the rights of war and peace - hugo grotius

385
The Online Library of Liberty A Project Of Liberty Fund, Inc. Hugo Grotius, The Rights of War and Peace (1901 ed.) [1625] The Online Library Of Liberty This E-Book (PDF format) is published by Liberty Fund, Inc., a private, non-profit, educational foundation established in 1960 to encourage study of the ideal of a society of free and responsible individuals. 2010 was the 50th anniversary year of the founding of Liberty Fund. It is part of the Online Library of Liberty web site http://oll.libertyfund.org , which was established in 2004 in order to further the educational goals of Liberty Fund, Inc. To find out more about the author or title, to use the site's powerful search engine, to see other titles in other formats (HTML, facsimile PDF), or to make use of the hundreds of essays, educational aids, and study guides, please visit the OLL web site. This title is also part of the Portable Library of Liberty DVD which contains over 1,000 books and quotes about liberty and power, and is available free of charge upon request. The cuneiform inscription that appears in the logo and serves as a design element in all Liberty Fund books and web sites is the earliest-known written appearance of the word “freedom” (amagi), or “liberty.” It is taken from a clay document written about 2300 B.C. in the Sumerian city-state of Lagash, in present day Iraq. To find out more about Liberty Fund, Inc., or the Online Library of Liberty Project, please contact the Director at [email protected] and visit Liberty Fund's main web site at www.libertyfund.org or the Online Library of Liberty at oll.libertyfund.org .

Upload: paulo201088

Post on 10-May-2017

233 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • The Online Library of LibertyA Project Of Liberty Fund, Inc.

    Hugo Grotius, The Rights of War andPeace (1901 ed.) [1625]

    The Online Library Of LibertyThis E-Book (PDF format) is published by Liberty Fund, Inc., aprivate, non-profit, educational foundation established in 1960 toencourage study of the ideal of a society of free and responsibleindividuals. 2010 was the 50th anniversary year of the founding ofLiberty Fund.

    It is part of the Online Library of Liberty web sitehttp://oll.libertyfund.org, which was established in 2004 in order tofurther the educational goals of Liberty Fund, Inc. To find out moreabout the author or title, to use the site's powerful search engine,to see other titles in other formats (HTML, facsimile PDF), or tomake use of the hundreds of essays, educational aids, and studyguides, please visit the OLL web site. This title is also part of thePortable Library of Liberty DVD which contains over 1,000 booksand quotes about liberty and power, and is available free of chargeupon request.

    The cuneiform inscription that appears in the logo and serves as adesign element in all Liberty Fund books and web sites is theearliest-known written appearance of the word freedom (amagi),or liberty. It is taken from a clay document written about 2300B.C. in the Sumerian city-state of Lagash, in present day Iraq.

    To find out more about Liberty Fund, Inc., or the Online Library ofLiberty Project, please contact the Director at [email protected] visit Liberty Fund's main web site at www.libertyfund.org orthe Online Library of Liberty at oll.libertyfund.org.

    www.princexml.comPrince - Non-commercial LicenseThis document was created with Prince, a great way of getting web content onto paper.

    http://oll.libertyfund.orgmailto:[email protected]://www.libertyfund.orghttp://oll.libertyfund.org

  • LIBERTY FUND, INC.8335 Allison Pointe Trail, Suite 300Indianapolis, Indiana 46250-1684

    Online Library of Liberty: The Rights of War and Peace (1901 ed.)

    PLL v7.0 (generated September, 2013) 2 http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/553

  • Edition Used:

    The Rights of War and Peace, including the Law of Nature and ofNations, translated from the Original Latin of Grotius, with Notesand Illustrations from Political and Legal Writers, by A.C. Campbell,A.M. with an Introduction by David J. Hill (New York: M. WalterDunne, 1901).

    Author: Hugo GrotiusTranslator: A.C. CampbellIntroduction: David Jayne Hill

    About This Title:

    Grotiuss magnum opus on international law and the laws of warand peace. He wrote this volume while the Thirty Years War ragedaround him in the hope that rational human beings might be able toagree to legal limits on wars destruction.

    Online Library of Liberty: The Rights of War and Peace (1901 ed.)

    PLL v7.0 (generated September, 2013) 3 http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/553

    http://oll.libertyfund.org/person/3775http://oll.libertyfund.org/person/4286http://oll.libertyfund.org/person/4287

  • About Liberty Fund:

    Liberty Fund, Inc. is a private, educational foundation establishedto encourage the study of the ideal of a society of free andresponsible individuals.

    Copyright Information:

    The text is in the public domain.

    Fair Use Statement:

    This material is put online to further the educational goals ofLiberty Fund, Inc. Unless otherwise stated in the CopyrightInformation section above, this material may be used freely foreducational and academic purposes. It may not be used in any wayfor profit.

    Online Library of Liberty: The Rights of War and Peace (1901 ed.)

    PLL v7.0 (generated September, 2013) 4 http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/553

  • Table Of Contents

    General PrefaceIntroductionBook I.Chapter I.Chapter II.: Inquiry Into the Lawfulness of War .Chapter III.: The Division of War Into Public and Private and

    the Nature of Sovereign Power .Book II.Chapter I.: Defence of Person and Property .Chapter II.: The General Rights of Things .Chapter III.: On the Original Acquistion of Things, and the

    Right of Property In Seas and Rivers .Chapter IV.: Title to Desert Lands By Occupancy, Possession,

    and Precription .Chapter IX. *: In What Cases Jurisdiction and Property Cease .Chapter X.: The Obligation Arising From Property .Chapter XI.: On Promises .Chapter XII.: On Contracts .Chapter XIII.: On Oaths .Chapter XV. *: On Treaties and On Engagements Made By

    Delegates, Exceeding Their Power .Chapter XVI.: The Interpretation of Treaties .Chapter XVII.: On Damages Occasioned By Injury and the

    Obligation to Repair Them .Chapter XVIII.: On the Right of Embassies .Chapter XIX.: On the Right of Burial .Chapter XX.: On Punishments .Chapter XXI.: On the Communication of Punishment .Chapter XXII.: On the Unjust Causes of War .Chapter XXIII.: On Doubtful Causes .Chapter XXIV.: Precautions Against Rashly Engaging In War,

    Even Upon Just Grounds .Chapter XXV.: The Causes of Undertaking War For Others .Book III.Chapter I.: What Is Lawful In War .Chapter II.: In What Manner the Law of Nations Renders the

    Property of Subjects Answerable For the Debts ofSovereigns. the Nature of Reprisals .

    Chapter III.: On Just Or, Solemn War According to the Law ofNations On Declarations of War .

    Chapter IV.: On the Right of Killing an Enemy In Lawful War,and Committing Other Acts of Hostility .

    Chapter V.: On the Right to Lay Waste an Enemys Country,and Carry Off His Effects .

    Online Library of Liberty: The Rights of War and Peace (1901 ed.)

    PLL v7.0 (generated September, 2013) 5 http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/553

  • Chapter VI.: On the Acquisition of Territory and Property ByRight of Conquest .

    Chapter VII.: On the Right Over Prisoners of War .Chapter VIII.: On Empire Over the Conquered .Chapter IX.: Of the Right of Postliminium .Chapter XI. *: the Right of Killing Enemies, In Just War, to Be

    Tempered With Moderation and Humanity .Chapter XII.: On Moderation In Despoiling an Enemys

    Country .Chapter XIII.: On Moderation In Making Captures In War .Chapter XV. *: On Moderation In Acquiring Dominion .Chapter XVI.: On Moderation With Respect to Things

    Excluded From the Right of Postliminium By the Law ofNations .

    Chapter XVII.: Respecting Those Who Are Neutral In War .Chapter XIX. *: On Good Faith Between Enemies .Chapter XX.: On the Public Faith, By Which War Is Concluded;

    Comprising Treaties of Peace, and the Nature of Arbitration,Surrender Hostages, Pledges .

    Chapter XXI.: On Faith During the Continuance of War, OnTruces, Safe-conducts, and the Redemption of Prisoners .

    Chapter XXII.: On the Faith On Those Invested WithSubordinate Powers In War .

    Chapter XXIV. *: On Tacit Faith .Chapter XXV.: Conclusion .

    Online Library of Liberty: The Rights of War and Peace (1901 ed.)

    PLL v7.0 (generated September, 2013) 6 http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/553

  • Online Library of Liberty: The Rights of War and Peace (1901 ed.)

    PLL v7.0 (generated September, 2013) 7 http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/553

  • Hugo Grotius. From an original painting.

    Online Library of Liberty: The Rights of War and Peace (1901 ed.)

    PLL v7.0 (generated September, 2013) 8 http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/553

  • [Back to Table of Contents]

    GENERAL PREFACEOftheLibrary ofUniversalClassics andRareManuscripts, twentyvolumes are devoted to the various branches of Government,Philosophy, Law, Ethics, English and French Belles Letters,Hebraic, Ottoman, and Arabian Literature, and one to a collectionof 150 reproductions, bound in English vellum, of the autographs,papers and letters of Rulers, Statesmen, Poets, Artists andCelebrities ranging through three centuries, crowned by anilluminated facsimile of that historic Document, the Magna Carta.The series in itself is an epitome of the best in History, Philosophyand Literature. The great writes of past ages are accessible toreaders in general solely through translations. It was, therefore,necessary that translations of such rare Classics as are embodied inthis series should be of the best, and should possess exactitude intext and supreme faithfulness in rendering the authors thought.Under the vigilant scholarship of the Editorial Council this hasbeen accomplished with unvarying excellence. The classification,selection and editing of the various volumes have been the subjectof much earnest thought and consultation on the part of more thantwenty of the best known scholars of the day.

