the philosophy of deleuze: on its thoroughness, historical

49
The philosophy of Deleuze: On its thoroughness, historical relativity and usefulness First Version Master’s Thesis Philosophy Marijn Knieriem 10018735 [email protected] 4 August 2017 Supervisor: prof. dr. J. Früchtl Second reader: dr. A. van Rooden 21230 words Abstract This thesis is concerned with three problems that appear with respect to Deleuze’s philosophy. The first issue deals with the question of whether Deleuze argues thoroughly for his positions, or whether he merely provides views that cannot convince anyone, but might be taken up if someone considers them useful. The second problem concerns the question of whether Deleuze’s philosophy is historically relative. The final issue considers in what way Deleuze and Guattari’s books Anti-Oedipus and A Thousand Plateaus can be understood as political philosophy. In order to deal with these issues, Deleuze’s endeavour to think difference in itself will be discussed, as well as his conception of philosophy.

Upload: others

Post on 22-Nov-2021

17 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: The philosophy of Deleuze: On its thoroughness, historical

The philosophy of Deleuze:

On its thoroughness, historical relativity

and usefulness

First Version Master’s Thesis Philosophy

Marijn Knieriem

10018735

[email protected]

4 August 2017

Supervisor: prof. dr. J. Früchtl

Second reader: dr. A. van Rooden

21230 words

Abstract

This thesis is concerned with three problems that appear with respect to Deleuze’s philosophy.

The first issue deals with the question of whether Deleuze argues thoroughly for his positions, or

whether he merely provides views that cannot convince anyone, but might be taken up if someone

considers them useful. The second problem concerns the question of whether Deleuze’s

philosophy is historically relative. The final issue considers in what way Deleuze and Guattari’s

books Anti-Oedipus and A Thousand Plateaus can be understood as political philosophy. In order

to deal with these issues, Deleuze’s endeavour to think difference in itself will be discussed, as

well as his conception of philosophy.

Page 2: The philosophy of Deleuze: On its thoroughness, historical

2

Table of Contents

Abbreviations p. 3

1. Introduction p. 4

2. Method, or How to Read Deleuze? p. 9

3. The Dogmatic Image of Thought and Difference in Itself p. 15

4. Ideas and the Necessity of Chance p. 26

5. Deleuze’s Conception of Philosophy p. 37

6. Conclusion and Discussion p. 44

Literature p. 47

Page 3: The philosophy of Deleuze: On its thoroughness, historical

3

Abbreviations

The following list contains the abbreviations of Deleuze’s works that are used in this thesis. It

contains both works of which Deleuze was the single author, and works that he wrote in

collaboration with others.

AO Deleuze, G., & Guattari, F. (2016a). Anti-Oedipus. London: Bloomsbury.

B Deleuze, G. (2011). Bergsonism. New York: Zone Books.

D Deleuze, G., & Parnet, C. (2007). Dialogues II. New York: Columbia University Press.

DI Deleuze, G. (2004). Desert Island and Other Texts 1953-1974. Los Angeles: Semiotext(e).

DR Deleuze, G. (1994). Difference and Repetition. New York: Columbia University Press.

ES Deleuze, G. (1991). Empiricism and Subjectivity. New York: Columbia University Press.

LS Deleuze, G. (2015). Logic of Sense. London: Bloomsbury.

N Deleuze, G. (1995). Negotiations, 1972-1990. New York: Columbia University Press.

NP Deleuze, G. (1983). Nietzsche and Philosophy. New York: Columbia University Press.

PS Deleuze, G. (2008). Proust and Signs. London: Continuum.

TP Deleuze, G., & Guattari, F. (2016b). A Thousand Plateaus. London: Bloomsbury.

TRM Deleuze, G. (2006). Two Regimes of Madness: Texts and Interviews 1975-1995. New York:

Semiotext(e).

WP Deleuze, G., & Guattari, F. (1994). What Is Philosophy? London: Verso.

Page 4: The philosophy of Deleuze: On its thoroughness, historical

4

1. Introduction

Gilles Deleuze has produced a body of work that is remarkably rich, but which can also be—and

maybe for that very reason—quite elusive at the same time. Among other things, Deleuze has

written extensively on the history of philosophy (e.g. on Hume, Bergson, Nietzsche and Spinoza),

on several branches of art (e.g. cinema, painting and literature), on language and on issues of a

political nature. As if the difficulties that stem from the fact that this list contains a vast array of

topics were not enough, Deleuze complicated his oeuvre even more by changing his vocabulary

with every book that he wrote. The evasiveness of Deleuze’s oeuvre is reflected in the secondary

literature that surrounds his work; thus far, no consensus has been reached with respect to how

Deleuze’s philosophy should be approached (this point will be discussed in more detail in the next

section).

However, the disagreements surrounding Deleuze’s thought are not merely due to the

scope of his work and the language he employs; it also results from the fact that, in Deleuze’s work,

one can find arguments in favour of theses which appear to be mutually exclusive. I will now turn

to three of these issue that can be discerned in Deleuze’s oeuvre.

First issue

The first issue that can be discerned in Deleuze’s philosophy has to do with how one should

evaluate the theses that Deleuze brings forth. Are his claims the result of a process of rigorous

reasoning that convinces the reader of the value of these theses, or do they rather present views

that one can use and cherish if they please, and forget and ignore if they do not? There is textual

evidence to be found in favour of both of these ways to assess Deleuze’s work. For example, in the

middle chapter of Difference and Repetition, Deleuze deals with the question of where to begin in

philosophy: what should philosophy’s starting point be? By doing this, Deleuze is inscribing

himself in the Cartesian project of finding an absolute beginning from which philosophy should

proceed. Deleuze does not criticize the effort to find philosophy’s starting point, nor does he deny

the importance of the ideal of finding such a beginning; in fact, he subscribes to the project of

doing philosophy without any presuppositions (Bryant, 2008, p. 15). While supporting this ideal,

Deleuze criticizes Descartes for not being severe enough, since Deleuze thinks that Descartes,

while doubting a lot, was still assuming too much, namely “subjective or implicit presuppositions

contained in opinions rather than concepts: it is presumed that everyone knows, independently

of concepts, what is meant by self, thinking, and being” (DR, p. 129). In other words, Deleuze is

criticizing Descartes for not being rigorous enough, and Deleuze tried to point out and overcome

these shortcomings. Deleuze is not the only one who criticized Descartes in this respect.

Descartes’s contemporaries already made the objection that, given his deceiver hypothesis, he

Page 5: The philosophy of Deleuze: On its thoroughness, historical

5

could not claim to know the meaning of words like ‘thought’ and ‘existence’, since he might have

been deluded in their meaning (Wilson, 2005, p. 31-33). Husserl, in his Cartesian Meditations, also

criticizes Descartes for not pushing his doubt far enough; in the phenomenological epoché,

questions of existence are suspended, and hence one does not encounter a thinking substance

under these conditions (Husserl, 1999, p. 24). Deleuze, thus, does not lack fellow-thinkers in his

critique on Descartes.

However, there are also remarks of Deleuze that give rise to the suspicion that he is not at

all interested in being a meticulous thinker. In the Dialogues II, for example, Deleuze says that he

does not want to deal with the opposition that other people bring forth towards his work: “Every

time someone puts an objection to me, I want to say: ‘OK, OK, let’s go on to something else’” (D, p.

1). Moreover, Deleuze does not seem to care very much about how his philosophy is employed

exactly: “concepts are exactly like sounds, colours or images, they are intensities which suit you

or not, which are acceptable or aren’t acceptable. Pop philosophy. There’s nothing to understand,

nothing to interpret” (p. 3). To amplify this point, Deleuze adds: “all mistranslations are good –

always provided that they do not consist in interpretations, but relate to the use of the book, that

they multiply its use” (p. 4). Here, Deleuze thus shows himself to be a pragmatist (cf. Patton, 2000,

pp. 6, 27-28).

On the one hand, we thus have a Deleuze who tries to be as thorough as he can be; on the

other hand, there is a Deleuze who says light-heartedly that he does not like to put forth

arguments and does not care about how his work is employed exactly. The question, then, is how

the tension between these two aspects of Deleuze’s philosophy should be understood. Is it

possible to explain why both facets are present in his philosophy?

Second issue

What kind of validity should be granted to Deleuze’s work? Is the validity of his books tied to a

specific historical period, or does his oeuvre transcend the era in which it was written? Just as

with the first issue, arguments in favour of both positions can be found in Deleuze’s philosophy.

In support of the claim that the usefulness of Deleuze’s ideas is relative to a historical era,

we can direct attention to what Deleuze wrote in the Postscript on Societies of Control (N, pp. 177-

182). In this short essay, he argued that the disciplinary societies that were described by Foucault

(1995) were on the verge of disappearing. In their place, a new societal form was in the process

of emerging. Deleuze called these new societies ‘control societies’ (N, p. 178). These societies no

longer try to mould people such that their behaviour coincides with a fixed norm; instead, the

norm itself now varies, such that people have to adapt themselves according to the circumstances.

Hence, Deleuze writes: “school is being replaced by continuing education and exams by continuous

assessment” (p. 179, emphases in original). Deleuze argues that one cannot say in general which

Page 6: The philosophy of Deleuze: On its thoroughness, historical

6

of these societal forms is the worst and which is the best, since each provides its own dangers and

opportunities (p. 178). However, if one wants to withstand control societies, one has to create

new means to resist them, since opposition to a new societal form demands new forms of

resistance, according to Deleuze: “It’s not a question of worrying or of hoping for the best, but of

finding new weapons” (ibid.). This provides an example of a more general thesis of Deleuze, which

he formulates in a conversation with Foucault: “A theory has to be used, it has to work … If there

is no one to use it … then a theory is worthless, or its time has not yet arrived” (DI, p. 208). Hence,

for Deleuze, the usefulness of a theory, and thus its validity, seems to be tied to a historical period.

On the other hand, in Difference and Repetition, Deleuze has formulated an ontology of

which the validity does not seem to be relative to a historical period. In The Method of

Dramatization (DI, pp. 94-116)—a text which contains an examination of elements of Deleuze’s

ontology that are discussed at greater length in Difference and Repetition—Deleuze, after having

elaborated on determinations such as the ‘field of individuation’ and ‘larval subjects’, writes the

following: “These determinations as a whole indeed are not connected with any particular

example borrowed from a physical or biological system, but articulate the categories of every

system in general” (DI, p. 98, my emphasis). Deleuze thus seems to believe that the validity of his

ontology is not tied to this or that particular system, but holds for every system; hence, its

correctness and its usefulness is not a relative to a historical period.

Deleuze thus sometimes talks as if the validity of theory is dependent on a historical

period; at other moments, he writes that his theory has a general validity. How can the presence

of both aspects in Deleuze’s philosophy be explained?

Third issue

The third and final issue has to do with Deleuze’s ethics and his political philosophy. In what sense

can Anti-Oedipus and A Thousand Plateaus be understood as works of ethics or of political

philosophy?

Foucault, in his preface to Anti-Oedipus, calls it “a book of ethics” (Foucault, 2016, p. xiii),

and he manages to distil seven principles from the book that together form an art of living which

can guard the reader against the seductions of fascism (pp. xiii-xiv). However, as Buchanan (2011)

points out, the principles that are formulated by Foucault are merely negative: “Foucault’s

instructions only specify what we should not do, and say nothing at all about what we should do”

(Buchanan, 2011, p. 11, emphasis in original). In other words, it is not clear what art of living is

actually affirmed in Anti-Oedipus.

Concerning the political aspirations of the Anti-Oedipus, the situation is not any clearer.

Deleuze can say that “Anti-Oedipus was from beginning to end a book of political philosophy” (N,

p. 170), but since the book does not engage in detail with topics that are traditionally seen as

Page 7: The philosophy of Deleuze: On its thoroughness, historical

7

topics belonging to political philosophy—like what a just distribution of wealth would be, or how

far the people should go in obeying their government—it is not evident what Deleuze exactly

means when he calls it ‘political philosophy’. Moreover, even though Deleuze says that the

“question [of revolution] has always been organizational, not at all ideological” (D, p. 109), he

never deals in detail with organizational difficulties that have to be solved in order to generate

social or cultural change (Buchanan, 2011, p. 7).

Given the fact that Deleuze and Guattari do not provide clarity on what art of living is

affirmed, nor sketch a picture of how their ideal society would look like, nor provide an account

of how organizational problems should be solved, then in what respect can Anti-Oedipus and A

Thousand Plateaus perform a practical function and form “a little cog in much more complicated

external machinery” (N, p. 8)? What is the objective with which these books have been written by

Deleuze and Guattari?

This thesis will deal with the questions that follow from these three issues. The goal of this thesis

is to show how these issues can be handled when the later works, namely Anti-Oedipus, A

Thousand Plateaus and What is Philosophy? are connected to Deleuze’s earlier books, in particular

Difference and Repetition and Logic of Sense. It will be argued that these three issues are

consequences from Deleuze’s earlier philosophy, and that Deleuze ultimately presents a coherent

view. One has to take the development of Deleuze’s thought into account, in order to appreciate

this point.

Although this thesis is concerned with the practical philosophy of Deleuze as it is

formulated in Anti-Oedipus and A Thousand Plateaus, I will not engage a lot with these books

directly. This is due to the fact that Deleuze contends that these books should be used rather than

interpreted; hence, they do not lend themselves for commentary of clarification (Stengers, 2005,

p. 151; 2012, p. 268; Colombat, 1991, p. 12). Instead, Anti-Oedipus and A Thousand Plateaus will

be treated as paradigms of a certain conception of philosophy; this conception of philosophy, in

turn, is something that can be clarified, and this, then, will be done.

This thesis is structured as follows. In the next section, the method that is employed in this

thesis to approach Deleuze’s philosophy will be discussed. This will be done by contrasting it with

other methods that are found in the secondary literature. The method used in this thesis consists

of starting from Deleuze’s project to think difference in itself, and then deduces which

commitments follow from this. In section three, we will deal with the questions of why it is

necessary, according to Deleuze, to think difference in itself, and why Deleuze thinks that other

thinkers failed in this respect. In order to do this, we have to discuss, among other things, what

Deleuze called the ‘dogmatic image of thought’ and his critique on this image. Then, in section four,

we will deal with the issue of how Deleuze tries to think difference in itself. He does this by

Page 8: The philosophy of Deleuze: On its thoroughness, historical

8

developing a theory of Ideas. These Ideas, as well as other notions that are necessary to

understand them, will be discussed in some detail in this section. Here, we will also discuss

Deleuze’s claim that thought is the result of fortuitous encounters, and discuss his thesis on the

necessity of chance. In section five, we will examine Deleuze’s conception of philosophy that

follows from what has been discussed thus far. Here, we will see why Deleuze conceives of

philosophy as the creation of concepts that should make a difference in the present. Finally, in the

conclusion and the discussion, we will return to the three issues that were presented in this

introduction. By then, all the elements should be present to deal with the questions that followed

from these issues.

