  For  so  defined,  these  positions  are  consistent  with  never  actually  achieving  the  relevant  aim;  

indeed,  they  are  consistent  with  the  impossibility  of  achieving  the  relevant  aim.  Defined  

aspirationally,  constructive  empiricism  is  consistent  with  the  belief  that  no  scientific  theory  is  

empirically  adequate,  and  with  the  belief  that  no  theory  will  ever  or  could  ever  be  empirically  

adequate.  The  same  moral  would  seem  to  apply  to  realism,  in  connection  with  a  more  

comprehensive  truth  of  theories,  covering  both  the  observable  and  the  unobservable.  This  

separation  of  views  concerning  what  science  aims  to  do  from  those  concerning  what  it  actually  

achieves,  or  is  capable  of  achieving,  is  perfectly  consistent  insofar  as  one  is  interested  in  aims  alone.  

But  from  the  point  of  view  of  epistemology,  it  is  too  weak.  Many  realists,  for  example,  believe  not  

only  that  the  sciences  aspire  to  truth,  but  that  under  certain  conditions,  they  achieve  this  aim,  in  a  

manner  to  be  specified.  Let  us  move  on  now,  to  consider  philosophical  approaches  to  scientific  

knowledge  that  explicitly  adopt  an  achievement  view  of  truth.  

 

4.  Truth  as  an  Achievement  of  Science  

 

4.1  The  many  forms  of  realism  

 

  There  are  many  analyses  of  scientific  knowledge  that  are  or  could  be,  if  interpreted  in  a  

favourable  manner,  consistent  with  the  idea  that  scientific  theories  are  true,  to  some  extent  or  

other.  This  last  qualification,  ‘to  some  extent  or  other’,  introduces  a  complication  which  I  have  thus  

far  ignored,  but  must  now  address.  Those  who  believe  that  the  sciences  yield  truths  are  often  very  

careful  about  how  they  describe  this  commitment  to  truth.  Some  scientific  claims  (for  example,  

certain  claims  about  what  sorts  of  things  exist),  they  might  say,  are  likely  true  simpliciter,  but  others  

(such  as  descriptions  of  laws  of  nature,  or  theories  taken  as  wholes)  are  often  merely  approximately  

true  –  that  is,  close  to  the  truth,  in  some  sense  to  be  explicated.  Convergentists  in  this  camp  then  

commonly  hold  that  scientific  theories  are  becoming  increasingly  approximately  true  over  time,  

Anjan  Chakravartty          Truth  and  the  Sciences  

  15  

with  the  development  of  science.  I  will  return  to  the  idea  of  approximate  truth  in  section  5,  but  let  it  

suffice  here  to  say  that  when  I  describe  views  that  take  truth  to  be  an  achievement  of  the  sciences,  I  

am  including  those  which  subscribe  to  the  of  idea  of  approximate  truth  as  an  appropriate  surrogate  

for  truth  simpliciter,  as  and  where  appropriate.    

  A  further  qualification  is  in  order  here,  concerning  the  breadth  of  positions  that  might,  on  a  

favourable  interpretation,  qualify  as  admitting  scientific  truths.  Many  so-­‐called  antirealist  positions  

in  the  philosophy  of  science  are  consistent  with  scientific  truth,  but  only  regarding  a  very  specific  

domain:  the  observable.  Instrumentalism,  for  example,  is  the  view  that  scientific  theories  are  simply  

instruments  for  predicting  observable  phenomena,  or  for  systematizing  observation  reports.  On  a  

traditional  reading,  this  view  also  holds  that  claims  pertaining  to  unobservable  things,  by  

themselves,  have  no  meaning  at  all  –  they  are  merely  instruments,  not  candidates  for  truth  or  

falsity.  Less  traditionally,  positions  are  sometimes  described  as  instrumentalist  if  they  admit  

epistemic  access  only  to  truths  about  observables;  claims  about  unobservables  here  may  be  true  or  

false,  but  the  relevant  truth  value  cannot  be  known.  In  either  case,  it  is  open  to  an  instrumentalist  to  

believe  that  the  sciences  yield  truths  about  observables  in  the  correspondence  sense.  Others,  such  

as  some  logical  empiricists,  might  agree,  but  only  insofar  as  truth  is  understood  in  terms  of  

coherence,  in  accordance  with  some  or  other  form  of  neo-­‐Kantianism.  Others,  such  as  Kuhn,  might  

extend  the  remit  of  the  neo-­‐Kantian-­‐coherence-­‐type  approach  to  truth  to  the  unobservable,  but  

only  within  periods  of  normal  science.  As  should  be  clear,  the  possible  combinations  of  restriction  

on  the  domain  of  truth,  and  theory  of  truth  applicable,  are  many!6  

  The  most  unequivocal  commitment  to  truth  talk  in  connection  with  the  sciences,  however,  

is  exemplified  by  versions  of  scientific  realism.  Most  realists  suggest,  either  explicitly  or  implicitly,  

that  our  best  scientific  theories  are  true  or  approximately  true  in  some  appropriate  sense  of  

correspondence  with  a  mind-­‐independent  world.7  Understood  this  way,  scientific  realism  is  

the  view  that  scientific  theories  correctly  describe  both  observable  and  unobservable  features  of  

the  world.  The  main  consideration  offered  in  support  of  realism  is  an  old  idea,  resonant  with  

common  sense,  to  the  effect  that  the  very  empirical  success  of  science  –  in  prediction  and                                                                                                                            