    The Universities of Yale, Washington, Cornell, Chicago,Pennsylvania, Columbia, London, Toronto and Edinburgh are allrepresented among the contributors, the writers of specialintroductions, or upon the consulting staff, the latter including thePresidents of five of the Universities mentioned. Among others whocontribute special essays upon given subjects may be mentionedthe late Librarian of the British Museum, Dr. Richard Garnett, whofurnishes the essay introducing Evelyns Diary. From theLibrarian of the National Library of France, Lon Valle, comes thefascinating introduction to the celebrated Memoirs of the Duc deSaint-Simon. The scholarly minister to Switzerland (late FirstAssistant Secretary of State), Dr. David J. Hill, lent his wide readingto the brilliant and luminous essay that precedes the Rights of Warand Peace. The resources of the Congressional Library atWashington, as well as of foreign libraries, have all been drawnupon in the gigantic task of compressing into the somewhat narrowlimits of twenty volumes all that was highest, best, most enduringand useful in the various ramifications of literature at large.

    The first section of the Library is devoted entirely to themanuscript reproductions of the autographs of celebrated men inall ranks and phases of life, covering a period of three centuries.They are, in fact, the American edition of the reproduction of rareand celebrated autographs drawn from the British Museum that

    Online Library of Liberty: The Rights of War and Peace (1901 ed.)

    PLL v7.0 (generated September, 2013) 9 http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/553

  • was issued in England under the editorship of the Assistant Keeperof the Manuscripts. They afford an opportunity to the inquiringreader to study the characters of Rulers, Statesmen, Writers, andArtists through the medium of their chirography.

    It has long been recognized that character is traceable throughhandwriting. So it is interesting to discern in the characters tracedby Henry VIII the hardened, sensual and selfish character of thatautocrat and polygamist; in the writing of Thomas Wolsey, thosecrafty traits combined with perseverance and mock humility whichraised him wellnigh to supremacy in the realm and led him finallyto a downfall more complete than any we read of in English history;and in that of Charles V, of Spain, the hard-headed continence ofcharacter and superb common sense which enabled him at theheight of glory to retire to a monastery while yet there was day-light in life, as he expressed it, for the making of his soul. Apartfrom the historical interest of these Documents, this study ofcharacter as revealed in them will prove fascinating to thinkingminds.

    The Magna Carta, greatest of all historical characters wrung fromthe various kings of England from Henry I downward, was grantedby King John at the pressing instance of the Barons and Commonsof England toward the end of his ill-judged and unfortunate reign.Of this Document, celebrated and historic as it is, but little isknown at large. Although Blackstone and other prominent lawyershave written upon it, information about it is hard to obtain. Noreproduction of the original Document has ever been offered toAmerican collectors. This facsimile is illuminated in colors with theshields of many of the Peers who compelled King John to accede totheir demands for civil and religious liberty. The original charterwas signed at a place called Runny-mede (the Council Meadow) aspot between Windsor and Staines, on the 15th of June, 1215,about a year before the death of John. It practically guaranteed tothe Commons of England all the civil and religious rights they enjoyto-day. It dealt with testamentary law as well, securing to widowsall the legal rights which they to-day possess. It dealt with therights of accused persons; with military service; with feudal tenure;with taxation, and it limited the heretofore autocratic power of theKing to an extent unknown before in the history of the world. If weexcept the Declaration of Independence, it is the most interestinghistorical record of all time.

    The Second Section of the Library (ten volumes) is devoted to thepresentation of Government, Philosophy, Law and Ethics. Thissection embraces such names as Grotius, Plato, Sir GeorgeCornewall Lewis, Adam Smith, Hamilton, Madison, Jay, WalterBatgehot, Spinoza, Schopenhauer, Machiavelli, as well as those

    Online Library of Liberty: The Rights of War and Peace (1901 ed.)

    PLL v7.0 (generated September, 2013) 10 http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/553

  • builders of Ideal Governments, More, Bacon, Campanella andRousseau.

    Of all benefactors in Literature of the human race, Grotius mayperhaps rank as first among his equals. Centuries have bornewitness to the justness of his premises and the wisdom of hisconclusions. The principles of national law laid down by him are to-day accepted as the axioms of the Science. Among the nations,perhaps the United States is most deeply interested in the rightadministration of the principles affirmed by Grotius in his giganticwork on the Rights of War and Peace, and it was therefore mostfitting, when the recent peace conference at the Hague completedthe great structure of international comity, the foundations ofwhich were laid by Grotius in 1625, that a silver wreath was laid bythe representative of the United States upon the grave of the manto whom the Conference owed its initial impulse, although at adistance in time of nearly three centuries.

    When the Publisher determined, under the advice of his EditorialCouncil, to publish Grotius, he found that only two volumes of thefirst edition were available in the Library of Congress. At muchexpense and trouble, he instituted a search in Europe and finallyobtained the missing volume, which he presented to theCongressional Library, where it now is.

    Sir George Cornewall Lewiss Government of Dependencies ischaracterized by the accuracy of its information It is a reliable textbook for the guidance of any nation in the treatment of itsdependencies and colonies. It is a Classic that will survive as longas colonization remains to be done, and it is remarkable thatalthough it was published for the first time sixty years ago, theillustrations afforded by the last two generations support thejustice of its principles and the exactness of its deductions.

    Adam Smiths Essay on Colonies presents an introductory view ofthe principles governing colonial policy. It is a fitting work to gohand in hand with the greater one of Sir George Cornewall Lewis.It is of practical use to American Statesmen, since the UnitedStates seems at present to be entering upon a world-wide colonialpolicy. Its practical wisdom, which has made it a Classic for alltimes, finds a special applicability in the conditions of today, forAdam Smith was a theorist in the best sense of the word, that is tosay, he was a man whose breadth of view, instead of unfitting himfor practical details, enabled him to deduce from the lessons ofhistory and experience the right solutions for the problems ofColonial policy.

    Online Library of Liberty: The Rights of War and Peace (1901 ed.)

    PLL v7.0 (generated September, 2013) 11 http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/553

  • Platos Republic and Statesman must be regarded to-day notmerely as historical records of a by-gone philosophy, but as living,teaching dissertations upon theories which cannot fail to awaken instudious minds the highest ideals of life and government. Modernproblems stated in the light of Platos philosophy, as it is expressedin these books, will find readier solutions when examined in thelight of its principles. No student of sociology, of politics, nationaland municipal, or of government in all its many-sided aspects, canafford to be without a knowledge of these immortal discourses.

    Goldwin Smith has declared that of all expositions of constitutionalGovernment, The Federalist ranks the highest. When Hamilton,Madison, and Jay first conceived the idea of printing in the commontongue their ideas upon the principles of free government, theyunwittingly laid the foundations of the best commentary on theprinciples of popular government ever written. Political scienceowes to them the most important contribution to its literature madesince its birth. The Essays are equally admirable for sagacity,simplicity, and patriotism, and while The Federalist will never beread for pleasure, it contains a mine of wisdom for the student andthe constitutional lawyer, and as a text book of political science iswithout a parallel.

    When Bagehot issued his work on the English Constitution, it washailed by the critics as the most wonderful and philosophicaldissertation on the subject in any language or from any pen. JohnStuart Mill used to say that of all great subjects much remained tobe written, and that especially was this true of the EnglishConstitution. Bagehots work, although affording the conclusionthat monarchy in England exists as a logical necessity, is sounbiased in its premises, so logical and clear in its deductions, thatthis manifest fairness, although leading one to conclusionsdistasteful to a republican mind, must endear him to his readers.Dealing with a subject somewhat dry in its details, he investsinanimate objects with so much light that they become realities. Inthe highest sense he combines popularity and scholarship.

    Spinozas philosophy may be traced both to the influence of Bacon,his predecessor, and to Descartes, his contemporary. Itscombination of positivism with the enthusiasm of pietycharacterizes his philosophy as unique in itself, for while treatingman from a purely mechanical standpoint, it asserts that themechanism itself is entirely divine. Spinoza was a voluntary martyrin the cause of Free Thought. He was at the same time bothPantheist and Monist, yet sincere in his devotion to nature and theGod of nature. His religion naturally made him a Monist, while hisphilosophy led him to express the pantheism that the lover of Godin Nature cannot avoid. While he renounced his Judaism and

    Online Library of Liberty: The Rights of War and Peace (1901 ed.)

    PLL v7.0 (generated September, 2013) 12 http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/553

  • entered the ranks of the Christian philosophers, he never receivedbaptism. He may be ranked among the greatest of the Germanmystics, whose work had such profound influence upon thedogmatic Christianity of a later day. The epithet conferred on him,namely, God-intoxicated, summarizes his whole attitude and thecharacter of his philosophy better than any lengthy dissertation.

    When Schopenhauer began to write, he declared himself a truedisciple of Kant, but he modifies and adapts Kants Critique ofPure Reason to such an extent that he reaches the attitude ofopposition. This attitude he manifests throughout all his writings.He is truly an Apostle of Protest, but in spite of his positivistcontradictions and his materialistic pantheism, he opens up a mineof suggestions to the literary and philosophical student. In spite ofthe apparent tragedy due to the conflict within him, we cannot helpgathering from Schopenhauer an immensity of what is true, what isgood and what is excellent. One thing especially noticeable abouthis writings is that while German philosophers are often ponderousand in fact nebulous, Schopenhauer is always clear, original, andreadable.

