those obscure objects of desire andrew

Upload: letitia-regarde

Post on 23-Feb-2018

221 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 7/24/2019 Those Obscure Objects of Desire Andrew

    1/14

    Artforum, summer 2015, pp. 318-23

    [319

    ]

    Those Obscure

    Objects of Desire

    Andrew Cole on the Uses and Abuses of Object-Oriented

    Ontology and Speculative Realism

    OVER THE PAST TEN YEARS, people in all manner of disciplines have turned to things:

    to matter, stuff, obdurate objects. Often loosely grouped under the rubric new

    materialisms, these strains of thought have captured the imagination of artists and

    critics alike. The art world just cant quit them, apparentlya perverse situation, since

    art and art history have, of course, already devoted hundreds of years to thinking

    precisely about objects as objects. But are things really as they seem? In the following

    pages, scholar ANDREW COLE takes the measure of the two new-materialist

    philosophies that have come to dominate the art-world conversation, arguing that

    object-oriented ontology and speculative realism are beset by contradictions, misguided

    assumptions, and outright fallacies. [eds.]

  • 7/24/2019 Those Obscure Objects of Desire Andrew

    2/14

    [320]

    A BRICK HOUSE CRUMBLESin the village of Veselovka, Russia, just a few miles

    from Kaliningrad. Its said that Immanuel Kant had something to do with this house

    back when the region was part of Prussia (and when Kaliningrad was known as

    Knigsberg), but what, exactly, is not clear. Ambiguities such as whether the

    philosopher really lived here didnt stop someone from regarding the house as his

    and tagging it with the declaration . These words, spray-painted in green

    and garnished with a groovy heart and a cute flower beneath, were translated in

    English-speaking media as Kant is a moron.

    You rarely hear the words irony and Kant used in the same sentence, but whats

    ironic about this vandalism is the fact that the house isnt Kantsthe existing

    structure dates from the nineteenth century. Only the foundations are contemporary

    with the philosopher, who lived in the area in the late 1740s. What we have here, I

    think, is a vivid illustration of how the critique of Kantwhether inscribed in graffiti

    or couched in academic proseusually misses its mark. You will often hear

    contemporary critics say that Kant is a moron owing to this or that failing of his, but

    this assessment almost always involves a misreadinga misidentification, as itwereof his philosophy. In such cases, the foundations of Kants system remain

    untouched and solid as ever. You see, even in death Kant is the reigning All-

    DestroyerDer Allzermalmende, as his friends called him, ribbing him for his

    annoying habit of exiting debates completely unscathed and triumphant.

    Yes, Kantian moral philosophy leaves something to be desired, as when the

    philosopher exemplifies the categorical imperative by asking readers to imagine

    having sex near the gallowseasy to say for a person who never got laid. But Kants

    epistemology, in particular his insight into how we experience the world, remains

    foundational. He tells us that ours is a world of phenomena, the infinite array of

    objects and events we experience, and he says also that the world is composed of

    noumena we cannot experience, the equally infinite number of things that exist, and

  • 7/24/2019 Those Obscure Objects of Desire Andrew

    3/14

    processes that transpire, apart from our minds thinking them. These two domains

    are radically different but nonetheless linked, inasmuch as noumena are the basis for

    the phenomena. Of course, theres far more to Kants critical philosophy than that,

    as well soon see. For example, we cant ignore such famously unfraught topics as

    thinking the unthinkable. But this is the gist, and enough to get us going.

    Our interest here is in showing that Kant doesnt crumble like his ersatz house

    (though props to the house for lasting this long). In fact, Kants ideas remain a

    crucial component of recent philosophies that try hard to vitiate his philosophy.

    Object-oriented ontology is one such philosophy, as is its cousin, speculative realism.

    What is object-oriented ontology, however? You might surmise that its a return to

    the object qua objecta renewed focus on the composition, vitality, materiality,

    autonomy, wonder, and durability of objects large and small, near and far. In this

    sense, you could say that any discipline or practice is object oriented, including not

    only art history and criticism but also architecture, graphic design, museum studies,

    archaeology, science and the philosophy of science, book history, literary criticism

    and rhetoric, and the culinary artsindeed, any field of study whose subject is

    objects. This crude understanding of object-oriented ontology also applies to

    speculative realism,which may explain why both have become irresistibly appealingto the art world.