Page 9: The philosophy of Deleuze: On its thoroughness, historical

9

2. Method, or How to Read Deleuze?

Why is it necessary to ask how one should read Deleuze? It has to do with the fact that Deleuze’s

oeuvre allows for multiple ways of approaching it, without there being one single method that is

clearly superior to the others. Nonetheless, the way in which Deleuze’s work is accessed is of the

utmost importance, since it ultimately determines which picture of Deleuze’s philosophy emerges.

In this section I will discuss several of the methods that are found in the secondary literature, in

combination with some of Deleuze’s remarks that justify these different methods. The goal of this

overview is not to give an extensive review of all the strategies that are employed; rather, the

different methods are presented in order to form a contrast with the method that will be used in

this thesis, such that the merits and dangers of the latter will come into focus.

The different approaches to Deleuze’s oeuvre that are distilled from the secondary

literature are categorized around three topics. The first topic deals with the issue of what role

Deleuze’s studies in the history of philosophy play in Deleuze’s own philosophy. Do Deleuze’s

historical studies form an integral part of Deleuze’s philosophy, or should a distinction be made

between his historical studies and the philosophy that he has written in his own name? The

second topic has to do with the internal consistency and the internal evolution of Deleuze’s

oeuvre. Should we see Deleuze’s work as a whole, in which one issue follows more or less naturally

from something that he discussed in an earlier book? Or are his different books separate entities

that do not have a necessary relation to one another, and should we hence also not expect that the

different works are consistent with each other? The third topic has to do with Deleuze’s rigour.

Should we approach Deleuze’s oeuvre as an attempt to be more rigorous than his predecessors,

pointing out their blind spots, compromises and concessions, or should we see his philosophy

simply as an alternative that is not necessarily more adequate than other philosophies?

These three topics will now be discussed. I will not immediately take a stance in the

debates; at first, the different positions and their arguments will be only presented. After this has

been done, I will present the method that will be employed in this thesis and reflect on how this

relates to the different approaches to Deleuze’s philosophy that are found in the secondary

literature.

Deleuze and the History of Philosophy

Deleuze has written extensively on several figures in the history of philosophy. However, it is not

exactly clear how these written histories fit in his oeuvre as a whole. Bryant (2008) argues that a

distinction should be made between Deleuze’s historical work and his own, original philosophy:

“We cannot assume that the contents of Deleuze’s [historical] studies are identical to his

independent philosophical works” (p. xi). Deleuze himself gives rise to the position that is held by

Page 10: The philosophy of Deleuze: On its thoroughness, historical

10

Bryant, since Deleuze himself subscribes to the same distinction between his original philosophy

and his historical studies:

There is a great difference between writing history of philosophy and writing philosophy.

In the one case, we study the arrows or the tools of a great thinker, the trophies and the

prey, the continents discovered. In the other case, we trim our own arrows, or gather those

which seem to us the finest in order to try to send them in other directions, even if the

distance covered is not astronomical but relatively small. (DR, p. xv)

Deleuze thus clearly does not group his historical studies together with his independent, original

work. Bryant suggests that the emphasis in the secondary literature on Deleuze’s historical

studies stems from the difficulty of Deleuze’s work; Bryant, however, disapproves of this practice:

“In a curious manner, this has given rise to a tendency to transform Deleuze into his histories

rather than to see how Deleuze departs from these histories” (Bryant, 2008, p. 222). Bryant

therefore thinks that, in studies regarding Deleuze’s own philosophy, references to his historical

studies are only justified when similar concepts and theories are found in the works that are

written in Deleuze’s own name (p. xii).

On the other side of this issue we find May (2005). May thinks that Spinoza, Bergson and

Nietzsche are the most important philosophers for Deleuze, and hence calls them “the Holy

Trinity” (p. 26). “It is they”, May writes, “who provide the motivation and the framework for the

ontologies Deleuze constructs over the course of his many writings” (ibid.). For May, there is thus

no need to make a categorical distinction between Deleuze’s historical works and the books

containing his own, original philosophy, since the latter are informed by and build upon the

former. Moreover, Deleuze has a very particular conception of what the history of philosophy is.

He writes the following about it:

I suppose the main way I coped with it at the time was to see the history of philosophy as

a sort of buggery or (it comes to the same thing) immaculate conception. I saw myself as

taking an author from behind and giving him a child that would be his own offspring, yet

monstrous. It was really important for it to be his own child, because the author had to

actually say all I had him saying. But the child was bound to be monstrous too, because it

resulted from all sorts of shifting, slipping, dislocations, and hidden emissions that I really

enjoyed. (N, p. 6).

This quote clearly shows that Deleuze did not merely want to explicate what the philosophers

whom he studied had written. Hence, Deleuze’s studies in the history of philosophy definitely bear

Page 11: The philosophy of Deleuze: On its thoroughness, historical

11

his signature. This makes that the borderline between Deleuze’s original thought and his historical

studies becomes fuzzy.

The Internal Development of Deleuze’s Oeuvre

How should one understand the development of Deleuze’s philosophy? Does his oeuvre develop

more or less naturally from one issue to the next, whereby the first subject matter preludes to the

second, the second to the third, etcetera? Or is it rather the case that Deleuze’s philosophy displays

ruptures that make it impossible to conceive it as a consistent whole?

Hardt (2007), although limiting himself to Deleuze’s apprenticeship in the philosophies of

Bergson, Nietzsche and Spinoza, thinks that his oeuvre should be approached as having its own

internal progression. Hardt argues, for example, that Deleuze’s study of Bergson left some themes

undeveloped and problems unresolved. These themes only reached maturity and these problems

only were solved when Deleuze got to the next phase of his development and turned towards

Nietzsche (pp. 21-22). Hardt therefore writes that Deleuze’s thought is characterized by “a sort of

theoretical process of aggregation” (p. xix) and hence posits the following methodological

principle: “Read Deleuze’s thought as an evolution” (p. xx).

Other scholars, however, think that Deleuze’s philosophy consists of breaks that preclude

it from being presented as a unified whole. Boundas, for example, writes that “Deleuze’s own

rhizomatic growth and his strategy of writing should have warned against homocentric

evolutionist readings” (Boundas, 1991, p. 11), and he presents three theses of Deleuze on

subjectivity that are, according to him, incomprehensible in an evolutionist reading. Bryant

(2008) argues that there is no simple evolution in Deleuze’s work, because the ontology of active

and reactive forces which Deleuze presents in Nietzsche and Philosophy, whereby one force

overpowers another, is inconsistent with the ontology of reciprocal determination between

differential relations that is found in Difference and Repetition. (Although it should be noted that

Somers-Hall [2013, pp. 38-42] does find a Nietzschean ontology of forces in Difference and

Repetition.) Finally, Patton argues that Deleuze “is an experimental thinker committed to a

conception of movement in thought … There is always movement and discontinuity in his thinking

from one problem or series of problems to the next” (Patton, 2010, p. 10). Hence, according to

Patton, it is only in vain that one could seek for “an essence of his philosophy” (p. 15). (It should

be remarked, though, that in an earlier book on Deleuze, Patton found more continuity in

Deleuze’s thought. This is shown by Patton’s remark that “In many respects, Deleuze’s constant

engagement in his earlier writings with the question of the nature of thought is a prolegomenon

to the distinctive practice of philosophy developed in collaboration with Guattari” [Patton, 2000,

p. 18].)

Page 12: The philosophy of Deleuze: On its thoroughness, historical

12

Deleuze’s Philosophy: Is it Superior or Merely One Alternative Among Others?

This third topic deals with the following issue: to what extent does Deleuze provide a philosophy

that is in some sense superior to the philosophies of earlier thinkers? Is it possible to say that

Deleuze’s thought provides an improvement in one respect or another, or is he merely providing

an alternative way to perceive the world, a model that can be used if it pleases and be forgotten if

it does not?

According to May (2003; 2005), Deleuze did the latter thing. May thinks that Deleuze’s

philosophy offers a new way of looking at things, without providing an ontology that is in some

way superior to others. As May writes of Deleuze: “He does not like to argue. He does not like to

harp on weaknesses in a philosopher’s work. He would rather change the subject” (May, 2005, p.

32). This is also how Deleuze appropriates other philosophers, according to May: “It is not that

Spinoza has detailed the difficulties of transcendence that fascinates Deleuze. Rather, it is that

Spinoza has successfully changed the subject, gone on to something else” (p. 33). May thus thinks

that Deleuze’s philosophy does not provide more satisfactory solutions to philosophical problems

than other systems of thought: “to follow Deleuze’s discussion of difference is not so much to

substitute a more adequate philosophical approach for a less adequate one. It is to follow thought

down another, more adventurous path: the path of concept-creation” (May, 2003, p. 145).

There are other authors, however, who think that Deleuze does provide a philosophy that

is in some sense more adequate than others and which solves certain problems in philosophy.

Foucault, for example, thinks that Deleuze does indeed deal with the weaknesses in the works of

other philosophers. Foucault writes the following about Deleuze’s relation to Western philosophy:

“He points out its interruption, its gaps, those small things of little value neglected by

philosophical discourse. He carefully reintroduces the barely perceptible omissions, knowing full

well that they imply an unlimited negligence” (Foucault, 1998, p. 348). In agreement with Foucault

and contrary to May, Hardt thinks that Deleuze does argue for his points of view: “the coherence

of his positions and the mode of explanation that supports them remain on the highest logical and

ontological planes” (Hardt, 2007, p. xviii). Finally, Bryant presents himself as a supporter of this

viewpoint when he writes that “one adopts the position [of transcendental empiricism] because

something is wrong with the philosophy of representation and transcendental empiricism is able

to solve this problem” (Bryant, 2008, p. 4). Explanations of Deleuze’s work that fail to argue for

the essential need of their positions “give one the sense that perhaps Deleuze’s thought amounts

to a simple thought experiment that ultimately amounts to nothing more than a set of ideas that

one might try out at one’s leisure” (p. 5).

Now that these three topics and the different positions within the debates have been discussed, it

is time to turn to the method that will be applied in this thesis. This method consists of one

Page 13: The philosophy of Deleuze: On its thoroughness, historical

13

guideline: start from Deleuze’s attempt to think difference in itself and analyze what commitments

follow from this endeavour.

First of all, I should clarify what is meant by starting from Deleuze’s attempt to think

difference in itself. This consists of two parts: the first part deals with the question of why Deleuze

thinks that it is necessary to think difference in itself; the second part deals with the question of

why Deleuze thinks that other philosophers before him did not succeed in doing this. When this

is done, it should be shown how Deleuze tries to think difference in itself.

By taking Deleuze’s project to think difference in itself as our starting point, his book

Difference and Repetition comes to occupy a privileged position, since that is the book in which he

takes on this project in the most direct fashion. Deleuze himself also attributes a prominent place

in his oeuvre to Difference and Repetition; he writes about it that it was “the first book in which I

tried to ‘do philosophy’. All that I have done since is connected to this book, including what I wrote

with Guattari” (DR, p. xv).

This immediately brings us to the issue of the internal development of Deleuze’s oeuvre.

The aforementioned quote testifies of the fact that Deleuze thinks that a continuity exists between

Difference and Repetition and his later work; this is a thought that will be employed in this thesis.

Hence, I will assume that Deleuze displays more continuity in his thought than Boundas (1991)

and Patton (2010) give him credit for. In fact, this thesis can be read as a construction of what

Deleuze could mean with the following remark: “In my earlier books, I tried to describe a certain

exercise of thought; but describing it was not yet exercising thought in that way … With Félix

[Guattari], all that became possible, even if we failed” (D, p. 13). With respect to the issue of

whether Deleuze’s philosophy should be considered as a whole, the position in this thesis is thus

that it should; his philosophy can be understood as a unity. However, for now, this can only be

stated, rather than shown; it is an issue that we will have to come back to in the discussion.

With respect to the issue of whether Deleuze’s work should be seen as an attempt to be as

rigorous as he can be, or merely as an alternative that provides an alternative lens through which

the world can be perceived, this method allies with the former position. Since it starts from

Deleuze’s attempt to think difference in itself, tries to explain why Deleuze thinks that it is

necessary to do so and to what positions this endeavour commits him, this thesis will try to paint

a picture of Deleuze as an uncompromising thinker.

Lastly, concerning the remaining topic: in what position does the methodological principle

that informs this thesis stand regarding the relationship between Deleuze’s original philosophy

and his studies in the history of philosophy? As was said above, starting from the attempt to think

difference in itself privileges Deleuze’s Difference and Repetition above other books. In this

respect, it can be said that the central focus of this thesis is on his original philosophy.

Page 14: The philosophy of Deleuze: On its thoroughness, historical

14

Nevertheless, his studies in the history of philosophy will also be employed. However, in the case

of discrepancies, the original philosophy will preponderate.

With respect to the method that is employed in this thesis, one thing remains to be done,

and that is answering the following question: why is Deleuze’s attempt to think difference in itself

the starting point that is chosen? Are there no other aspects of Deleuze’s work that could serve

equally well, or even better, as a way into his thought? There are three reasons that can be given

in favour of the starting point that is chosen in this thesis.

First of all, the attempt to think difference in itself is a central concern in Deleuze’s

philosophy. We have already seen the importance that Deleuze has granted to his book Difference

and Repetition in relation to the rest of his oeuvre. Moreover, Deleuze does not eschew big words

when he reflects on the significance of thinking difference in itself. The attempt to think difference

no longer as a derivative of identity, but rather to think identity as a derivative of difference—

which then would need to have its own concept, i.e. difference in itself—amounts, according to

Deleuze, to nothing less than “a Copernican revolution” (DR, p. 40) in philosophy.

The second reason is of a pragmatic nature. By starting from Deleuze’s attempt to think

difference in itself, and following the consequences of what this project entails, all the elements

that are necessary to answer the questions that were posed in the introduction, will be presented.