    To Machiavelli belongs by acclaim the honor of having written theideal biography of a State. His clear, straightforward, concisestatement of conditions and characters as he saw then is a modelfor all writers of record. He was the first great Italian historian, andno man has ever been more ardent in his patriotism or a moreearnest supporter of government for and by the people. Thegreatest tribute to his inflexible honesty of character is the factthat while no man had greater opportunities to enrich himself atthe cost of the State, he died leaving his family in the greatestpoverty. His varied political experience, and his assiduous study ofclassic writers, gave him the ability as well as the desire to writethe history of his native State. Time has pronounced this History tobe a classic worthy of preservation, and the perspective of time hasalso enabled us to form a juster and greater estimate of its author.

    The Ideal Republics and Empires that have been constructed fromtime to time by political dreamers have all the attractiveness ofworks like Pilgrims Progress or Gullivers Travels, combined with aphilosophy and political insight that give them a double claim to beconsidered Classics. Modern progress may be more deeplyindebted than we can estimate to the fantasies and airy castles ofmen like Rousseau, More, and Campanella. The four IdealRepublics or Governments described in this volume are perhaps themost famous of all, since they rank not only as great creations ofthe imagination but as literature of the highest class; and theirwriters have a further claim upon posterity from the fact that theyhelped to make history.

    Online Library of Liberty: The Rights of War and Peace (1901 ed.)

    PLL v7.0 (generated September, 2013) 13 http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/553

  • The Third and concluding Section of the Library deals with thattremendous range of world-wide literature which we call, for wantof a better name, Belles Lettres. Goethe contributes his brilliantand sagacious observations on men and things as he communicatedthem to Eckerman. Landor, of whom Swinburne has said thatMilton alone stands higher, both in prose and verse, furnishes uswith his Classical Conversations. Montesquieu and Goldsmith aredrawn on for their Persian and Chinese Letters. Lord Chesterfieldgives us the irony and hard-headed criticism combined with worldlycommon sense contained in the Letters to His Son, and the variousnames best known in French and English Belles Letters yield whatis greatest in them. Ottoman Literature, comprising Arabian,Persian, and Hebraic Poems, affords the reader an insight into theromantic and dramatic character of the Oriental. The Dabistan,possibly the most extraordinary book ever written in the East, findsitself at home in this section, while the Literature of the Hebrews isideally represented in that most wonderful of all monuments ofhuman wisdom, and perhaps folly, the Talmud, together with thebasis of modern metaphysics, the Kabbala.

    The Sufistic Quatrains of Omar Khayyam are here for the first timepresented complete in a collection of this order. The variouseditions of Fitzgerald are reprinted, collated, and to them is addedthe valuable Heron-Allen analysis of Fitzgeralds sources ofinspiration. The very rare Whinfield version is found here complete;and for the first time in English appears M. Nicolas Frenchtranscription of the Teheran Manuscript. It is safe to say that anylover of Omar wishing to add to his collection the versions herequoted would be compelled to disburse more than one hundredtimes the amount this book will cost him.

    While the Library of Universal Classics does not claim to be thefinal condensation of the treasure houses of human philosophy andlore, whether practical or ideal, it does most emphatically assert itsright to be called the most useful, most attractive, and mostrepresentative selection, within the limits assigned to it, of thoseworld-masterpieces of literature which men, for lack of a moreluminous name, call Classics.

    Robert Arnot

    Online Library of Liberty: The Rights of War and Peace (1901 ed.)

    PLL v7.0 (generated September, 2013) 14 http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/553

  • [Back to Table of Contents]

    INTRODUCTION

    The Work And Influence Of Hugo Grotius.The claims of the great work of Grotius, De Jure Belli ac Pacis, tobe included in a list of Universal Classics, do not rest upon thefelicity of style usually expected in a classic composition. His workis marked by frequent rhetorical deformities, tedious and involvedforms of reasoning, and perplexing obscurities of phraseologywhich prevent its acceptance as an example of elegant writing.Notwithstanding these external defects, it is, nevertheless, one ofthe few notable works of genius which, among the labors ofcenturies, stand forth as illustrations of human progress andconstitute the precious heritage of the human race.

    If it is not literature in the technical sense, the masterpiece ofGrotius is something higher and nobler,a triumph of intelligenceover irrational impulses and barbarous propensities. Its publicationmarks an era in the history of nations, for out of the chaos oflawless and unreasoning strife it created a system of illuminatingprinciples to light the way of sovereigns and peoples in the paths ofpeace and general concord.

    I. The Reign Of War.The idea of peaceful equity among nations, now accepted as ahuman ideal, though still far from realization, was for ages adifficult, if not an impossible, conception. All experience spokeagainst it, for war was the most familiar phenomenon of history.

    Among the Greek city-states, a few temporary leagues andfederations were attempted, but so feeble were the bonds of peace,so explosive were the passions which led to war, that even amongthe highly civilized Hellenic peoples, community of race, language,and religion was powerless to create a Greek nation. It wasreserved for the military genius of Alexander the Great, at last, byirresistible conquest, to bring the Greek Empire into being, to bedestroyed in turn by superior force.

    The Roman Empire almost achieved the complete political unity ofEurope, and bound parts of three continents under one rule, butthe corruption of the military power which held it together led toits inevitable dismemberment.

    Online Library of Liberty: The Rights of War and Peace (1901 ed.)

    PLL v7.0 (generated September, 2013) 15 http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/553

  • After the conflicts of the barbaric kingdoms which followed thedissolution of the Western Empire were ended by the predominanceof the Frankish monarchy, the world believed that the Pax Romanwas to be restored in Europe by the hand of Charles the Great; butthe disruptive forces were destined to prevail once more, and theHoly Roman Empire never succeeded in reviving the power ofancient Rome. And thus the dream of a universal monarchy, of acentral authority able to preside over kings and princes, adjustingtheir difficulties, and preserving the peace between them, was atlast proved futile.

    In each of the great national monarchies that had already risen orwere still rising on the ruins of imperial dominion, particularly inFrance, England, Holland, and the States of Germany, a continuousinternal conflict over questions of religion complicated thebitterness and destructiveness of foreign wars until Europe wasreorganized by the Peace of Westphalia, in 1648.

    It was in the midst of these wars that Grotius was born. He saw hisown country rising from a baptism of blood and all Europe rent andtorn by the awful struggle of the Thirty Years War, in the midst ofwhich his great work was written and to whose conclusion it servedas a guide and inspiration. The Empire, dismembered, had beenreduced to almost complete impotence, the Church had beendisrupted, and no international authority was anywhere visible.Amid the general wreck of institutions Grotius sought for light andguidance in great principles. Looking about him at the generalhavoc which war had made, the nations hostile, the faith of agesshattered, the passions of men destroying the commonwealthswhich nourished them, he saw that Europe possessed but onecommon bond, one vestige of its former unity,the human mind. Tothis he made appeal and upon its deepest convictions he sought toplant the Law of Nations.

    II. The Predecessors Of Grotius.It is historically accurate to say, that, until formulated by Grotius,Europe possessed no system of international law. Others hadpreceded him in touching upon certain aspects of the rights andduties of nations, but none had produced a system comparable tohis.

    The earliest attempt to formulate recognized international customswas the formation of the early maritime codes, rendered necessaryby the expansion of medival commerce from the end of theeleventh to the end of the sixteenth century, such as the Jugemensd Olron, adopted by the merchants of France, England, andSpain, and reissued under other names for the merchants of The

    Online Library of Liberty: The Rights of War and Peace (1901 ed.)

    PLL v7.0 (generated September, 2013) 16 http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/553

  • Netherlands and the Baltic. The Consolato del Mare, a moreelaborate compilation, was made, apparently at Barcelona, aboutthe middle of the fourteenth century, and accepted generally by thetraders of the chief maritime powers. It was in the cradle ofcommerce, therefore, that international law awoke toconsciousness.

    As the Church was often intrusted with the task of pacification, it isbut natural to look among her representatives for the earliestwriters on the laws of international relations. It is, in fact, amongthe theological moralists that we find the first students of thissubject. As early as 1564, a Spanish theologian, Vasquez, conceivedof a group of free states with reciprocal rights regulated by jusnaturale et gentium, without regard to a world-power, eitherimperial or ecclesiastical. In 1612, Saurez pointed out that a kind ofcustomary law had arisen from the usages of nations, and distinctlydescribed a society of interdependent states bound by fundamentalprinciples of justice.

    At the close of the fifteenth and the beginning of the sixteenthcenturies, a series of circumstances arose necessitating theextension of jurisprudence beyond its ancient boundaries, and thustending to produce a group of international jurists. Among thejuristic writers of this time are Balthazar Ayala, a Spanishjurisconsult, who died in 1584, having written in a historico-judicialspirit on the subject of war in his De Jure et Officiis Belli; ConradBrunus, a German Jurist, who wrote of the rights and duties ofambassadors in his De Legationibus, published in 1548; and pre-eminent above all, Albericus Gentilis, an Italian professor ofjurisprudence and lecturer at Oxford, a writer of force andoriginality, who published his De Legationibus in 1583 and hisDe Jure Belli in 1589.

    III. The Life And Personality Of Grotius.HUGO GROTIUS, to use the Latin form of his name by which he isbest known, or Hugo de Groot as he is called in Holland, descendedfrom a race of scholars and magistrates, was born at Delft, on April10th, 1583. His family history has been related with much detail byDe Burigny, in his Vic de Grotius, published in French atAmsterdam in 1754; and by Vorsterman van Oyen, in his Hugo deGroot en Zijn Gesclacht, a complete genealogy in Dutch, publishedat Amsterdam in 1883, which gives the descendants of Grotiusdown to the present generation. His origin is traced from aFrenchgentleman, Jean Cornets, who took up his residence in TheNetherlands in 1402. His descendant, Cornelius Cornets, marriedthe daughter of a burgomaster of Delft on condition that the futurechildren of this marriage should bear the name of their mothers

    Online Library of Liberty: The Rights of War and Peace (1901 ed.)