    But object-oriented ontology, as it happens, isntall that. Instead, it is, well, an

    ontologyand, as such, involves a set of theses about All That Is. Lets dive in,

    surveying its three major tenets. First, everything is an object, including you and

    each of your thoughts. Second, and accordingly, no object relates to any other

    object, because the universe itself is devoid of all relation. Why is there no relation

    in the universe? Its because objects sever relations with every other object and

    withdraw into themselves to become self-subsisting, autonomous beings. Its also

    because relation is typically a human mode of apprehending, describing, and

    interacting with the world. Given that not every object is a human, though every

    human is an object, you cant have an object-oriented ontology if humans are at the

  • 7/24/2019 Those Obscure Objects of Desire Andrew

    4/14

    center of it. Such an anthropocentric object-oriented ontology would be a

    contradiction in terms, because objects are not a means to our ends: They are

    meaningful whether or not we perceive them. Thirdand finallyall objects are

    equal and, ontologically speaking, on the same plane. You, a speck of flea shit, an

    electric chair, and a solar flare are all equal objects.

    NOT EVERY SCHOLAR, critic, curator, or practitioner adheres to these major points,

    much less retails them, when declaring an object-oriented approach to this or that

    field of study or aesthetic endeavor. You see this quite a lot: People follow a trend,

    but only in spirit. For that reason, it might be helpful to think about this new

    philosophy as a philosophyto look at the letter of its laws and [321] see how it

    fares against the likes of Kant, the All-Destroyer. Why this focus on Kant? To be sure,

    object-oriented ontology builds on the work of several thinkers (Heidegger, Husserl,

    Whitehead, Latour, even Deleuze), but it devotes much of its energy trying to get

    out from under Kant. Does it succeed?

    That sounds like a rhetorical question. But its earnest. For no sooner does Graham

    Harman, the founder of object-oriented ontology, start to divide objects into

    different kinds with various sorts of qualities than we begin to wonder whether wearent in Kants domicile. Harman establishes the basic elements of an object-

    oriented metaphysics in his short, lucid book The Quadruple Object(2011), arguing

    that, while there may be an infinity of objects in the cosmos, they come in only two

    kinds: the real object that withdraws from all experience, and the sensual object that

    exists only in experience. And along with these we also have two kinds of qualities:

    the sensual qualities found in experience, and the real ones Husserl says are

    accessible intellectually rather than through sensuous intuition.1So we have a

    distinction between the real object and the sensual object. The former is

    withdrawn, autonomous, and free of all relation, and the latter is available to our

    perception. Hasnt this been thought already by Kant, whose insight in the

    Transcendental Analytic put forward in his Critique of Pure Reason(1781/1787)

  • 7/24/2019 Those Obscure Objects of Desire Andrew

    5/14

  • 7/24/2019 Those Obscure Objects of Desire Andrew

    6/14

  • 7/24/2019 Those Obscure Objects of Desire Andrew

    7/14

    we make of it). Rather, he understood that the problem of relation is exactly the

    same as the problem of the thing-in-itself: There are relations in the noumenal

    world, but we cannot think them directly because we have access only to

    phenomenal relations, the imperfect representations of noumenal relations. The

    human version of relation, in other words, isnt the same as noumenal relation, and

    isnt the only kind of relation. This idea is all over Kants lectures in metaphysics,

    which none of the object-oriented ontologists seem to know.

    The epistemological gambit of object-oriented ontology is to say that object

    relations are thinkable because they are real, even if withdrawn and unknowable.

    Realism is obviously what you could call this philosophyor, as Harman has it,

    weird realism. But realism (weird or otherwise) is a point of view about the world

    a human point of view that requires the world to be accessible to us and structured

    in such a way that we can think it. Its here that Harmans ten modes of relation

    reveal themselves to be equivalent to Kants forms of possible experience. These

    ten modes guarantee in advancethat, say, an object somewhere will be sincere to

    another object at some point in time, or that an object somewhere will confront

    another object three days from now. Even if we arent on[322] the scene,

    somewhere in Ohio, observing an object indifferently theorizing another object, wecan know that objects are doing things with other objects and will continue to do so

    behind our backs. Now, one might say that Harman has simply extended the Kantian

    forms of possible experience to objects, which thus experience other objects in

    multifarious ways. That would be partly right, foraccording to this philosophy

    objects themselves have experiences, as you will see below. But theres more: The

    fact that we can also think these object relations means that the relations are

    already thinkablealready correlated to our minds and thus already something we

    knowabout the world. The much maligned correlationism that object-oriented

    ontology hopes to expunge from its thinking is in fact its preeminent feature.