6  For  a  formative  influence  on  instrumentalism,  see  Duhem  1954/1906.  For  discussion  of  the  neo-­‐Kantian  reading  of  logical  empiricism,  see  Richardson  1998  and  Friedman  1999,  and  for  a  reading  more  compatible  with  realism,  see  Psillos  forthcoming.  The  neo-­‐Kantian  theme  is  developed  differently  under  the  label  ‘internal  realism’  in  Putnam  1981.  For  a  consideration  of  fictionalism,  which  holds  that  things  in  the  world  are  and  behave  is  as  if  our  best  scientific  theories  are  true  (thus  admitting  truths  about  observables),  see  Vaihinger  1923/1911  and  Fine  1993.  7  There  are  exceptions,  however.  For  arguments  in  favour  of  separating  realism  from  the  correspondence  theory  of  truth,  see  Ellis  1988,  Leeds  2007,  and  Devitt  2010  (especially  chapters  2  and  4).  I  will  return  to  this  idea  in  another  form  in  section  5.  

Anjan  Chakravartty          Truth  and  the  Sciences  

  16  

manipulation  of  the  natural  world,  not  to  mention  technological  applications  –  indicates  that  its  

theories  are  true.  In  recent  times  this  idea  is  commonly  referred  to  as  the  ‘miracle  argument’  (or  

‘no-­‐miracles  argument’),  after  Hilary  Putnam’s  (1975,  p.  73)  contention  that  realism  ‘is  the  only  

philosophy  that  doesn’t  make  the  success  of  science  a  miracle’.  In  other  words,  it  would  be  

miraculous  if  the  sciences  were  as  empirically  successful  as  they  are,  and  yet  their  theories  were  

untrue,  thus  suggesting  the  greater  credibility  of  an  explanation  of  success  that  appeals  to  truth.  As  

we  shall  see  momentarily,  however,  the  miracle  argument  is  highly  contested.  

  As  it  happens,  there  are  many  varieties  of  scientific  realism,  some  developed  with  the  

intention  of  responding  to  forms  of  antirealist  scepticism  such  as  that  concerning  the  miracle  

argument.  The  most  general  form  of  realism  subscribes  to  the  formula  I  have  already  presented:  a  

general  endorsement  of  the  truth  of  our  best  scientific  theories.  Of  the  variations  on  this  formula  to  

emerge,  two  in  particular  have  come  to  prominence  in  recent  philosophy  of  science,  both  of  which  

offer  a  more  specific  prescription  for  realist  commitment.  Entity  realism  is  the  view  that  under  

conditions  in  which  one  has  significant  causal  knowledge  of  a  putative  (unobservable)  entity,  

allowing  one  (ex  hypothesi)  to  manipulate  it  and  use  it  to  intervene  in  other  phenomena,  one  has  

good  reason  to  think  it  exists,  and  consequently,  that  claims  about  the  existence  of  such  entities  are  

true.  The  negative  implication  of  this  commitment  is  that  the  theories  that  describe  these  entities  

need  not  be  true,  and  this  raises  a  question  about  whether  an  antirealism  about  theories  is  

ultimately  compatible  with  a  realism  about  the  entities  they  describe.  This  view  also  appears  to  

entail  that  one  may  continue  to  believe  in  the  existence  of  an  entity  despite  radical  changes  in  one’s  

(theoretical)  understanding  of  what  that  entity  is  like.  This  in  particular  might  seem  problematic  

from  a  historicist  point  of  view,  or  indeed,  from  any  point  of  view  that  takes  accurate  description  to  

be  an  important  component  of  successful  reference  to  an  entity.  

  A  second  more  specific  version  of  realism  is  structural  realism,  which  holds  that  insofar  as  

scientific  theories  offer  true  descriptions,  they  do  not  tell  us  about  the  natures  of  things  like  

unobservable  entities.  Instead,  they  correctly  describe  the  structure  of  the  unobservable  realm.  

There  are  two  main  sorts  of  structural  realist  positions:  those  that  take  the  distinction  between  

structure  and  nature  to  be  an  epistemic  distinction;  and  those  that  take  it  to  be  an  ontological  

distinction.  The  former  suggest  that  knowledge  of  the  entities  that  participate  in  the  structural  

relations  described  by  theories  (for  example,  by  mathematical  laws)  is  simply  beyond  our  grasp,  

but  that  theories  furnish  a  kind  of  structural  knowledge  nonetheless.  The  latter  suggest  that  

structural  knowledge  is  the  most  a  realist  can  hope  for,  because  there  are  in  fact  no  entities  that  

stand  in  those  relations,  or  that  if  there  are  such  entities,  they  are  in  some  sense  emergent  from  or  

Anjan  Chakravartty          Truth  and  the  Sciences  

  17  

dependent  on  the  structures  in  which  they  seem  to  appear.  Like  entity  realism,  structural  realism  

faces  interesting  challenges.  One  might  wonder,  for  example,  about  how  clear  the  distinction  

between  structure  and  nature  is,  or  whether  this  distinction  is  tenable  in  connection  with  the  

concrete  systems  of  things  investigated  by  the  sciences.  The  ontological  version  specifically  faces  

the  challenge  of  making  the  relevant  ideas  of  emergence  and  dependence  of  entities  intelligible.8  

 

4.2  Scepticism  about  realism  

 