    PLL v7.0 (generated September, 2013) 17 http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/553

  • family, in order to perpetuate the distinction which it had achieved.The maternal name imposed by Cornelius Cornetss Dutch father-in-law, Dirk van Kraayenburg de Groot, was de Groot, meaning theGreat, and is said to have been bestowed for signal servicesrendered to his country by the first who had borne it four hundredyears before. From this marriage sprung a Hugo de Groot,distinguished for his learning in Greek, Latin, and Hebrew and fivetimes burgomaster of his native city. His eldest son, Cornelius, wasa noted linguist and mathematician who studied law in France andreceived high office in his own country, afterward becoming aprofessor of law and many times rector of the University of Leyden.Another son, John de Groot, the father of Hugo Grotius, studiedthere under the famous Lipsius, who speaks of him with the highestcommendation. Four times burgomaster of Delft, John de Grootbecame curator of the University of Leyden, a position which hefilled with great dignity and honor.

    In his earliest years the young Hugo gave evidence of marked andvaried ability. At eight he wrote Latin verses which betrayed poetictalent; at twelve he entered the University where he became apupil of that prince of scholars, Joseph Scaliger, who directed hisstudies; and at fifteen he defended with the greatest applauseLatin theses in philosophy and jurisprudence. His fame as a prodigyof diversified learning spread far and wide, and great scholarsdeclared they had never seen his equal.

    Grotius had won celebrity even in foreign lands when, in 1600, atthe age of seventeen, he was admitted to the bar. The youthfulprodigy had already accompanied the Grand Pensionary, John ofOldenbarneveld on a special embassy to France, where he waspresented to Henry IV., who bestowed upon him his portraittogether with a gold chain, and graciously called him The Miracleof Holland. At Orleans he was made a Doctor of Laws.

    Married in 1609 to Marie van Reigersberg, whose devotion wasworthy of his deep affection, and loaded with public honors, havingbeen named the official historian of the United Provinces and theadvocate-general of two provinces, Holland and Zeeland, Grotiusset his hand to a work entitled Mare Librum, in which hedefended the freedom of the sea and the maritime rights of hiscountry against the arrogant pretensions of the Portuguese insuppressing the commerce of other nations in Eastern waters,atreatise destined to become still more celebrated in the history ofinternational law by Seldens reply, Mare Clausum, written in1635. Next, turning his attention to the history of The Netherlands,he devoted himself for a time to his Annals of the War ofIndependence.

    Online Library of Liberty: The Rights of War and Peace (1901 ed.)

    PLL v7.0 (generated September, 2013) 18 http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/553

  • In 1613, Grotius added to his laurels as poet, jurist, and historianby entering the field of politics, and he was appointed Pensionary ofRotterdam upon the condition that he should continue in officeduring his own pleasure. It was during a visit to England upon adiplomatic mission in this same year that he met the great scholarIsaac Casaubon, who said in a letter to Daniel Heinsius: I cannotsay how happy I esteem myself in having seen so much of one sotruly great as Grotius. A wonderful man! This I knew him to bebefore I had seen him; but the rare excellence of that divine geniusno one can sufficiently feel who does not see his face and hear himspeak. Probity is stamped on all his features.

    Closely related by personal friendship as well as by his officialduties to the Grand Pensionary, John of Oldenbarneveld, Grotiuswas destined to share with that unfortunate patriot the proscriptionand punishment which Maurice of Orange visited upon the twoconfederates in the defense of religious tolerance. Risking all as theapostles of peace, they were soon condemned to be its martyrs.Oldenbarneveld, having incurred the bitter hatred of theStadtholder, was condemned to death by decapitation on May 12th,1619. Grotius, less offensive to Maurice on account of his youth andhis gracious personality, was sentenced six days later to perpetualimprisonment. On the 6th of June, 1619, he was incarcerated in thefortress of Loevestein.

    Rigorously treated at first, his docility and resignation soon wonthe respect and affection of his keepers. Writing materials andbooks were in time accorded him, and finally, on condition that shewould continue to share his captivity, he was granted the presenceof his wife. The studious prisoner and his devoted companioncompletely disarmed all suspicion of an intention to escape, and theponderous chest in which books came and went continued to bringperiodic consolation to the mind of the busy scholar. A treatise onthe truth of the Christian religion, a catechism for the use of hischildren, a digest of Dutch law, and other compositions served tooccupy and alleviate the weary months of confinement, until oneday when the time seemed opportune Madame Grotius secretlyinclosed her husband in the great chest and it was borne away bytwo soldiers. Descending the stone steps of the prison the bearersremarked that the trunk was heavy enough to contain an Arminian,but Madame Grotiuss jest on the heaviness of Arminian bookssmoothed over the suspicion, if one was really entertained, and thegreat jurist was sent in the chest safe to Gorcum, attended by afaithful domestic, where in the house of a friend the prisoneremerged without injury and in the guise of a stone mason hastenedto Antwerp. From Antwerp he took refuge in France, where hearrived in April, 1621, and was joined by his faithful wife at Paris inthe following October.

    Online Library of Liberty: The Rights of War and Peace (1901 ed.)

    PLL v7.0 (generated September, 2013) 19 http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/553

  • The bitterness of exile was now to be added to the miseries ofimprisonment, for Grotius was not only excluded from TheNetherlands, but in extreme poverty. His letters reveal his anguishof spirit at this period, but a generous Frenchman, Henri de Mme,placed his country house at Balagni at his disposition, and there,supported by a small pension, which Louis XIII had graciouslyaccorded him, though irregularly and tardily paid, Grotiuscommenced his great work, De Jure Belli ac Pacis, in the summerof 1623.

    Much speculation has been indulged in regarding the causes whichled to the composition of this masterpiece, but a recent discoveryhas rendered all this superfluous, as well as the ascription ofspecial merit to the Counselor Peyresc for suggesting the idea ofthe work. It is, indeed, to the pacific genious of Grotius more thanto all other causes that the world owes the origin of his great work;for it sprang from his dominant thought, ever brooding on thehorrors of war and the ways of peace, during more than twentyyears, and never wholly satisfied till its full expression wascompleted.

    In the winter of 1604, there had sprung out of his legal practice theidea of a treatise entitled De Jure Praedae, fully written out, butnever printed by its author. The manuscript remained unknown byall his biographers until it was brought to light and printed underthe auspices of Professor Fruin at The Hague in 1868. Thisinteresting document proves that not only the general conceptionbut the entire plan and even the arrangement of the De Jure Belliac Pacis were in the mind of Grotius when he was only twenty-oneyears of age. The difference between the earlier work and the lateris chiefly one of detail and amplification, the difference whichtwenty years of reading, experience, meditation and maturity offaculty would inevitably create.

    The curious may find in his letters the almost daily chronicle of hisprogress with his book to the time of its publication after excessivelabors lasting more than a year. In March, 1625, the printing of thefirst edition, which had occupied four months, was completed andcopies were sent to the fair at Frankfort. His honorarium as authorconsisted of two hundred copies, many of which he presented to hisfriends. From the sale of the remainder at a crown each, he was notable to reimburse his outlay. In the following August he wrote to hisfather and brother that if he had their approbation and that of afew friends, he would have no cause for complaint but would besatisfied. Louis XIII, to whom the work was dedicated, accepted thehomage of the author and a handsomely bound copy, but failed toexercise the grace customary with monarchs by according agratification. At Rome, the treatise was proscribed in the index in

    Online Library of Liberty: The Rights of War and Peace (1901 ed.)

    PLL v7.0 (generated September, 2013) 20 http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/553

  • 1627. Almost penniless and suffering from his protracted toil,Grotius seemed destined to neglect and oblivion, yet from his exilehe wrote to his brother: It is not necessary to ask anything for me.If my country can do without me, I can do without her. The world islarge enough.

    Invited to enter the service of France by Richelieu, Grotius wouldnot accept the conditions which the Cardinal wished toimpose,such at least is the inevitable inference from his letters.His pension was not paid and his circumstances became so seriousthat one of his children had but a single coat. At length, pushed tothe utmost extremity of want and instigated by his energetic wife,Grotius resolved to return to Holland. Driven from Rotterdam toAmsterdam, where he hoped to settle down as a lawyer, the StatesGeneral twice ordered his arrest and named a price for his deliveryto the authorities. The new Stadtholder, Frederick Henry, who,before succeeding his brother Maurice, had written kindly toGrotius after his escape from imprisonment, now approved hisproscription. Abandoned by his prince as well as by hiscountrymen, Grotius once more turned his face toward exile andset out for Hamburg.

    IV. The Work Of Grotius.It may be of interest at this point in the career of Grotius todescribe briefly the character of the great work which was soon towin for him a new celebrity, and materially change his prospects inlife.

    The inspiration of his De Jure Belli ac Pacis was the love of peace,yet he was far from being one of those visionaries who totallycondemn the use of armed force and proscribe all war as wrongand unnecessary. On the contrary, he seeks to discover when, how,and by whom war may be justly conducted.

    His plan of treatment is as follows:

    In the First Book, he considers whether any war is just, which leadsto the distinction between public and private war, and this in turnto a discussion of the nature and embodiment of sovereignty.

