the lottery paradox - rensselaer polytechnic...

123
The Lottery Paradox Rensselaer AI & Reasoning (RAIR) Lab Department of Cognitive Science Department of Computer Science Lally School of Management & Technology Rensselaer Polytechnic Institute (RPI) Troy, New York 12180 USA Intro to Logic 4/28/2016 Selmer Bringsjord • Kevin O’Neill

Upload: others

Post on 06-Oct-2020

3 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

The Lottery Paradox

Rensselaer AI & Reasoning (RAIR) LabDepartment of Cognitive ScienceDepartment of Computer Science

Lally School of Management & TechnologyRensselaer Polytechnic Institute (RPI)

Troy, New York 12180 USA

Intro to Logic4/28/2016

Selmer Bringsjord • Kevin O’Neill

Page 2: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Homeworks 3&4: Oops :).

Page 3: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Homeworks 3&4: Oops :).

A+ problem with significant prize coming …

Page 4: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Paradoxes are engines of progress in formal logic.

E.g., Russell’s Paradox — as we’ve seen.

Page 5: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

The paradox in this case?

Page 6: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

The paradox in this case?

• A perfectly rational person can never believe P and believe ¬P at the same time.

Page 7: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

The paradox in this case?

• A perfectly rational person can never believe P and believe ¬P at the same time.

• The Lottery Paradox (apparently) shows, courtesy of its two Sequences (of Reasoning), that a perfectly rational person can indeed have such a belief (upon considering a fair, large lottery).

Page 8: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

The paradox in this case?

• A perfectly rational person can never believe P and believe ¬P at the same time.

• The Lottery Paradox (apparently) shows, courtesy of its two Sequences (of Reasoning), that a perfectly rational person can indeed have such a belief (upon considering a fair, large lottery).

• Contradiction! — and hence a paradox!

Page 9: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Types of Paradoxes

• Deductive Paradoxes. The reasoning in question is exclusively deductive.

• Russell’s Paradox

• The Liar Paradox

• Richard’s Paradox

• Inductive Paradoxes Some of the reasoning in question uses non-deductive reasoning (e.g., probabilistic reasoning, abductive reasoning, analogical reasoning, etc.).

Page 10: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Types of Paradoxes

• Deductive Paradoxes. The reasoning in question is exclusively deductive.

• Russell’s Paradox

• The Liar Paradox

• Richard’s Paradox

• Inductive Paradoxes Some of the reasoning in question uses non-deductive reasoning (e.g., probabilistic reasoning, abductive reasoning, analogical reasoning, etc.).

Page 11: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

To set the stage, we bring to your attention OSCAR, now resurrected in the RAIR Lab @ RPI, courtesy of Kevin O’Neill…

Page 12: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Automated Theorem Provers (ATPs)While there are countless ATPs available in the AI community, almost all use techniques like resolution which don’t directly reflect human reasoning. This means that nobody can intuitively understand complex machine-generated proofs – your experience with Slate won’t help.

As far as we know, the epistemic reasoner in John Pollock’s OSCAR was the only ATP which exclusively makes use of natural deduction (for now…we’re building a successor, MATR). But after Pollock’s death, the OSCAR project was abandoned for decades. Within the past year, we have managed to fully restore OSCAR’s ATP to its former glory.

Now, we can get automatically generated natural deduction proofs!

Page 13: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Automated Theorem Provers (ATPs)

While there are countless ATPs available in the AI community, almost all use techniques like resolution which don’t directly reflect human reasoning. This means that nobody can intuitively understand complex machine-generated proofs – your experience with Slate won’t help.

As far as we know, the epistemic reasoner in John Pollock’s OSCAR was the only ATP which exclusively makes use of natural deduction (for now…we’re building a successor, MATR). But after Pollock’s death, the OSCAR project was abandoned for decades. Within the past year, we have managed to fully restore OSCAR’s ATP to its former glory.

Now, we can get automatically generated natural deduction proofs!

Page 14: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Automated Theorem Provers (ATPs)While there are countless ATPs available in the AI community, almost all use techniques like resolution which don’t directly reflect human reasoning. This means that nobody can intuitively understand complex machine-generated proofs – your experience with Slate won’t help.

As far as we know, the epistemic reasoner in John Pollock’s OSCAR was the only ATP which exclusively makes use of natural deduction (for now…we’re building a successor, MATR). But after Pollock’s death, the OSCAR project was abandoned for decades. Within the past year, we have managed to fully restore OSCAR’s ATP to its former glory.

Now, we can get automatically generated natural deduction proofs!

Page 15: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Schubert Steamroller ProblemWolves, foxes, birds, caterpillars, and snails are animals, and there are some of each of them. Also, there are some grains, and grains are plants. Every animal either likes to eat all plants or all animals smaller than itself that like to eat some plants. Caterpillars and snails are much smaller than birds, which are much smaller than foxes, which in turn are much smaller than wolves. Wolves do not like to eat foxes or grains while birds like to eat caterpillars but not snails. Caterpillars and snails like to eat some plants.

Prove: there is an animal that likes to eat a grain-eating animal.

You can imagine how much work it would be to make this proof by hand, but OSCAR finds the solution instantaneously!

Page 16: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Schubert Steamroller ProblemWolves, foxes, birds, caterpillars, and snails are animals, and there are some of each of them. Also, there are some grains, and grains are plants. Every animal either likes to eat all plants or all animals smaller than itself that like to eat some plants. Caterpillars and snails are much smaller than birds, which are much smaller than foxes, which in turn are much smaller than wolves. Wolves do not like to eat foxes or grains while birds like to eat caterpillars but not snails. Caterpillars and snails like to eat some plants.

Prove: there is an animal that likes to eat a grain-eating animal.

You can imagine how much work it would be to make this proof by hand, but OSCAR finds the solution instantaneously!

See the transcript of Kevin’s interaction with OSCAR!

Page 17: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Types of Paradoxes

• Deductive Paradoxes. The reasoning in question is exclusively deductive.

• Russell’s Paradox

• The Liar Paradox

• Richard’s Paradox

• Inductive Paradoxes Some of the reasoning in question uses non-deductive reasoning (e.g., probabilistic reasoning, abductive reasoning, analogical reasoning, etc.).

Page 18: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Types of Paradoxes

• Deductive Paradoxes. The reasoning in question is exclusively deductive.

• Russell’s Paradox

• The Liar Paradox

• Richard’s Paradox

• Inductive Paradoxes Some of the reasoning in question uses non-deductive reasoning (e.g., probabilistic reasoning, abductive reasoning, analogical reasoning, etc.).

