the ethical power of music- ancient greek and chinese thoughts

16
Yuhwen Wang is Assistant Professor at National Taiwan University. Her recent re- search focuses on the relationship between music and body. Journal of Aesthetic Education, Vol. 38, No. 1, Spring 2004 ©2004 Board of Trustees of the University of Illinois The Ethical Power of Music: Ancient Greek and Chinese Thoughts YUHWEN WANG Both the ancient Chinese and Greeks from around the fifth century B.C. to around third century A.D. recognized the immense impact that music has on the development of one’s personality, and both regarded it as crucial in cultivation for the proper disposition in youth. Music’s power over one’s ethos 1 — that is, human disposition — was emphasized by Plato and by Chi- nese authors of various documents. 2 As will become clear, music in both cultures was considered an important means for a proper education and a powerful tool for cultivating and controlling the people of a nation-state. In both cases, the power of music was further connected to the way the uni- verse works. Yet despite their similar views about music, the reasoning strate- gies used in the two cultures differ enormously. Observing how the two re- mote cultures conceived the relationship between music and the ethos may give us some insight to music’s role in aesthetic education among us modern listeners. In this essay, I investigate how the power of music was understood and explained in these two ancient cultures, and the similarities and differences in their explanations and reasoning strategies. What mechanisms were thought to be at work behind this musical power? How close are ancient Greeks and Chinese in their conceptions of musical power upon the ethos? In particular, the Yue Ji (Record of Music, from the Li Ji) and the Yue Shu (Book of Music, from the Shi Ji) from ancient China, and Plato’s writings from ancient Greece will be taken as the foci of the comparison. The Yue Ji and Yue Shu are two of the most important documents in ancient Chinese musical philosophy, respectively included as individual sections in the Li Ji (Record of Rituals) and Shi Ji (Records of the Grand Histo- rian). Both are believed to be later versions of the same source document, which has never been found. In the Chinese textual tradition, the Yue Ji is the earliest fully developed treatise on music that has come down to us. Its authorship has been debated for centuries, but scholars generally agree that

Upload: stavros-girgenis

Post on 28-Oct-2014

127 views

Category:

Documents


1 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: The Ethical Power of Music- Ancient Greek and Chinese Thoughts

Yuhwen Wang is Assistant Professor at National Taiwan University. Her recent re-search focuses on the relationship between music and body.

Journal of Aesthetic Education, Vol. 38, No. 1, Spring 2004©2004 Board of Trustees of the University of Illinois

The Ethical Power of Music: Ancient Greek andChinese Thoughts

YUHWEN WANG

Both the ancient Chinese and Greeks from around the fifth century B.C. toaround third century A.D. recognized the immense impact that music hason the development of one’s personality, and both regarded it as crucial incultivation for the proper disposition in youth. Music’s power over one’sethos1 — that is, human disposition — was emphasized by Plato and by Chi-nese authors of various documents.2 As will become clear, music in bothcultures was considered an important means for a proper education and apowerful tool for cultivating and controlling the people of a nation-state. Inboth cases, the power of music was further connected to the way the uni-verse works. Yet despite their similar views about music, the reasoning strate-gies used in the two cultures differ enormously. Observing how the two re-mote cultures conceived the relationship between music and the ethos maygive us some insight to music’s role in aesthetic education among us modernlisteners.

In this essay, I investigate how the power of music was understood andexplained in these two ancient cultures, and the similarities and differencesin their explanations and reasoning strategies. What mechanisms werethought to be at work behind this musical power? How close are ancientGreeks and Chinese in their conceptions of musical power upon the ethos?In particular, the Yue Ji (Record of Music, from the Li Ji) and the Yue Shu (Bookof Music, from the Shi Ji) from ancient China, and Plato’s writings from ancientGreece will be taken as the foci of the comparison.

The Yue Ji and Yue Shu are two of the most important documents inancient Chinese musical philosophy, respectively included as individualsections in the Li Ji (Record of Rituals) and Shi Ji (Records of the Grand Histo-rian). Both are believed to be later versions of the same source document,which has never been found. In the Chinese textual tradition, the Yue Ji isthe earliest fully developed treatise on music that has come down to us. Itsauthorship has been debated for centuries, but scholars generally agree that

Mary Botto
Page 2: The Ethical Power of Music- Ancient Greek and Chinese Thoughts

90 Yuhwen Wang

it was completed prior to the middle of the Western Han dynasty (secondand first centuries B.C.) The entire contents of the Yue Ji are included in theYue Shu. The latter contains additional material, is organized in a more logicalway, and is also thought to have been compiled during the Western Handynasty.3

In the first part of this essay, I will use the Yue Ji, the Yue Shu, and Plato’swritings to show how the concept of music’s power over the ethos evolvedin the two ancient cultures. This is closely related to their views on music’seffect in regulating human behavior, its educational value, its benefits forgoverning a state, and its close association with Nature and the universe.Then in the second part, I will focus on the ways that Plato and the authorsof the Yue Ji and Yue Shu explained this power, and the reasoning strategiesthat they used.