    In the Second Book, the causes from which wars arise, the natureof property and personal rights which furnish their occasions, theobligations that pertain to ownership, the rule of royal succession,the rights secured by compacts, the force and interpretation oftreaties, and kindred subjects are examined.

    Online Library of Liberty: The Rights of War and Peace (1901 ed.)

    PLL v7.0 (generated September, 2013) 21 http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/553

  • In the Third Book, the question is asked, What is lawful war?which prepares for the consideration of military conventions andthe methods by which peace is to be secured.

    From the authority of the Empire and the Church, no longereffectual as an international agency, Grotius appeals to Humanityas furnishing the true law of nations. Beginning with the idea thatthere is a kinship among men established by nature, he sees in thisbond a community of rights. The society of nations, including as itdoes the whole human race, needs the recognition of rights asmuch as mere local communities. As nations are but largeraggregations of individuals, each with its own corporate coherence,the accidents of geographic boundary do not obliterate that humandemand for justice which springs from the nature of man as amoral being. There is, therefore, as a fundamental bond of humansocieties, a Natural Law, which, when properly apprehended, isperceived to be the expression and dictate of right reason. It is thusupon the nature of man as a rational intelligence that Grotiusfounds his system of universal law.

    As this law of human nature is universally binding wherever menexist, it cannot be set aside by the mere circumstances of time andplace, whence it results that there is a law of war as well as a lawof peace. As this law applies to the commencement of armedconflicts, war is never to be undertaken except to assert rights, andwhen undertaken is never to be carried on except within the limitsof rights. It is true that in the conflict of arms laws must be silent,but only civil laws, which govern in times of peace. Those lawswhich are perpetual, which spring from the nature of man as man,and not from his particular civil relations, continue even duringstrife and constitute the laws of war. To deny these, or to disobeythem, implies a repudiation of human nature itself and of the divineauthority which has invested it with rights and obligations. Todisavow the imperative character of these perpetual laws, is torevert to barbarism.

    It is necessary, however to distinguish between Natural Law, thatprinciple of justice which springs from mans rational nature, andConventional Law, which results from his agreements andcompacts. Natural Law remains ever the same, but institutionschange. While the study of abstract justice, apart from all that hasits origin in the will or consent of men, would enable us to create acomplete system of jurisprudence, there is another source whichmust not be neglected, since men have established the sanctity ofcertain rules of conduct by solemn convention.

    The Law of Nations does not consist, therefore, of a mere body ofdeductions derived from general principles of justice, for there is

    Online Library of Liberty: The Rights of War and Peace (1901 ed.)

    PLL v7.0 (generated September, 2013) 22 http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/553

  • also a body of doctrine based upon consent; and it is this system ofvoluntarily recognized obligations which distinguishes internationaljurisprudence from mere ethical speculation or moral theory. Thereare customs of nations as well as a universally accepted law ofnature, and it is in this growth of practically recognized rules ofprocedure that we trace the evolution of law internationaljusinter gentesas a body of positive jurisprudence.

    It is evident that the mind of Grotius is continually struggling toestablish a science upon this positive basis, and it is this whichgives a distinctive character to his effort. The great writers of allages are cited with a superfluous lavishness, not so much tosupport his claims by an aggregation of individual opinions stillless to display his erudition, as his critics have sometimescomplainedas to give a historic catholicity to his doctrine byshowing that the laws he is endeavoring to formulate have, in fact,been accepted in all times and by all men. For this purpose also, hemakes abundant use of the great authorities on Roman Law, whosedoctrines and formulas were certain to carry conviction to theminds of those whom he desired to convince.

    It is needless, perhaps, to point out that the work of Grotius is notand could not be a work of permanent authority as a digest ofinternational law. His own wise appreciation of the positive andhistorical elementthe authority derived from customshouldexempt him from the pretense of absolute finality. It is the Book ofGenesis only that he has given us, but it is his indefeasibledistinction to have recorded the creation of order out of chaos inthe great sphere of international relationship, justly entitling him tothe honor accorded to him by the spontaneous consent of futuretimes as the Father of International Jurisprudence.

    It is not difficult after more than three centuries of thought andexperience to point out the defects in his doctrine. If he justifiesslavery, it is not without ingenuity; for, he argues, if a man may sellhis labor, why not his liberty? and if the conqueror may impose hiswill upon the property of the vanquished, why not also upon hisperson? If he identifies sovereignty with supreme power withoutany adequate conception of its ethical basis, he is at least asadvanced in his thinking as the conceptions of his time, which hadnot yet grasped the idea of the state as a moral organism. If he hasno adequate notion of neutrality, believing it to be the duty of anation to enlist its energies for what it deems the right side, ratherthan to disavow all responsibility for actions foreign to its owninterests, he is at least supported in this by the opinion of themultitude even at the present time; and even among jurists themodern conception of neutrality is hardly a century old. If the newschools of jurisprudence make light of Natural Law as a foundation

    Online Library of Liberty: The Rights of War and Peace (1901 ed.)

    PLL v7.0 (generated September, 2013) 23 http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/553

  • of public and private rights, it is not certain that Grotius may notyet be vindicated as representing a doctrine at least as clear as anyother which has been substituted for it. But, finally, to all thesecriticisms it may be answered, that no great thinker can be justlyestimated except in relation to his predecessors andcontemporaries. Measured by these, Grotius stands alone amongthe jurists of his century for originality of thought and power ofexposition.

    V. The Influence Of Grotiuss Work.It was during his sojourn in Hamburg in 1633, eight years after thepublication of his De Jure, and while he was still suffering frompainful pecuniary embarrassment, that Europe suddenly awoke to asense of his importance; and, almost at one time, Poland, Denmark,Spain, England, and Sweden all extended friendly invitationsurging him to enter into their public service. His fame as a juristhad become international and, rudely repelled by his nativeHolland, he became the center of European interest. GustavusAdolphus had placed the work of Grotius along side his Bible underhis soldiers pillow, as he prosecuted his campaigns in the ThirtyYears War. The first edition of that work, written in Latin, thecosmopolitan language of learned Europe, had been quicklyexhausted and widely scattered. Another had soon been called forat Paris, but the death of Buon, the publisher, created obstacles toits appearance. A second edition had appeared at Frankfort in1626, another at Amsterdam in 1631, and still another with notesby the author in 1632. The book had aroused the thought of kingsas well as of scholars, and in the circles of high influenceeverywhere in Europe the name of Grotius had become well known.His book had excited the most opposite sentiments and awakenedthe most contradictory judgments, but among lawyers andstatesmen its reception was from the first generally marked byadmiration. In spite of exile, poverty, and misfortune, Grotius hadbecome a European celebrity and was about to enter into thereward of his labors. He had created a code for war and aprogramme of peace, and henceforth no statesman could afford toneglect him.

    Gustavus Adolphus, the king of Sweden, before his death on thebattlefield of Ltzen, had commended Grotius to his greatChancellor, Oxenstiern. By the death of Gustavus the Chancellorhad, in 1633, recently come into the regency of the kingdom at acritical moment when a retreat from the bitter contest with theEmpire seemed to be foredoomed unless prevented by the supportand friendship of France. Recalling the commendation of the lateking, Oxenstiern sought and found in Grotius an ambassador ofSweden to negotiate a new Franco-Swedish alliance. Accepting this

    Online Library of Liberty: The Rights of War and Peace (1901 ed.)

    PLL v7.0 (generated September, 2013) 24 http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/553

  • appointment in 1634, Grotius arrived at Paris on his diplomaticmission on March 2d, 1635.

    Richelieu, having failed to draw the great jurist into the orbit of hisinfluence as a satellite, resented his appearance in a character soinfluential and honorable as that of ambassador of Sweden, andGrotius made little progress in his negotiation. Preoccupied withliterature, he took more interest in the composition of a sacredtragedy on The Flight into Egypt than in reminding France of theexisting treaty of Heilbronn or consolidating the new Franco-Swedish alliance. Where Grotius the theorist failed, Oxenstiern, thepractical statesman, by a few dexterous strokes of diplomacyduring a brief visit to Paris, easily succeeded; and the ambassadorsmission was simplified to the rle of a mere observer and reporterof occurrences.

    By taste, nature, and training, Grotius was a jurist and not adiplomatist, and he soon realized that the two vocations, if notdiametrically opposed, are at least separated from each other by avast interval. His diplomatic correspondence betrays the keenobserver and the conscientious moralist rather than theaccomplished negotiator. Among the observations recorded in hisdispatches, one may be quoted as an example of his penetrationand his humor. Speaking of the Dauphin, the future Louis XIV, hesays: His frightful and precocious avidity is a bad omen forneighboring peoples; for he is at present on his ninth nurse, whomhe is rending and murdering as he has the others!

    It is painful to behold the great father of internationaljurisprudence descending in his dispatches to petty details ofprecedence and alienating from himself the sympathies of hiscolleagues by ridiculous ceremonial pathies of his colleagues byridiculous ceremonial pretensions. He would no longer visitMazarin, because the Cardinal insisted on calling him Eminenceinstead of Excellence; Grotius considering this distinction of termsa slight upon his rank as ambassador. So persistent was he in thesefollies and so rancorous were the feuds that the apostle of peaceelicited that, in December, 1636, less than two years after hisarrival at Paris, he advised Sweden to send to France a simpleCharg dAffaires, instead of an ambassador, in order to restorediplomatic relations.