Page 19: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Inductive Logic

Page 20: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Inductive Logic

Page 21: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Inductive Logic

Deductive (familiar)

Page 22: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Inductive Logic

Deductive (familiar)

Page 23: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Inductive Logic

Deductive (familiar)

Inductive (new)

Page 24: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Defeasible Reasoning in OSCARImagine the following: Keith tells you that the morning news predicts rain in Tucson today. However, Alvin tells you that the same news report predicted sunshine.

Without any other source of information, it would be irrational to place belief in either Keith’s or Alvin’s statements.

Further, suppose you happened to watch the noon news report, and that report predicted rain. Then you should believe that it will rain despite your knowledge of Alvin’s argument.

Page 25: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Defeasible Reasoning in OSCARImagine the following: Keith tells you that the morning news predicts rain in Tucson today. However, Alvin tells you that the same news report predicted sunshine.

Without any other source of information, it would be irrational to place belief in either Keith’s or Alvin’s statements.

Further, suppose you happened to watch the noon news report, and that report predicted rain. Then you should believe that it will rain despite your knowledge of Alvin’s argument.

Page 26: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Defeasible Reasoning in OSCARImagine the following: Keith tells you that the morning news predicts rain in Tucson today. However, Alvin tells you that the same news report predicted sunshine.

Without any other source of information, it would be irrational to place belief in either Keith’s or Alvin’s statements.

Further, suppose you happened to watch the noon news report, and that report predicted rain. Then you should believe that it will rain despite your knowledge of Alvin’s argument.

Page 27: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Defeasible Reasoning in OSCAR (cont.)

K- Keith says that MA- Alvin says that ~MM- The morning news said that RR- It is going to rain this afternoonN- The noon news says that R

Page 28: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Defeasible Reasoning in OSCAR (cont.)

K- Keith says that MA- Alvin says that ~MM- The morning news said that RR- It is going to rain this afternoonN- The noon news says that R

See the transcript of Kevin’s interaction with OSCAR!

Page 29: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

The Lottery Paradox …

Page 30: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe
Page 31: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe
Page 32: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

E: “Please go down to Stewart’s & get the T U.”

Page 33: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

E: “Please go down to Stewart’s & get the T U.”

S: “I’m sorry, E, I’m afraid I can’t do that.It would be irrational.”

Page 34: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

E: “Please go down to Stewart’s & get the T U.”

S: “I’m sorry, E, I’m afraid I can’t do that.It would be irrational.”

Page 35: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe
Page 36: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Sequence 1

Page 37: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Sequence 1

Page 38: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Sequence 1

Page 39: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Sequence 1

Page 40: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Sequence 1

Page 41: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Sequence 1

Page 42: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Sequence 1 Sequence 2

Page 43: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Sequence 1 Sequence 2

Page 44: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Sequence 1 Sequence 2

Page 45: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Sequence 1 Sequence 2

Page 46: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Sequence 1 Sequence 2

Page 47: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Sequence 1 Sequence 2

Page 48: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Sequence 1 Sequence 2

Contradiction!

Page 49: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Sequence 1

Page 50: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Sequence 1Let D be a meticulous and perfectly accurate description of a 1,000,000,000,000-ticket lottery, of which rational agent a is fully apprised.

Page 51: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Sequence 1Let D be a meticulous and perfectly accurate description of a 1,000,000,000,000-ticket lottery, of which rational agent a is fully apprised.

From D it obviously can be proved that either ticket 1 will win or ticket 2 will win or … or ticket 1,000,000,000,000 will win. Let’s write this (exclusive) disjunction as follows:

Page 52: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Sequence 1Let D be a meticulous and perfectly accurate description of a 1,000,000,000,000-ticket lottery, of which rational agent a is fully apprised.

From D it obviously can be proved that either ticket 1 will win or ticket 2 will win or … or ticket 1,000,000,000,000 will win. Let’s write this (exclusive) disjunction as follows:

Wt1 �Wt2 � . . .�Wt1T (1)

Page 53: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Sequence 1Let D be a meticulous and perfectly accurate description of a 1,000,000,000,000-ticket lottery, of which rational agent a is fully apprised.

From D it obviously can be proved that either ticket 1 will win or ticket 2 will win or … or ticket 1,000,000,000,000 will win. Let’s write this (exclusive) disjunction as follows:

We then deduce from this that there is at least one ticket that will win, a proposition represented — using standard notation — as:

Wt1 �Wt2 � . . .�Wt1T (1)

Page 54: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Sequence 1Let D be a meticulous and perfectly accurate description of a 1,000,000,000,000-ticket lottery, of which rational agent a is fully apprised.

From D it obviously can be proved that either ticket 1 will win or ticket 2 will win or … or ticket 1,000,000,000,000 will win. Let’s write this (exclusive) disjunction as follows:

We then deduce from this that there is at least one ticket that will win, a proposition represented — using standard notation — as:

9tiWti (2)

Wt1 �Wt2 � . . .�Wt1T (1)

Page 55: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Sequence 1Let D be a meticulous and perfectly accurate description of a 1,000,000,000,000-ticket lottery, of which rational agent a is fully apprised.

From D it obviously can be proved that either ticket 1 will win or ticket 2 will win or … or ticket 1,000,000,000,000 will win. Let’s write this (exclusive) disjunction as follows:

We then deduce from this that there is at least one ticket that will win, a proposition represented — using standard notation — as:

Very well; perfectly clear so far. And now we can add another deductive step: Since our rational agent a can follow this deduction sequence to this point, and since D is assumed to be indubitable, it follows that our rational agent in turn believes (2); i.e., we conclude Sequence 1 by obtaining the following:

9tiWti (2)

Wt1 �Wt2 � . . .�Wt1T (1)

Page 56: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Sequence 1Let D be a meticulous and perfectly accurate description of a 1,000,000,000,000-ticket lottery, of which rational agent a is fully apprised.

From D it obviously can be proved that either ticket 1 will win or ticket 2 will win or … or ticket 1,000,000,000,000 will win. Let’s write this (exclusive) disjunction as follows:

We then deduce from this that there is at least one ticket that will win, a proposition represented — using standard notation — as:

Very well; perfectly clear so far. And now we can add another deductive step: Since our rational agent a can follow this deduction sequence to this point, and since D is assumed to be indubitable, it follows that our rational agent in turn believes (2); i.e., we conclude Sequence 1 by obtaining the following:

Ba9tiWti (3)

9tiWti (2)

Wt1 �Wt2 � . . .�Wt1T (1)

Page 57: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Sequence 1

Page 58: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Sequence 1

Page 59: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Sequence 2

Page 60: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Sequence 2As in Sequence 1, once again let D be a meticulous and perfectly accurate description of a 1,000,000,000,000-ticket lottery, of which rational agent a is fully apprised.