However, again, for now this can only be declared, and not yet demonstrated; hence, it is an issue

that has to be reflected upon in the discussion.

The third and final reason has to do with the issue of what picture of Deleuze will be

painted in this thesis. By taking difference in itself as a starting point and analysing what

commitments follow from this, it is possible to display Deleuze as a rigorous thinker. This is not

the only image of Deleuze that can be drawn—the other approaches in the secondary literature

that were discussed above testify of this fact—and it is not to say that the other appropriations of

Deleuze’s philosophy are incorrect. However, the upside of the current method is that it constructs

Deleuze’s philosophy as a body of work that is compelling; it cannot simply be put aside if it does

not please, but instead it demands a reaction. In that respect, this method is close to the position

of Bryant (2008, p. 5), namely in that it tries to avoid to present Deleuze as a philosopher who

only has something to say to those who already find him appealing, while others may simply leave

his thought behind.

Now we can end our methodological reflections. It has been an extensive discussion of the

method employed, and how it relates to other approaches to Deleuze’s work; however, given

Deleuze’s elusive philosophy and the different readings that it has given rise to, it was necessary

to linger over the method. Now, after a long detour, we can finally turn to Deleuze’s philosophy

itself.

Page 15: The philosophy of Deleuze: On its thoroughness, historical

15

3. The Dogmatic Image of Thought and Difference in Itself

In this section, we will deal with two issues in Deleuze’s attempt to think difference in itself. The

first question is: why does Deleuze think that it is necessary to think difference in itself? What is

missing from a philosophy that does not include difference in itself? The second question is: why

is it, according to Deleuze, that other philosophers before him did not succeed in thinking

difference in itself? What is it that they overlooked, and why does Deleuze think that he can avoid

this omission? For finding an answer to the first question, we have to examine why Deleuze thinks

that problems emerge in a philosophy that lacks a concept for difference in itself. In order to

answer the second question, we have to discuss what Deleuze called the ‘dogmatic image of

thought’ and his critique on it. According to Deleuze, this image consists of a wrong understanding

of what it means to think, and this is what precluded his predecessors from thinking difference in

itself. First of all, however, we need to introduce what Deleuze has in mind when he talks about

difference.

When Deleuze uses the word ‘difference’, he is not referring to the variety of phenomena

that exist in the world. As he explains it: “Difference is not diversity. Diversity is given, but

difference is that by which the given is given, that by which the given is given as diverse. Difference

is not phenomenon but the noumenon closest to the phenomenon” (DR, p. 222). This quote

testifies of the fact that Deleuze operates against a transcendental-philosophical background, and

that there is something beyond what we perceive, and which gives rise to the perceived. Diversity,

then, means that there are multiple individuals and that there “is no individual absolutely identical

to another individual” (LS, p. 275). Or, as Deleuze formulates it elsewhere: “no two grains of dust

are absolutely identical, no two hands have the same distinctive points, no two typewriters have

the same strike, no two revolvers score their bullets in the same manner” (DR, p. 26). It is

difference, however, that gives rise to this diversity of entities: “Every phenomenon refers to an

inequality by which it is conditioned. Every diversity and every change refers to a difference which

is its sufficient reason” (DR, p. 222). It is clear, then, that Deleuze thinks that we should not search

for difference at the level of phenomena; we have to go beyond the phenomena and into

metaphysics in order to reach difference in itself.

Why Difference in Itself?

Why is it necessary to think difference in itself? The short answer is that without difference in

itself, it is impossible to account for the genesis of both thought and beings. In other words, this

issue has both a transcendental and an ontological component.

Aristotle is a main target in Deleuze’s critique on how difference has been conceptualized

in the history of philosophy. For Aristotle, there can only be a difference between two entities if

Page 16: The philosophy of Deleuze: On its thoroughness, historical

16

these entities have something in common at a higher level (Somers-Hall, 2013, p. 25; Smith, 2012,

p. 38). As Deleuze explains Aristotle’s notion of difference: “two terms differ when they are other,

not in themselves, but in something else; thus when they also agree in something else: in genus

when they are differences in species, in species for differences in number” (DR, p. 30). Hence, man,

as a rational being, differs from other animals by the fact that he is endowed with the ability to

think rationally; but this only counts as a difference, because man and other animals have

something in common, namely their belonging to the genus of animals (Somers-Hall, 2013, p. 25).

This Aristotelian conception of difference, in which difference between two entities refers

back to what they have in common, corresponds to what Deleuze calls a ‘sedentary distribution’

(DR, p. 36; Somers-Hall, 2013, p. 40). “A distribution of this type”, Deleuze writes, “proceeds by

fixed and proportional determinations which may be assimilated to ‘properties’ or limited

territories within representation” (DR, p. 36). According to Deleuze, representation consists of

four elements: identity (the concept has an identity and is hence always applicable in the same

way); analogy (judgment operates in the same way with respect to different concepts: a table is a

table because it satisfies the properties of the concept table, just as an animal is an animal because

it satisfies the predicates of the concept animal); opposition (two concepts are each other’s

negation: A is not-B and B is not-A); and resemblance (two different things belong to the same

concept because of a resemblance between these two things) (DR, pp. 29, 137-138; Groot, 2012,

p. 117; Williams, 2003, p. 62). These four elements make that an animated, rational being fits the

concept of man and hence belongs to that species. Moreover, by being a man this entity forfeits

the possibility of being anything else than a human being; since this being is rational, and

rationality is a property that only belongs to the species of man, this being cannot belong to any

other species (cf. May, 2005, p. 75). Therefore, Deleuze writes that the different determinations

occupy a ‘limited territory’ within the system of representation.

The sedentary distribution thus grants a concept to each individual and negates the

possibility of attributing another concept to that individual. In this distribution, things are what

they are, because they have properties that exclude them from being a member of another class;

the sedentary distribution operates according to the logic of “this and not that” (Somers-Hall,

2013, p. 41). The identity of a thing makes that it differs from another species, because it does not

have the properties of this other species; difference is thus derived from identity and

conceptualized as negation, that is, as the negation of belonging to another species. Now, what

does the sedentary distribution fail to explain? According to Deleuze, this distribution is “a

dividing up of that which is distributed” (DR, p. 36). Hence, the sedentary distribution only applies

a certain order to that which exists; it does assume the existence of that which is divided up, and

thus fails to explain how it came into being: “[Representation] mediates everything, but mobilises

and moves nothing” (pp. 55-56). If there is nothing essential above the identity of things, nothing

Page 17: The philosophy of Deleuze: On its thoroughness, historical

17

that distorts their identities, then their creation and their destruction cannot be explained.

Deleuze, however, wants to give a sufficient reason for the existence of a variety of beings and

thus has to account for how they came into being. The notion of sufficient reason is borrowed by

Deleuze from Leibniz and refers to the principle that a reason should be given for why existing

beings exist, rather than other beings (Smith, 2012, pp. 44-45). In order to fulfil his aim, Deleuze

has to turn to those aspects that escape the sedentary distribution.

In order to understand the becoming of beings, we need to turn to another kind of

distribution. Deleuze, in this respect, talks about a ‘nomadic distribution’ (DR, p. 36). In this

distribution, “there is no longer a division of that which is distributed but rather a division among

those who distribute themselves in an open space – a space which is unlimited, or at least without

precise limits” (DR, p. 36, emphasis in original). In this distribution, beings are not organized

according to the categories of representation. Rather, in the nomadic distribution, beings organize

themselves and break through the conceptual determinations of representation: objects no longer

have a fixed identity, but are understood in their process of coming into being (p. 37). This means

that the nomadic distribution is not limited; if beings come into existence through a process of

becoming, and if this process continues to produce new beings, then the distribution cannot be

closed-off (ibid.; cf. Baugh, 1992, p. 136). If beings can no longer be understood as having an

unchanging identity, then the process of becoming must remain opaque for an understanding that

operates via representation which tries to capture beings within concepts (Williams, 2003, p. 66).

The nomadic distribution presents a world in which beings overflow the identities that

are assigned to them by representation, and representation cannot capture this overflowing. How,

then, can this world be grasped? Deleuze says the following about it: “There is a crucial experience

of difference and a corresponding experiment: every time we find ourselves confronted or bound

by a limitation or an opposition, we should ask what such a situation presupposes” (DR, p. 50).

Thus, one cannot remain satisfied with merely representing the world as it appears. Instead, one

has to investigate what is presupposed by the identities that are represented in concepts.

Deleuze’s answer is the following: “It presupposes a swarm of differences, a pluralism of free, wild

or untamed differences” (ibid.). These differences belong to a ‘sub-representative’ domain (p. 56).

The continuous change and becoming of objects makes that beings cannot be understood as fixed

by a concept. “The object must therefore be in no way identical, but torn asunder in a difference

in which the identity of the object as seen by a seeing subject vanishes” (ibid.). Deleuze

consequently formulates the following requirement that a philosophy of difference should fulfil:

“Every object, every thing, must see its own identity swallowed up in difference, each being no

more than a difference between differences. Difference must be shown differing” (ibid., emphasis

in original). One can only understand how the variety of beings came into existence if one breaks

free from the demands of representation and no longer thinks that the identity of beings is

Page 18: The philosophy of Deleuze: On its thoroughness, historical

18

ontologically primitive: “difference, potential difference and difference in intensity as the reason

behind qualitative diversity. It is in difference that movement is produced as an ‘effect’” (p. 57).

Now, one might protest and say the following: what if there is not necessarily something

that eludes concepts? If there are concepts that do not merely capture the properties of things as

they are, but also all the relations to all other beings that generated their becoming in the first

place? In that case, concepts would express the totality of the world from their own point of view

(since they would contain all relations of a being to all other beings), and have an extension of one

(since this set of relations is unique for each individual being); in other words, it would be much

like the way in which Leibniz conceived of concepts, i.e. as referring to individual beings, thus

without any generality (see Smith, 2012, pp. 44-48). In that case, the difference between two

beings is captured by the differences between their respective concepts, and hence difference

would always be conceptual difference, which would make a concept of difference in itself

superfluous (DR, pp. 11-12; Smith, 2012, p. 49). However, we then have to ask the following

question: is it possible to develop these complete concepts, that refer to one object only and

express the totality of the world? Deleuze thinks that this is a hopeless endeavour. One of

Deleuze’s arguments is found in the existence of words (DR, p. 13). Words have definitions, but

these do not preclude words from being applied in different sentences, different contexts, etcetera

(ibid.). One and the same word is necessarily applicable on multiple occasions; this “forms the real

power of language in speech and writing” (ibid.). The concept or definition of a word thus

necessarily has an extension that is greater than one. (For a more comprehensive discussion of

the incompleteness of concepts in the context of Deleuze’s philosophy, see Bearn [2000, pp. 444-

446].)

Here, Deleuze makes the same point as Derrida when the latter refers to the essential

iterability of words (Derrida, 1988, p. 7). The meaning of a word always contains an excess that

makes it possible to use it in different contexts, but this also implies that a word always means

more than was intended by the writer or the speaker: “it leaves us no choice but to mean (to say)

something that is (already, always, also) other than what we mean (to say)” (p. 62). For Derrida,

concepts are thus never able to refer to one thing and to one thing only, and Deleuze agrees with

him in this respect. However, Deleuze does not remain satisfied with this point, for it is one thing

to talk about the inadequacy of concepts, it is quite another to explain why this adequacy becomes

manifest; in this regard, Deleuze moves beyond the Derridean point (Bearn, 2000, p. 446). It may

be true that concepts do not refer to one single object, but this does not yet explain how the

different referents came into being in the first place. As Bearn expresses this point: “The top may

have been loose, but all by itself, that will not explain why the jar leaked: the jar could have been

empty” (Bearn, 2000, p. 446). Therefore, Deleuze thinks of the inadequacy of the concept that it

only provides a negative explanation (DR, p. 16). What is still needed is a positive explanation, and

Page 19: The philosophy of Deleuze: On its thoroughness, historical

19

Deleuze finds this in difference in itself. Here we see the importance of what Deleuze called ‘the

experience of difference’, as we have seen above: the fact that concepts fail to refer to one thing

and one thing only does not merely presuppose the inadequacy of concepts (a negative

explanation), but also the genesis of different beings that can be subsumed under the same

concept. This process of genesis is captured by Deleuze’s nomadic distribution.

This nomadic distribution is ontologically prior to the sedentary distribution, according to

Deleuze. This is because of the fact that one can go from the nomadic distribution to the sedentary

distribution, but one cannot go the other way around. The sedentary distribution can be derived

from the nomadic distribution when the four elements of representation are imposed on the

latter; things are then understood as having an identity, and one perceives objects as static beings,

rather than grasping their process of becoming. Inversely, the nomadic distribution cannot be

derived from the sedentary distribution. When objects are captured by concepts, and difference

is consequently understood as the negation of belonging to another concept, then one cannot

account for how these objects came into being in the first place; this makes it impossible to grasp

the processes that overflow the categories of representation and which are the subject matter of

the nomadic distribution. Hence Deleuze concludes: “Those who bear the negative know not what

they do: they take the shadow for the reality, they encourage phantoms, they uncouple

consequences from premises and they give epiphenomena the value of phenomena and essences”

(DR, p. 55).

This also accounts for Deleuze’s interpretation of Nietzsche’s eternal return, and for why

Deleuze uses the eternal return as a model to conceive of the world of difference in itself. If it is

no longer possible to think of identity as the primary ontological term, but one rather has to take

difference as ontologically primitive, then it is no longer the same that returns, but rather the

different; identity, then, is only derived from difference. What is it, therefore, that returns?

“Returning is being, but only the being of becoming. The eternal return does not bring back ‘the

same’, but returning constitutes the only Same of that which becomes” (DR, p. 41). Thus, it is only

that which becomes, what differs from itself, that returns. Therefore, it is true that the eternal

return can be said to be the recurrence of the same, but only under the condition that the same

refers to difference: “the circle of the eternal return … is a tortuous circle in which Sameness is

said only of that which differs” (p. 57). Now, one might object against taking Nietzsche’s eternal

return as an ontological doctrine in which the same (as the same) does not return, and ask, as

Tanner does: “if by ‘Eternal Recurrence’ [Nietzsche] did not mean Eternal Recurrence, why did he

not call it what he did mean?” (Tanner, 2000, p. 62). Deleuze’s interpretation is susceptible to this

critique, since he clearly appropriates Nietzsche’s doctrine and uses it for his own philosophy of

difference (cf. Malabou, 2010). However, rather than criticizing Deleuze for distorting the

Nietzschean view, one might also argue, like Foucault, that it is a creative misreading, such that

Page 20: The philosophy of Deleuze: On its thoroughness, historical

20

the originality of this vision should not be attributed to Nietzsche, but “will bear the name of

Deleuze” (Foucault, 1998, p. 367; see also Leigh, 1978, p. 223).