    His quarrels concerning precedence, which rendered him an objectof ridicule at the French Court, were not the only griefs of theambassador of Sweden. Inadequately recompensed, he was obligedto wait two years for his salary and finally, being reduced to acondition in which he could no longer maintain existenceotherwise, he was compelled to demand of the royal treasury of

    Online Library of Liberty: The Rights of War and Peace (1901 ed.)

    PLL v7.0 (generated September, 2013) 25 http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/553

  • France a part of the subsidies promised to the army of his adoptedcountry. Weary of his importunities, the France governmentrepeatedly requested his recall. Disgusted with his mission, Grotiusat last abandoned the duties of his office to the intriguingadventurer, Cerisante, who was sent to aid him, and buried himselfin his books until his return to Sweden at his own request in 1645.

    Queen Christina of Sweden, a patroness of scholars, desirous ofaiding Grotius and of retaining him in the service of her kingdom,made many offers and promises, but their execution beingdeferred, he became impatient of his lot, refused a position ascounselor of state, and resolved to leave the country. His plan toabandon Stockholm secretly was prevented by a messenger of thequeen who followed him to the port where he intended to embarkand induced him to return for a farewell audience. With ahandsome present of money and silver plate he took passage on avessel placed at his disposition to convey him to Lbeck. Off thecoast near Dantzic a violent tempest arose. On the 17th of August,1645, the vessel was driven ashore and Grotius, overcome by histrying experiences, was taken ill at Rostock, where a few days laterhe passed away.

    The later years of his life had been chiefly devoted to plans for theestablishment of peace in the religious world, whose dissensionsgave him great distress of mind.

    The country of his birth, which had so long denied him citizenship,received him at last to the silent hospitality of the tomb. His bodywas taken to Delft, his native town, where his name is now held ingrateful reverence.

    At the time when Grotius left Stockholm, the last of theplenipotentiaries had arrived at Mnster and Osnabrck to attendthe great European congress convoked to terminate the hostilitiesof the Thirty Years War. It is a tradition, but incapable ofsatisfactory proof, that it was with the purpose of being present atthe councils of this congress that the author of De Jure Belli acPacis left Sweden for Germany. However this may be, it is certainthat the mediation of the king of Denmark at Osnabrck and of thepapal legate at Mnster, though unsuccessful, was in accordancewith the idea of Grotius expressed in the words: It would beuseful, and indeed it is almost necessary, that certain congresses ofChristian powers should be held, in which controversies that havearisen among some of them may be decided by others who are notinterested. The immediate establishment of an internationaltribunal, evidently contemplated in this suggestion, was not inharmony with the temper of those times; but it cannot be doubtedthat the Peace of Westphalia, whose treaties were to form a code of

    Online Library of Liberty: The Rights of War and Peace (1901 ed.)

    PLL v7.0 (generated September, 2013) 26 http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/553

  • public law for Europe, was to a great degree an embodiment of theprinciples which Grotius was the first to enunciate.

    His De Jure Belli ac Pacis had already become a classic evenbefore the authors death, and special professorships were soonfounded in the universities to expound its principles. It would betedious to name the numerous editions, translations, andcommentaries which have given it an exceptional place in theliterature of Europe. This task has been in part performed,however, by Dr. Rogge in his Bibliotheca Grotiana, published atThe Hague in 1883, and intended to be a full bibliography ofGrotiuss works. The whole number of titles included is 462, butthey do not comprise the writings of the generations of jurists whohave been inspired by the great master or of the critics andbiographers who have discussed his life and work.

    Tardily, but with full contrition for the bitter wrong done to one ofher greatest and noblest sons, the memory of Grotius has receivedfrom his native land abundant recognition and commemoration.The appropriate tomb that marks his resting place in the NieuweKerk at Delft, symbolical of his learning, genius, and renown, waserected in 1781. On the 17th of September, 1886, a noble statue ofthe great jurist was unveiled in the public square of his native townin front of the church which contains his tomb. Thus, more than acentury after his death, and again still another century later,Holland has paid her tribute of respect to her illustrious citizen.

    The later years have also brought new honors to Grotiuss feet. Atthe recent Peace Conference at The Hague was completed thegreat structure of international comity whose corner stone was laidby him in 1625. It was most fitting that an international congresscalled in the interest of peace should blend with the negotiation ofconventions for the pacific settlement of disputes between nationsby a permanent tribunal, and for the amelioration of the laws ofwar, a celebration of the distinguished writer whose great thoughthad at last borne such precious fruits. In pursuance of instructionsreceived from the Secretary of State, the United States Commissioninvited their colleagues in the congress, the heads of the Dutchuniversities, and the high civic authorities to join with them inobserving the 4th of July by celebrating the memory of the greatjurist. With appropriate exercises in the apse of the old church,near the monument of Grotius and mausoleum of William theSilent, the representatives of twenty-six nations gathered to do himhonor. A beautiful commemorative wreath of silver was laid uponGrotiuss tomb bearing the inscription:

    Online Library of Liberty: The Rights of War and Peace (1901 ed.)

    PLL v7.0 (generated September, 2013) 27 http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/553

  • to THE MEMORY OF HUGO GROTIUS in Reverence andGratitudefrom the United States of Americaon theOccasion of theInternational Peace ConferenceatThe Hague July 4th, 1899.

    An eloquent oration by the Honorable Andrew D. White,Ambassador of the United States to Germany, and the head of theCommission, followed by other appropriate addresses, recalled thedebt of mankind to the author of De Jure Belli ac Pacis and thusthe plenipotentiaries of the nineteenth century did homage to theexile of the sixteenth who had taught the world that even in theshock and storm of battle humanity cannot escape the dominion ofits own essential laws, and that even independent states areanswerable before the bar of human nature for obedience toprinciples imposed by a Power higher than the prerogatives ofprinces or the will of nations.

    David J. Hill

    THE RIGHTS Of WAR AND PEACE, IncludingThe Law Of Nature And Of Nations.

    BOOK I.

    CHAPTER I.Of WarDefinition of WarRight, of Governors and of thegoverned, and of equalsRight as a Quality divided into Facultyand FitnessFaculty denoting Power, Property, and CreditDividedinto Private and SuperiorRight as a Rule, natural andvoluntaryLaw of Nature dividedProofs of the Law ofNatureDivision of Rights into human and divineHumanexplainedDivine statedMosaic Law not binding upon Christians.

    I. The disputes arising among those who are held together by nocommon bond of civil laws to decide their dissensions, like theancient Patriarchs, who formed no national community, or thenumerous, unconnected communities, whether under the directionof individuals, or kings, or persons invested with Sovereign power,as the leading men in an aristocracy, and the body of the people ina republican government; the disputes, arising among any of these,all bear a relation to the circumstances of war or peace. Butbecause war is undertaken for the sake of peace, and there is nodispute, which may not give rise to war, it will be proper to treat allsuch quarrels, as commonly happen, between nations, as an articlein the rights of war: and then war itself will lead us to peace, as toits proper end.

    Online Library of Liberty: The Rights of War and Peace (1901 ed.)

    PLL v7.0 (generated September, 2013) 28 http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/553

  • II. In treating of the rights of war, the first point, that we have toconsider, is, what is war, which is the subject of our inquiry, andwhat is the right, which we seek to establish. Cicero styled war acontention by force. But the practice has prevailed to indicate bythat name, not an immediate action, but a state of affairs; so thatwar is the state of contending parties, considered as such. Thisdefinition, by its general extent, comprises those wars of everydescription, that will form the subject of the present treatise. Norare single combats excluded from this definition. For, as they are inreality more ancient than public wars, and undoubtedly, of thesame nature, they may therefore properly be comprehended underone and the same name. This agrees very well with the truederivation of the word. For the Latin word, Bellum,war, comes fromthe old word, Duellum, a duel, as Bonus from Duonus, and Bis fromDuis. Now Duellum was derived from Duo; and there by implied adifference between two persons, in the same sense as we termpeace, Unity, from Unitas, for a contrary reason. So the Greekword, commonly used to signify war, expresses in its original, anidea of multitude. The ancient Greeks likewise called it, whichimports a disunion of minds; just as by the term they meant thedissolution of the parts of the body. Nor does the use of the word,War, contradict this larger acceptation of it. For though some timesit is only applied to the quarrels of states, yet that is no objection,as it is evident that a general name is often applied to someparticular object, entitled to peculiar distinction. Justice is notincluded in the definition of war, because the very point to bedecided is, whether any war be just, and what war may be socalled. Therefore we must make a distinction between war itself,and the justice of it.

    III. As the Rights of War is the title, by which this treatise isdistinguished, the first inquiry, as it has been already observed, is,whether any war be just, and, in the next place, what constitutesthe justice of that war. For, in this place, right signifies nothingmore than what is just, and that, more in a negative than a positivesense; so that right is that, which is not unjust. Now any thing isunjust, which is repugnant to the nature of society, establishedamong rational creatures. Thus for instance, to deprive another ofwhat belongs to him, merely for ones own advantage, is repugnantto the law of nature, as Cicero observes in the fifth Chapter of histhird book of offices; and, by way of proof, he says that, if thepractice were general, all society and intercourse among men mustbe overturned. Florentinus, the Lawyer, maintains that is impiousfor one man to form designs against another, as nature hasestablished a degree of kindred amongst us. On this subject,Seneca remarks that, as all the members of the human body agreeamong themselves, because the preservation of each conduces tothe welfare of the whole, so men should forbear from mutual

    Online Library of Liberty: The Rights of War and Peace (1901 ed.)