  Entity  realism  and  structural  realism  each  face  challenges  aimed  at  the  coherence  of  their  

specific  formulations  of  realist  commitment.  Additionally,  it  is  important  to  note  that  all  the  reasons  

we  encountered  earlier  for  being  suspicious  of  the  notion  of  correspondence  truth,  in  connection  

with  different  views  regarding  the  nature  of  scientific  knowledge,  are  also  ultimately  challenges  to  

scientific  realism  as  it  is  usually  conceived.  Often,  in  the  background  of  these  worries,  are  more  

general  sceptical  concerns  about  scientific  knowledge  that  any  realism  must  face  if  it  is  to  be  

defensible.  Indeed,  the  advent  of  both  entity  realism  and  structural  realism  was  intended,  in  part,  to  

offer  responses  to  some  of  these  more  general  concerns.  I  will  not  here  consider  whether  or  to  what  

extent  they  are  successful  in  this  regard,  but  given  the  importance  of  these  concerns  to  motivating  

(sometimes  explicitly  but  often  implicitly)  a  number  of  the  antirealist  positions  we  encountered  

earlier,  let  us  consider  them  briefly.  This  more  general  antirealist  scepticism  stems  from  three  

notable  issues:  the  ubiquitous  use  in  science  of  a  form  of  reasoning  called  inference  to  the  best  

explanation;  the  so-­‐called  underdetermination  of  theories  by  data;  and  discontinuities  in  scientific  

theories  over  time.  

  Scientific  inferences  are  generally  inductive.  One  is  rarely  if  ever  in  a  position  to  generate  

scientific  conclusions,  laws,  theories,  and  so  on,  by  means  of  arguments  that  are  deductively  valid.  

Instead,  one  marshals  evidence  by  means  of  observation  and  experiment,  and  reasons  on  the  basis  

of  this  and  other  commitments  to  conclusions  that  are,  ideally,  inductively  strong.  In  the  sciences,  a  

particular  form  of  inductive  inference  is  prevalent,  viz.  inference  to  the  best  explanation,  according  

to  which  one  infers  hypotheses  that,  if  true,  would  provide  the  best  explanation  for  whatever  it  is  

that  one  is  attempting  to  explain.  Natural  though  this  pattern  of  inference  may  be,  antirealists  have  

                                                                                                                         

8  For  a  defence  of  scientific  realism,  see  Psillos  1999.  For  a  discussion  of  novel  predictions,  often  invoked  in  characterizing  what  it  might  mean  for  something  to  be  one  of  our  best  theories,  see  Leplin  1997.  Cartwright  1983  and  Hacking  1983  are  definitional  texts  for  entity  realism,  as  are  Worrall  1989,  French  1998,  and  Ladyman  &  Ross  2007  for  structural  realism.  For  a  discussion  of  the  relationships  between  scientific  realism,  entity  realism,  and  structural  realism,  see  Chakravartty  2007.  

Anjan  Chakravartty          Truth  and  the  Sciences  

  18  

been  quick  to  point  out  two  potential  difficulties  with  it  in  connection  with  truth.  First,  in  order  that  

one  infer  the  truth,  one  must  have  the  capacity  to  rank  rival  hypotheses  reliably  with  respect  to  

their  likelihood  of  being  true.  But  what  assurance  is  there  that  the  sorts  of  criteria  typically  

employed  in  the  sciences  for  purposes  of  ranking  –  the  simplicity  of  a  hypothesis,  its  consistency  

with  other  hypotheses  one  may  like,  its  heuristic  value,  and  so  on  –  are  indicative  of  truth?  And  

even  if  one  were  to  grant  that  the  criteria  for  choice  employed  in  scientific  practice  are  truth-­‐

tracking,  in  order  for  inference  to  the  best  explanation  to  result  in  true  belief,  it  is  imperative  that  

the  true  hypothesis  be  among  those  one  is  considering.  But  this,  arguably,  is  not  generally  

something  one  can  know  in  advance.9  

  Moving  on  now  to  our  second  sceptical  concern,  the  idea  of  the  underdetermination  of  theory  

by  data,  derived  from  the  work  of  Pierre  Duhem,  runs  this  way.10  Scientific  hypotheses  do  not  yield  

predictions  all  by  themselves.  In  order  to  derive  predictions,  they  must  be  conjoined  with  background  

theories,  other  theories,  theories  about  instruments  and  measurements,  and  so  on.  Now,  if  observation  

and  experiment  result  in  data  that  do  not  agree  with  one’s  predictions,  what  part  of  one’s  scientific  

belief  set  should  one  adjust  accordingly?  Naively,  one  might  think  that  the  hypothesis  under  test  

should  now  be  viewed  suspiciously,  but  Duhem  points  out  that  given  all  of  the  things  one  must  assume  

in  order  to  derive  the  faulty  prediction  in  the  first  place,  it  is  not  so  obvious  which  part  of  this  

apparatus  deserves  suspicion.  Different  adjustments  to  one’s  belief  set  –  different  overall  conjunctions  

of  hypotheses  and  theories  –  will  be  consistent  with  the  data.  Therefore,  there  is  always  more  than  one  

overall  set  of  beliefs  that  is  consistent  with  the  data.  In  more  contemporary  discussions,  

underdetermination  is  usually  presented  slightly  differently,  in  terms  of  the  idea  that  every  scientific  

theory  has  empirically  equivalent  rivals:  ones  that  agree  with  respect  to  the  observable,  but  differ  

elsewhere.  This  then  serves  as  the  basis  for  a  sceptical  argument  regarding  the  truth  of  any  particular  

rival  chosen  for  belief.  It  is  precisely  this  sort  of  scepticism  that  underwrites  the  worries  about  

correspondence  truth  commonly  found  in  SSK  and  feminist  critiques  of  science.  