Page 61: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Sequence 2As in Sequence 1, once again let D be a meticulous and perfectly accurate description of a 1,000,000,000,000-ticket lottery, of which rational agent a is fully apprised.

From D it obviously can be proved that the probability of a particular ticket ti winning is 1 in 1,000,000,000,000. Using ‘1T’ to denote 1 trillion, we can write the probability for each ticket to win as a conjunction:

Page 62: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Sequence 2As in Sequence 1, once again let D be a meticulous and perfectly accurate description of a 1,000,000,000,000-ticket lottery, of which rational agent a is fully apprised.

From D it obviously can be proved that the probability of a particular ticket ti winning is 1 in 1,000,000,000,000. Using ‘1T’ to denote 1 trillion, we can write the probability for each ticket to win as a conjunction:

prob(Wt1) =1

1, 000, 000, 000, 000=

1

1T^ prob(Wt2) =

1

1T^ . . . ^ prob(Wt1T ) =

1

1T(1)

Page 63: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Sequence 2As in Sequence 1, once again let D be a meticulous and perfectly accurate description of a 1,000,000,000,000-ticket lottery, of which rational agent a is fully apprised.

From D it obviously can be proved that the probability of a particular ticket ti winning is 1 in 1,000,000,000,000. Using ‘1T’ to denote 1 trillion, we can write the probability for each ticket to win as a conjunction:

For the next step, note that the probability of ticket t1 winning is lower than, say, the probability that if you walk outside a minute from now you will be flattened on the spot by a door from a 747 that falls from a jet of that type cruising at 35,000 feet. Since you have the rational belief that death won't ensue if you go outside (and have this belief precisely because you believe that the odds of your sudden demise in this manner are vanishingly small), the inference to the rational belief on the part of a that t1 won’t win sails through— and this of course works for each ticket. Hence we have:

prob(Wt1) =1

1, 000, 000, 000, 000=

1

1T^ prob(Wt2) =

1

1T^ . . . ^ prob(Wt1T ) =

1

1T(1)

Page 64: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Sequence 2As in Sequence 1, once again let D be a meticulous and perfectly accurate description of a 1,000,000,000,000-ticket lottery, of which rational agent a is fully apprised.

From D it obviously can be proved that the probability of a particular ticket ti winning is 1 in 1,000,000,000,000. Using ‘1T’ to denote 1 trillion, we can write the probability for each ticket to win as a conjunction:

For the next step, note that the probability of ticket t1 winning is lower than, say, the probability that if you walk outside a minute from now you will be flattened on the spot by a door from a 747 that falls from a jet of that type cruising at 35,000 feet. Since you have the rational belief that death won't ensue if you go outside (and have this belief precisely because you believe that the odds of your sudden demise in this manner are vanishingly small), the inference to the rational belief on the part of a that t1 won’t win sails through— and this of course works for each ticket. Hence we have:

prob(Wt1) =1

1, 000, 000, 000, 000=

1

1T^ prob(Wt2) =

1

1T^ . . . ^ prob(Wt1T ) =

1

1T(1)

Ba¬Wt1 ^Ba¬Wt2 ^ . . . ^Ba¬Wt1T (2)

Page 65: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Sequence 2As in Sequence 1, once again let D be a meticulous and perfectly accurate description of a 1,000,000,000,000-ticket lottery, of which rational agent a is fully apprised.

From D it obviously can be proved that the probability of a particular ticket ti winning is 1 in 1,000,000,000,000. Using ‘1T’ to denote 1 trillion, we can write the probability for each ticket to win as a conjunction:

For the next step, note that the probability of ticket t1 winning is lower than, say, the probability that if you walk outside a minute from now you will be flattened on the spot by a door from a 747 that falls from a jet of that type cruising at 35,000 feet. Since you have the rational belief that death won't ensue if you go outside (and have this belief precisely because you believe that the odds of your sudden demise in this manner are vanishingly small), the inference to the rational belief on the part of a that t1 won’t win sails through— and this of course works for each ticket. Hence we have:

prob(Wt1) =1

1, 000, 000, 000, 000=

1

1T^ prob(Wt2) =

1

1T^ . . . ^ prob(Wt1T ) =

1

1T(1)

Ba¬Wt1 ^Ba¬Wt2 ^ . . . ^Ba¬Wt1T (2)Of course, if a rational agent believes P, and believes Q as well, it follows that that agent will believe the conjunction P & Q. Applying this principle to (2) yields:

Page 66: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Sequence 2As in Sequence 1, once again let D be a meticulous and perfectly accurate description of a 1,000,000,000,000-ticket lottery, of which rational agent a is fully apprised.

From D it obviously can be proved that the probability of a particular ticket ti winning is 1 in 1,000,000,000,000. Using ‘1T’ to denote 1 trillion, we can write the probability for each ticket to win as a conjunction:

For the next step, note that the probability of ticket t1 winning is lower than, say, the probability that if you walk outside a minute from now you will be flattened on the spot by a door from a 747 that falls from a jet of that type cruising at 35,000 feet. Since you have the rational belief that death won't ensue if you go outside (and have this belief precisely because you believe that the odds of your sudden demise in this manner are vanishingly small), the inference to the rational belief on the part of a that t1 won’t win sails through— and this of course works for each ticket. Hence we have:

prob(Wt1) =1

1, 000, 000, 000, 000=

1

1T^ prob(Wt2) =

1

1T^ . . . ^ prob(Wt1T ) =

1

1T(1)

Ba¬Wt1 ^Ba¬Wt2 ^ . . . ^Ba¬Wt1T (2)Of course, if a rational agent believes P, and believes Q as well, it follows that that agent will believe the conjunction P & Q. Applying this principle to (2) yields:

Ba(¬Wt1 ^ ¬Wt2 ^ . . . ^ ¬Wt1T ) (3)

Page 67: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Sequence 2As in Sequence 1, once again let D be a meticulous and perfectly accurate description of a 1,000,000,000,000-ticket lottery, of which rational agent a is fully apprised.