Essential Belief in Music’s Power

The close relationship between music and the ethos is explicitly announcedin the Yue Ji and the Yue Shu. Both documents state approvingly that “musicrepresented (made clear) virtue” for the ancient rulers (SSJ, 5, 678).4 Variouskinds of music are then pointed out as having different effects upon humanethos and emotion:

Men have powers of the body and powers of the mind but they can-not remain stable with regard to grief, pleasure, joy, and anger. Theyare moved by external causes. Thus originates the appearance of thevarious affections. Therefore, if feeble, trivial, and rushed music pre-vails, people will be sad. If harmonious, peaceful, varied but simplemusic prevails, people will be gratified and happy. If vigorous, violent,and forceful music prevails, which arouses people to move their limbsand animates their blood circulation, they will be steadfast and resolute.If straightforward, steady, peaceful, and stately music prevails, peoplewill be dignified and pious. If broad, serene, orderly, and flowing musicprevails, people will be compassionate. If licentious, evil, hasty, andsuperficial music prevails, people will be dissolute.5

Music of various qualities affects people differently. When proper music isapplied, it helps cultivate their proper ethos, and furthermore equips themwith spiritual power:

If music is examined and investigated carefully in order to regulatethe mind, the mind will develop peacefully, straightforwardly, com-passionately, and honestly. A peaceful, straightforward, compassion-ate and honest mind brings joy. This joy brings calmness, and calm-ness brings endurance. As one endures in this [virtuous] state forlong, people believe in him as in heaven. As they believe in him as inheaven, they are kept in awe of him as of God. He who has achievedsuch heavenly qualities does not need to speak — he is believed. He

Page 3: The Ethical Power of Music- Ancient Greek and Chinese Thoughts

Ethical Power of Music 91

who has achieved such godliness does not need to become severe —he is awe-inspiring. This is the sequence of the states of mind if mas-tering of music is applied to regulate them (SSJ, 5, 698, trans. based onKong Ying-Da’s annotation).

Proper music cultivates virtuous qualities such as peacefulness, straight-forwardness, compassion, and honesty. These qualities ultimately developheavenly qualities and godliness in the individual. In other words, theyequip him or her with spiritual power, so that he or she is believed andawe-inspiring without the need to speak or to be severe. Having indicatedmusic’s power over the personality, the contents of the Yue Ji and Yue Shuconcern themselves less about the relationship per se between music and ethosthan about the practical effects of music’s power in such areas as educationand statecraft.

In contrast, Plato chose to describe music’s power over the ethos in muchmore explicit terms, arguing that gracelessness, evil rhythm, and dishar-mony in music are associated with evil temper, while the opposites areassociated with sober and more positive dispositions.6 He maintained thatindividuals who have true music within themselves will always desire toattune the body in order preserve the harmonia of their souls, while impropermusic can result in disobedience and contempt for religion.7 In Laws hedescribed the effect of improper music in the listener:

refusal to submit to the magistrates, and on this will follow emancipa-tion from the authority and correction of parents and elders; then…comes the effort to escape obedience to the law, and, when that goal isall but reached, contempt for oaths, for the plighted word, and all re-ligion. The spectacle of the Titanic nature about which our old leg-ends speak is re-enacted; man returns to the old condition of a hell ofunending misery.8

Plato offered a more detailed description of music’s influence upon humandisposition than was found in the Yue Ji and Yue Shu. He explicated the vari-ous stages through which individuals are affected by music, and indicatedhow one can be affected differently by the same music through different de-grees of immersion. The same music may have a positive effect if listened tofor a short period, but exert a negative effect after a longer period. In TheRepublic, Plato gave this example of how one becomes a “feeble warrior” bycontinuously listening to “sweet, soft, and dirge-like” music:

Now when a man abandons himself to music to play upon him andpour into his soul as it were through the funnel of his ears thosesweet, soft, and dirge-like harmonia…and gives his entire time to thewarblings and blandishments of song, the first result is that the prin-ciple of high spirit, if he had it, is softened like iron and is made use-ful instead of useless and brittle. But when he continues the practicewithout remission and is spellbound, the effect begins to be that he

Page 4: The Ethical Power of Music- Ancient Greek and Chinese Thoughts

92 Yuhwen Wang

melts and liquefies till he completely dissolves away his spirit, cutsout as it were the very sinews of his soul and makes of himself a“feeble warrior.”9

While Plato provided more detail than the authors of the Yue Ji or YueShu on the processes of music’s effect on human disposition, his observa-tion on the different musical effects resulting from different degrees of im-mersion in the same music were not further developed. When he addressedthe political and educational effects of music, he did so according to itsmodes and instruments, without considering the amount of immersion.

Based on the observation of music’s immense impact upon disposition,its power was then suggested for education in both ancient Greek andChinese thoughts. In The Republic, Plato argued that to understand musicwas to develop both aesthetic taste and proper personality:

education in music is most sovereign, because more than anything elserhythm and harmonia find their way to the inmost soul and take stron-gest hold upon it, bringing with them and imparting grace, if one isrightly trained, and otherwise the contrary.…And further, becauseomissions and the failure of beauty in things badly made or grownwould be most quickly perceived by one who was properly educatedin music, and so, feeling distaste rightly, he would praise beautifulthings and take delight in them and receive them into his soul to fos-ter its growth and become himself beautiful and good. The ugly hewould rightly disapprove of and hate while still young and yet be un-able to apprehend the reason, but when reason came the man thusnurtured would be the first to give her welcome, for by this affinityhe would know her (SMH, 14).