    PLL v7.0 (generated September, 2013) 29 http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/553

  • injuries, as they were born for society, which cannot subsist unlessall the parts of it are defended by mutual forbearance and goodwill. But as there is one kind of social tie founded upon an equality,for instance, among brothers, citizens, friends, allies, and anotheron pre-eminence, as Aristotle styles it, subsisting between parentsand children, masters and servants, sovereigns and subjects, Godand men. So justice takes place either amongst equals, or betweenthe governing and the governed parties, notwithstanding theirdifference of rank. The former of these, if I am not mistaken, maybe called the right of equality, and the latter the right of superiority.

    IV. There is another signification of the word right, different fromthis, but yet arising from it, which relates directly to the person. Inwhich sense, right is a moral quality annexed to the person, justlyentitling him to possess some particular privilege, or to performsome particular act. This right is annexed to the person, although itsometimes follows the things, as the services of lands, which arecalled real rights, in opposition to those merely personal. Notbecause these rights are not annexed to persons, but thedistinction is made, because they belong to the persons only whopossess some particular things. This moral quality, when perfect iscalled a faculty; when imperfect, an aptitude. The former answersto the act, and the latter to the power, when we speak of naturalthings.

    V. Civilians call a faculty that Right, which every man has to hisown; but we shall hereafter, taking it in its strict and proper sense,call it a right. This right comprehends the power, that we have overourselves, which is called liberty, and the power, that we have overothers, as that of a father over his children, and of a master overhis slaves. It likewise comprehends property, which is eithercomplete or imperfect; of the latter kind is the use or possession ofany thing without the property, or power of alienating it, or pledgesdetained by the creditors till payment be made. There is a thirdsignification, which implies the power of demanding what is due, towhich the obligation upon the party indebted, to discharge what isowing, corresponds.

    VI. Right, strictly taken, is again twofold, the one, private,established for the advantages of each individual, the other,superior, as involving the claims, which the state has uponindividuals, and their property, for the public good. Thus the Regalauthority is above that of a father and a master, and the Sovereignhas a greater right over the property of his subjects, where thepublic good is concerned, than the owners themselves have. Andwhen the exigencies of the state require a supply, every man ismore obliged to contribute towards it, than to satisfy his creditors.

    Online Library of Liberty: The Rights of War and Peace (1901 ed.)

    PLL v7.0 (generated September, 2013) 30 http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/553

  • VII. Aristotle distinguishes aptitude or capacity, by the name ofworth or merit, and Michael of Ephesus, gives the epithet ofsuitable or becoming to the equality established by this rule ofmerit.

    IX. * There is also a third signification of the word Right, which hasthe same meaning as Law, taken in its most extensive sense, todenote a rule of moral action, obliging us to do what is proper. Wesay obliging us. For the best counsels or precepts, if they lay usunder no obligation to obey them, cannot come under thedenomination of law or right. Now as to permission,? it is no act ofthe law, but only the silence of the law, it however prohibits any onefrom impeding another in doing what the law permits. But we havesaid, the law obliges us to do what is proper, not simply what isjust; because, under this notion, right belongs to the substance notonly of justice, as we have explained it, but of all other virtues. Yetfrom giving the name of a right to that, which is proper, a moregeneral acceptation of the word justice has been derived. The bestdivision of right, in this general meaning, is to be found in Aristotle,who, defining one kind to be natural, and the other voluntary, callsit a lawful right in the strictest sense of the word law; and sometimes an instituted right. The same difference is found among theHebrews, who, by way of distinction, in speaking, call that naturalright, precepts, and the voluntary right, statutes: the former ofwhich the Septuagint call and the latter .

    X. Natural right is the deictate of right reason, shewing the moralturpitude, or moral necessity,* of any act from its agreement ordisagreement with a rational nature, and consequently that such anact is either forbidden or commanded by God, the author of nature.The actions, upon which such a dictate is given, are either bindingor unlawful in themselves, and therefore necessarily understood tobe commanded or forbidden by God. This mark distinguishesnatural right, not only from human law, but from the law, whichGod himself has been pleased to reveal, called, by some, thevoluntary divine right, which does not command or forbid things inthemselves either binding or unlawful, but makes them unlawful byits prohibition, and binding by its command. But, to understandnatural right, we must observe that some things are said to belongto that right, not properly, but, as the schoolmen say, by way ofaccommodation. These are not repugnant to natural right, as wehave already observed that those things are called just, in whichthere is no injustice. Some times also, by a wrong use of the word,those things which reason shews to be proper, or better than thingsof an opposite kind, although not binding, are said to belong tonatural right.

    Online Library of Liberty: The Rights of War and Peace (1901 ed.)

    PLL v7.0 (generated September, 2013) 31 http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/553

  • We must farther remark, that natural right relates not only to thosethings that exist independent of the human will, but to many things,which necessarily follow the exercise of that will. Thus property, asnow in use, was at first a creature of the human will. But, after itwas established, one man was prohibited by the law of nature fromseizing the property of another against his will. Wherefore, Paulusthe Lawyer said, that theft is expressly forbidden by the law ofnature. Ulpian condemns it as infamous in its own nature; to whoseauthority that of Euripides may be added, as may be seen in theverses of Helena:

    For God himself hates violence, and will not have us to grow richby rapine, but by lawful gains. That abundance, which is the fruit ofunrighteousness, is an abomination. The air is common to men, theearth also, where every man, in the ample enjoyment of hispossession, must refrain from doing violence or injury to that ofanother.

    Now the Law of Nature is so unalterable, that it cannot be changedeven by God himself. For although the power of God is infinite, yetthere are some things, to which it does not extend. Because thethings so expressed would have no true meaning, but imply acontradiction. Thus two and two must make four, nor is it possibleto be otherwise; nor, again, can what is really evil not be evil. Andthis is Aristotles meaning, when he says, that some things are nosooner named, than we discover their evil nature. For as thesubstance of things in their nature and existence depends uponnothing but themselves; so there are qualities inseparablyconnected with their being and essence. Of this kind is the evil ofcertain actions, compared with the nature of a reasonable being.Therefore God himself suffers his actions to be judged by this rule,as may be seen in the xviiith chap. of Gen. 25. Isa. v. 3. Ezek. xviii.25. Jer. ii. 9. Mich. vi. 2. Rom. ii. 6., iii. 6. Yet it sometimes happensthat, in those cases, which are decided by the law of nature, theundiscerning are imposed upon by an appearance of change.Whereas in reality there is no change in the unalterable law ofnature, but only in the things appointed by it, and which are liableto variation. For example, if a creditor forgive me the debt, which Iowe him, I am no longer bound to pay it, not because the law ofnature has ceased to command the payment of a just debt, butbecause my debt, by a release, has ceased to be a debt. On thistopic, Arrian in Epictetus argues rightly, that the borrowing ofmoney is not the only requisite to make a debt, but there must bethe additional circumstance of the loan remaining undischarged.Thus if God should command the life, or property of any one to betaken away, the act would not authorise murder or robbery, wordswhich always include a crime. But that cannot be murder orrobbery, which is done by the express command of Him, who is the

    Online Library of Liberty: The Rights of War and Peace (1901 ed.)

    PLL v7.0 (generated September, 2013) 32 http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/553

  • sovereign Lord of our lives and of all things. There are also somethings allowed by the law of nature, not absolutely, but according toa certain state of affairs. Thus, by the law of nature, beforeproperty was introduced, every one had a right to the use ofwhatever he found unoccupied; and, before laws were enacted, toavenge his personal injuries by force.

    XI. The distinction found in the books of the Roman Law, assigningone unchangeable right to brutes in common with man, which in amore limited sense they call the law of nature, and appropriatinganother to men, which they frequently call the Law of Nations, isscarcely of any real use. For no beings, except those that can formgeneral maxims, are capable of possessing a right, which Hesiod,has placed in a clear point of view, observing that the supremeBeing has appointed laws for men; but permitted wild beasts,fishes, and birds to devour each other for food. For they havenothing like justice, the best gift, bestowed upon men.

    Cicero, in his first book of offices, says, we do not talk of the justiceof horses or lions. In conformity to which, Plutarch, in the life ofCato the elder, observes, that we are formed by nature to use lawand justice towards men only. In addition to the above, Lactantiusmay be cited, who, in his fifth book, says that in all animals devoidof reason we see a natural bias of self-love. For they hurt others tobenefit themselves; because they do not know the evil of doingwillful hurt. But it is not so with man, who, possessing theknowledge of good and evil, refrains, even with inconvenience tohimself, from doing hurt. Polybius, relating the manner in whichmen first entered into society, concludes, that the injuries done toparents or benefactors inevitably provoke the indignation ofmankind, giving an additional reason, that as understanding andreflection form the great difference between men and otheranimals, it is evident they cannot transgress the bounds of thatdifference like other animals, without exciting Universalabhorrence of their conduct. But if ever Justice is attributed tobrutes, it is done improperly, from some shadow and trace ofreason they may possess. But it is not material to the nature ofright, whether the actions appointed by the law of nature, such asthe care of our offspring, are common to us with other animals ornot, or, like the worship of God, are peculiar to man.

    XII. The existence of the Law of Nature is proved by two kinds ofargument, a priori, and a posteriori, the former a more abstruse,and the latter a more popular method of proof. We are said toreason a priori, when we show the agreement or disagreement ofany thing with a reasonable and social nature; but a posteriori,when without absolute proof, but only upon probability, any thing isinferred to accord with the law of nature, because it is received as

    Online Library of Liberty: The Rights of War and Peace (1901 ed.)