    THIS QUESTIONof thinkingversus knowingis an important one, because it points

    to further Kantian problems lingering at the center of a purported anti-Kantianism.

  • 7/24/2019 Those Obscure Objects of Desire Andrew

    8/14

    For example, Harman urges us to reject the idea that we cannot think something

    without thinking itthat is, to reject the notion that we can only think what is

    available to us as phenomena we experience.7He asks us instead to perform a

    thought experiment by thinking what you cannot think, such as the tree outside of

    thought.8Here, Harman attempts to get the human mind out of the picture entirely

    by resorting to a realism that assures us that we can think objects as those objects

    are, outside our minds.

    These are intriguing claims because they are Kantian at heart. Kant was obsessed

    with precisely these questions of what we can think and what we can experience,

    what is intelligible to us and what is knowable. You could say that one feature of his

    intellectual biography, ever since the writing of his inaugural dissertation, shows Kant

    offering a variety of opinions about how we can think the unthinkable noumena. He

    tells us early in the Critique of Pure Reasonthat to thinkan object and to knowan

    object are by no means the same thing.9This distinction between thinking and

    knowing is crucial for Kant, for it bespeaks the difference between thinking what you

    cannot experience firsthand, such as the cinnabar outside of thought, and knowing,

    or cognizing, the cinnabar in thought, the cinnabar as you experience it.

    Kant goes on to expand the possibilities of thinking what we cannot experience or

    know. In fact, his entire Critique of Judgment(1790) is nothing if not an exercise in

    extending the possibilities of thinkingnoumena of various kinds: positive, causal,

    worldly, natural, human, and divine. He tells us that to think these noumenal

    realities, no matter how mundane or sublime, you have to make up your own

    concepts and, in short, use whatever imaginative means you have at your disposal.

    He suggests we can think the unconditioned from our vantage point in the sensibly

    conditioned, using various media as the bridge from here to there: language, poetry,

    art, analogy, math, and allusion. This is precisely what Harman and his followers

    claim to have invented: We can think the unthinkable if we adopt allusion or other

    oblique approaches to the object world we cannot directly experience.10Again,

    thats about as Kantian as you can get. Similarly, thespeculative realist Quentin

  • 7/24/2019 Those Obscure Objects of Desire Andrew

    9/14

    Meillassoux says that objects have mathematizable properties that exist equally in

    thought as outside itreal properties we can think as they really are. Having studied

    a few semesters of advanced calculus, I admit that Alain Badiou is right in saying

    that Kant was terrible at math. But he nevertheless tried his hand at it, attempting to

    construe extension (after Descartes) as just one way to think the noumenal or, as he

    also terms it, the supersensible (bersinnliche) world. Meillassoux, for his part,

    broadens the Cartesian insight about extension into a whole thesis about our

    mathematical perception of objects, but writes as if Kant had never attempted this

    himself.11

    The only answer I have for why two voracious readers of philosophy, from whom

    many others receive lessons about the history of Western thought, would exhibit

    such a partial view of Kant is that either their reading of Kant is incomplete or they

    know this about Kant already but arent telling. Ill abstain from answering

    definitively, becausebelieving in dialecticsI think its a little of both. Harmans

    Kant is only the Kant of the Critique of Pure Reason; Meillassouxs Kant is the Kant

    of the critical philosophy. Meillassoux in fact embraces a pre-critical philosophy in

    order to revise decisions often considered as infrangible since Kant.12That we are

    supposed to look to precritical philosophy as an end run around the critical Kant is acompelling idea for theorists who can sense the persistent mdivalitor

    dogmatism of modern thought. Butand this is a pronounced problem in theory

    more broadlyit is wrong to uphold the distinction between the pre- and

    postcritical, insofar as Kant himself violates the distinction left and right in his work

    up to the very end. Contra Meillassoux, we can embrace the critical Kant and still

    think the unthinkable, if we so wish.