Proper education in music cultivates aesthetic taste, and thus one is able topraise and take delight in beautiful things. More important, such aesthetictaste enters “into one’s soul,” and helps establish a noble personality, makingone “beautiful and good.” All these may occur without his or her consciousawareness of the causes, since the influence of music upon one does not comethrough reasoning or intellectual understanding (“the ugly he would rightlydisapprove of and hate while still young and yet be unable to apprehendthe reason”), but enters directly and “unmediatedly” “into his soul.” Moreabout the detailed route and process of musical influence will follow.

Similarly, in ancient China, music was also considered an indispensableeducational tool for cultivating a proper personality. It was included in thesix basic subjects (liu yi) that a young man had to master in order to becomea “superior person” (jun zu). The Analects of Confucius indicates that a youngman “grows through odes, establishes through rites (li), and accomplishesthrough music.”10 The Book of Rites states that

Rites and music were adopted by the three great former kings in edu-cating their sons. Music was for the cultivation of the inside; rites forthe outside. With rites and music combined in the young man’s inside

Page 5: The Ethical Power of Music- Ancient Greek and Chinese Thoughts

Ethical Power of Music 93

and expressed in the outside, he becomes joyous, pious, and gentle(SSJ, 5, 397).

As shown in this paragraph, music was often considered together with therites for educational and governing purposes in Yue Ji. Music and rites (orrituals, ceremonies; all three words are expressed as Li in these Chinese docu-ments) are often mentioned together in ancient China. Both of them werebelieved to a have strong effect upon one’s personality: Music affects theinner disposition, while rites, the outer demeanor. Education of the youngwas thus conceived both inside and outside.

In society, music’s educational effect was further adopted for an effec-tive and virtuous governance. Rulers were encouraged to promote educa-tion in music in order to guide their people toward a virtuous and orderedstate. This idea is expressed in the Yue Ji and Yue Shu as:

It is music which provides pleasure to the sages and (it is music) whichimproves the minds of the people. The ancient rulers used music ineducation as it influenced the people profoundly and changed theircustoms and manners.…the superior man…uses music in a far-reach-ing manner in order to complete the education of his people. Whenmusic predominates and people develop their righteous character,one can behold the virtue of the ruler (SSJ, 5, 678, 682).

Music’s main contribution to governing a state comes through its effect uponhuman ethos and the consequent educational power. The passage on the de-velopment of heavenly quality and godliness was actually addressed to theruler, and is succeeded by the following words:

Therefore music acts upon the inside, rites upon the outside. In manmusic effects the highest of harmony, and rites effects the highest ofpiety. When one turns harmonious in the inside and deferential in theoutside, people, simply looking at him, will not confront him. Simplybehold his face, and people will not show insolence or rudeness. Asvirtues radiate from the inside [of the ruler], everybody is willing toobey him. As righteous and reasoned behavior is shown in the outside[of the ruler], people are submissive to him (SSJ, 5, 698).

Proper music helps not only the people being governed, making them com-pliant to orders, but also the ruler himself, making him virtuous and equip-ping him with spiritual power. Thus when incorporated into a system thatincludes rites, a penal code, and laws of conduct, music is regarded as oneof four essential devices for ruling a country. From the Yue Ji and Yue Shu:

Rites are meant for turning people’s minds in the right direction, mu-sic for harmonizing the voices, laws of conduct for creating order, apenal code for avoiding misconduct. The purpose of rites, music,laws of conduct, and a penal code is one and the same: they are usedto achieve proper governing for an ideal state (SSJ, 5, 608).

Page 6: The Ethical Power of Music- Ancient Greek and Chinese Thoughts

94 Yuhwen Wang

The use of music in ruling a state greatly concerned Plato as well. He wentso far as to argue that improper music be banned from society at the sametime that proper music was adopted for educational and political purposes.Any new innovations in music are also to be carefully scrutinized:

The overseers must be watchful against [music’s] insensible corrup-tion. They must throughout be watchful against innovations in musicand gymnastics counter to the established order, and to the best oftheir power, guard against them.…For a change to a new type of mu-sic is something to beware of as a hazard toward all our fortunes. Forthe modes of music are never disturbed without unsettling of themost fundamental political and social conventions.11

Plato did not describe the direct political use of music by a state ruler to thesame extent as was done in the Yue Ji and Yue Shu, but he did specify thetypes of music that should be maintained and those that should be aban-doned in order to promote an ideal state. The “dirge-like harmonia,” such asthe Mixolydian and the intense Lydian, had to be abandoned, for they are“useless even to women who are to make the best of themselves, let alone tomen.” Also to be abandoned were the “soft and convivial harmonia” — theIonian and Lydian, since they induce qualities like “drunkenness,” “softness,”and “sloth,” which he felt were not befitting for the guardians of the state.What remains for cultivating the proper attitudes of the people and thusgoverning the state are the Dorian and the Phrygian:

“[Dorian] would fittingly imitate the utterances and the accents of abrave man who is engaged in warfare or in any enforced business,and who, when he has failed, either meeting wounds or death or hav-ing fallen into some other mishap, in all these conditions confrontsfortune with steadfast endurance and repels her strokes. And [Phryg-ian] for such a man engaged in works of peace, not enforced but vol-untary, either trying to persuade somebody of something and implor-ing him — whether it be a god, through prayer, or a man, by teachingand admonition — or contrariwise yielding himself to another who ispetitioning or teaching him or trying to change his opinions, and inconsequence faring according to his wish, and not bearing himself ar-rogantly, but in all this acting modestly and moderately and acquiesc-ing in the outcome. Leave us these two harmonia — the enforced andthe voluntary — that will best imitate the utterances of men failing orsucceeding, the temperate, the brave — leave us these (SMH, 9-11).