From D it obviously can be proved that the probability of a particular ticket ti winning is 1 in 1,000,000,000,000. Using ‘1T’ to denote 1 trillion, we can write the probability for each ticket to win as a conjunction:

For the next step, note that the probability of ticket t1 winning is lower than, say, the probability that if you walk outside a minute from now you will be flattened on the spot by a door from a 747 that falls from a jet of that type cruising at 35,000 feet. Since you have the rational belief that death won't ensue if you go outside (and have this belief precisely because you believe that the odds of your sudden demise in this manner are vanishingly small), the inference to the rational belief on the part of a that t1 won’t win sails through— and this of course works for each ticket. Hence we have:

prob(Wt1) =1

1, 000, 000, 000, 000=

1

1T^ prob(Wt2) =

1

1T^ . . . ^ prob(Wt1T ) =

1

1T(1)

Ba¬Wt1 ^Ba¬Wt2 ^ . . . ^Ba¬Wt1T (2)Of course, if a rational agent believes P, and believes Q as well, it follows that that agent will believe the conjunction P & Q. Applying this principle to (2) yields:

Ba(¬Wt1 ^ ¬Wt2 ^ . . . ^ ¬Wt1T ) (3)But (3) is logically equivalent to the statement that there doesn’t exist a winning ticket; i.e., (3) is logically equivalent to this result from Sequence 2:

Page 68: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Sequence 2As in Sequence 1, once again let D be a meticulous and perfectly accurate description of a 1,000,000,000,000-ticket lottery, of which rational agent a is fully apprised.

From D it obviously can be proved that the probability of a particular ticket ti winning is 1 in 1,000,000,000,000. Using ‘1T’ to denote 1 trillion, we can write the probability for each ticket to win as a conjunction:

For the next step, note that the probability of ticket t1 winning is lower than, say, the probability that if you walk outside a minute from now you will be flattened on the spot by a door from a 747 that falls from a jet of that type cruising at 35,000 feet. Since you have the rational belief that death won't ensue if you go outside (and have this belief precisely because you believe that the odds of your sudden demise in this manner are vanishingly small), the inference to the rational belief on the part of a that t1 won’t win sails through— and this of course works for each ticket. Hence we have:

prob(Wt1) =1

1, 000, 000, 000, 000=

1

1T^ prob(Wt2) =

1

1T^ . . . ^ prob(Wt1T ) =

1

1T(1)

Ba¬Wt1 ^Ba¬Wt2 ^ . . . ^Ba¬Wt1T (2)Of course, if a rational agent believes P, and believes Q as well, it follows that that agent will believe the conjunction P & Q. Applying this principle to (2) yields:

Ba(¬Wt1 ^ ¬Wt2 ^ . . . ^ ¬Wt1T ) (3)But (3) is logically equivalent to the statement that there doesn’t exist a winning ticket; i.e., (3) is logically equivalent to this result from Sequence 2:

Ba¬9tiWti (4)

Page 69: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Sequence 2

Page 70: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Sequence 2

Page 71: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Sequence 1 Sequence 2

Page 72: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Sequence 1 Sequence 2

√√ Ba9tiWtiBa¬9tiWti

Page 73: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Sequence 1 Sequence 2

(The contradiction we sketched earlier has arrived.)√√ Ba9tiWtiBa¬9tiWti

Page 74: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

A Solution to The Lottery Paradox …

Page 75: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Strength-Factor Continuum

Certain

Evident

Beyond Reasonable Doubt

Probable

Counterbalanced

Improbable

Beyond Reasonable Belief

Evidently False

Certainly False

Page 76: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Strength-Factor Continuum

Certain

Evident

Beyond Reasonable Doubt

Probable

Counterbalanced

Improbable

Beyond Reasonable Belief

Evidently False

Certainly False

Page 77: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Strength-Factor ContinuumCertain

Evident

Beyond Reasonable Doubt

Probable

Counterbalanced

Improbable

Beyond Reasonable Belief

Evidently False

Certainly False

Page 78: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Strength-Factor ContinuumCertain

Evident

Beyond Reasonable Doubt

Probable

Counterbalanced

Improbable

Beyond Reasonable Belief

Evidently False

Certainly False

Page 79: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Strength-Factor ContinuumCertain

Evident

Beyond Reasonable Doubt

Probable

Counterbalanced

Improbable

Beyond Reasonable Belief

Evidently False

Certainly False

Epistemically Positive

Page 80: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Strength-Factor ContinuumCertain

Evident

Beyond Reasonable Doubt

Probable

Counterbalanced

Improbable

Beyond Reasonable Belief

Evidently False

Certainly False

Epistemically Positive

Epistemically Negative

Page 81: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Strength-Factor ContinuumCertain

Evident

Beyond Reasonable Doubt

Probable

Counterbalanced

Improbable

Beyond Reasonable Belief

Evidently False

Certainly False

Epistemically Positive

Epistemically Negative

Page 82: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Strength-Factor ContinuumCertain

Evident

Beyond Reasonable Doubt

Probable

Counterbalanced

Improbable

Beyond Reasonable Belief

Evidently False

Certainly False

Epistemically Positive

Epistemically Negative

(4)

(3)

(2)

(1)

(0)

(-1)

(-2)

(-3)

(-4)

Page 83: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Strength-Factor ContinuumCertain

Evident

Beyond Reasonable Doubt

Probable

Counterbalanced

Improbable

Beyond Reasonable Belief

Evidently False

Certainly False

Epistemically Positive

Epistemically Negative

(4)

(3)

(2)

(1)

(0)

(-1)

(-2)

(-3)

(-4)

Page 84: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Certain

Evident

Beyond Reasonable Doubt

Probable

Counterbalanced

Improbable

Beyond Reasonable Belief

Evidently False

Certainly False

Epistemically Positive

Epistemically Negative

(4)

(3)

(2)

(1)

(0)

(-1)

(-2)

(-3)

(-4)

Page 85: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Certain

Evident

Beyond Reasonable Doubt

Probable

Counterbalanced

Improbable

Beyond Reasonable Belief

Evidently False

Certainly False

Epistemically Positive

Epistemically Negative

(4)

(3)

(2)

(1)

(0)

(-1)

(-2)

(-3)

(-4)

Key Principles

Page 86: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Certain

Evident

Beyond Reasonable Doubt

Probable

Counterbalanced

Improbable

Beyond Reasonable Belief

Evidently False

Certainly False

Epistemically Positive

Epistemically Negative

(4)

(3)

(2)

(1)

(0)

(-1)

(-2)

(-3)

(-4)

Deduction preserves strength.

Key Principles

Page 87: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Certain

Evident

Beyond Reasonable Doubt

Probable

Counterbalanced

Improbable

Beyond Reasonable Belief

Evidently False

Certainly False

Epistemically Positive

Epistemically Negative

(4)

(3)

(2)

(1)

(0)

(-1)

(-2)

(-3)

(-4)

Deduction preserves strength.

Clashes are resolved in favor of higher strength.