    THERE'S MORE TOthe curriculum of object-oriented ontology. Each object, no

    matter what it is, is abstracted in the same way. Each, that is, conforms to a

    template: All objects have insides and outsides, interiors and exteriors, depths and

    surfaces, andespeciallyessences and accidents. Its here, in the ontologists very

    idea of the object, that another contradiction in the philosophy appears. As

  • 7/24/2019 Those Obscure Objects of Desire Andrew

    10/14

    Heidegger, Merleau-Ponty, and Deleuze have shown, each in his own particular style,

    the construct of inside/outside in any ontology, whether it concerns objects or

    subjects or both, is a function of the old subject/object dualism, which is a dualism

    precisely because there is a sovereign subject around to proclaim what makes the

    cut, what qualifies as an object or notand whose very perspective on that object

    determines what is inside and what out. The point isnt that object-oriented

    ontology unwittingly centers an autonomous subject at the heart of objects simply

    in the way it tells us to look at objects. Rather, its that Heidegger had already

    created a philosophy whose very purpose was to destroy these old ontological

    constructions of essences and accidents, interiors and exteriors. Such terms, he

    thought, obstruct the genuine thinking of Dasein, or being there in the moment.

    This is important because object-oriented ontology claims to be a Heideggerian

    philosophy based on select passages in Being and Time(1927). Likewise, the reader

    (i.e., Harman) who could discover in Heideggers opaque essay The Thing (1950) a

    schematic for quadruple objects must have missed this philosophers poetic

    discussion of the jug in that very same paper, along with his caution about realist

    perspectives on objects: Science represents something real, by which it is objectively

    controlled. Butis this reality the jug? No.13 [323]

    Regarding anthropomorphism and anthropocentrism, object-oriented ontology cant

    seem to avoid these perspectives after all: The aforementioned modes of relation

    fission, fusion, allure, sincerity, theory, confrontation, and so forthare themselves

    human-centric. Some of these terms read like authorial observations on the fickle

    characters in a novelDickensian descriptions of who is sincere, who is

    confrontational, who is alluring, and so forthwhile others, such as theory, denote

    contemplation in its most humanly reclusive form. Yet other terms, such as fusion,

    recall problems my friend Charlie is trying to solve in the plasma lab where

    astrophysicists are creating a miniature star. Fusionevokes the mysterious

    supersensible processes in our sun as much as it conjures up the human effort to

    duplicate and harness these processes before we destroy the planet with our

    capitalism and carbon emissions. Maybe its just me, but fission prompts a similar

  • 7/24/2019 Those Obscure Objects of Desire Andrew

    11/14

    thoughtthis time about whether an atomic bomb is really equal to a doorknob,

    or the blasts at Hiroshima and Nagasaki equal to a unicorn. This term requires

    some serious epoch, or mental bracketing, for us to picture the pure object relation

    its meant to describe.

    Can we bracket our thoughts in this fashion, when the father of this practice,

    Husserl, could never do it himself, describing (for example) a piece of paper on his

    desk but never thinking the paper as the paper really is? To be sure, these new

    terms for relation in object-oriented ontology are meant to help us decenter

    ourselves as we reflect on objects relating to other objects, forcing us to realize that

    a rock cares not a whit about the difference between a nuclear weapon and a

    doorknob when it confronts them. But we access this object relation by thinking

    about the nameof the relation, and all of these names are decidedly human,

    cultural, social, and literarythat is, the names are in fact predicates, chock-full of

    meanings you cant unthink or bracket. Contemplate fusionor fission, for example,

    and youll soon encounter the problems of production and technology right where

    they shouldnt manifestin the object relation. Or think about confrontation and

    youll eventually face the politics of what it means to be autonomous, right where

    issues of freedom or necessity shouldnt appearin the object relation. This problemextends to the ethics of why we should even think a thoroughly reified world, as

    called for by object-oriented ontology, or why we should even fantasize about

    objects as scholastic assemblages, Erector Sets of the imagination.