This distinction between proper and improper music recalls similar en-gagement in the Yue Ji and Yue Shu. In these documents, types of musicsuch as that found in the countries of Zheng and Wei are described as evil.They are thought to have the opposite effect from the “ancient” music such as“Shao” and “Wu.”12 The Yue Shu goes further as to repeatedly warn theruler how listening to evil music resulted in the annihilation of countries inhistory.13

Page 7: The Ethical Power of Music- Ancient Greek and Chinese Thoughts

Ethical Power of Music 95

Both Plato’s view of music and that found in the Yue Ji and Yue Shu asso-ciate closely not only with the ethos, education, and government, but alsowith their respective views of the cosmos — with what is observed on earthand in the cosmic universe. In the Chinese documents, a strong connectionwas established between music and the harmony found in Heaven (tian)and Earth (di).

Great music shares in the harmony of Heaven and Earth. Great Ritualshares in the regulated order of Heaven and Earth. When there is har-mony, things do not suffer loss of their meaning and effect. Whenthere is regulated order, [there are] distinguished sacrifices to Heavenand to Earth (SSJ, 5, 668; LJJ, 616).

Music reflects the harmony between heaven and earth. Ceremonyshows orderly relationship between heaven and earth. All things re-ceive their existence and orderly distinctions from harmony. Heavenis the origin of music; earth brings into being (the various forms of)ceremony. If there are too many forms, chaos would appear; if thereis too much invention in music, violence would prevail. Only if theinteraction (between heaven and earth) is well understood, ceremonyand music will have correct presentations (SSJ, 5, 669; LJJ, 618, trans.Kaufmann, 40).

Underlying the Chinese association of music with Heaven and Earth is thenotion that music exemplifies Nature’s harmony. Various musical param-eters were viewed as representing different forms of the natural phenom-ena. Order and regularity in each of the parameters were taken to symbolizethe same in Nature:

Clarity and explicitness [in the music] denote (the same in) Heaven.Broadness and enormity [in the music] denote Earth. The circular se-quence [of notes] denote (the same in) the seasons. The turning mo-tions [of the dancers] denote (the same in) wind and rain. Like thefive colors in Nature, [the five scalar notes] create an ordered andundistorted whole. Like the eight winds in Nature, [the eight instru-ments] follow the correct tuning without confusion. All measurements[in the instruments] are regulated in correct proportions. High andlow notes complete one another. The beginning and end [of the scale]create each other. The sequence [of notes] and size [of intervals] serveinterchangeably as regulating devices.14

The Chinese association of music and the cosmos was established uponwhat was actually observed on the earth, especially regular, natural phe-nomena such as the seasons, wind, and rain. In contrast, Plato’s discussionof the cosmos in correspondence with music is based on the proportions —particularly the shared proportions with which God created the universe,humans, and the revolutionary ratios of the armillary sphere. The GreekPythagoreans saw shared numerical relationships between the musical in-tervals and the cosmic spheres. Plato made similar observations in the

Page 8: The Ethical Power of Music- Ancient Greek and Chinese Thoughts

96 Yuhwen Wang

Timaeus. There he explained how music, the soul, and the cosmic universewere associated in shared numerical relationships. Proportions found with-in musical intervals, such as 1:2, 3:2, 4:3, 9:8, and 256:243 are identified asbeing identical to those with which God created the soul.15

Despite such differences in the aspects of the universe with which musicwas connected, both Plato and the authors of the Yue Ji and Yue Shu valueshared harmony between music and the universe. Futhermore, implied inall these writings is a conviction that harmony between music and the cos-mos entails harmony among and within humans. As succinctly stated in theYue Ji and Yue Shu, “music reflects the harmony between heaven andearth.…all things receive their existence and orderly distinctions from har-mony,” and “in man music effects the highest of harmony.” In Plato, the sameproportions that underlie music and the creation of the universe also underliethe creation of human souls. Harmony between music and the universewould thus entail harmony between human beings on the one hand andthe universe on the other.

How Music Affects the Ethos

What, then, is the mechanism through which music exerts its power over hu-man ethos? One may think of the medium of the associated words, in otherwords, the meaning of the musical text, as Plato stated, “the harmonia andthe rhythm must follow the text” (SMH, 10). The meaning of words, ratherthan the musical sound phenomena (“the harmonia and the rhythm”) mightseem to be most important in his conception of musical power.

However, as given earlier in the excerpt on musical training, when Platoexplained music’s educational power, he referred to its sound phenomenon,and indicated that “more than anything else rhythm and harmonia find theirway to the inmost soul and take strongest hold upon it” (SMH, 10).16 It isthe sound organization (rhythm and harmonia), rather than the meaning ofthe text, that has the power of affecting ethos. In other words, although rhythmand harmonia must follow the words, what makes music so powerful is thefirst two, not the meaning of the third.