  Finally,  let  us  turn  to  an  argument  that  is  often  simply  referred  to  as  the  ‘pessimistic  

induction’,  or  the  ‘pessimistic  meta-­‐induction’.  The  history  of  the  sciences  is  replete  with  

discontinuities  in  the  knowledge  they  ostensibly  provide.  Over  time,  older  theories  recede  into  the  

past  as  newer  theories  are  proposed  and  accepted,  resulting  in  changes  in  belief  with  respect  to  the  

                                                                                                                         

9  For  a  thorough  exploration  of  inference  to  the  best  explanation,  see  Lipton  2004,  and  for  an  influential  critique  of  it,  see  van  Fraassen  1989,  chapter  6.  10  The  idea  of  underdetermination  is  commonly  traced  to  Duhem  1954/1906,  chapter  6,  and  many  see  affinities  here  with  the  later  “confirmational  holism”  of  W.  V.  O.  Quine  (1953).  For  this  reason,  it  is  sometimes  called  the  ‘Duhem-­‐Quine  thesis’.  

Anjan  Chakravartty          Truth  and  the  Sciences  

  19  

entities,  their  properties  and  relations,  and  laws  described  by  these  theories.  Thus,  from  the  point  

of  view  of  any  given  moment  in  time,  most  past  theories  must  be  considered  false,  strictly  speaking.  

By  induction,  then,  is  it  not  likely  that  most  present-­‐day  theories  are  also  false?  The  ways  in  which  

they  will,  in  future,  be  revealed  as  false  may  not  yet  be  clear  to  us,  but  the  inductive  challenge  

remains.  Given  a  knowledge  of  the  history  of  theorizing  in  any  particular  domain  of  scientific  

investigation,  realism  may  thus  appear  a  rather  too  optimistic  position  regarding  scientific  

knowledge.  This  general  sceptical  worry  can  be  posed  in  a  number  of  different  ways,  focusing  on  

the  falsity  of  past  theories,  unsuccessful  reference  on  the  part  of  their  central  terms,  and  in  other  

ways  besides.11  

  Worries  about  inference  to  the  best  explanation,  the  underdetermination  of  theory  by  data,  

and  the  pessimistic  induction  have  been  highly  influential  in  the  philosophy  of  science.  It  would  be  

irresponsible  not  to  mention,  however,  that  realists  of  various  stripes  have  responded  to  these  

concerns  in  a  number  of  ways,  and  the  ensuing  debates  are  very  much  alive.  A  thorough  canvassing  

of  the  details  of  these  debates  lies  far  beyond  the  scope  of  this  essay  –  indeed,  these  details  

comprise  a  large  proportion  of  the  field  itself.  I  hope,  however,  that  the  ways  in  which  the  notion  of  

truth  bears  on  the  sciences  is  now  substantially  clearer  than  when  we  began.  My  aims  in  this  regard  

now  largely  fulfilled,  let  us  turn  in  the  next  and  final  section  to  a  few  important  considerations  

involving  truth  to  emerge  in  areas  of  very  recent  interest  in  the  philosophy  of  science.  

 

5.  Truth  and  scientific  models  

 

5.1  Abstraction  and  idealization  

 

  One  of  the  most  important  developments  in  the  philosophy  of  science  over  the  past  two  

decades  has  been  an  increasing  awareness  and  study  of  the  role  of  scientific  models  in  discussions  

of  scientific  knowledge.  In  keeping  with  a  general  movement  towards  closer  attention  to  scientific  

practice  in  the  wake  of  the  historical  turn,  a  traditional  emphasis  on  knowledge  encapsulated  by  

scientific  theories  has  been  supplemented  (and  perhaps,  in  some  authors’  estimations,  replaced)  by  

an  emphasis  on  the  ways  in  which  models  associated  with  these  theories  are  used  to  represent  

target  systems  in  the  world.  One  reason  for  this,  no  doubt,  is  that  ‘scientific  theory’  is  a  somewhat  

loosely  defined  concept  –  its  referents  vary  significantly  depending  on  the  context  of  its  use.  One                                                                                                                            

11  Canonical  formulations  of  the  pessimistic  induction  are  most  often  drawn  from  Laudan  1981.  For  a  related  and  more  recent  version  of  history-­‐induced  scepticism,  see  Stanford  2006.  

Anjan  Chakravartty          Truth  and  the  Sciences  

  20  

and  the  same  theory  may  be  identified  in  some  cases  with  a  set  of  equations,  and  in  other  cases  with  

various  models  applied  to  different  classes  of  phenomena  putatively  described  by  those  equations,  

but  in  different  ways.  These  different  adaptations  of  mathematical  descriptions  to  fit  particular  

sorts  of  cases  –  sometimes  even  in  ways  that  are  mutually  inconsistent  –  suggests  that  in  many  

situations,  it  is  the  models  themselves  that  are  the  primary  representational  tools  of  scientific  

description.  Thus,  a  spotlight  is  turned  onto  the  relationship  between  modelling  and  truth.  