    AT THIS STAGE, you could throw up your hands and just admit that Kant was right:

    There are object relations, yes, but we cant really know or describe them in detail,

    only allude to them in our inevitably human way. Or you could press on, chalking up

    these considerable difficulties in naming to the problem of language and solving

    them by taking a page from Heidegger, who uses neologisms to refresh the addled

    language of philosophythough who really wants to hear more jargon? You could

    also consult your local analytic philosopher, who will tell you that metaphysical

    mistakes are mistakes in natural language: Artificial languages, anyone? In any event,

  • 7/24/2019 Those Obscure Objects of Desire Andrew

    12/14

  • 7/24/2019 Those Obscure Objects of Desire Andrew

    13/14

    meaning for us nonetheless and becomes ensouled under our gaze. We so admire

    the table as a commodity that it magically changes into a thing like no other. It

    not only stands with its feet on the ground, but . . . stands on its head, and evolves

    out of its wooden brain grotesque ideas, far more wonderful than if it were to begin

    dancing of its own free will.18This is what Marx calls the mystical character of the

    commoditymystical because we can only think the objects inner properties by

    personifying it in a focus so narrow that we ignore the larger drama, the greater

    historical process that makes a commodity a commodity, an object an object, and

    capitalism capitalism. This is, in short, the metaphysics of capitalism, then as now.

    Ours is a time when schools of interpretation ask us to personify and caricature

    objects as autonomous and alivewhether they are the objects who speak in the

    new so-called vibrant materialism, or objects who fuss and act up in actor-network

    theory, or objects with primitive psyches in object-oriented ontology. Is this really

    the way to think at this moment? For Marx, at least, this way of thinking about

    objects is what keeps capitalism ticking. To adopt such a philosophy, no questions

    asked, is fantasycommodity fetishism in academic form. To identify such

    philosophy as the metaphysics of capitalism is theory, ever attentive to historys

    impress on our imaginations, whatever we may dream.

    Andrew Cole,a professor of English atPrinceton University,is the author ofThe

    Birth of Theory(University of Chicago Press, 2014).

    [384]

    NOTES

    1. Graham Harman, The Quadruple Object(Alresford, UK: Zero Books, 2011), 49.

    2. Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, trans. Norman Kemp Smith (New York: St.

    Martins Press, 1965), 116.

    3. Ibid., 118.

    4. Harman, The Quadruple Object, 47, 128.

    https://princeton.academia.edu/AndrewColehttps://princeton.academia.edu/AndrewColehttps://english.princeton.edu/people/andrew-colehttps://english.princeton.edu/people/andrew-colehttps://english.princeton.edu/people/andrew-colehttp://press.uchicago.edu/ucp/books/book/chicago/B/bo18008957.htmlhttp://press.uchicago.edu/ucp/books/book/chicago/B/bo18008957.htmlhttp://press.uchicago.edu/ucp/books/book/chicago/B/bo18008957.htmlhttp://press.uchicago.edu/ucp/books/book/chicago/B/bo18008957.htmlhttp://press.uchicago.edu/ucp/books/book/chicago/B/bo18008957.htmlhttp://press.uchicago.edu/ucp/books/book/chicago/B/bo18008957.htmlhttp://press.uchicago.edu/ucp/books/book/chicago/B/bo18008957.htmlhttps://english.princeton.edu/people/andrew-colehttps://princeton.academia.edu/AndrewCole
  • 7/24/2019 Those Obscure Objects of Desire Andrew

    14/14

    5. Ibid., 108.

    6. Ibid., 107, 11415.

    7. Ibid., 62.

    8. Ibid., 6566.

    9. Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, 161.

    10. Harman, The Quadruple Object, 98.

    11. Quentin Meillassoux, After Finitude: An Essay on the Necessity of Contingency, trans. Ray

    Brassier (London: Bloomsbury, 2013), 76, 31, 35.

    12. Ibid., 26.

    13. Martin Heidegger, The Thing, in Poetry, Language, Thought, trans. Albert Hofstadter

    (New York: Harper & Row, 1971), 170.

    14. Harman, The Quadruple Object, 103.

    15. Ibid., 110.

    16. Ibid., 103.

    17. Ibid., 133.

    18. Karl Marx, Capital: A Critique of Political Economy, vol. 1, trans. Ben Fowkes

    (Harmondsworth, UK: Penguin, 1976), 16364.