How do the rhythm and the harmonia find their way to the “innermostsoul?” This problem is crucial if the mechanism by which music affects thedisposition in Plato’s thinking is to be clarified. Boethius indicated a resem-blance between sound organization and the internal nature of humans. Inhis understanding of Plato, individuals are “united” in their “likeness” be-tween the sound organization (“what in sound is well and fitly combined”)and what is inside themselves:

From this may be discerned the truth of what Plato not idly said, thatthe soul of the universe is united by musical concord. For when, bymeans of what in ourselves is well and fitly ordered, we apprehend

Page 9: The Ethical Power of Music- Ancient Greek and Chinese Thoughts

Ethical Power of Music 97

what in sounds is well and fitly combined, and take pleasure in it, werecognize that we ourselves are united by this likeness. For likeness isagreeable, unlikeness hateful and contrary.17

“Likeness” between musical sound and the individual’s inside is indeedimplied by Plato in an earlier quotation about musical training: “One whois properly educated in music would…receive [beautiful things] into hissoul to foster its growth and become himself beautiful and good.” The sameidea is also indicated in his description of what separates fair dictions frombad ones:

Seemliness and unseemliness are attendant upon the good rhythmand the bad.…And, further,…good rhythm and bad rhythm accom-pany, the one fair diction, assimilating itself thereto, and the other theopposite, and so of the apt and the unapt, if…the rhythm and harmoniafollow the words and not the words these. And…the manner of thediction, and the speech…follow and conform to the disposition of thesoul (SMH, 13, italics added).

Good rhythm assimilates itself to “fair diction,” which in turn follows andconforms to the disposition of the soul. Thus ultimately, rhythm has to fol-low and conform to the disposition. Indeed, “likeness” between musicalsound organization and proper human disposition is an important qualitywhen Plato identifies proper music: As is shown in the earlier quotationconcerning the Dorian and the Phrygian modes, what distinguishes properfrom improper music in Plato’s thinking is whether the music “assimilates”a desirable disposition. Music, as well as poetry, is required to conform tothe kind of man’s speech in which “rhythms of a life that is orderly andbrave” is observed (SMH, 12). In the same manner as diction, speech andother arts, music should “follow and conform to the [proper] disposition ofthe soul.”

If “likeness” is the key notion through which music possesses power, inwhat respect does this “likeness” exist? Does it exist in a concrete, practicalmanner, which can be observed, sensed or measured? Earlier it has been in-dicated that Plato held a numerical correspondence between music and thecosmic universe. This correspondence was in fact also held for the humansoul. Agreeing with the Pythagorean thinking, Plato observed likeness amongmusic, the cosmos, and the human soul through the concept of harmonia:

So much of music as is adapted to the sound of the voice and to thesense of hearing is granted to us for the sake of harmonia; and harmo-nia, which has motions akin to the revolutions of our souls, is not regardedby the intelligent votary of the Muses as given by them with a view toirrational pleasure, which is deemed to be the purpose of it in ourday, but as meant to correct any discord which may have arisen in thecourses of the soul, and to be our ally in bringing her into harmoniaand agreement with herself; and rhythm too was given by them forthe same reason, on account of the irregular and graceless ways whichprevail among mankind generally, and to help up against them.18

Page 10: The Ethical Power of Music- Ancient Greek and Chinese Thoughts

98 Yuhwen Wang

Here music’s power in correcting discord in the soul, and in helping oneagainst “irregular and graceless ways,” is associated with the motions “akinto the revolutions of our souls.” Yet, what do the “revolutions of the souls”mean? How does the soul “revolve?” To understand how music exerts itspower upon ethos in Plato’s conception, this is the key point, since this ex-plains how music bears likeness to the soul and thus to the disposition.

According to Plato, the soul “revolves upon herself.” In his conception,God created the soul in some kind of a ring shape, with an outer and aninner circle:

The outer movement he named the movement of the Same; the inner,the movement of the Different. The movement of the Same he causedto revolve to the right by way of the side; the movement of the Differentto the left by way of the diagonal.19

This statement looks like a description of the revolution of stars in the armil-lary sphere. Indeed, in Plato’s thinking, the human soul is inseparable fromthe soul of the universe, and this serves as a basis for his overall conceptionof the universe and its creation:

And the soul, being everywhere inwoven from the center to the outer-most heaven and enveloping the heaven all round on the outside, re-volving within its own limit, made a divine beginning of ceaselessand intelligent life for all time. Now the body of the heaven has beencreated visible; but she is invisible, and, as a soul having part in rea-son and harmonia, is the best of things brought into being by the mostexcellent of things intelligible and eternal.20

By equating the human soul with the universal soul, Plato appealed tointellectual speculation, rather than tangible, observable, or sensible facts.Consequently, the likeness he observed between proportions in music andthose in the human/universal soul has also to be grasped intellectually. Hisexplanation of music’s ethical power through such likeness, in turn, isbased on intellectual speculation, rather than practical, tangible experienceor observable facts.

One might take a discussion such as Ann Moyer’s to support an inter-pretation of musical power in Plato close to human practical experience ormeasurable facts. Explaining the likeness between music and the soul inPlato, Moyer evokes “sympathetic vibration” between musical sound andthe human soul and body. Men’s reaction to the power of music is now ex-plained as “a physiological response” as well as an intellectual judgment ofpleasantness.