  The  term  ‘scientific  model’  covers  many  things  here.  It  includes:  abstract  entities,  such  as  

theoretical  models  about  which  scientists  may  have  some  shared  conception;  concrete  objects,  such  

as  graphs,  diagrams,  other  illustrations,  and  three-­‐dimensional  physical  representations,  such  as  

scale  models;  and  processes,  such  as  computer  simulations.  Though  the  forms  of  these  

representations  are  many,  the  question  of  how  they  can  be  thought  to  represent  their  targets  

veridically,  if  at  all,  has  become  a  central  topic  of  debate,  not  least  because,  as  it  happens,  scientific  

models  are  often  constructed  so  as  to  deviate  from  the  truth.  There  are  two  primary  ways  in  which  

this  occurs,  and  I  will  call  these  practices  abstraction  and  idealization.  Although  these  are  terms  of  

art,  used  in  slightly  different  ways  by  a  growing  number  of  philosophers,  there  is  something  of  a  

consensus  regarding  the  basic  distinction.  For  purposes  of  illustration,  I  will  sketch  a  representative  

version  of  this  distinction  below.12  

  ‘Abstraction’  and  ‘idealization’  can  be  thought  of  as  labelling  processes  –  ones  by  means  of  

which  models  are  constructed  –  as  well  as  the  resultant  models  themselves.  Thus,  an  abstract  

model  is  the  result  of  a  process  of  abstraction,  a  process  in  which  only  some  of  the  potentially  many  

factors  that  are  relevant  to  the  nature  or  behaviour  of  something  in  the  world  are  represented  in  a  

model  of  it.  In  the  process  of  abstraction,  other  factors  are  ignored,  often  intentionally,  in  order  to  

allow  for  the  construction  of  models  that  are  mathematically  or  otherwise  tractable;  and  often  

relevant  factors  are  unintentionally  ignored,  because  their  relevance  is  unknown.  Consider,  for  

example,  the  model  of  a  simple  pendulum.  Many  simplifying  assumptions  are  made  in  constructing  

this  model,  such  as  the  omission  of  frictional  resistance  due  to  the  air  in  which  the  pendulum  

swings.  Such  assumptions  are  commonly  held  to  compromise  the  truth  of  models  not  only  because  

theoretically  important  aspects  of  their  target  systems  in  the  world  are  left  out,  but  also  because,  as  

a  result,  the  predictions  of  these  models  differ  from  that  which  one  finds  in  reality.  One  might  argue  

that  in  both  of  these  ways,  abstraction  introduces  falsehood  into  practices  of  scientific  

                                                                                                                         

12  For  influential  discussions  in  this  area,  see  McMullin  1985,  Cartwright  1989  (chapter  5),  and  Suppe  1989  (pp.  82-­‐83,  94-­‐99).  For  a  comprehensive  treatment,  see  Jones  2005.  My  take  on  the  distinction  here  is  abridged  from  Chakravartty  2010a,  which  considers  the  implications  for  truth  in  some  detail.  

Anjan  Chakravartty          Truth  and  the  Sciences  

  21  

representation.  By  the  same  token,  however,  the  notion  of  abstraction  suggests  one  way  of  making  

sense  of  the  idea  that  one  representation  can  be  more  approximately  true  than  another:  by  

incorporating  a  greater  number  of  factors  that  are  causally  (or  otherwise)  relevant  to  their  natures  

or  behaviours.  

  Similarly,  an  idealized  model  is  the  result  of  a  process  of  idealization,  a  process  in  which  at  

least  one  of  the  features  of  the  target  system  incorporated  into  the  model  is  represented  in  a  

distorted  or  simplified  manner.  This  process  differs  from  abstraction  in  that  one  is  not  excluding  

factors,  but  rather  incorporating  them  in  such  a  manner  as  to  represent  them  in  ways  they  are  not.  

(In  order  to  sharpen  the  distinction  between  abstraction  and  idealization  further,  I  view  the  latter  

in  terms  of  representing  things  in  ways  they  could  not  be,  given  the  laws  of  nature.  This  is  

sometimes  but  not  always  true  of  abstract  models:  some  abstract  descriptions  may  be  true  of  other  

systems  in  the  world  in  which  the  omitted  factors  happen  not  to  be  present,  which  is  something  

scientists  often  contrive  in  laboratory  settings.  In  any  case,  given  that  abstraction  and  idealization  

are  not  mutually  exclusive  processes,  some  models  may  be  both  abstract  and  idealized.)  Idealized  

models  are,  in  a  stronger  sense  than  in  the  case  of  abstractions,  false  representations  of  things  in  

the  world.  It  is  an  implicit  assumption  of  classical  physics,  for  example,  that  the  masses  of  bodies  

are  concentrated  at  extensionless  points  at  their  centres  of  gravity,  but  this  is  something  we  clearly  

know  to  be  false,  notwithstanding  the  predictive  and  explanatory  efficacy  of  models  in  classical  

physics.  In  such  cases,  understanding  how  one  model  can  be  more  approximately  true  than  another  

is  more  complex  than  in  the  case  of  abstraction,  turning  on  how  “degrees”  of  distortion  may  be  

conceived  in  particular  cases.  

 

5.2  Approximate  truth  and  deflation  

 

  The  notion  of  approximate  truth  is  generally  viewed  as  important  to  scientific  realism,  

versions  of  which,  as  we  have  seen,  are  commonly  more  interested  to  characterize  scientific  

knowledge  in  terms  of  truth  than  any  other  philosophical  assessment  of  the  sciences.  The  apparent  

importance  of  approximate  truth  here  is  plain,  given  that  even  realists  must  acknowledge  that  

many  if  not  all  scientific  theories  contain  falsehoods,  and  are  thus,  strictly  speaking,  false.  The  task  

of  reconciling  the  realist’s  positive  appraisal  of  scientific  knowledge  in  terms  of  truth  with  such  

obviously  recalcitrant  evidence  of  falsity  provides  strong  motivation  for  thinking  about  how  one  

theory  can  be  “better  off”  than  another  with  respect  to  truth,  even  when  both  are  false.  