Key Principles

Page 88: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Certain

Evident

Beyond Reasonable Doubt

Probable

Counterbalanced

Improbable

Beyond Reasonable Belief

Evidently False

Certainly False

Epistemically Positive

Epistemically Negative

(4)

(3)

(2)

(1)

(0)

(-1)

(-2)

(-3)

(-4)

Deduction preserves strength.

Clashes are resolved in favor of higher strength.

Any proposition p such that prob(p) < 1 is at most evident.

Key Principles

Page 89: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Certain

Evident

Beyond Reasonable Doubt

Probable

Counterbalanced

Improbable

Beyond Reasonable Belief

Evidently False

Certainly False

Epistemically Positive

Epistemically Negative

(4)

(3)

(2)

(1)

(0)

(-1)

(-2)

(-3)

(-4)

Deduction preserves strength.

Clashes are resolved in favor of higher strength.

Any proposition p such that prob(p) < 1 is at most evident.

Key Principles

Any rational belief that p, where the basis for p is at most evident, is at most an evident (= level 3) belief.

Page 90: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Sequence 1, “Rigorized”Let D be a meticulous and perfectly accurate description of a 1,000,000,000,000-ticket lottery, of which rational agent a is fully apprised.

From D it obviously can be proved that either ticket 1 will win or ticket 2 will win or … or ticket 1,000,000,000,000 will win. Let’s write this (exclusive) disjunction as follows:

We then deduce from this that there is at least one ticket that will win, a proposition represented — using standard notation — as:

Very well; perfectly clear so far. And now we can add another deductive step: Since our rational agent a can follow this deduction sequence to this point, and since D is assumed to be indubitable, it follows that our rational agent in turn believes (2); i.e., we conclude Sequence 1 by obtaining the following:

Ba9tiWti (3)

9tiWti (2)

Wt1 �Wt2 � . . .�Wt1T (1)

Page 91: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Sequence 1, “Rigorized”Let D be a meticulous and perfectly accurate description of a 1,000,000,000,000-ticket lottery, of which rational agent a is fully apprised.

From D it obviously can be proved that either ticket 1 will win or ticket 2 will win or … or ticket 1,000,000,000,000 will win. Let’s write this (exclusive) disjunction as follows:

We then deduce from this that there is at least one ticket that will win, a proposition represented — using standard notation — as:

Very well; perfectly clear so far. And now we can add another deductive step: Since our rational agent a can follow this deduction sequence to this point, and since D is assumed to be indubitable, it follows that our rational agent in turn believes (2); i.e., we conclude Sequence 1 by obtaining the following:

Ba9tiWti (3)

9tiWti (2)

Wt1 �Wt2 � . . .�Wt1T (1)

4

Page 92: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Sequence 1, “Rigorized”Let D be a meticulous and perfectly accurate description of a 1,000,000,000,000-ticket lottery, of which rational agent a is fully apprised.

From D it obviously can be proved that either ticket 1 will win or ticket 2 will win or … or ticket 1,000,000,000,000 will win. Let’s write this (exclusive) disjunction as follows:

We then deduce from this that there is at least one ticket that will win, a proposition represented — using standard notation — as:

Very well; perfectly clear so far. And now we can add another deductive step: Since our rational agent a can follow this deduction sequence to this point, and since D is assumed to be indubitable, it follows that our rational agent in turn believes (2); i.e., we conclude Sequence 1 by obtaining the following:

Ba9tiWti (3)

9tiWti (2)

Wt1 �Wt2 � . . .�Wt1T (1)

4

4

Page 93: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Sequence 1, “Rigorized”Let D be a meticulous and perfectly accurate description of a 1,000,000,000,000-ticket lottery, of which rational agent a is fully apprised.

From D it obviously can be proved that either ticket 1 will win or ticket 2 will win or … or ticket 1,000,000,000,000 will win. Let’s write this (exclusive) disjunction as follows:

We then deduce from this that there is at least one ticket that will win, a proposition represented — using standard notation — as:

Very well; perfectly clear so far. And now we can add another deductive step: Since our rational agent a can follow this deduction sequence to this point, and since D is assumed to be indubitable, it follows that our rational agent in turn believes (2); i.e., we conclude Sequence 1 by obtaining the following:

Ba9tiWti (3)

9tiWti (2)

Wt1 �Wt2 � . . .�Wt1T (1)

4

4

4

Page 94: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Sequence 1, “Rigorized”Let D be a meticulous and perfectly accurate description of a 1,000,000,000,000-ticket lottery, of which rational agent a is fully apprised.

From D it obviously can be proved that either ticket 1 will win or ticket 2 will win or … or ticket 1,000,000,000,000 will win. Let’s write this (exclusive) disjunction as follows:

We then deduce from this that there is at least one ticket that will win, a proposition represented — using standard notation — as:

Very well; perfectly clear so far. And now we can add another deductive step: Since our rational agent a can follow this deduction sequence to this point, and since D is assumed to be indubitable, it follows that our rational agent in turn believes (2); i.e., we conclude Sequence 1 by obtaining the following:

Ba9tiWti (3)

9tiWti (2)

Wt1 �Wt2 � . . .�Wt1T (1)

4

4

4

4

Page 95: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Sequence 1, “Rigorized”Let D be a meticulous and perfectly accurate description of a 1,000,000,000,000-ticket lottery, of which rational agent a is fully apprised.

From D it obviously can be proved that either ticket 1 will win or ticket 2 will win or … or ticket 1,000,000,000,000 will win. Let’s write this (exclusive) disjunction as follows:

We then deduce from this that there is at least one ticket that will win, a proposition represented — using standard notation — as:

Very well; perfectly clear so far. And now we can add another deductive step: Since our rational agent a can follow this deduction sequence to this point, and since D is assumed to be indubitable, it follows that our rational agent in turn believes (2); i.e., we conclude Sequence 1 by obtaining the following:

9tiWti (2)

Wt1 �Wt2 � . . .�Wt1T (1)

4

4

4

4

Page 96: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Sequence 1, “Rigorized”Let D be a meticulous and perfectly accurate description of a 1,000,000,000,000-ticket lottery, of which rational agent a is fully apprised.