Once the Pythagoreans established the notion of consonant musicalproportion to their own satisfaction, the matter of human response tothese intervals had to be addressed. Plato’s Timaeus does so by argu-ing that the human soul is patterned on the World Soul and is therefore

Page 11: The Ethical Power of Music- Ancient Greek and Chinese Thoughts

Ethical Power of Music 99

ordered in these same proportions. Similarly, the three parts of thesoul, and even the physical proportions of the human body itself,all participate in these ratios. The consonant intervals, then are pleas-ant to the ear because of their similarity to these same proportionswithin the listener. This argument accounts for the effects of music onthe soul or on the emotions: by a sort of sympathetic vibration thesounds resonate with and therefore emphasize similar aspects of thesoul. Appreciation of beauty or ugliness in music may therefore beseen as a physiological response as well as a conscious judgment bythe intellect.21

Nevertheless, as Moyer indicates, the “sympathetic vibration” is but pro-portional correspondence between music on the one hand and the humansoul and body on the other, rather than some sort of actual vibration foundin both. Even in terms of the physical activity, Moyer’s account of “sympa-thetic vibration,” remains an abstract notion of proportional correspon-dence between music and “the physical proportions [instead of “vibration”]of the human body.”

How was the source of musical power explained in the ancient Chinesedocuments? Like Plato, the authors of the Yue Ji and Yue Shu also located thepower of music in its sound phenomena, rather than in the meaning of thetexts. This is explicitly indicated in an earlier-cited passage, which indicatesthat order and regularity in music, rather than the meaning of the words,symbolize the same in Nature. A more important clue to music’s ethicalpower can be discovered in the passage that immediately succeeds this inthe Yue Ji and Yue Shu. In order to consider these two passages together, theformer is presented here once again together with the latter:

Clarity and explicitness [in the music] denote (the same in) Heaven.Broadness and enormity [in the music] denote Earth. The circular se-quence [of the melodies] denote (the same in) the seasons. The turn-ing motions [of the dancers] denote (the same in) wind and rain. Likethe five colors in Nature, [the five scalar notes] create an ordered andundistorted whole. Like the eight winds in Nature, [the eight instru-ments] follow the correct tuning without confusion. All measurements[in the instruments] are regulated in correct proportions. High andlow notes complete one another. The beginning and end [of the scale]create each other. The sequence [of notes] and size [of intervals] serveinterchangeably as regulating devices.…Therefore, when [proper]music dominates, it leads toward the clarification of human relations.Ears and eyes become acute and perceptive; the forces of blood andenergy become orderly and calm. Customs and manners are thus[properly] affected, and there is peace in the world (SSJ, 5, 681; LJJ,629-30).

Turning to people’s “customs and manners,” this statement indicates thatorder and regularity in music are associated with its power over these hu-man qualities. Notice that the meaning of the musical text is not mentioned

Page 12: The Ethical Power of Music- Ancient Greek and Chinese Thoughts

100 Yuhwen Wang

at all. Instead, only aspects in the organization of the musical sound — themelody, instrumentation, pitch collection, and tuning — are referred to inrelation with Nature and with the “customs and manners.”

Proper music, according to this statement, enhances circulation in thephysical body (“the forces of blood and energy become orderly and calm”),sharpens the sense organs (“ears and eyes become acute and perceptive”),and appropriately orients people’s customs and manners. That is, it affectsone’s physical conditions as well as mental conditions. If the “customs andmanners” constitute (as I believe they do) part of human disposition — thatis, what we call ethos — then this passage describes an association betweenmusic’s effect on ethos and its effect on the physical body, implying that theyoccur simultaneously.

Is this association part of the mechanism through which music was be-lieved to affect ethos in ancient China? One might suspect that the fact thatmusic’s ethical power is here mentioned in connection with its physical ef-fects is merely a rhetorical strategy, rather than a clue to the mechanismthrough which music affects the ethos. For one thing, such association is notstraightforwardly asserted in this passage. For another, this is the only occa-sion in the Yue Ji where this association can be found.

Fortunately, while such an association may not be clear enough in theYue Ji, it is stated explicitly and given much more detail in the Yue Shu,which contains a list of the paths through which music affects human ethosand cultivates various moral qualities in listeners:

music is what activates the bloodflow and the meridian, circulates theenergy, and harmonizes the appropriate ethos. Hence the Gong modeinteracts with the spleen [meridian], and sincerity is harmoniouslystrengthened. The Shang mode interacts with the lung [meridian],and righteousness is harmoniously strengthened. The Jue mode in-teracts with the liver [meridian], and humaneness is harmoniouslystrengthened. The Zhi mode interacts with the heart [meridian], andpropriety is harmoniously strengthened. The Yu mode interacts withthe kidney [meridian], and wisdom is harmoniously strengthened.Hence, music reinforces the right ethos on the inside, while it differen-tiates between the respectable and the indecent on the outside (SSJ, 5,698).

Not only does this passage affirm that music “activates the blood circula-tion and meridian,” but it also explicitly indicates how music helps createvarious kinds of ethical qualities by means of activating various meridianpaths and physical parts in the body.

In contrast to Plato, the Chinese documents Yue Ji and Yue Shu appeal tophysical effects of music in explaining its ethical power. The concern is notwith how the universe came into being, or with some abstract notion thatmusic, the cosmos and ethos have in common, as found in Plato, but with aconcrete, tangible route. According to these Chinese excerpts, the mechanism

Page 13: The Ethical Power of Music- Ancient Greek and Chinese Thoughts

Ethical Power of Music 101

by which music affects ethos works (at least partly) through changes in thephysical body. By activating various parts of the body, which connect tospecific ethical qualities, music enhances certain ethical qualities in the lis-tener. In the Yue Ji, connection among musical sound, body, and ethos areonly roughly suggested, while in the Yue Shu, the specific routes throughwhich music strengthens various kinds of ethical qualities are explicitlypointed out.