Up to now, we have only seen why Deleuze thinks that it is necessary to think difference

in itself, and what requirements the thought of difference in itself should fulfil. It should be

emphasized, however, that Deleuze does not argue that identity does not exist; rather, he argues

against the primacy of identity and replaces this with the primacy of difference. Deleuze does not

deny identity, but argues that it should not be taken as ontologically primitive: “That identity not

be first, that is exist as a principle but as a second principle, as a principle become; that it revolve

around the Different” (DR, p. 40, emphasis in original), such is the philosophy that Deleuze

propagates. This puts Deleuze to the task of thinking difference in itself. We have not yet seen how

Deleuze actually fulfils this job; this is the subject matter of the next chapter. First, however, we

need to turn to another question: how does Deleuze explain that other philosophers did not

manage to think difference in itself? In order to find an answer to this question, we have to discuss

Deleuze’s conception of the dogmatic image of thought.

The Dogmatic Image of Thought

The most extensive discussion of the dogmatic image of thought that Deleuze provides, is found

in the middle chapter of Difference and Repetition, of which he writes in the preface to the English

edition that it “now seems to me the most necessary and the most concrete, and which serves to

introduce subsequent books up to and including the research undertaken with Guattari” (DR, p.

xvii). The image of thought is an issue that preoccupies Deleuze during his entire philosophical

life: it is found in the books that he wrote early in his career (in Nietzsche and Philosophy and

Proust and Signs), up until his latest collaboration with Guattari (What is Philosophy?). For

Deleuze, the image of thought is “the image thought gives itself of what it means to think” (WP, p.

37). The image of thought fulfils a regulative function with respect to thought: “The image of

thought retains only what thought can claim by right” (ibid.). Hence, the image of thought

determines which elements belong essentially to thought, and what the contingent features are

from which thought should be purified.

In Difference and Repetition, Deleuze argues that the dogmatic image of thought consists

of eight postulates (DR, p. 167). In the Dialogues II, an abbreviated version of these is formulated:

They can all be summarized in the order-word: have correct ideas! It is first of all the image

of good nature and good will – good will of the thinker who seeks the ‘truth’, good nature

of thought which possesses ‘the true’ by right. Then, it is the image of a ‘common sense’ –

harmony of all the faculties of a thinking being. Then, again, it is the image of recognition

– ‘to recognize’, doesn’t this mean that something or someone is set up as a model of the

Page 21: The philosophy of Deleuze: On its thoroughness, historical

21

activities of the thinker who makes use of all his faculties on an object which is supposedly

the same. Then again, it is the image of error – as if thought had only to mistrust external

influences capable of making it take the ‘false’ as true. Finally, it is the image of knowledge

– as place of truth, and truth as sanctioning answers or solutions for questions and

problems which are supposedly ‘given’. (D, p. 18)

What is it, according to Deleuze, that is wrong with this image? The problem with this image of

thought is that it presupposes too much. It assumes that thought has a natural affinity with the

truth, but does not explain where this affinity comes from. It assumes that thought is directed at

producing knowledge by answering certain questions, but does not explain why these questions

are the only questions worth asking. Deleuze does not argue that there are no correct ideas (which

would be a self-contradictory statement), but that it should not be assumed that thought

converges naturally towards the correct and the true. Thought can also be about ideas that are

not correct. As Deleuze expresses it: “no correct ideas, just ideas [pas d’idées justes, justes des

idées]” (D, p. 7). If one assumes as a fact of nature that an alliance exists between thought on the

one hand and truth and knowledge on the other hand, and if one is interested in the conditions

that make these facts of nature possible, one only finds out what one has assumed beforehand;

this is the mistake that Kant made (Smith, 2012, p. 238). As Deleuze elucidates: “Kant traces the

so-called transcendental structures from the empirical acts of a psychological consciousness: the

transcendental synthesis of apprehension is directly induced from an empirical apprehension,

and so on” (DR, p. 135). When one tries to explain an empirical phenomenon by finding the

conditions that make it possible, one is merely finding back what one has presupposed all along;

hence, such a project involves circular reasoning that should be avoided, at least according to

Deleuze (p. 129). Moreover, it is not only Kant who makes this mistake of tracing the

transcendental from the empirical; Deleuze discerns the same mistake in the philosophy of

Husserl (LS, p. 100).

Tracing the transcendental conditions from the empirical exercise of a faculty amounts to

anticipating the results of an investigation; one knows what should be looked for and only focuses

on that. Deleuze, however, argues that “nothing can be said in advance, one cannot prejudge the

outcome of research” (DR, p. 143). The reason for this is that, in searching for what one is looking

for, one loses sight of all the things that were not anticipated and which may surprise the

researcher. Therefore, Deleuze argues that we should not presuppose what thought is; we should

thus not assume beforehand that thought is about recognition. Deleuze writes the following about

this:

Page 22: The philosophy of Deleuze: On its thoroughness, historical

22

it is apparent that acts of recognition exist and occupy a large part of our daily life: this is

a table, this is an apple, this the piece of wax, Good morning Theaetetus. But who can

believe that the destiny of thought is at stake in these acts, and that when we recognise,

we are thinking? (p. 135)

If we want to know what thought is capable of, then we should not limit ourselves to investigating

only the cognitive acts of everyday life. The dogmatic image of thought should be criticized for

taking these acts as a model, and turning them into a norm by extrapolating an ideal of what

belongs to thought by right from what belongs to thought by fact, “as though thought should not

seek its models among stranger and more compromising adventures” (ibid.).

Deleuze’s focus on the ‘strange adventures’ of thought is not the result of a particular taste

for the extraordinary and the bizarre, but should rather be seen as a consequence of

methodological considerations. By concentrating on what falls outside of the everyday and

ordinary operation of thought, one can avoid turning the normal functioning of thought into a

model to which thought should obey, and hence find out of what thought is capable (Bryant, 2008,

p. 138). This also explains the role of paradoxes in Deleuze’s Logic of Sense. They are not evoked,

just for the fun of it:

Paradoxes are recreational only when they are considered as initiatives of thought. They

are not recreational when they are considered as ‘the Passion of thought’, or as discovering

what can only be thought, what can only be spoken, despite the fact that it is both ineffable

and unthinkable. (LS, p. 77)

Paradoxes put thought into movement; they generate thought by showing that current solutions

and the current understanding do not suffice, and hence that thought should proceed along other

paths (Williams, 2008, pp. 24-25).

Why is it, according to Deleuze, that recognition should not be counted as thought?

Deleuze defines recognition as “the harmonious exercise of all the faculties upon a supposed same

object: the same object may be seen, touched, remembered, imagined or conceived” (DR, p. 133).

One can walk past a house and see how it looks; this view coincides with the memory that one has

of how the house looked yesterday; one can then touch the bricks of the house and feel that they

engender the excitement that one expected, etcetera. If all these different sensations agree with

one another, there is a reciprocal confirmation of the correctness of all of them, and one recognizes

the house as a house. The possibility of recognition, then, is based upon the sameness of the object

that is experienced: “An object is recognized … when one faculty locates it as identical to that of

another, or rather when all the faculties together relate their given and relate themselves to a form

Page 23: The philosophy of Deleuze: On its thoroughness, historical

23

of identity in the object” (ibid.). Recognition is thus intimately related to representation:

recognition as the accord of the different faculties paves the way for thinking that objects have

fixed identities. When all the faculties are in agreement, it becomes possible to think of objects in

terms of identities from which nothing escapes; in this way, recognition is a first step on the way

towards representation (p. 138). When objects are seen as having identities, and difference is

reduced to difference between these identities, it is no longer possible to conceive of difference in

itself.

Moreover, if everything is captured by the identities of things, there is nothing left that

disturbs thought. In order to understand what animates thinking, we need to leave the domain of

representation and recognition and enter the realm of encounters. As Deleuze says: “recognizing

is the opposite of the encounter” (D, p. 7). The concept of the encounter refers to something very

specific in Deleuze’s philosophy. It is important to emphasize this, since, one might ask, is it not

true that one also encounters the objects of recognition? Not according to the vocabulary that

Deleuze employs. For Deleuze, we can only speak of an encounter if “Something in the world forces

us to think” (DR, p. 139). The object of the encounter is thus not something that can be recognized.

Deleuze uses the word ‘sign’ to refer to the object of the encounter (PS, p. 62). The sign is hence

something on which the different faculties cannot find an accord with one another.

Deleuze characterizes the sign as follows: “its primary characteristic is that it can only be

sensed … It is not a sensible being but the being of the sensible (DR, pp. 139-140, emphasis in

original). Deleuze calls it the ‘being of the sensible’, because it is not the sensible itself, but rather

that which gives rise to the variety of experiences (Bryant, 2008, p. 64). As Deleuze says of the

sign: “It is not the given but that by which the given is given. It is therefore in a certain sense the

imperceptible. It is imperceptible precisely from the point of view of recognition” (DR, p. 140).

As we saw, the sign is that which forces us to think. Hence, thought has an essential

relationship with signs, and no longer with truths and certainties: “Certainties force us to think no

more than doubts” (DR, p. 139). What is lacking from the dogmatic image of thought are “the claws

of absolute necessity … of a strangeness or an enmity which alone would awaken thought from its

natural stupor or eternal possibility” (ibid.). In terms of modality, we could thus say the following:

one could try to determine the conditions of possible experience, but this does not yet explain how

actual experience is realized. The conditions of possible experience “are too general or too large

for the real. The net is so loose that the largest fish pass through” (DR, p. 68). In order to account

for real experience, one has to determine what adds necessity to the possibility, such that the

latter will be realized. Deleuze finds this necessity in the encounter with the sign.

Determining the conditions of real experience: this is one of Deleuze’s main goals in

Difference and Repetition. These conditions of real experience “are not larger than the

conditioned” (DR, p. 68). If the conditions were larger, then they would merely be conditions of

Page 24: The philosophy of Deleuze: On its thoroughness, historical

24

possible experience (Smith, 2012, p. 240). Encounters fulfil this requirement of not being larger

than what they condition, since they are the encounters with signs, i.e. beings that force us to

think; if they do not force to think, they are not signs. In other words, the potential of signs to

engender thinking is always fully realized; signs do not have an excess potential which was not

realized, but could have led to thought if the circumstances were somewhat different. Signs are

thus not larger than what they engender, namely instances of thought. Each encounter has its own

signs and forces us to think in its own way. Therefore, encounters are the conditions of real

experience, rather than merely of possible experience.

Now, we have seen that recognition and representation fail to capture difference in itself.

We have also seen that signs are the opposite of recognition; while the latter is only the condition

of possible experience, the encounters of signs are the conditions of real experience. Signs escape

thought that is understood on the basis of the model of recognition and representation. What,

then, is the relationship between difference in itself and signs? Deleuze writes the following about

it: “It is in difference that movement is produced as an ‘effect’, that phenomena flash their meaning

like signs” (DR, p. 57). It is thus difference that gives rise to signs. There are therefore two aspects

to Deleuze’s project of thinking difference in itself. On the one hand, difference in itself is a

necessary concept to account for the nomadic distribution, which is that which generates the

sedentary distribution and thus accounts for the coming into existence of the phenomena to which

the categories of representation, in turn, can be applied. This is the ontological aspect. On the other

hand, difference in itself is that which gives rise to signs that account for real experience. This,

then, is the transcendental aspect of Deleuze’s philosophy of difference.

In this chapter, we have first dealt with the question of why Deleuze thinks that it is necessary to

come up with a concept of difference in itself. Deleuze argues that the categories of representation

primarily conceive of beings in terms of identity. Difference, then, is understood as a derivative of

identity; a thing is different from another thing when it has other properties and therefore cannot

share the latter thing’s identity. When the categories of representation are into play, difference is

understood as negation. A thing has an identity of which nothing escapes; therefore, a being is

‘this and not that’, i.e. it is negated the identities of other things. However, this leaves unexplained

how things came into being, and in order to account for that, one has to refer to that which escapes

from the identities that things have under the reign of representation; therefore, one can no longer

think of difference as something that exists because things have an identity. Rather, one has to

take difference as the primary term, and identity as a derivative, in order to account for the

becoming of being. Hence, one has to think difference in itself.

The reason that philosophers before him (with the exception of Nietzsche) have not been

able to think difference in itself, is explained by Deleuze by the fact that they were subject to the

Page 25: The philosophy of Deleuze: On its thoroughness, historical

25

dogmatic image of thought. One of the elements of this image is the postulate of recognition, which

entails the agreement of different faculties and is based on the supposed identity of the object that

is apprehended; this, in turn, makes it impossible to think difference in itself. However, the

dogmatic image of thought cannot account for what gives rise to thought; it merely provides a

picture of possible thought, but lacks the necessity that ensures that thought is realized. The

encounter with a sign provides the necessity to thought, and it is difference that gives rise to the

sign. It is thus difference in itself that provides the key to the process of genesis in Deleuze’s

philosophy: difference in itself gives rise both to beings and to thought.

We have not yet discussed in what way Deleuze actually fulfils his project of thinking

difference in itself. We did see, however, what difference was not: difference should not be

confused with diversity of phenomena, it is not something that can be represented, and difference

should not be thought of as a derivative of identity. How can this be done, thinking difference in

itself, independent of a prior identity? The answer to this question lies in Deleuze’s appropriation

of empiricism. According to Deleuze, the distinctive property of empiricism is the externality of

relations: “Relations are external to their terms” (ES, p. 99). Deleuze will employ this thesis and

push it to its extremes, up to the point that relations no longer even require prior relata (Smith,

2012, p. 245). Empiricism, then, is a theory of multiplicities, since in “a multiplicity, what counts

are not the terms or the elements, but what there is ‘between’, the between, a set of relations

which are not separable from each other” (D, p. vii).