    PLL v7.0 (generated September, 2013) 33 http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/553

  • such among all, or at least the more civilized nations. For a generaleffect can only arise from a general cause. Now scarce any othercause can be assigned for so general an opinion, but the commonsense, as it is called, of mankind. There is a sentence of Hesiod thathas been much praised, that opinions which have prevailedamongst many nations, must have some foundation. Heraclitus,establishing common reason as the best criterion of truth, says,those things are certain which generally appear so. Among otherauthorities, we may quote Aristotle, who says it is a strong proof inour favour, when all appear to agree with what we say, and Ciceromaintains that the consent of all nations in any case is to beadmitted for the law of nature. Seneca is of the same opinion, anything, says he, appearing the same to all men is a proof of its truth.Quintilian says, we hold those things to be true, in which all menagree. We have called them the more civilized nations, and notwithout reason. For, as Porphyry well observes, some nations are sostrange that no fair judgment of human nature can be formed fromthem, for it would be erroneous. Andronicus, the Rhodian says, thatwith men of a right and sound understanding, natural justice isunchangeable. Nor does it alter the case, though men of disorderedand perverted minds think otherwise. For he who should deny thathoney is sweet, because it appears not so to men of a distemperedtaste, would be wrong. Plutarch too agrees entirely with what hasbeen said, as appears from a passage in his life of Pompey,affirming that man neither was, nor is, by nature, a wild unsociablecreature. But it is the corruption of his nature which makes him so:yet by acquiring new habits, by changing his place, and way ofliving, he may be reclaimed to his original gentleness. Aristotle,taking a description of man from his peculiar qualities, makes himan animal of a gentle nature, and in another part of his works, heobserves, that in considering the nature of man, we are to take ourlikeness from nature in its pure, and not in its corrupt state.

    XIII. It has been already remarked, that there is another kind ofright, which is the voluntary right, deriving its origin from the will,and is either human or divine.

    XIV. We will begin with the human as more generally known. Nowthis is either a civil right, or a right more or less extensive than thecivil right. The civil right is that which is derived from the civilpower. The civil power is the sovereign power of the state. A stateis a perfect body of free men, united together in order to enjoycommon rights and advantages. The less extensive right, and notderived from the civil power itself, although subject to it, is various,comprehending the authority of parents over children, mastersover servants, and the like. But the law of nations is a moreextensive right, deriving its authority from the consent of all, or atleast of many nations.

    Online Library of Liberty: The Rights of War and Peace (1901 ed.)

    PLL v7.0 (generated September, 2013) 34 http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/553

  • It was proper to add many, because scarce any right can be foundcommon to all nations, except the law of nature, which itself too isgenerally called the law of nations. Nay, frequently in one part ofthe world, that is held for the law of nations, which is not so inanother. Now this law of nations is proved in the same manner asthe unwritten civil law, and that is by the continual experience andtestimony of the Sages of the Law. For this law, as Dio Chrysostomwell observes, is the discoveries made by experience and time. Andin this we derive great advantage from the writings of eminenthistorians.

    XV. The very meaning of the words divine voluntary right, showsthat it springs from the divine will, by which it is distinguished fromnatural law, which, it has already been observed, is called divinealso. This law admits of what Anaxarchus said, as Plutarch relatesin the life of Alexander, though without sufficient accuracy, thatGod does not will a thing, because it is just, but that it is just, orbinding, because God wills it. Now this law was given either tomankind in general, or to one particular people. We find threeperiods, at which it was given by God to the human race, the first ofwhich was immediately after the creation of man, the second uponthe restoration of mankind after the flood, and the third upon thatmore glorious restoration through Jesus Christ. These three lawsundoubtedly bind all men, as soon, as they come to a sufficientknowledge of them.

    XVI. Of all nations there is but one, to which God particularlyvouchsafed to give laws, and that was the people of Israel, whomMoses thus addresses in the fourth Chap. Of Deuteronomy, ver. 7.What nation is there so great who hath God so nigh unto them, asthe Lord our God is in all things that we call upon him for? Andwhat nation is there so great, who have statutes and judgments sorighteous, as all this law, which I set before you this day! And thePsalmist in the cxlvii. Psalm, God shewed his word unto Jacob, hisstatutes and ordinances unto Israel. He hath not dealt so with anynation, and as for his judgments they have not known them. Norcan we doubt but that those Jews, with whom we may classTryphon in his dispute with Justin, are mistaken, who suppose thateven strangers, if they wish to be saved, must submit to the yoke ofthe Mosaic Law. For a law does not bind those, to whom it has notbeen given. But it speaks personally to those, who are immediatelyunder it. Hear O Israel, and we read everywhere of the covenantmade with them, by which they became the peculiar people of God.Maimonides acknowledges and proves the truth of this from thexxxiii. Chapter and fourth verse of Deuteronomy.

    But among the Hebrews themselves there were always living somestrangers, persons devout and fearing God, such was the

    Online Library of Liberty: The Rights of War and Peace (1901 ed.)

    PLL v7.0 (generated September, 2013) 35 http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/553

  • Syrophoenician woman, mentioned in the Gospel of St. Matthew, xv.22. Cornelius the Centurion. Acts. x. the devout Greeks, Acts xviii.6. Sojourners, or strangers, also are mentioned. Levit. xxv. 47.These, as the Hebrew Rabbis themselves inform us, were obliged toobserve the laws given to Adam and Noah, to abstain from idolsand blood, and other things, that were prohibited; but not in thesame manner to observe the laws peculiar to the people of Israel.Therefore though the Israelites were not allowed to eat the flesh ofa beast, that had died a natural death; yet the strangers livingamong them were permitted. Deut. Xiv. 21. Except in someparticular laws, where it was expressly said, that strangers no lessthan the native inhabitants were obliged to observe them.Strangers also, who came from other countries, and were notsubject to the Jewish laws, might worship God in the temple ofJerusalem, but standing in a place separate and distinct from theIsraelites. I. Kings viii. 41. 2 Mac. iii. 35. John xii 20. Acts viii. 27.Nor did Elisha ever signify to Naaman the Syrian, nor Jonas to theNinevites, nor Daniel to Nebuchadnezzar, nor the other Prophets tothe Tyrians, the Moabites, the Egyptians, to whom they wrote, thatit was necessary for them to adopt the Mosaic Law.

    What has been said of the whole law of Moses applies tocircumcision, which was a kind of introduction to the law. Yet withthis difference that the Israelites alone were bound by the MosaicLaw, but the whole posterity of Abraham by the law ofcircumcision. From hence we are informed by Jewish and GreekHistorians, that the Idumaeans, or Edomites were compelled by theJews to be circumcised. Wherefore there is reason to believe thatthe numerous nations, who, besides the Israelites, practicedcircumcision, and who are mentioned by Herodotus, Strabo, Philo,Justin, Origen, Clemens, Alexandrinus, Epiphanius, and Jerom,were descended from Ishmael, Esau, or the posterity of Keturah.But what St. Paul says, Rom. ii. 14. holds good of all other nations;that the Gentiles, not having the law, yet doing by nature the thingscontained in the law, become a law to themselves. Here the wordnature may be taken for the primitive source of moral obligation;or, referring it to the preceding parts of the Epistle, it may signifythe knowledge, which the Gentiles acquired of themselves withoutinstruction, in opposition to the knowledge derived to the Jewsfrom the law, which was instilled into them from their cradle, andalmost from their birth. So the Gentiles show the work, or themoral precepts of the law, written in their hearts, their consciencesalso bearing witness, and their thoughts the mean while accusingor else excusing one another. And again in the 26th ver.; If theuncircumcision keep the righteousness of the law, shall not hisuncircumcision be counted for circumcision? Therefore Ananias,the Jew, as we find in the history of Josephus, very properly taughtTzates, or as Tacitus calls him, Ezates, the Adiabenian, that even

    Online Library of Liberty: The Rights of War and Peace (1901 ed.)

    PLL v7.0 (generated September, 2013) 36 http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/553

  • without circumcision, God might be rightly worshipped andrendered propitious. For though many strangers were circumcised,among the Jews, and by circumcision bound themselves to observethe law, as St. Paul explains it in Gal. V. 3.; they did it partly toobtain the freedom of the country; for proselytes called by theHebrews, proselytes of righteousness, enjoyed equal privilegeswith the Israelites. Num. xv.: and partly to obtain a share in thosepromises, which were not common to mankind, but peculiar to theJewish people, although it cannot be denied, that in later ages anerroneous opinion prevailed, that there was no salvation out of theJewish pale. Hence we may infer, that we are bound by no part ofthe Levitical law, strictly and properly so called; because anyobligation, beyond that arising from the law of nature, mustproceed from the express will of the law-giver. Now it cannot bediscovered by any proof, that God intended any other people, butthe Israelites to be bound by that law. Therefore with respect toourselves, we have no occasion to prove an abrogation of that law;for it could never be abrogated with respect to those, whom itnever bound. But the Israelites were released from the ceremonialpart, as soon as the law of the Gospel was proclaimed; a clearrevelation of which was made to one of the Apostles, Acts x. 15.And the other parts of the Mosaic law lost their peculiar distinction,when the Jews ceased to be a people by the desolation anddestruction of their city without any hopes of restoration. Indeed itwas not a release from the law of Moses that we, who werestrangers to the Commonwealth of Israel, obtained by the comingof Christ. But as before that time, our hopes in the goodness of Godwere obscure and uncertain, we gained the assurance of an expresscovenant, that we should be united in one Church with the seed ofIsrael, the children of the patriarchs, their law, that was the wall ofseparation between us, being broken down. Eph. ii. 14.

    XVII. Since then the law given by Moses imposes no directobligation upon us, as it has been already shown, let us considerwhether it has any other use both in this inquiry into the rights ofw