Kong Ying-da (574-648 A.D.), an authoritative interpreter of the Yue Ji,expressed a similar tripartite connection among music, ethos and body inhis interpretation of an earlier-cited excerpt. His account serves as an inter-esting echo to the above-discovered relationship, and therefore deserves ourattention. For the Yue Ji’s statement that the joy which music brings througha peaceful, straightforward, compassionate, and honest mind “brings calm-ness, and calmness brings endurance,” he provided the following explana-tion: When the heart-mind is in joy [because of music], the physical body iscalm instead of perturbed or anxious. As the body is not perturbed, the lifeis long (SSJ, 5, 698).

In his understanding of the Yue Ji, music’s ethical power is closely relatedto its effect upon the body, such as physical calmness, anxiety, and distur-bance. Kong went so far as to suggest that by acting positively upon thephysical body, proper music might ultimately lead to longevity.

Conclusion

After an investigation on the political situation and intellectual and techno-logical outputs of ancient Greek and Chinese societies, G.E.R. Lloyd findsdifferent premises and preoccupations, and indicates dominant strands inthe two complex sets of traditions: the “Greek preoccupation with founda-tional questions and a readiness to countenance extreme or radical solu-tions to theoretical issues,” and the Chinese “pragmatic tendencies, with afocus on practicalities, on what works or can be put to use.”23 Through theabove survey, these strands are also revealed in the Greek and Chinese no-tions of music and their explanation procedures. Plato’s discussion ofmusic’s impact per se upon the ethos is more detailed and more substantialthan that in the Chinese Yue Ji and Yue Shu, which shows his preoccupationwith foundational questions. His appeal to corresponding proportions be-tween music and “revolutions” of the soul betrays a predilection for abstractspeculation. In contrast, the Yue Ji and Yue Shu give much less attention tothe relationships per se between music and the ethos. Rather, there is muchenthusiastic argument for the practical use of music in education and gov-ernance. There is no account of the creation of the universe, although em-phasis is given to the close relationship between music on the one hand andHeaven and Earth on the other.24 Even in their explanations of the musical

Page 14: The Ethical Power of Music- Ancient Greek and Chinese Thoughts

102 Yuhwen Wang

power, these Chinese sources show an appeal to practical, physical effectson the body, rather than to abstract notions.

While many similar views are found in the two ancient cultures, Lloydemphasizes the underlying difference, regarding it as closely related to theirdivergent social and political circumstances.25 Such difference is indeed im-mense and its significance should never be underestimated. Nevertheless,just because of the enormous divergence in the reasoning strategies andsocio-political contexts of the two cultures, the similarity in their views onmusical power becomes even more highlighted: Even in cultures of suchvast difference, the ethical power of music is emphasized to a similarly greatextent. Music’s ethical power and utility for education, statecraft and itsconnection with the universe, therefore, may enjoy cross-cultural value andimportance, which need not be confined merely to the two ancient tradi-tions. Rather, it deserves consideration for human beings today as well.26

NOTES

1. In this essay, “ethos” is used interchangeably with “disposition.” The twowords are meant in the same sense, referring to enduring temperamental quali-ties in an individual. This differs from the fleeting, momentary, evanescent emo-tions often discussed by musicologists and aestheticians as aroused, exempli-fied, conveyed, or expressed in music, which may occur, change, and disappearfrequently during the course of music.

2. For discussions of Plato and Damon on music, consult, for example, M.L. West,Ancient Greek Music (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992), esp. chap. 8 and EnricoFubini, The History of Music Aesthetics, trans. Michael Hatwell (London: Macmil-lan, 1990), part 1.

3. For the authorship and date of the Yue Ji, see, for example, Scott Cook, “Yue Ji —Record of Music: Introduction, Translation, Notes, and Commentary,” AsianMusic 26, no. 2 (1995): 2-3 and Wang Meng-Ou, Li Ji Jiao Zheng [Examination onLi Ji] (Taipei: Yi Wen Publisher, 1976), 268. For the relations between the Yue Jiand Yue Shu, see, for instance, Wang Meng-Ou, Li Ji Jiao Zheng, 253-78 and SunYao-Nian, “Yue Ji Zuo Zhe WenTi Kao Bian” [Examination in the Authorship ofYue Ji], in Yue Ji Lun Bian [Debates on Yue Ji] (Beijin: Ren Min Yin Yue, 1983),148-75. For interpretations of Yue Ji, see Wang Meng-Ou, Li Ji Jin Zhu Jin Yi[Contemporary Connotation and Interpretation of the Li Ji], vol. 2 (Taipei:Shang Wu Publisher, 1998), 607-52. This work will be cited as LJJ in the text withpage numbers for all subsequent references. Shi-San Jing Zhu Shu [Interpreta-tions and Explanations of the Thirteen Classics], vol. 5 (Taipei: Yi-Wen Pub-lisher, 1979), Li Ji, 662-708, which includes Kong Ying-Da’s annotation. Thiswork will be cited as SSJ in the text with volume and page numbers for all sub-sequent references. For interpretations of Yue Shu, see Zheng Xuan et al., Shi JiSan Jia Zhu [Three Interpretations of Shi Ji], vol. 3 (Taipei: Hong Shi, 1974), 1175-237; Long Yu-Chun et al., Bai Hua Shi Ji [Shi Ji in Today’s Ordinary Chinese Lan-guage], vol. 1 (Taipei: Lian Jing Publisher, 1994), 281-314. For English transla-tions of Yue Ji, see Walter Kaufmann, Musical References in the Chinese Classics(Detroit: Information Coordinators, Inc., 1976); and Cook, “Yue Ji,” 1-96. In thefollowing discussion, for each excerpt from Yue Ji and Yue Shu, I will adopt whatI deem to be the most lucid and appropriate translation from either of thesetranslations, or otherwise provide my own.