From D it obviously can be proved that either ticket 1 will win or ticket 2 will win or … or ticket 1,000,000,000,000 will win. Let’s write this (exclusive) disjunction as follows:

We then deduce from this that there is at least one ticket that will win, a proposition represented — using standard notation — as:

Very well; perfectly clear so far. And now we can add another deductive step: Since our rational agent a can follow this deduction sequence to this point, and since D is assumed to be indubitable, it follows that our rational agent in turn believes (2); i.e., we conclude Sequence 1 by obtaining the following:

9tiWti (2)

Wt1 �Wt2 � . . .�Wt1T (1)

4

4

4

4 B4a9tiWti (3)

Page 97: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Sequence 2, “Rigorized”As in Sequence 1, once again let D be a meticulous and perfectly accurate description of a 1,000,000,000,000-ticket lottery, of which rational agent a is fully apprised.

From D it obviously can be proved that the probability of a particular ticket ti winning is 1 in 1,000,000,000,000. Using ‘1T’ to denote 1 trillion, we can write the probability for each ticket to win as a conjunction:

For the next step, note that the probability of ticket t1 winning is lower than, say, the probability that if you walk outside a minute from now you will be flattened on the spot by a door from a 747 that falls from a jet of that type cruising at 35,000 feet. Since you have the rational belief that death won't ensue if you go outside (and have this belief precisely because you believe that the odds of your sudden demise in this manner are vanishingly small), the inference to the rational belief on the part of a that t1 won’t win sails through— and this of course works for each ticket. Hence we have:

prob(Wt1) =1

1, 000, 000, 000, 000=

1

1T^ prob(Wt2) =

1

1T^ . . . ^ prob(Wt1T ) =

1

1T(1)

Ba¬Wt1 ^Ba¬Wt2 ^ . . . ^Ba¬Wt1T (2)Of course, if a rational agent believes P, and believes Q as well, it follows that that agent will believe the conjunction P & Q. Applying this principle to (2) yields:

Ba(¬Wt1 ^ ¬Wt2 ^ . . . ^ ¬Wt1T ) (3)But (3) is logically equivalent to the statement that there doesn’t exist a winning ticket; i.e., (3) is logically equivalent to this result from Sequence 2:

Ba¬9tiWti (4)

Page 98: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Sequence 2, “Rigorized”As in Sequence 1, once again let D be a meticulous and perfectly accurate description of a 1,000,000,000,000-ticket lottery, of which rational agent a is fully apprised.

From D it obviously can be proved that the probability of a particular ticket ti winning is 1 in 1,000,000,000,000. Using ‘1T’ to denote 1 trillion, we can write the probability for each ticket to win as a conjunction:

For the next step, note that the probability of ticket t1 winning is lower than, say, the probability that if you walk outside a minute from now you will be flattened on the spot by a door from a 747 that falls from a jet of that type cruising at 35,000 feet. Since you have the rational belief that death won't ensue if you go outside (and have this belief precisely because you believe that the odds of your sudden demise in this manner are vanishingly small), the inference to the rational belief on the part of a that t1 won’t win sails through— and this of course works for each ticket. Hence we have:

prob(Wt1) =1

1, 000, 000, 000, 000=

1

1T^ prob(Wt2) =

1

1T^ . . . ^ prob(Wt1T ) =

1

1T(1)

Ba¬Wt1 ^Ba¬Wt2 ^ . . . ^Ba¬Wt1T (2)Of course, if a rational agent believes P, and believes Q as well, it follows that that agent will believe the conjunction P & Q. Applying this principle to (2) yields:

Ba(¬Wt1 ^ ¬Wt2 ^ . . . ^ ¬Wt1T ) (3)But (3) is logically equivalent to the statement that there doesn’t exist a winning ticket; i.e., (3) is logically equivalent to this result from Sequence 2:

Ba¬9tiWti (4)

4

Page 99: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Sequence 2, “Rigorized”As in Sequence 1, once again let D be a meticulous and perfectly accurate description of a 1,000,000,000,000-ticket lottery, of which rational agent a is fully apprised.

From D it obviously can be proved that the probability of a particular ticket ti winning is 1 in 1,000,000,000,000. Using ‘1T’ to denote 1 trillion, we can write the probability for each ticket to win as a conjunction:

For the next step, note that the probability of ticket t1 winning is lower than, say, the probability that if you walk outside a minute from now you will be flattened on the spot by a door from a 747 that falls from a jet of that type cruising at 35,000 feet. Since you have the rational belief that death won't ensue if you go outside (and have this belief precisely because you believe that the odds of your sudden demise in this manner are vanishingly small), the inference to the rational belief on the part of a that t1 won’t win sails through— and this of course works for each ticket. Hence we have:

prob(Wt1) =1

1, 000, 000, 000, 000=

1

1T^ prob(Wt2) =

1

1T^ . . . ^ prob(Wt1T ) =

1

1T(1)

Ba¬Wt1 ^Ba¬Wt2 ^ . . . ^Ba¬Wt1T (2)Of course, if a rational agent believes P, and believes Q as well, it follows that that agent will believe the conjunction P & Q. Applying this principle to (2) yields:

Ba(¬Wt1 ^ ¬Wt2 ^ . . . ^ ¬Wt1T ) (3)But (3) is logically equivalent to the statement that there doesn’t exist a winning ticket; i.e., (3) is logically equivalent to this result from Sequence 2:

Ba¬9tiWti (4)

4

4

Page 100: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Sequence 2, “Rigorized”As in Sequence 1, once again let D be a meticulous and perfectly accurate description of a 1,000,000,000,000-ticket lottery, of which rational agent a is fully apprised.

From D it obviously can be proved that the probability of a particular ticket ti winning is 1 in 1,000,000,000,000. Using ‘1T’ to denote 1 trillion, we can write the probability for each ticket to win as a conjunction:

For the next step, note that the probability of ticket t1 winning is lower than, say, the probability that if you walk outside a minute from now you will be flattened on the spot by a door from a 747 that falls from a jet of that type cruising at 35,000 feet. Since you have the rational belief that death won't ensue if you go outside (and have this belief precisely because you believe that the odds of your sudden demise in this manner are vanishingly small), the inference to the rational belief on the part of a that t1 won’t win sails through— and this of course works for each ticket. Hence we have:

prob(Wt1) =1

1, 000, 000, 000, 000=

1

1T^ prob(Wt2) =

1

1T^ . . . ^ prob(Wt1T ) =

1

1T(1)

Of course, if a rational agent believes P, and believes Q as well, it follows that that agent will believe the conjunction P & Q. Applying this principle to (2) yields:

Ba(¬Wt1 ^ ¬Wt2 ^ . . . ^ ¬Wt1T ) (3)But (3) is logically equivalent to the statement that there doesn’t exist a winning ticket; i.e., (3) is logically equivalent to this result from Sequence 2:

Ba¬9tiWti (4)

4

4

Page 101: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Sequence 2, “Rigorized”As in Sequence 1, once again let D be a meticulous and perfectly accurate description of a 1,000,000,000,000-ticket lottery, of which rational agent a is fully apprised.