This leads us to the topic of the next chapter: how does Deleuze proceed in thinking

difference in itself? How does he think relations without prior relata? In order to answer these

questions, we have to turn to Deleuze’s notion of ‘Ideas’ and his discussion of the differential

calculus.

Page 26: The philosophy of Deleuze: On its thoroughness, historical

26

4. Ideas and the Necessity of Chance

In this chapter, Deleuze’s notion of Ideas will be discussed. Deleuze adopts this notion from Kant,

for whom Ideas are intimately connected to problems: “Kant never ceased to remind us that Ideas

are essentially ‘problematic’. Conversely, problems are Ideas” (DR, p. 168). For Kant, Ideas result

when the categories are used outside of their rightful domain, i.e. when they are no longer tied to

the intuition (Kant, 1998, B377). For example, the category of causality can be applied in such a

way that we can think of the totality of all causal relations (in other words: the world), even though

we can never know it (since knowing, for Kant, involves both concepts and intuition) (B391-392;

Smith, 2012, p. 108). Now, when the causal nexus is extended to infinity, we can ask questions

like: did the world have a beginning? To such a question, no answer can be given, because it refers

to an object that we do not find in experience (Smith, 2012, p. 109). Hence, for Kant, the object of

the Idea is “a problem permitting of no solution” (Kant, 1998, B510). Ideas are thus problems that

are constructed by reason when the categories are applied without the input of the intuition.

However, Deleuze does not remain satisfied with Kant’s discussion. With Kant, according

to Deleuze, the Ideas are only determined by means of an analogy with the objects of experience,

which leaves their determination extrinsic to the Ideas themselves (DR, p. 169-170; Smith, 2012,

p. 110). Deleuze believes that this shortcoming can be overcome if the challenge that Salomon

Maimon posed to Kant is taken up. Maimon argued that Kant simply assumes knowledge and

morality as matters of fact, and subsequently seeks the conditions of their possibility; instead,

Kant should have shown how knowledge and morality are generated in the first place (Smith,

2012, p. 111). As a second point of critique, Maimon argued that Kant did not succeed in explaining

why the categories of the understanding are applicable to the sensed data of the intuition; there

is a gap between the understanding and sensibility, and Kant did not manage to bridge this gap

(for a more comprehensive discussion of this point, see Voss [2011, pp. 63-67]). Therefore,

Maimon thinks that Kant’s viewpoint of external conditioning between concepts and intuition

should be replaced by a method of internal genesis (Smith, 2012, p. 111; Voss, 2011, p. 63). This

internal genesis is based on differentials that determine each other in a reciprocal relationship,

and are therefore not determined extrinsically. Deleuze follows Maimon in this respect, but

disagrees with the latter regarding the location of the differential Ideas; for Maimon, these Ideas

are enclosed within the understanding of the subject, whereas for Deleuze these Ideas are not

enclosed within the realm of a subject (Voss, 2011, p. 71). Instead, Deleuze speaks of “a fractured

I” (DR, p. 169) and that “Ideas swarm in the fracture” (ibid.), which means that there is an essential

relation between thought and an outside.

In this chapter, we will discuss Deleuze’s theory of Ideas. These Ideas allow Deleuze to

elaborate on how one can think of difference in itself, without subordinating it to a prior identity.

Page 27: The philosophy of Deleuze: On its thoroughness, historical

27

The examination of Deleuzian Ideas will lead us to his use of the differential calculus, the

Bergsonian notions of the virtual and the actual, and to Deleuze’s thesis of the necessity of chance.

First, however, we will discuss what Deleuze has in mind when he talks about problems.

Problems

In the last chapter, we have seen that Deleuze uses the notion of ‘sign’ to refer to that which forces

us to think. The sign accomplishes this, because the sign “moves the soul, ‘perplexes’ it – in other

words, forces it to pose a problem: as though the object of encounter, the sign, were the bearer of

a problem – as though it were a problem” (DR, p. 140). How do we find out about the problem?

Deleuze, in this respect, makes a distinction between knowledge on the one hand, and learning or

apprenticeship on the other. Knowledge is defined by Deleuze as something that one possesses by

finding a solution to a problem, which in turn makes that the latter disappears (p. 164). Learning,

on the other hand, is a process which is engendered by an ‘objecticity’ that does not disappear

when an answer is found (ibid.). This objecticity is the problem. Although the problem “does not

exist, apart from its solutions”, it does not disappear when these are determined, but rather

“insists and persists in these solutions” (p. 163). A favourite example of Deleuze in this respect is

the relationship between the eye and light: “An organism is nothing if not the solution to a problem

… such as the eye which solves a light ‘problem’” (p. 211). This shows clearly the insistence and

persistence of the problem when a solution is found. The light problem does not vanish when the

eye exists; rather, the light problem persists and might invite different solutions in the future, such

as an eye that can see sharper, or that has a better night vision. Moreover, this example shows that

the problem changes as a result of earlier solutions. The first phase of the light problem may have

been concerned with how a simple photosensitive organ can be developed. After this has been

done, more complex eyes can emerge that can build on the earlier solution. The problem thus

changes as a result of the fact that it progresses from earlier solutions, but it is never solved in a

definite way (Williams, 2003, p. 134). Therefore, the process of learning about the problem is

never finished. According to Deleuze, this means that the problem cannot be grasped in a concept

and be represented in consciousness (DR, p. 192). The problem gives rise to “propositions of

consciousness which designate cases of solution, but those propositions by themselves give a

completely inaccurate notion of the instance which engenders them as cases” (ibid.).

As a result, learning about the problem is not a conscious activity. Problems are what gives

rise to solutions that are represented in consciousness, but problems themselves remain

unconscious: “problematic Ideas are precisely the ultimate elements of nature and the subliminal

objects of little perceptions” (DR, p. 165). Ontologically, we should understand problematic Ideas

then as what gives rise to the diversity of beings; transcendentally, we should understand these

Ideas as that which gives rise to thought. As we saw, however, Deleuze also argued that difference

Page 28: The philosophy of Deleuze: On its thoroughness, historical

28

in itself is that which gives rise to both thoughts and beings. This claim, and the claim that Ideas

are responsible for the genesis of beings and thought, turn out to be consistent when we

understand that Ideas are made up of differential relations (ibid.). This will be explained in more

detail in this chapter. The fact that, for Deleuze, problematic Ideas are subliminal, means that they

belong to an unconscious; however, this is not a Freudian unconscious (Smith, 2012, p. 55). The

unconscious that Deleuze has in mind is more like the unconscious as it is conceived of by Leibniz

and Maimon, i.e. as a realm of differentials that give rise to conscious perceptions when the

differentials determine each other reciprocally (pp. 54-55). This reciprocal determination will be

examined in more detail below, but for now this suffices in order to see that, according to Deleuze,

problematic Ideas do not appear to consciousness; therefore “‘learning’ always takes place in and

through the unconscious, thereby establishing the bond of a profound complicity between nature

and mind” (DR, p. 165).

The Idea or the problem, then, is something that is not experienced in consciousness; it is

something which insists or persists, even when the solution is found; the Idea is made up of

differential relations; and Ideas are the entities that give rise to both thought and beings. In order

to make this more concrete, we can look at an example of Ideas, which Deleuze finds in the

differential calculus.

Ideas and the Differential Calculus

In the differential calculus, Deleuze finds a model for thinking difference in itself. The differential

calculus provides an example of how one can think about that which gives rise to the variety of

beings and thought, but which itself cannot be experienced empirically. Deleuze writes the

following about it:

The symbol dx appears as simultaneously undetermined, determinable and

determination. Three principles which together form a sufficient reason correspond to

these three aspects: a principle of determinability corresponds to the undetermined as

such (dx, dy); a principle of reciprocal determination corresponds to the really

determinable (dy/dx); a principle of complete determination corresponds to the

effectively determined (values of dy/dx). In short, dx is the Idea. (DR, p. 171)

The differential relation of the calculus shows how it is possible to think of difference in itself,

independent of a prior identity. The differential calculus was developed in order to deal with the

question of how two variables were related to one another (Somers-Hall, 2013, p. 132). An

example of such a relation between two variables is average velocity: average velocity (v) is the

distance covered (∆s) divided by the time that was needed for this (∆t). In the form of a formula,

Page 29: The philosophy of Deleuze: On its thoroughness, historical

29

this gives: v = ∆s/∆t. This method works for determining average velocities, but it fails if one wants

to determine the speed at a moment of time (ibid.). In that case, the value of ∆t would be zero, and

since it is impossible to divide something by zero, it would be impossible to calculate the speed.

The differential calculus provides the tools to overcome this problem by providing a logic of

relations. In order to understand the differential calculus as a logic of relations, one has to leave

the Leibnizian notion of differentials—i.e., infinitesimals that converge towards zero—behind and

stop thinking that differentials have a value on their own (DR, p. 172; DI, p. 176; Smith, 2012, p.

246). Deleuze therefore writes:

The relation dy/dx is not like a fraction which is established between particular quanta in

intuition, but neither is it a general relation between variable algebraic magnitudes or

quantities. Each term exists absolutely only in its relation to the other: it is no longer

necessary, or even possible, to indicate an independent variable. (DR, p. 172)

If differentials only exist in relation to each other, and thus have no independent existence, then

one avoids the problem of having to attach a value to the individual differentials. In this way, the

problem of a fraction with a denominator which has the value of zero, does not appear. It is only

in a relation that differentials can determine each other reciprocally, and it is only in this relation

that differentials exist. In this sense, it can be said that the differential calculus provides a logic of

relations that exist independently of prior relata. Moreover, these relations persist, even when its

terms no longer exist.

Differentials are thus undetermined in themselves; we have also seen that they are

reciprocally determinable when they enter into a relation with one another. We have not yet seen,

however, what Deleuze means with ‘complete determination’, which he distinguishes from the

reciprocal determination between differentials (DR, p. 175). The complete determination of Ideas

is fulfilled when values are attached to the differential relation (ibid.). This, in turn, gives a

distribution of singular and ordinal points (ibid.; Smith, 2012, pp. 115-116). An example might

clarify this distinction between the two kinds of points. If we have the function y = x2 and hence

the differential relation dy/dx = 2x, then we can speak of a complete determination when values

are given to x, such that we find the values of dy/dx. If x has negative values, then dy/dx also has

negative values, which decrease in absolute value when x increases; if x has the value of zero, then

dy/dx also has the value of zero; and if x is positive, then dy/dx is also positive. When x has the

value of zero, we have an example of a singular point, because it marks the place where the

function changes its direction, i.e., from a decrease to an increase. The other points on the curve

of the function are the ordinary points. The singular points are thus defined as the points where a

transformation occurs.

Page 30: The philosophy of Deleuze: On its thoroughness, historical

30

We have now seen the three aspects that belong to Ideas that are made up of differentials.

By conceptualizing Ideas in this way, Ideas fulfil the requirements that were formulated above:

they are not accessible by consciousness, since differentials do not have an independent existence

that could be apprehended; they only exist in a reciprocal relation, which persists and insists even

when the differentials do not exist; and this accounts for the genesis of determinate entities. At

this place, it should be emphasized that Deleuze uses the differential calculus as a model of Ideas.

In fact, Ideas exist in many different forms; Deleuze gives the examples of physical Ideas, biological

Ideas, and social Ideas, amongst others (DR, pp. 184-186). What they all have in common is that

they are constituted according to a threefold structure: the undetermined, the determinable, and

the determined.

Moreover, the Idea accounts for how thought is produced. As we have seen, thought is the

result of an encounter with a sign, but the sign is the product of two differential elements that

enter into a relation with each other (DR, p. 57). The differentials that give rise to thought are the

minute and unconscious perceptions that become discernible to consciousness when they enter

into a reciprocal relation with one another (Smith, 2012, pp. 94, 119-120). Therefore, Deleuze can

write that “thought thinks only on the basis of an unconscious” (DR, p. 199), i.e., on the basis of

the minute perceptions that cannot be perceived but which nevertheless give rise to thought.

These Deleuzian Ideas are therefore unlike the clear and distinct ideas of Descartes (DR,

p. 213). Only to the extent that differentials enter into a relation with one another, they become

clear to consciousness; however, they are then no longer distinct, but rather confused. When these

differentials are distinct and thus not in a relation, they do not become clear to consciousness and

remain obscure (Smith, 2012, p. 97). Deleuze, following Leibniz, replaces the clear-distinct couple

therefore with two other couples: the clear-confused experience and the distinct-obscure

differentials that give rise to this experience (DR, p. 213).

If Ideas are made up of differential relations that are undetermined in themselves and only

determinable when they are determined reciprocally, then there is no longer any resemblance

between the genetic elements and that to which they give rise. The differentials are nothing in

themselves, but only in relation to each other and give rise to something that is determined; in

this way, difference is constitutive and productive of that which is determined. In order to capture

this absence of resemblance between the determined and its genetic elements, Deleuze employs

the terms ‘virtual’ and ‘actual’.

The Virtual and the Actual

Deleuze makes a distinction between two pairs of terms. On the one hand, there are the possible

and the real; on the other hand, we have the virtual and the actual (B, p. 96; DR, p. 211). This is a

distinction that Deleuze adopts from Bergson. It should be emphasized that Deleuze does not

Page 31: The philosophy of Deleuze: On its thoroughness, historical

31

think that this distinction is applicable to the thought of every philosopher. For example, Deleuze

notices that Heidegger’s notion of the possible is in fact a virtuality (DR, p. 201). However, in order

to appreciate the function of the distinction between the two pairs of terms (possible-real and

virtual-actual), we have to follow the definitions that Deleuze proposes.

For Deleuze, the relation between the possible and the real is of a very different nature

than the relation between the virtual and the actual. Realization, the process of going from the

possible to the real, is defined by two rules: resemblance and limitation (B, p. 97). It is

characterized by resemblance, since “the real is supposed to be in the image of the possible that it

realizes”, because the real is the same as the possible, only with “existence or reality added to it”

(ibid.). The possible thus resembles the real, and they are therefore captured by the same concept

(ibid.). The second rule is that of limitation. Realization is a process of limitation, because not every

possibility is realized: “realization involves a limitation by which some possibles are supposed to

be repulsed or thwarted, while others ‘pass’ into the real” (ibid.). The rule of limitation thus

ensures that not all possibilities are realized, but only a certain number of them.