Anjan  Chakravartty          Truth  and  the  Sciences  

  22  

  The  concept  of  approximate  truth,  and  others  such  as  ‘verisimilitude’  and  ‘truthlikeness’  

(sometimes  used  synonymously  with  ‘approximate  truth’  and  in  other  cases  not,  reflecting  the  

intentions  of  different  authors),  have  become  subjects  of  detailed  and  technically  striking  work  in  

their  own  right.  I  will  not  consider  these  developments  here  (but  another  essay  in  this  volume  does;  

see  Oddie).  Instead,  my  goal  in  this  last  section  is  to  complete  an  examination  of  the  implications  of  

the  recent  interest  in  scientific  modelling  for  considerations  of  approximate  truth,  and  for  truth  

more  generally.  For  some  advocates  of  the  modelling  conception  of  science  hold  that  once  one  

appreciates  how  models  are  used  to  represent  things  in  the  world,  all  substantive  concerns  about  

truth  in  this  context  are  dissolved.  These  concerns  arise  in  the  face  of  two  challenges:  first,  the  

challenge  of  explicating  the  notion  of  correspondence  truth;  and  second,  the  challenge  of  explicating  

the  notion  of  approximate  truth.  Given  the  difficulties  inherent  in  both  of  these  challenges,  if  it  were  

the  case  that  paying  attention  to  practices  of  scientific  modelling  could  obviate  the  need  to  meet  

them,  this  would  be  a  significant  result.  Let  us  consider  the  prospects  for  doing  so.  

  The  most  straightforward  exposition  of  the  idea  that  considerations  of  scientific  modelling  

dissolve  substantive  issues  of  truth  for  the  realist  is  found  in  the  work  of  Ronald  Giere,  on  whose  

view  a  scientific  theory  is  constituted  by  ‘two  elements:  (1)  a  population  of  models,  and  (2)  various  

hypotheses  linking  those  models  with  systems  in  the  real  world’  (1988,  p.  85).13  Hypotheses  assert  

relationships  of  similarity  between  aspects  of  models  and  their  target  systems,  and  are  true  or  false  

depending  on  whether  these  relationships  obtain.  It  is  the  fact  that  models  are  the  tools  by  means  of  

which  these  epistemic  commitments  are  expressed  that  dissolves  concerns  about  truth,  or  so  the  

argument  goes.  On  this  approach,  Giere  contends,  there  is  no  question  of  attempting  to  forge  any  

sort  of  correspondence  between  linguistic  entities  and  the  world,  and  consequently,  the  challenge  

to  explicate  the  notion  of  correspondence  truth  does  not  even  arise.  All  that  is  required  are  

assertions  of  similarity  between  models  and  the  world,  and  for  this  a  deflationary  account  of  truth  

will  suffice.  

  Deflationism  about  truth  holds  that  there  is  nothing  metaphysically  substantive  (such  as  the  

notion  of  correspondence)  to  the  idea  of  truth  (see  Azzouni  in  this  volume).  One  influential  version  

of  the  view  suggests  that  the  predicate  ‘is  true’  in  ‘α  is  true’  is  redundant;  it  adds  nothing  to  the  

meaning  or  the  assertion  of  ‘α’.  Thus,  to  say  that  it  is  true  that  a  two-­‐body  Newtonian  gravitational  

model  is  similar  in  various  ways  to  the  system  comprising  the  earth  and  moon,  for  example,  is                                                                                                                            

13  Giere  refines  this  portrait  of  scientific  theories  in  subsequent  work,  but  the  refinements  are  immaterial  for  present  purposes.  For  his  most  developed  view  of  scientific  knowledge  borne  of  modelling,  see  Giere  2006,  and  for  an  appraisal  of  this  sort  of  approach,  see  Chakravartty  2010b.  For  a  longer  discussion  of  modelling,  correspondence,  and  approximate  truth,  see  Chakravartty  2007,  sections  7.4-­‐7.5.    

Anjan  Chakravartty          Truth  and  the  Sciences  

  23  

simply  to  say  that  these  similarities  obtain  –  the  truth  predicate  is  redundant.  And  once  scientific  

claims  take  the  form  of  asserted  model  similarities,  clarified  in  terms  of  respects  and  degrees  of  

similarity,  the  need  for  an  overarching  account  of  approximate  truth  is  likewise  superfluous,  or  so  

one  might  argue.  

  The  modelling  approach  facilitates  many  important  insights  into  the  nature  of  scientific  

knowledge,  but  it  does  not,  I  suspect,  make  the  issue  of  correspondence  disappear  for  the  realist.  

Whether  one  prefers  to  think  of  correspondence  in  terms  of  a  property  shared  by  all  truth-­‐bearers,  

or  in  terms  of  the  existence  of  truth-­‐makers  for  scientific  claims,  some  form  of  correspondence  is  a  

requirement  of  realism.  As  a  quick  demonstration  of  the  insufficiency  of  asserted  model  similarities  

in  this  context,  consider  the  claim  that  the  double-­‐helical  structure  of  Watson  and  Crick’s  physical  

model  of  the  DNA  molecule  is  similar  to  the  double-­‐helical  structure  of  DNA  molecules.  Most  

scientific  realists  would  endorse  this  claim,  but  so  too  would  most  traditional  instrumentalists.  The  

assertion  of  similarity  here  does  not  by  itself  distinguish  the  different  ontological  significance  these  

different  parties  attach  to  it.  For  the  realist,  the  assertion  of  similarity  is  interpreted  as  truly  

describing  the  properties  of  an  unobservable  entity,  whereas  for  the  instrumentalist,  it  is  

interpreted  as  asserting  something  that  is  neither  true  nor  false,  but  useful  as  a  vehicle  for  the  

derivation  of  observable  predictions.  It  is  only  by  admitting  the  relevance  of  considerations  of  

correspondence,  in  one  form  or  another,  that  allows  one  to  distinguish  these  interpretations.  