From D it obviously can be proved that the probability of a particular ticket ti winning is 1 in 1,000,000,000,000. Using ‘1T’ to denote 1 trillion, we can write the probability for each ticket to win as a conjunction:

For the next step, note that the probability of ticket t1 winning is lower than, say, the probability that if you walk outside a minute from now you will be flattened on the spot by a door from a 747 that falls from a jet of that type cruising at 35,000 feet. Since you have the rational belief that death won't ensue if you go outside (and have this belief precisely because you believe that the odds of your sudden demise in this manner are vanishingly small), the inference to the rational belief on the part of a that t1 won’t win sails through— and this of course works for each ticket. Hence we have:

prob(Wt1) =1

1, 000, 000, 000, 000=

1

1T^ prob(Wt2) =

1

1T^ . . . ^ prob(Wt1T ) =

1

1T(1)

Of course, if a rational agent believes P, and believes Q as well, it follows that that agent will believe the conjunction P & Q. Applying this principle to (2) yields:

Ba(¬Wt1 ^ ¬Wt2 ^ . . . ^ ¬Wt1T ) (3)But (3) is logically equivalent to the statement that there doesn’t exist a winning ticket; i.e., (3) is logically equivalent to this result from Sequence 2:

Ba¬9tiWti (4)

4

4

B3a¬Wt1 ^B3

a¬Wt2 ^ . . . ^B3a¬Wt1T (2)

Page 102: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Sequence 2, “Rigorized”As in Sequence 1, once again let D be a meticulous and perfectly accurate description of a 1,000,000,000,000-ticket lottery, of which rational agent a is fully apprised.

From D it obviously can be proved that the probability of a particular ticket ti winning is 1 in 1,000,000,000,000. Using ‘1T’ to denote 1 trillion, we can write the probability for each ticket to win as a conjunction:

For the next step, note that the probability of ticket t1 winning is lower than, say, the probability that if you walk outside a minute from now you will be flattened on the spot by a door from a 747 that falls from a jet of that type cruising at 35,000 feet. Since you have the rational belief that death won't ensue if you go outside (and have this belief precisely because you believe that the odds of your sudden demise in this manner are vanishingly small), the inference to the rational belief on the part of a that t1 won’t win sails through— and this of course works for each ticket. Hence we have:

prob(Wt1) =1

1, 000, 000, 000, 000=

1

1T^ prob(Wt2) =

1

1T^ . . . ^ prob(Wt1T ) =

1

1T(1)

Of course, if a rational agent believes P, and believes Q as well, it follows that that agent will believe the conjunction P & Q. Applying this principle to (2) yields:

But (3) is logically equivalent to the statement that there doesn’t exist a winning ticket; i.e., (3) is logically equivalent to this result from Sequence 2:

Ba¬9tiWti (4)

4

4

B3a¬Wt1 ^B3

a¬Wt2 ^ . . . ^B3a¬Wt1T (2)

Page 103: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Sequence 2, “Rigorized”As in Sequence 1, once again let D be a meticulous and perfectly accurate description of a 1,000,000,000,000-ticket lottery, of which rational agent a is fully apprised.

From D it obviously can be proved that the probability of a particular ticket ti winning is 1 in 1,000,000,000,000. Using ‘1T’ to denote 1 trillion, we can write the probability for each ticket to win as a conjunction:

For the next step, note that the probability of ticket t1 winning is lower than, say, the probability that if you walk outside a minute from now you will be flattened on the spot by a door from a 747 that falls from a jet of that type cruising at 35,000 feet. Since you have the rational belief that death won't ensue if you go outside (and have this belief precisely because you believe that the odds of your sudden demise in this manner are vanishingly small), the inference to the rational belief on the part of a that t1 won’t win sails through— and this of course works for each ticket. Hence we have:

prob(Wt1) =1

1, 000, 000, 000, 000=

1

1T^ prob(Wt2) =

1

1T^ . . . ^ prob(Wt1T ) =

1

1T(1)

Of course, if a rational agent believes P, and believes Q as well, it follows that that agent will believe the conjunction P & Q. Applying this principle to (2) yields:

But (3) is logically equivalent to the statement that there doesn’t exist a winning ticket; i.e., (3) is logically equivalent to this result from Sequence 2:

Ba¬9tiWti (4)

4

4

B3a¬Wt1 ^B3

a¬Wt2 ^ . . . ^B3a¬Wt1T (2)

B3a(¬Wt1 ^ ¬Wt2 ^ . . . ^ ¬Wt1T ) (3)

Page 104: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Sequence 2, “Rigorized”As in Sequence 1, once again let D be a meticulous and perfectly accurate description of a 1,000,000,000,000-ticket lottery, of which rational agent a is fully apprised.

From D it obviously can be proved that the probability of a particular ticket ti winning is 1 in 1,000,000,000,000. Using ‘1T’ to denote 1 trillion, we can write the probability for each ticket to win as a conjunction:

For the next step, note that the probability of ticket t1 winning is lower than, say, the probability that if you walk outside a minute from now you will be flattened on the spot by a door from a 747 that falls from a jet of that type cruising at 35,000 feet. Since you have the rational belief that death won't ensue if you go outside (and have this belief precisely because you believe that the odds of your sudden demise in this manner are vanishingly small), the inference to the rational belief on the part of a that t1 won’t win sails through— and this of course works for each ticket. Hence we have:

prob(Wt1) =1

1, 000, 000, 000, 000=

1

1T^ prob(Wt2) =

1

1T^ . . . ^ prob(Wt1T ) =

1

1T(1)

Of course, if a rational agent believes P, and believes Q as well, it follows that that agent will believe the conjunction P & Q. Applying this principle to (2) yields:

But (3) is logically equivalent to the statement that there doesn’t exist a winning ticket; i.e., (3) is logically equivalent to this result from Sequence 2:

4

4

B3a¬Wt1 ^B3

a¬Wt2 ^ . . . ^B3a¬Wt1T (2)

B3a(¬Wt1 ^ ¬Wt2 ^ . . . ^ ¬Wt1T ) (3)

Page 105: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Sequence 2, “Rigorized”As in Sequence 1, once again let D be a meticulous and perfectly accurate description of a 1,000,000,000,000-ticket lottery, of which rational agent a is fully apprised.