Why does the possible-real distinction not suffice, according to Deleuze? Deleuze argues

that it is necessary to invoke the virtual-actual pair, because something is missing from an account

that only refers to the possible and the real. This is due to the similarity between the possible and

the real. If the possible and the real resemble each other, then “we no longer understand anything

either of the mechanism of difference or of the mechanism of creation” (B, p. 98). If there is no

difference between the possible and the real except for the existence of the latter, then “we are

forced to conceive of existence as a brute eruption, a pure act or leap which always occurs behind

our backs and is subject to a law of all or nothing” (DR, p. 211). The possible-real pair leaves

unexplained why this, rather than that, came into existence. Moreover, it fails to account for the

creation of something new; if the real is simply the possible, only with existence added to it, then

there is no way in which anything new—i.e. something which is not captured by the possible—

can come into being. Given the fact that Deleuze tries to develop an ontology that provides the

conditions under which the new can emerge, the notion of possibility does not suffice for him

(Smith, 2012, pp. 237, 252-253).

According to Deleuze, then, the Idea cannot be understood along the lines of the possible

and its realization. Therefore, Deleuze writes: “The virtuality of the Idea has nothing to do with

possibility” (DR, p. 191). The virtual and the actual are related to each other in quite a different

manner than the possible and the real. The rules of resemblance and limitation of realization are

replaced by the following two rules: difference or divergence and creation (B, p. 97). These two

rules result from the fact that the virtual and the actual do not resemble each other: “Actualisation

breaks with resemblance as a process no less than it does with identity as a principle” (DR, p. 212).

The process of actualisation thus entails more than just adding existence to the virtual; in the

Page 32: The philosophy of Deleuze: On its thoroughness, historical

32

process of actualisation, the virtual elements undergo a divergence, such that the actualized

beings no longer resemble the virtuality that served as their genetic counterpart. This is also

captured by the fact that actualization is the process in which the distinct-obscure virtual

elements of the Idea enter into a relation and turn into the clear-confused that is experienced

(Smith, 2012, p. 120). The absence of any resemblance between the virtual Idea and the

corresponding actuality means that actualisation “is always a genuine creation” (DR, p. 212). Since

the virtual is not a pre-existing possibility that is realized via limitation, but instead consists of

differential relations that bear no resemblance to what they give rise to, one could say that the

process of actualisation is the creation of something that is genuinely new (ibid.; Colebrook, 2002,

p. 96).

The process of actualization is not the same as the interaction that takes place between

actualized elements. Therefore, Deleuze writes, it involves “a genesis without dynamism, evolving

necessarily in the element of a supra-historicity” (DR, p. 183). It is without dynamism, because it

is a genesis that is not caused by the interplay of one actual element with another, but by a

movement from a virtual structure to its actual incarnation (ibid.). Therefore, Deleuze refers to

this form of genesis by the term ‘static genesis’ (ibid.).

Because there is no resemblance between the virtual and the actual, Deleuze avoids

tracing the transcendental from the empirical. In this way, Deleuze avoids the circular reasoning

that he discerns in a transcendental philosophy that is only interested in the conditions of possible

experience (Alliez, 1998, p. 50). Deleuze criticizes Kant for making this mistake, because the latter

determines the transcendental structures of experience on the basis of the empirical acts of

psychological consciousness, and hence only finds back what he has assumed beforehand (DR, p.

135). The possible, then, is not what gives rise to the real, but it mirrors the real “because it has

been abstracted from the real once made, arbitrarily extracted from the real like a sterile double”

(B, p. 98). The possible-real couple thus takes the real as given and traces the possible from it,

which leaves unexplained how the real came into being in the first place.

The absence of any resemblance between the virtual and the actual can be made more

concrete by using the case of genetics as an example (May, 2005, pp. 48, 88). A person’s DNA could

be conceived of as a virtual Idea. DNA is located in the cell nucleus and contains information about

how this cell will develop, through all the embryonic and foetal stages, to an actual person. DNA

thus explains differences between individual persons; however, it does not explain all these

differences. For example, identical twins have exactly the same DNA, but they do not have identical

fingerprints (Jain, Prabhakar & Pankanti, 2002, p. 2655). Hence, not all differences between

individual persons can be led back to differences in their DNA. Therefore, it is incorrect to

understand DNA as a ‘blueprint’ of the living organism (Dawkins, 2011, pp. 196-199). One could

derive a blueprint from the house and one could also go in the opposite direction, since each

Page 33: The philosophy of Deleuze: On its thoroughness, historical

33

element in the drawing corresponds to an element in the house, and vice versa. It is impossible,

however, to ‘reconstruct’ someone’s DNA on the basis of all his phenotypical characteristics; based

on the different fingerprints, one would then be led to the conclusion that identical twins have

different DNA, which is false. It is thus impossible to understand DNA in terms of the possible and

the real; rather, one has to understand DNA in terms of virtuality and actuality, whereby DNA’s

actualization is the process through which something genuinely new is produced.

The process of actualization is thus a process in which something new emerges, whereby

the actualized entity does not resemble the virtual elements that are its genetic factors. But how

is this process of actualization determined? What is it that is responsible for the fact that the

actualized being is as it is, that this rather than another being is actualized? In order to answer

this question, we need to turn to Deleuze’s notion of intensity. “The expression ‘difference of

intensity’ is a tautology”, Deleuze writes, “Intensity is the form of difference in so far as this is the

reason of the sensible” (DR, p. 222). Intensity is the reason of the sensible by virtue of its

interaction with the Idea (DR, pp. 244-246; Somers-Hall, 2013, p. 181). If one would think that the

Idea is solely responsible for the actualisation of the virtual, and hence would be the sufficient

reason of all phenomena, then one would be making the error of “confusing the virtual with the

possible” (DR, p. 247; cf. Somers-Hall, 2013, p. 181). If the Idea were not related to something

outside of it, then the virtual would already have to contain the actual as a possibility; the process

of actualization would be nothing more than a limitation of all that was included in the virtual;

and there would be no creation of anything genuinely new, since the actual was already potentially

present in the virtual. Therefore, the Idea is actualised in interaction with an environment that

makes that the Idea’s virtual elements are actualized along lines of divergence; this environment

is the space of intensive quantity or, as Deleuze also calls it, the spatium (DR, pp. 230-231; cf.

Smith, 2012, pp. 95-96). Because of the essential relation that the virtual Idea has with an outside

and which determines what eventually will be actualized, entities will only be actualized if the

outside conditions are such that this actualization can take place; because of this dependence,

some actualizations can only take place at certain places and at certain moments (cf. Bell, 2009,

pp. 137-139).

Again, we can take genetics as an illustration in order to make this more concrete. As

Deleuze notes: “A living being is not only defined genetically, by the dynamisms which determine

its internal milieu, but also ecologically, by the external movements which preside over its

distribution” (DR, p. 216; cf. Bryant, 2012, pp. 376-377). Again, this becomes clear when we look

at the differences between the fingerprints of identical twins. This difference is explained by the

fact that the two foetuses from which the twins emerge, are located at different locations in the

womb (Jain, Prabhakar & Pankanti, 2002, p. 2655). Thus, it is the interaction between the virtual

Idea and the intensity of the exteriority, which ultimately gives rise to the diversity of things.

Page 34: The philosophy of Deleuze: On its thoroughness, historical

34

Therefore, Deleuze can say that intensity “is the sufficient reason of all phenomena, the condition

of that which appears” (DR, p. 222).

The necessity of relating the Idea to the field of intensities has consequences for what

questions should be asked. Since the actualization of Ideas depends on their place in the spatium,

it no longer makes sense to search for their essences by asking the question ‘what is X?’ (DI, pp.

95-96). Instead, it is the concrete situation in which the Idea is placed, that determines how the

process of actualization unfolds. Therefore, one has to investigate the concrete conditions. The

Idea “can be determined only with the questions who? how? how much? where and when? in which

case?” (DI, p. 96, emphasis in original).

Up to now in this chapter we have seen that an Idea or problem becomes pressing due to

an encounter with a sign; we have also seen that the actualization of an Idea happens in the

interaction between the Idea and a field of intensities. These two elements lead us to another claim

of Deleuze, which is of the utmost importance to answer the questions with were posed in the

introduction. This is the Deleuzian thesis that there is a necessity of chance.

The Necessity of Chance

We have seen that the encounter of the sign is that which adds necessity to the possibility of

thought, and thereby constitutes the condition of real experience. However, this is only half the

story. The other half is that “it is precisely the contingency of the encounter that guarantees the

necessity of what it leads us to think” (PS, p. 62). There is nothing that guarantees that a certain

sign will occur and that the encounter will happen. The encounter is always the encounter with

something outside of thought: “more important than thought is ‘what is food for thought’” (PS, p.

21). It is therefore not the subject who initiates thought; rather, he is dependent on an outside

which forces him to think. What can be thought is therefore relative to the time and place in which

someone finds himself: “Ideas no more Problems do not exist only in our heads but occur here and

there in the production of an actual historical world” (DR, p. 190). Thought thus reacts to the

problems with which it is confronted in a historical era (Patton, 2000, p. 21). Because of the chance

encounters that are necessary to engender thought, Deleuze describes his procedure for doing

philosophy as a ‘pick-up procedure’ (D, p. 14)

In order to avoid confusion, we need to determine what Deleuze has in mind when he talks

about ‘chance’. Chance, according to Deleuze, should not be understood along the lines of an

expected value. Deleuze, in this respect, refers to the throw of two dice (NP, pp. 25-26). If one

throws multiple times, the outcomes will follow a certain probability distribution and one could

expect an average outcome of seven. If one throws a thousand times, one can be quite certain

about what the average outcome will be (given, of course, that we are not dealing with loaded

dice). However, if one throws only once, there is no certainty about the outcome. This is what

Page 35: The philosophy of Deleuze: On its thoroughness, historical

35

Deleuze talks about when he refers to chance: the absence of certainty and predictability about

the outcome of a process.

Why does Deleuze think that chance, understood in this way, necessarily exists? This has

to do with the fact that actualization is an unpredictable process (cf. Baugh, 1992, pp. 139, 141).

As we have seen, the actual does not resemble the virtual. Therefore, the actualization is a process

in which something genuinely new is produced, something that was not contained in the virtuality

from which it sprang, and hence it cannot be known beforehand how the actualized being will look

exactly. This is determined by the place where the virtual Idea is located in the spatium, and this

is fortuitous. The thought or the being that emerges as a result is therefore also fortuitous.

The statement that there is a necessity of chance thus has two senses (Bryant, 2008, p.

208). The first is that there necessarily is chance; one cannot predict what will result from the

actualization of a virtual Idea. The second sense of the necessity of chance is that the chance

encounter leads to thought: thought is something that necessarily follows from the sign which one

encounters only by chance. Thinking thus only appears as the result of an interplay between

chance and necessity: “the accident of the encounter and the necessity of thought: ‘fortuitous and

inevitable’” (PS, p. 65).

This chapter dealt with the question of how Deleuze works out a way to think difference in itself.

He does this by use of the Idea. The Idea is made up of differentials that are nothing until they

enter into a relation with one another. In this relation, the differentials are reciprocally

determinable and are completely determined in the distribution of ordinary and singular points

that they generate. Because there is no resemblance between the differentials and that to which

they give rise, the possible-real couple has to be replaced by the virtual-actual couple. The process

of actualization is the creation of something that did not exist before; thereby, it provides an

explanation for the variety of beings and thoughts, and shows how difference gives rise to

diversity.

The process of actualization is an unpredictable process. As a result of this, Deleuze can

speak of the necessity of chance. The necessity of chance is thus a result of Deleuze’s attempt to

think difference in itself. There necessarily is chance, and the encounter is the result of this chance.

This encounter, in turn, necessitates thought. There are hence two senses in which the necessity

of chance should be understood.

Deleuze did not merely want to declare that there is a necessity of chance; he also wanted

to think about what the consequences of this finding are. In particular, Deleuze argue that it has

repercussions for what it means to think and for what it means to do philosophy. The dogmatic

image of thought does not suffice in this respect. Therefore, a new image of thought and a new

conception of philosophy have to be developed.

Page 36: The philosophy of Deleuze: On its thoroughness, historical

36

This task constitutes an important part of Deleuze’s later philosophical work, which he

often carried out in collaboration with others. The next chapter deals with Deleuze’s vision on

philosophy. We will discuss what the task of philosophy is, according to Deleuze, and how he

thinks that this task should be fulfilled. It will be argued that Deleuze’s views on philosophy, which

are formulated in his later work, exhibit a continuity with his project to think difference in itself.

Page 37: The philosophy of Deleuze: On its thoroughness, historical

37

5. Deleuze’s Conception of Philosophy

In this chapter, we will deal with Deleuze’s conception of philosophy, which is a quite idiosyncratic

one. Philosophy, according to Deleuze, is a creative activity; philosophers are just as creative as,

for example, artists and scientists (TRM, p. 318). More specifically, Deleuze thinks that philosophy

is about creating concepts (WP, p. 5). Philosophy should be useful, and this usefulness can be

measured by the extent to which new concepts give rise to a change regarding certain aspects of

the present (Patton, 2010, p. 64). Therefore, according to Deleuze, “Philosophy does not consist

in knowing and is not inspired by truth. Rather, it is categories like Interesting, Remarkable, or

Important that determine success or failure” (WP, p. 82).

This chapter will first of all deal with Deleuze’s conception of philosophy as an instrument

that should be used. Then, we will turn to the essential relation that philosophy has with the

present. Finally, we will discuss the means that philosophy employs, and discuss what the creation

of concepts actually entails.

Theory as an Instrument

In a conversation with Foucault on the relation between theory and practice, Deleuze says that

theory is a ‘tool box’: “A theory has to be used, it has to work. And not just for itself. If there is no

one to use it … then a theory is worthless, or its time has not yet arrived” (DI, p. 208). A theory is

thus not worthwhile on its own, according to Deleuze. A theory should be connected to something

outside of it, and for which it fulfils a practical function. Deleuze, in this respect, also refers to the

relay: “Praxis is a network of relays from one theoretical point to another, and theory relays one

praxis to another. A theory cannot be developed without encountering a wall, and a praxis is

needed to break through” (p. 206). This means that there is no totalization between theory and

practice; new theories make new practices possible and vice versa, but the one does not determine

fully what the other looks like (ibid.).