  Neither  does  the  possibility  of  describing  similarities  between  scientific  models  and  their  

target  systems  eliminate  the  yearning  for  an  account  of  approximate  truth.  Though  similarities  of  

this  sort  are  the  bread  and  butter  of  scientific  representation,  there  are  undoubtedly  other  

epistemic  contexts,  of  a  broader  and  grander  sort,  in  which  scientists  and  philosophers  alike  find  

themselves,  understandably,  reflecting  on  the  notion  of  truth.  Stepping  back  from  the  minutiae  of  

particular  representations  to  the  world  of  scientific  knowledge  more  broadly  conceived,  there  are  

contexts  within  which  it  is  entirely  appropriate  to  contend  that  relativistic  physics  is  closer  to  the  

truth  than  classical  physics,  or  that  the  modern  synthesis  in  evolutionary  biology  is  closer  to  the  

truth  of  the  nature  of  organisms  and  their  populations  than  biology  before  Darwin.  It  is  precisely  

this  sense  of  progress  that  is  celebrated  by  many  realists,  and  in  different  ways  by  other  

convergentists,  and  disputed  by  varieties  of  historicists  and  social  constructivists.  It  is  this  sense  of  

truth  that  is  the  subject  of  so  many  of  our  most  important  and  productive  philosophical  disputes  

about  the  relationship  of  truth  to  the  sciences.  

 

 

Anjan  Chakravartty          Truth  and  the  Sciences  

  24  

Acknowledgments  

 

For  helpful  comments  on  an  earlier  version  of  this  essay,  I  am  grateful  to  Agnes  Bolinska  and  

Michael  Glanzberg.  

 

References  

 Alcoff,  L.  &  E.  Potter  (eds.)  1993:  Feminist  Epistemologies,  London:  Routledge.    Azzouni,  J.  2011:  ‘Deflationism’,  in  M.  Glanzberg  (ed.),  The  Oxford  Handbook  of  Truth.  Oxford:  Oxford  University  Press.    Barnes,  B.,  B.  Bloor  &  J.  Henry  1996:  Scientific  Knowledge,  London:  Athlone.    Bird,  A.  2000:  Thomas  Kuhn.  Chesham:  Acumen.    Cartwright,  N.  1983:  How  the  Laws  of  Physics  Lie.  Oxford:  Clarendon  Press.    Cartwright,  N.  1989:  Nature’s  Capacities  and  Their  Measurement.  Oxford:  Clarendon.    Chakravartty,  A.  2007:  A  Metaphysics  for  Scientific  Realism:  Knowing  the  Unobservable.  Cambridge:  Cambridge  University  Press.    Chakravartty,  A.  2010a:  ‘Truth  and  Representation  in  Science:  Two  Inspirations  from  Art’,  in  R.  Frigg  &  M.  Hunter  (eds.),  Beyond  Mimesis  and  Convention:  Representation  in  Art  and  Science,  pp.  33-­‐50.  Boston  Studies  in  the  Philosophy  of  Science.  Dordrecht:  Springer.    Chakravartty,  A.  2010b:  ‘Perspectivism,  Inconsistent  Models,  and  Contrastive  Explanation’,  Studies  in  History  and  Philosophy  of  Science  41:  405-­‐412.    Collins,  H.  &  T.  J.  Pinch  1993:  The  Golem.  Cambridge:  Cambridge  University  Press.    David,  M.  2011:  ‘The  Correspondence  Theory  of  Truth’,  in  M.  Glanzberg  (ed.),  The  Oxford  Handbook  of  Truth.  Oxford:  Oxford  University  Press.    Devitt,  M.  2010:  Putting  Metaphysics  First:  Essays  on  Metaphysics  and  Epistemology.  Oxford:  Oxford  University  Press.    Duhem,  P.  M.  M.  1954/1906:  The  Aim  and  Structure  of  Physical  Theory,  P.  P.  Wiener  (tr.).  Princeton:  Princeton  University  Press.    Ellis,  B.  1988:  ‘Internal  Realism’,  Synthese  76:  409-­‐434.    Fine,  A.  1993:  ‘Fictionalism’,  Midwest  Studies  in  Philosophy  18:  1-­‐18.    van  Fraassen,  B.  C.  1980:  The  Scientific  Image.  Oxford:  Clarendon.    