From D it obviously can be proved that the probability of a particular ticket ti winning is 1 in 1,000,000,000,000. Using ‘1T’ to denote 1 trillion, we can write the probability for each ticket to win as a conjunction:

For the next step, note that the probability of ticket t1 winning is lower than, say, the probability that if you walk outside a minute from now you will be flattened on the spot by a door from a 747 that falls from a jet of that type cruising at 35,000 feet. Since you have the rational belief that death won't ensue if you go outside (and have this belief precisely because you believe that the odds of your sudden demise in this manner are vanishingly small), the inference to the rational belief on the part of a that t1 won’t win sails through— and this of course works for each ticket. Hence we have:

prob(Wt1) =1

1, 000, 000, 000, 000=

1

1T^ prob(Wt2) =

1

1T^ . . . ^ prob(Wt1T ) =

1

1T(1)

Of course, if a rational agent believes P, and believes Q as well, it follows that that agent will believe the conjunction P & Q. Applying this principle to (2) yields:

But (3) is logically equivalent to the statement that there doesn’t exist a winning ticket; i.e., (3) is logically equivalent to this result from Sequence 2:

4

4

B3a¬Wt1 ^B3

a¬Wt2 ^ . . . ^B3a¬Wt1T (2)

B3a(¬Wt1 ^ ¬Wt2 ^ . . . ^ ¬Wt1T ) (3)

B3a¬9tiWti (4)

Page 106: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Paradox Solved!Deduction preserves strength.

Clashes are resolved in favor of higher strength; clashes propagate backwards through inverse deduction.

Any proposition p such that prob(p) < 1 is at most evident.

Any rational belief that p, where the basis for p is at most evident, is at most an evident (= level 3) belief.

Page 107: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Paradox Solved!Deduction preserves strength.

Clashes are resolved in favor of higher strength; clashes propagate backwards through inverse deduction.

Any proposition p such that prob(p) < 1 is at most evident.

Any rational belief that p, where the basis for p is at most evident, is at most an evident (= level 3) belief.

B4a9tiWti (3)

Page 108: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Paradox Solved!Deduction preserves strength.

Clashes are resolved in favor of higher strength; clashes propagate backwards through inverse deduction.

Any proposition p such that prob(p) < 1 is at most evident.

Any rational belief that p, where the basis for p is at most evident, is at most an evident (= level 3) belief.

B4a9tiWti (3) B3

a¬9tiWti (4)

Page 109: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Paradox Solved!Deduction preserves strength.

Clashes are resolved in favor of higher strength; clashes propagate backwards through inverse deduction.

Any proposition p such that prob(p) < 1 is at most evident.

Any rational belief that p, where the basis for p is at most evident, is at most an evident (= level 3) belief.

B4a9tiWti (3) B3

a¬9tiWti (4)

Page 110: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Paradox Solved!Deduction preserves strength.

Clashes are resolved in favor of higher strength; clashes propagate backwards through inverse deduction.

Any proposition p such that prob(p) < 1 is at most evident.

Any rational belief that p, where the basis for p is at most evident, is at most an evident (= level 3) belief.

B4a9tiWti (3)B3a¬9tiWti (4)

Page 111: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Paradox Solved!Deduction preserves strength.

Clashes are resolved in favor of higher strength; clashes propagate backwards through inverse deduction.

Any proposition p such that prob(p) < 1 is at most evident.

Any rational belief that p, where the basis for p is at most evident, is at most an evident (= level 3) belief.

B4a9tiWti (3)

Page 112: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Paradox Solved!Deduction preserves strength.

Clashes are resolved in favor of higher strength; clashes propagate backwards through inverse deduction.

Any proposition p such that prob(p) < 1 is at most evident.

Any rational belief that p, where the basis for p is at most evident, is at most an evident (= level 3) belief.

B4a9tiWti (3)

B3a¬Wt1 ^B3

a¬Wt2 ^ . . . ^B3a¬Wt1T (2)

Page 113: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Paradox Solved!Deduction preserves strength.

Clashes are resolved in favor of higher strength; clashes propagate backwards through inverse deduction.

Any proposition p such that prob(p) < 1 is at most evident.

Any rational belief that p, where the basis for p is at most evident, is at most an evident (= level 3) belief.

B4a9tiWti (3)

B3a¬Wt1 ^B3

a¬Wt2 ^ . . . ^B3a¬Wt1T (2)

Page 114: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Paradox Solved!Deduction preserves strength.

Clashes are resolved in favor of higher strength; clashes propagate backwards through inverse deduction.

Any proposition p such that prob(p) < 1 is at most evident.

Any rational belief that p, where the basis for p is at most evident, is at most an evident (= level 3) belief.

B4a9tiWti (3)

B3a¬Wt1 ^B3

a¬Wt2 ^ . . . ^B3a¬Wt1T (2)

This is why, to Mega Millions ticket holder: “Sorry. I’m rational, and I believe you won’t win.”

Page 115: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Pollock’s Solution to The Lottery Paradox …

Page 116: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Pollock’s Solution to LPFor any ticket, it would seem reasonable to conclude that it will not win the lottery.

But since you can make the same argument for every ticket, given that all other tickets lose, you could deductively conclude that your ticket will win at an equal level of belief. Then, paradoxically, it would seem that you believe that every ticket will lose, but also win.

There is no way to choose between the two competing arguments, so it would be irrational to believe one over the other. However, we still deductively believe that some ticket will win.

Page 117: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Pollock’s Solution to LPFor any ticket, it would seem reasonable to conclude that it will not win the lottery.

But since you can make the same argument for every ticket, given that all other tickets lose, you could deductively conclude that your ticket will win at an equal level of belief. Then, paradoxically, it would seem that you believe that every ticket will lose, but also win.

There is no way to choose between the two competing arguments, so it would be irrational to believe one over the other. However, we still deductively believe that some ticket will win.

Page 118: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Pollock’s Solution to LPFor any ticket, it would seem reasonable to conclude that it will not win the lottery.

But since you can make the same argument for every ticket, given that all other tickets lose, you could deductively conclude that your ticket will win at an equal level of belief. Then, paradoxically, it would seem that you believe that every ticket will lose, but also win.

There is no way to choose between the two competing arguments, so it would be irrational to believe one over the other. However, we still deductively believe that some ticket will win.

Page 119: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Pollock’s solution to LP

Page 120: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Kevin demos Pollock’s Proposed Solution …

Page 121: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

Kevin demos Pollock’s Proposed Solution …

See the transcript of Kevin’s interaction with OSCAR!

Page 122: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe
Page 123: The Lottery Paradox - Rensselaer Polytechnic Institutekryten.mm.rpi.edu/COURSES/INTLOGW/Lottery_Paradox.pdfThe paradox in this case? • A perfectly rational person can never believe

slutten