Deleuze’s view on theory as a tool box or as an instrument that should be used, is inspired

by Proust’s view on his own books (DI, p. 208). Deleuze appropriates this view and uses it in order

to explain his view on what theory is. Although a theory should be used, this does not mean that

there is only one correct way to employ the theory. In fact, there are many different possible ways

to make use of a theory; the theory can be whatever one likes it to be. As Deleuze writes with

respect to Proust’s novels: “[It] is anything it may seem; it is even its very property of being

whatever we like, of having the overdetermination of whatever we like, from the moment it works”

(PS, p. 94, emphasis in original). The theorist does not prescribe how the theory should be utilized;

someone can employ the theory as he thinks fit. However, Deleuze emphasizes, if the theory is of

Page 38: The philosophy of Deleuze: On its thoroughness, historical

38

no value to the user, then one should not go back to this theory, but rather invent new ones (DI, p.

208).

If theories have to be used, and if there is not one correct way to use them, then one should

not try to interpret a theory or try to understand what the theorist had in mind when he developed

the theory. Another way of reading books of theory is needed in order to do justice to them.

Deleuze calls this an ‘intensive way of reading’, i.e. a manner of reading that is “in contact with

what’s outside the book … as a series of experiments for each reader in the midst of events that

have nothing to do with books” (N, pp. 8-9). A theoretical book should thus not be approached as

something that is sufficient in itself; it always has to connect with something that is external to the

book. A theory can, for example, be connected to political struggles that are going on, to social

transformations, etcetera, and form a ‘relay’ that allows for new practices to emerge (DI, p. 207).

How a book is used is thus not an intrinsic property of the book, but is determined ‘between’ the

book and its outside (cf. D, p. vii).

The intensive way of reading has as its correlate a view on what a book should be. If a book

is to be used to make a difference in the world, it should not be an image of the world; if a book is

thought of in this way, it merely invites an attempt to interpret the book in order to understand

the world (TP, pp. 3-5). According to Deleuze and Guattari, a book should rather be like a ‘rhizome’

(p. 5). A rhizomatic book does not represent the world, but rather forms a connection with it (p.

10). It does this by ‘mapping’ the world, rather than ‘tracing’ it. Tracing the world is the attempt

to mirror the world as it is, while mapping the world has to do with performance, with fostering

links between beings that had no connection before (pp. 11-12). Tracing is thus an activity that

has no effect on the world, but only creates the world’s double in the form of a representation,

whereas mapping changes the world by creating new connections (Oosterling, 2012, p. 191).

In this respect, Bell (2009) makes an informative comparison between Deleuze and

Latour. The existence of entities is not a matter of all or nothing; it is not the case that something

either exists, or does not exist (p. 137). Instead, it would be better to speak of the ‘relative

existence’ of entities, since entities will exist more fully if they can enter into relations with other

beings and hence can influence other entities to a greater extent (p. 138). In other words, by

creating new connections between beings, their power of acting is increased. For Deleuze, the use

of a book is only legitimate if it increases someone’s power of acting and does not separate him

from his power of acting; these are the ‘immanent criteria’ that distinguish between legitimate

and illegitimate uses of a book (AO, p. 132). (For an extensive discussion of Deleuze’s immanent

ethics, see Smith [2012, pp. 146-159].)

Theories thus should be useful, and they are only useful if they are connected to an outside.

The theorist does not prescribe how the theory should be used; everyone can employ the theory

Page 39: The philosophy of Deleuze: On its thoroughness, historical

39

as it suits him. However, the theorist does not develop a theory out of the blue; the theory has a

specific connection to the present. This is the point to which we will turn now.

Making a Difference in the Present

Although a theorist does not prescribe how a theory should be used, there are nevertheless some

things that can be said about the way in which a theory functions. Philosophy is the activity that

involves the creation of concepts, but concepts do not leave things as they are: “Concepts cut up

and combine the things corresponding to them in various and always new ways. They cannot be

distinguished from a way of perceiving things: a concept forces us to see things differently” (TRM,

p. 330). By forcing us to see the world in a different light, concepts make a difference in the

present.

Deleuze often emphasizes that philosophy is intimately connected to the present. Deleuze

discerns this also in concepts of other philosophers: in Péguy’s ‘Aternal’ and in Foucault’s ‘Actual’

(which should not be confused with the meaning that Bergson and Deleuze give to this term), but

most importantly in ‘the Untimely’ of Nietzsche (WP, pp. 111-113). Although Deleuze refers

regularly to the Untimely and mentions Nietzsche’s name in connection to it, Deleuze’s use of this

concept is not exactly the same as Nietzsche’s (Lundy [2009] provides a discussion regarding

Deleuze’s appropriation of this concept of Nietzsche). For Deleuze, acting in an untimely fashion

amounts to the following: “Acting counter to the past, and therefore on the present, for the benefit,

let us hope, of a future” (WP, p. 112). This future, however, does not refer to some moment or

period in a time to come, but rather to a becoming (ibid.). This means that the becoming which

Deleuze has in mind does not belong to history. Rather, becoming should be distinguished from

what happens in history: “Becoming isn’t part of history; history amounts only the set of

preconditions, however recent, that one leaves behind in order to ‘become’, that is, to create

something new” (N, p. 171). As we saw, something new is created through the process of

actualization, and this is what Deleuze has in mind when he refers to becoming (May, 2003, p.

148). Since actualization is an unpredictable process, Deleuze writes that the result of becoming

cannot be foreseen; therefore, becoming has to do with experimentation: “experimentation is

always that which is in the process of coming about—the new, remarkable, and interesting” (WP,

111). Experimentation does not take place in history; rather, history provides the “set of almost

negative conditions that make possible the experimentation of something that escapes history.

Without history experimentation would remain indeterminate and unconditioned, but

experimentation is not historical. It is philosophical” (ibid.). In this respect, it is helpful to think of

experimentation as a static genesis; just as the actualization of the virtual is something that

escapes from the interaction of actualized entities, experimentation is something that escapes

from history.

Page 40: The philosophy of Deleuze: On its thoroughness, historical

40

Deleuze thinks that the Untimely and experimentation belong to philosophy proper, and

the centrality of the presence therefore also informs his reading of other philosophers. This

becomes clear when Deleuze clarifies what it means to engage with Bergson’s philosophy.

Returning to Bergson “does not only mean a renewed admiration for a great philosopher but a

renewal or an extension of his project today, in relation to the transformations of life and society,

in parallel with the transformations of science” (B, p. 115). The same holds in the case of Nietzsche;

we should not ask what Nietzsche’s philosophy is, but what Nietzsche’s philosophy is today (DI, p.

252). The meaning of Nietzsche’s philosophy only becomes clear when it is related to an outside,

and since this outside does not stay the same all the time, Nietzsche’s philosophy itself also

undergoes changes, according to Deleuze (p. 256). Hence, reading philosophy is itself an

experimentation, turning it into something new and making it relevant to the present.

Why does Deleuze emphasize the importance of the present so much? Why should

philosophy be able to make a change in the current situation, rather than providing eternal truths

that are always valid and useful? It has to do with something that we have already discussed,

namely with the fact that thought is provoked by the sign. The sign disturbs the mind, makes that

something is experienced as problematic, and therefore demands a response. This is what

happens in a chance encounter. This encounter does not have to happen. It comes from the outside

and “does violence to thought” (PS, p. 62). This makes that something is experienced as

problematic. The problem, however, is relative to already existing solutions; as we saw, the light

problem changes as a result of earlier solutions (different eyes) to that same problem. Strictly

speaking, we should therefore not speak of the light problem, but instead of different problems

and thus of different signs that are encountered. Because of the dependence on earlier solutions,

one could say that our problems are the problems of our era; they could not have appeared in this

specific form at an earlier moment (cf. Patton, 2000, p. 21). Hence, we cannot take over a problem

as it was centuries ago. As Deleuze writes: “we have new problems to discover, instead of trying

to ‘return’” (TRM, p. 355).

It is by means of experimentation that it is possible to find answers to the problems that

one encounters. It is thus because of the fact that our problems belong to the present, that

philosophy, as a response to these problems, is also tied to the present. Furthermore, because a

problem only emerges as a result of a fortuitous encounter, not everyone in a current era

necessarily shares the same problem, and hence philosophical concepts do not appeal to everyone

equally. As Deleuze and Guattari express it: “one person’s creative line is the other’s

imprisonment” (TP, p. 240). It is also because of the fortuitousness of the encounter that Deleuze

does not want to prescribe how a theory should be used; someone might find a theory useful for

a problem, even when the theorist did not anticipate on this (cf. May, 1991, pp. 33-34).

Page 41: The philosophy of Deleuze: On its thoroughness, historical

41

An example of this form of philosophy, i.e., philosophy as a response to contemporary

problems, is provided by Anti-Oedipus, a book in which psychoanalysis is subjected to a harsh

critique. Deleuze writes the following about it:

Our outside … was a particular mass of people (especially young people) who are fed up

with psychoanalysis. They’re ‘trapped’, … because they generally continue in analysis even

after they’ve started to question psychoanalysis—but in psychoanalytic terms … The fact

that this current is there made Anti-Oedipus possible. (N, p. 8)

It is thus only in connection to an outside which is specific to a historical era, that philosophy fulfils

its untimely role. It is only in relation to people who are trapped in psychoanalysis, that Anti-

Oedipus fulfils its task. Deleuze and Guattari do not shy away from accepting the consequences

that follow from such a view on philosophy. At the end of Anti-Oedipus, after having spent a book

on criticizing psychoanalysis, they write: “If someone reading this book feels that things are fine

in psychoanalysis, we’re not speaking for him, and for him we take back everything we have said”

(AO, p. 431).

We have now seen that, according to Deleuze, philosophy provides theoretical tools that

can be employed if they suit the user, and left behind if they do not. Philosophy is tightly connected

to the present, because the problems to which philosophy responds, are also problems of the

present. We have not yet seen, however, in what way philosophy fulfils this function. This is the

concrete practice of philosophy, to which we will now turn.

Philosophy as the Creation of Concepts

For Deleuze, as we have already noticed, philosophy is the creation of concepts, but the

philosopher does not create concepts without any urgency. Rather, concepts are created out of

necessity, as a response to problems (N, p. 136; WP, p. 16). However, for Deleuze, as we have seen,

the necessity of finding a response to the problem emerges as a result of the fortuitous encounter

with a sign that disturbs the mind and “forces us to think” (PS, p. 12). Therefore, there is no

contradiction between the view that philosophy is the creation of necessary concepts, and the

claim that “philosophy does have a principle, but it is a synthetic and contingent principle—an

encounter, a conjunction. It is not insufficient by itself but contingent in itself” (WP, p. 93).

Furthermore, since history will always throw up new problems, the task of philosophy is never

finished. Therefore, it is useless, according to Deleuze, to speak of the death of philosophy (N, p.

136). The creation of concepts, as a response to new problems, is something that belongs to

philosophy and to philosophy alone (ibid.; WP, p. 33).

Page 42: The philosophy of Deleuze: On its thoroughness, historical

42

What is the concept, according to Deleuze? What is his conception of the concept? It is

important to emphasize that Deleuze’s understanding of concepts does not remain the same

during the development of his oeuvre (Bearn, 2000, pp. 443-444). In Difference and Repetition, for

example, the concept is the pendant of representation, and captures the presumed identities of

things (DR, p. 29; Groot, 2012, p. 115). In What is Philosophy? another conception of the concept

comes forth. Here, the concept no longer simply refers to a thing; rather, Deleuze and Guattari

write that the concept “has no reference: it is self-referential” (WP, p. 22, emphasis in original).

Hence, when Deleuze and Guattari use the concept of nomadism, they do not refer to actual

nomads in the same way as an anthropological study does (Patton, 2010, p. 35). On the other hand,

a concept should also not be confused with a metaphor. It is not the case that concepts are in some

respect comparable to the thing that they stand for: “In none of the cases are we making a

metaphorical use of it: we don’t say that is ‘like’ black holes in astronomy, that is ‘like’ a white

canvas in painting” (D, p. 14). Concepts should rather be understood as fictions; they are made,

not with the goal of being an accurate description of something, but in order to influence how

something is perceived (Patton, 2000, pp. 25-26; 2010, pp. 72-73). By coining new terms for, for

example, political events and social processes, philosophy is able to influence everyday life

(Patton, 2010, p. 73). Moreover, concepts do not remain the same all the time, since they enter

into relations and undergo resonances with other concepts; concepts, thus, are essentially mobile

(D, p. 108; N, p. 122; Patton, 2010, p. 32). An existing concept may thus become different when it

is related to a problem with which it did not have a connection before.

If philosophy is the creation of concepts that “have an impact on ordinary life, on the flows

of ordinary or day-to-day thinking” (TRM, p. 176), then the opposite of philosophy is thinking

always in the same way and along the same lines. Deleuze calls this opposite of philosophy

variously ‘stupidity’, ‘opinion’ or ‘cliché’ (e.g. DR, p. 151; WP, p. 150). When opinions and clichés

reign, there is no possibility of ever being disturbed by a problem, since everything that could

potentially disrupt day-to-day thinking is reduced to the familiar (Patton, 2000, p. 20; Smith, 2012,

p. 144). As we have seen, this is also a critique that Deleuze formulated against recognition, and it

is therefore no surprise that, according to Deleuze, opinion “is closely molded on the form of

recognition” (WP, p. 145). Philosophy can counter the threat of opinion to thought by creating

concepts, since “Concepts are what stops thought being a mere opinion” (N, p. 136). Concepts thus

are not merely a response to problems, but they also ensure that the problem develops its full

force and is not immediately rendered impotent by opinions and clichés (Smith, 2012, p. 136).

Because of the fact that a concept is unfamiliar, it cannot be led back to something that is

recognizable (N, p. 136). Now it is true that, after some time, newly invented concepts may become

clichés as well, thereby losing their power to make a difference in the present. However, new

problems will keep coming up and demand responses in the form of concepts. The fact that

Page 43: The philosophy of Deleuze: On its thoroughness, historical

43

concepts may lose their ability to have an effect on the present therefore merely means, according

to Deleuze, that philosophy has to continue its task of creating new concepts; it is in this way, that

philosophy “is by nature creative or even revolutionary” (ibid.).