Page 15: The Ethical Power of Music- Ancient Greek and Chinese Thoughts

Ethical Power of Music 103

4. My translation following Long Yu-Chu et al.’s interpretation in Bai Hua Shi Jivol. 1, 297. Another annotation provided by Kong Ying-Da is, “music was madeby the ancient rulers in order for the people to imitate their virtues.”

5. Translation from Kaufmann, Musical References, 38 (Reference 37-II-8).6. Plato, Republic, 3, trans. Paul Shorey, in Plato in Twelve Volumes, vol. 5, The Re-

public, Books I-V, Loeb Classical Library, vol. 237 (Cambridge: Harvard Univer-sity Press, 1969), 400b-c.

7. Ibid., 9, 591d.8. Plato, Laws 701b-c., trans. Lane Cooper et al., in The Collected Dialogues of Plato

Including the Letters, ed. Edith Hamilton and Huntington Cairns (New York:Pantheon Books, 1961), 1294-95.

9. Plato, Republic III, 410a-b, 287-95, rev. Thomas Mathiesen, in Source Readings inMusic History, gen. ed. Oliver Strunk and Leo Treitler (New York: Norton, 1998),18. This book will be cited as SMH in the text for all subsequent references. Forthe difference between harmonia and harmoniai, see SMH, 10, fn. 3.

10. Confucius, The Analects of Confucius, the Tai Bo Chapter.11. Plato, Republic 424b-c; trans. Cooper, 665-66.12. For English translation of these passages, consult References 37-I-17, 37-III-8, 37-

III-17 in Kaufmann, Musical References, 34, 42-45.13. See the opening and closing sections of Yue Shu, in Shi Ji San Jia Zhu, 1175-76;

1235-36.14. My translation based on Sun Hsi-Dan, Li Ji Ji-Jie [Collected Interpretations of Li

Ji] (Taipei: We Shi Zhe Publisher, 1990), 1004-5.15. See, for instance, Timaeus 35a-48c.16. As Mathiesen indicates, “harmonia” in Plato has a broad sense of an entire com-

plex of relationships among pitches, and may often involve larger universal orcosmic relationships. See also Edward A. Lippman, Musical Thought in AncientGreece (New York: Columbia University Press, 1964), chap. 1.

17. Boethius, De institutione musica, Book I; trans. William Strunk, Jr., and OliverStrunk, in Oliver Strunk, Source Readings in Music History: Antiquity and theMiddle Ages (New York: W.W. Norton, 1965), 80.

18. Plato, Timaeus 47b-d; trans. Jowett in The Collected Dialogues of Plato, 1175. Myitalics. In order to be consistent, I have replaced the word “harmony” with “har-monia,” as Mathiesen uses the word in the earlier-quoted passages.

19. Plato, Timaeus 36c-d, trans. Francis MacDonald Cornford in Plato’s Cosmology:The Timaeus of Plato Translated with a Running Commentary (New York: HumanitiesPress, 1937) 58-59, rev. Mathiesen, 20.

20. Plato, Timaeus 36e-37a, trans. Cornford rev. Mathiesen, SMH, 22. See alsoCornford, Plato’s Cosmology, 6.

21. Ann E. Moyer, Musica Scientia: Musical Scholarship in the Italian Renaissance (Ithaca:Cornell University Press, 1992), 18.

22. From Shi Ji San Jia Zhu, vol. 3, 1236-37; my translation.23. G.E.R. Lloyd, Demystifying Mentalities (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,

1990), 124.24. This is not surprising, considering that Yue Ji is part of a book on rites (Li Ji,

Record of Rituals), and Yue Shu is part of historical records (Shi Ji, Records of theGrand Historian), while Plato — especially in Timaeus, where he gave a thor-ough account for the relationship between music and ethos — was more con-cerned in giving a systematic thinking of the creation of the universe and thehuman world.

25. This is shown not only in Lloyd’s Demystifying Mentalities, but especially in hisAdversaries and Authorities: Investigations into Ancient Greek and Chinese Science(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996). For other comparison and ex-ploration of similarities between ancient Greek and Chinese thinking, see DavidL. Hall and Roger T. Ames, Thinking Through Confucius (Albany: State Univer-sity of New York, 1987); David L. Hall and Roger T. Ames, Anticipating China:Thinking Through the Narratives of Chinese and Western Culture (Albany: State

Page 16: The Ethical Power of Music- Ancient Greek and Chinese Thoughts

104 Yuhwen Wang

University of New York, 1995); David L. Hall and Roger T. Ames, Thinking fromthe Han: Self, Truth, and Transcendence in Chinese and Western Culture (Albany:State University of New York, 1998); Lisa Raphals, Knowing Words: Wisdom andCunning in the Classical Traditions of China and Greece (Ithaca: Cornell UniversityPress, 1992); and Steven Shankman and Stephen Durrant, The Siren and theSage: Knowledge and Wisdom in Ancient Greece and China (London: Cassell, 2000).

26. An earlier version of this essay was presented at the 25th International Congressof Aesthetics in Japan, 27-31 August 2001. It has been substantially revised sincethen.