Anjan  Chakravartty          Truth  and  the  Sciences  

  25  

van  Fraassen,  B.  C.  1989:  Laws  and  Symmetry.  Oxford:  Clarendon.    French,  S.  1998:  ‘On  the  Withering  Away  of  Physical  Objects’,  in  E.  Castellani  (ed.),  Interpreting  Bodies:  Classical  and  Quantum  Objects  in  Modern  Physics,  pp.  93-­‐113.  Princeton:  Princeton  University  Press.    Friedman,  M.  1999:  Reconsidering  Logical  Positivism.  Cambridge:  Cambridge  University  Press.    Giere,  R.  N.  1988:  Explaining  Science:  A  Cognitive  Approach.  Chicago:  University  of  Chicago  Press.    Giere,  R.  N.  2006:  Scientific  Perspectivism.  Chicago:  University  of  Chicago  Press.    Hacking,  I.  1983:  Representing  and  Intervening.  Cambridge:  Cambridge  University  Press.    Harding,  S.  1986:  The  Science  Question  in  Feminism.  Ithaca:  Cornell  University  Press.    Haraway,  D.  1988.  ‘Situated  Knowledges’,  Feminist  Studies  14:  575-­‐600.    Horwich,  P.  (ed.)  1993:  World  Changes:  Thomas  Kuhn  and  the  Nature  of  Science.  Cambridge,  MA:  MIT  Press.    Hoyningen-­‐Huene,  P.  1993:  Reconstructing  Scientific  Revolutions:  The  Philosophy  of  Science  of  Thomas  S.  Kuhn.  Chicago:  University  of  Chicago  Press.    James,  W.  1979/1907:  Pragmatism.  Cambridge,  MA:  Harvard  University  Press.    Jones,  M.  R.  2005:  ‘Idealization  and  Abstraction:  A  Framework’,  in  M.  R.  Jones  &  N.  Cartwright  (eds.),  Idealization  XII:  Correcting  the  Model,  Poznań  Studies  in  the  Philosophy  of  the  Sciences  and  the  Humanities  86:  173-­‐217.    Keller,  E.  F.  1985:  Reflections  on  Gender  and  Science.  New  Haven:  Yale  University  Press.    Knorr-­‐Cetina,  K.  1981:  The  Manufacture  of  Knowledge.  Oxford:  Pergamon.    Kuhn,  T.  1970/1962:  The  Structure  of  Scientific  Revolutions.  Chicago:  University  of  Chicago  Press.    Kuhn,  T.  S.  1983:  ‘Commensurability,  Comparability,  Communicability’,  PSA  1982:  669-­‐688.    Ladyman,  J.  &  D.  Ross  2007:  Everything  Must  Go:  Metaphysics  Naturalized.  Oxford:  Oxford  University  Press.    Latour,  B  &  S.  Woolgar  1986:  Laboratory  Life:  The  Construction  of  Scientific  Facts  (2nd  ed.).  Princeton:  Princeton  University  Press.    Laudan,  L.  1981:  ‘A  Confutation  of  Convergent  Realism’,  Philosophy  of  Science  48:  19-­‐48.  

Leeds,  S.  2007:  ‘Correspondence  Truth  and  Scientific  Realism’,  Synthese  159:  1-­‐21.    Leplin,  J.  1997:  A  Novel  Defence  of  Scientific  Realism.  Oxford:  Oxford  University  Press.    

Anjan  Chakravartty          Truth  and  the  Sciences  

  26  

Lipton,  P.  2004:  Inference  to  the  Best  Explanation,  2nd  edition.  London:  Routledge    Longino,  H.  1990:  Science  as  Social  Knowledge:  Values  and  Objectivity  in  Scientific  Inquiry.  Princeton:  Princeton  University  Press.    Misak,  C.  2011:  ‘Pragmatist  Theories  of  Truth’,  in  M.  Glanzberg  (ed.),  The  Oxford  Handbook  of  Truth.  Oxford:  Oxford  University  Press.    McMullin,  E.  1985:  ‘Galilean  Idealization’,  Studies  in  History  and  Philosophy  of  Science  16:  247-­‐273.    Nelson,  L.  H.  &  J.  Nelson  (eds.)  (1996):  Feminism,  Science,  and  the  Philosophy  of  Science.  Dordrecht:  Kluwer.    Oddie,  G.  2011:  ‘Truth  and  Truthlikeness’,  in  M.  Glanzberg  (ed.),  The  Oxford  Handbook  of  Truth.  Oxford:  Oxford  University  Press.    Peirce,  C.  S.  1998/1992:  The  Essential  Peirce,  N.  Houser,  C.  Kloesel,  &  the  Peirce  Edition  Project    (eds.).  Bloomington:  Indiana  University  Press.      Pickering,  A.  1984:  Constructing  Quarks:  A  Sociological  History  of  Particle  Physics.  Edinburgh:  Edinburgh  University  Press.    Psillos,  S.  1999:  Scientific  Realism:  How  Science  Tracks  Truth.  London:  Routledge.    Psillos,  S.  forthcoming:  ‘Choosing  the  Realist  Framework’,  Synthese.      Putnam,  H.  1975:  Mathematics,  Matter  and  Method.  Cambridge:  Cambridge  University  Press.    Putnam,  H.  1981:  Reason,  Truth,  and  History.  Cambridge:  Cambridge  University  Press.    Quine,  W.  1953:  ‘Two  Dogmas  of  Empiricism’,  in  From  a  Logical  Point  of  View,  pp.  20-­‐46.  Cambridge,  MA:  Harvard  University  Press.    Richardson,  A.  W.  1998:  Carnap's  Construction  of  the  World.  Cambridge:  Cambridge  University  Press.    Sankey,  H.  1994:  The  Incommensurability  Thesis.  London:  Ashgate.    Shapin,  S.  &  S.  Schaffer:  1985.  Leviathan  and  the  Air  Pump.  Princeton:  Princeton  University  Press.    Stanford,  P.  K.  2006:  Exceeding  Our  Grasp:  Science,  History,  and  the  Problem  of  Unconceived  Alternatives.  Oxford:  Oxford  University  Press.    Vaihinger,  H.  1923/1911:  The  Philosophy  of  ‘As  If’,  C.K.  Ogden  (tr.).  London:  Kegan  Paul.    Walker,  R.  2011:  ‘The  Coherence  Theory  of  Truth’,  in  M.  Glanzberg  (ed.),  The  Oxford  Handbook  of  Truth.  Oxford:  Oxford  University  Press.    Worrall,  J.  1989:  ‘Structural  Realism:  The  Best  of  Both  Worlds?’,  Dialectica  43:  99-­‐124.  Reprinted  in  D.  Papineau  (ed.)  1996:  The  Philosophy  of  Science,  pp.  139-­‐165.  Oxford:  Oxford  University  Press.