Along these lines we can understand Deleuze and Guattari’s claim that “to create is to

resist” (WP, p. 110). By creating novel concepts, the ways of thinking that are suggested in the

present, are resisted. As Deleuze notes: “Stupidity’s never blind or mute. So it’s not a problem of

getting people to express themselves but of providing little gaps of solitude and silence in which

they might eventually find something to say” (N, p. 129). New concepts serve as a blockage for

opinions and clichés, and makes that their murmur is silenced. This ensures an open future, and

makes that philosophy aligns with the Untimely.

In this chapter Deleuze’s conception of philosophy has been discussed. He views philosophy as a

tool that should be employed by users to make a difference in the present. Philosophy achieves

this by creating concepts that are opposed to mere opinions, and which disturb day-to-day

thought.

It has been argued that Deleuze’s conception of philosophy follows from his project to

think difference in itself. Deleuze sees problems as the result of chance encounters with signs that

unsettle thought. Because of this, the problems that one encounters are always contemporary

problems; therefore, philosophy has an essential relation to the present. Moreover, not everybody

in a certain era has these encounters and hence experiences the same problems. Therefore,

Deleuze thinks that it is not a disqualification of philosophy if it does not serve everybody equally;

this simply follows from the fact that all do not share the same problems. Furthermore, Deleuze’s

conception of concepts as that which distorts opinion exhibits a continuation with his critique on

recognition. In Difference and Repetition, Deleuze criticized recognition for not being able to think

difference in itself; in his later work, recognition is made impotent by the creation of unfamiliar

concepts that distort recognition’s functioning.

With this discussion of Deleuze’s conception of philosophy and its relation to Deleuze’s

project to think difference in itself, we now have all the elements to answer the questions that

were posed in the introduction. This will be done now, in the conclusion and the discussion.

Page 44: The philosophy of Deleuze: On its thoroughness, historical

44

6. Conclusion and Discussion

This thesis started with three issues that follow from Deleuze’s philosophy. The first issue dealt

with the status of Deleuze’s theses: are these claims the result of rigorous reasoning that can

convince his readers, or are they merely alternative visions that can be cherished if they please,

and be forgotten if they do not? The second issue focused on the validity of Deleuze’s philosophy:

is the validity of his philosophy tied to a certain historical era, or does it transcend the moment in

which it was written? The third and final issue focuses on the question of in what way Anti-Oedipus

and A Thousand Plateaus can be understood as books of political philosophy. Now, after having

discussed Deleuze’s endeavour to think difference in itself and how this relates to his conception

of philosophy, we are in the position to formulate answers to these three questions.

With respect to the first issue, we have seen that Deleuze tries to think difference in itself,

not just because it might be an interesting project, but because he discerns serious problems with

an ontology that reduces difference to a derivative of identity, and hence does not have a concept

for difference in itself. Without difference in itself, it is neither possible to explain how something

new comes into being, and neither is it possible to explain how actual thoughts come forth.

Deleuze argues that the inability to think difference in itself is a result of the demands of

representation. In order to overcome these problems, Deleuze developed the notion of the virtual

Idea, which contains differentials that only exist when they enter into a relation with each other.

The actualization of the virtual, however, is an unpredictable process, such that the problems with

which we are confronted are the result of chance. Concepts, which are responses to problems, are

thus only useful to those who have certain problems and can find a use for the tools that Deleuze

provides. Deleuze thus does not argue for the usefulness of these tools or for how they should be

used; if a concept resonates with the problems of its users, then these users themselves are able

to find employment for the concept and do not have to be convinced by Deleuze. Deleuze’s

pragmatic conception of philosophy, in which theory should be judged according to its usefulness

and where arguments do not play a central role, thus follows from Deleuze’s project to think

difference in itself and for which Deleuze does provide reasons that can convince his readers. The

absence in his later work of any attempt to convince his readers thus is a result of his earlier work,

which was characterized by argumentation.

Regarding the second issue, which deals with the historical relativity of Deleuze’s work,

we can make a similar distinction between Deleuze’s earlier and his later work. In Difference and

Repetition, Deleuze argued that problems are the result of chance encounters; therefore, some

problems can only occur at certain moments and at certain places. Hence, the usefulness of the

concepts that are a response to these problems, is also dependent on a historical period, and it is

therefore correct to speak of the historical relativity of Deleuze’s philosophy. On the other hand,

Page 45: The philosophy of Deleuze: On its thoroughness, historical

45

Deleuze has also argued that there necessarily is chance; since the process of actualization is an

unpredictable process, one cannot know in advance which problem will emerge. What problems

we will confront is thus the contingent result of fortuitous encounters; but it is necessary that

these problems will be the result of chance. The necessity of chance is something that is true for

every historical period. It is because of this thesis, which holds true for every historical era, that it

is necessary to create concepts whose usefulness is relative to a historical period.

It is thus necessary to make a distinction between Deleuze’s earlier work and his later

work, in order to appreciate the philosophy that he develops in both periods. If one would, for

example, read Difference and Repetition merely as an alternative view that can be used if it pleases

and forgotten if it does not, then one loses sight of the arguments that Deleuze puts forth in this

work. On the other hand, if one wants to be convinced of the usefulness of the concepts that

Deleuze develops in his later philosophy, one would end up disappointed, because he does not try

to convince the reader of their value. However, this pragmatism of Deleuze’s later work follows

from his earlier philosophy. The earlier work provides the necessity for a new image of thought,

but does not present this new image; the later work is an example of this new image of thought.

Both aspects of Deleuze’s philosophy become more unsettling when the continuity between them

is taken into account, and such an interpretation is therefore in line with Deleuze’s view on what

thought should be (cf. DR, pp. 135-136).

The third issue concerned the question of how Deleuze’s later philosophy can be

understood as an ethics and a political philosophy, since he does not provide concrete guidelines

for action, and neither formulates how an ideal society looks like. This should not be understood

as an omission, however. According to Deleuze, thought emerges as a result of fortuitous

encounter, and is hence tied to a historical period. The concept’s usefulness is therefore relative

to a historical period. This explains why Deleuze does not formulate rules or images of an ideal

society that have a universal validity. Deleuze’s philosophy is practical in a more specific way, in

the sense that it provides a way to deal with concrete problems. If these problems get a response

when a new concept is created that allows us to see the world in a new light, then the practical

use of philosophy should be sought in concrete situations; it should not be viewed as a way to deal

with abstract or universal problems.

Now that we have formulated answers to the three questions that were posed in the

introduction, we still need to reflect on two issues that were brought forth in the methodological

section. The first issue was whether Deleuze’s philosophy should be considered as a whole. As

was argued above, there should be made a distinction between Deleuze’s earlier and his later

work; nevertheless, a continuity can be discerned in his oeuvre. Deleuze’s conception of

philosophy as the creation of concepts that should have an impact on the present, follows from

Page 46: The philosophy of Deleuze: On its thoroughness, historical

46

his earlier philosophy. In this sense, Deleuze’s philosophy should be viewed as a whole, and not

as a composition of fragments that do not have a relation to each other.

The second issue to which we have to come back is whether the methodological choice, to

start off from Deleuze’s attempt to think difference in itself, is justified. Was it necessary to invoke

this endeavour to answer the questions that were posed in the introduction? In the above sections,

it was argued that, according to Deleuze, a philosophy that does not have a concept for difference

in itself does not succeed in explaining how new beings and new thoughts can emerge. From the

project to think difference in itself, several commitments followed for Deleuze. One of these was

that the problems with which thought is faced, are the result of chance encounters and dependent

on history. This accounts for the historical relativity of the concepts of Deleuze’s later philosophy,

and the absence of any attempt to convince his readers of the usefulness of these. However, the

fact that new beings and new thoughts emerge in this way is something that has a universal

validity, according to Deleuze, and makes that this transcends historical periods. In order to

provide an answer to the problems that were posed in the introduction, it was thus necessary to

take this detour along Deleuze’s attempt to think difference in itself.

In this thesis, it was argued that Deleuze’s philosophy gains in interest when the continuity

between his earlier and his later work is taken into account. With respect to the earlier philosophy,

the emphasis in this thesis was on Difference and Repetition, because of the focus on Deleuze’s

endeavour to think difference in itself. However, other continuities might have been discerned

when Deleuze’s Logic of Sense and his philosophy of language would have been the emphasis. How

this Deleuzian logic of sense functions in the later work that he produced in collaboration with

Guattari, is one of the aspects of Deleuze’s philosophy that deserves further exploration.

Page 47: The philosophy of Deleuze: On its thoroughness, historical

47

Literature

Alliez, E. (1998). Sur la philosophie de Gilles Deleuze: une entrée en matière. Rue Descartes, 20,

49-57.

Baugh, B. (1992). Transcendental empiricism: Deleuze’s response to Hegel. Man and World, 25(2),

133-148.

Bearn, G. C. F. (2000). Differentiating Derrida and Deleuze. Continental Philosophy Review, 33(4),

441-465.

Bell, J. A. (2009). Deleuze’s Hume: Philosophy, Culture and the Scottish Enlightenment. Edinburgh:

Edinburgh University Press.

Boundas, C. V. (1991). Translator’s Introduction: Deleuze, Empiricism, and the Struggle for

Subjectivity. In G. Deleuze, Empiricism and Subjectivity (pp. 1-19). New York: Columbia

University Press.

Bryant, L. (2008). Difference and Givenness: Deleuze’s Transcendental Empiricism and the Ontology

of Immanence. Evanston, Illinois: Northwestern University Press.

Bryant, L. (2012). Individuering. In E. Romein, M. Schuilenburg & S. van Tuinen (Eds.), Deleuze

Compendium (pp. 372-387). Amsterdam: Boom.

Buchanan, I. (2011). Desire and Ethics. Deleuze Studies, 5(supplement), 7-20.

Colebrook, C. (2002). Gilles Deleuze. London and New York: Routledge.

Colombat, A. P. (1991). A Thousand Trails to Work with Deleuze. Substance, 20(3), 10-23.

Dawkins, R. (2011). Het Grootste Spektakel ter Wereld. Amsterdam: Nieuw Amsterdam Uitgevers.

Deleuze, G. (1983). Nietzsche and Philosophy. New York: Columbia University Press.

Deleuze, G. (1991). Empiricism and Subjectivity. New York: Columbia University Press.

Deleuze, G. (1994). Difference and Repetition. New York: Columbia University Press.

Deleuze, G. (1995). Negotiations, 1972-1990. New York: Columbia University Press.

Deleuze, G. (2004). Desert Island and Other Texts 1953-1974. Los Angeles: Semiotext(e).

Deleuze, G. (2006). Two Regimes of Madness: Texts and Interviews 1975-1995. New York:

Semiotext(e).

Deleuze, G. (2008). Proust and Signs. London: Continuum.

Deleuze, G. (2011). Bergsonism. New York: Zone Books.

Deleuze, G. (2015). Logic of Sense. London: Bloomsbury.

Deleuze, G., & Guattari, F. (1994). What Is Philosophy? London: Verso.

Deleuze, G., & Guattari, F. (2016a). Anti-Oedipus. London: Bloomsbury.

Deleuze, G., & Guattari, F. (2016b). A Thousand Plateaus. London: Bloomsbury.

Deleuze, G., & Parnet, C. (2007). Dialogues II. New York: Columbia University Press.

Derrida, J. (1988). Limited Inc. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.

Page 48: The philosophy of Deleuze: On its thoroughness, historical

48

Foucault, M. (1995). Discipline and Punish. New York: Vintage Books.

Foucault, M. (1998). Theatrum Philosophicum. In J. D. Faubion (Ed.), Essential Works of Foucault:

Aesthetics, Method, and Epistemology (pp. 343-368).

Foucault, M. (2016). Preface. In G. Deleuze & F. Guattari, Anti-Oedipus (pp. xi-xiv). London:

Bloomsbury.

Groot, G. (2012). Différence et répétition. In E. Romein, M. Schuilenburg & S. van Tuinen (Eds.),

Deleuze Compendium (pp. 113-131). Amsterdam: Boom.

Hardt, M. (2007). Gilles Deleuze: An Apprenticeship in Philosophy. Minneapolis: University of

Minnesota Press.

Husserl, E. (1999). Cartesian Meditations. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

Jain, A. K., Prabhakar, S., & Pankanti, S. (2002). On the similarity of identical twin fingerprints.

Pattern Recognition, 35(11), 2653-2663.

Kant, I. (1998). Critique of Pure Reason. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Leigh, J. A. (1978). Deleuze, Nietzsche and the eternal return. Philosophy Today, 22(3), 206-223.

Lundy, C. (2009). Deleuze’s Untimely: Uses and Abuses in the Appropriation of Nietzsche. In J. A.

Bell & C. Colebrook (Eds.), Deleuze and History (pp. 188-205). Edinburgh: Edinburgh

University Press.

Malabou, C. (2010). The Eternal Return and the phantom of difference. Parrhesia, 10, 21-29.

May, T. (1991). The Politics of Life in the Thought of Gilles Deleuze. Substance, 20(3), 24-35.

May, T. (2003). When is a Deleuzian Becoming? Continental Philosophy Review, 36(2), 139-153.

May, T. (2005). Gilles Deleuze: An Introduction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Oosterling, H. (2012). Rizoom. In E. Romein, M. Schuilenburg & S. van Tuinen (Eds.), Deleuze

Compendium (pp. 188-204). Amsterdam: Boom.

Patton, P. (2000). Deleuze and the Political. London and New York: Routledge.

Patton, P. (2010). Deleuzian Concepts: Philosophy, Colonization, Politics. Stanford, California:

Stanford University Press.

Smith, D. W. (2012). Essays on Deleuze. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.

Somers-Hall, H. (2013). Deleuze’s Difference and Repetition. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University

Press.

Stengers, I. (2005). Deleuze and Guattari’s Last Enigmatic Message. Angelaki, 10(2), 151-167.

Stengers, I. (2012). Leven/denken. In E. Romein, M. Schuilenburg & S. van Tuinen (Eds.), Deleuze

Compendium (pp. 265-282). Amsterdam: Boom.

Tanner, M. (2000). Nietzsche: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Voss, D. (2011). Maimon and Deleuze: the viewpoint of internal genesis and the concept of

differentials. Parrhesia, 11, 62-74.

Page 49: The philosophy of Deleuze: On its thoroughness, historical

49

Williams, J. (2003). Gilles Deleuze’s Difference and Repetition. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University

Press.

Williams, J. (2008). Gilles Deleuze’s Logic of Sense. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.

Wilson, M. D. (2005). Descartes. New York: Routledge.