taylor.talk.paris.may.2012.as given

Upload: hscottarmstrong3302

Post on 04-Jun-2018

214 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/13/2019 Taylor.talk.Paris.may.2012.as Given

    1/33

    1

    Abrahamic creation and Neoplatonic emanation in Greek, Arabic

    and Latin.

    Reflections on a recent paper by Richard Taylor

    0.1 Introduction

    One of the most important and most frequently occurring questions in both ancient and

    modern philosophy is, of course, the following : has the world always existed, or did it come

    into being at a specific moment of time ? The former was the position of Aristotle and,

    following him, of most pagan philosophers down to the closing of the Platonic Academy in529AD. The latter was the view of a few renegade pagan philosophers in Antiquity

    especially such Middle Platonists as Plutarch, Atticus and Galen who gave a literal

    interpretation of the passages in Plato's Timaeusin which the Demiurge seems to create the

    world in time and of some Christians such as John Philoponus, who were concerned to

    defend the literal truth of the Biblical account of creation as narrated in theBook of Genesis.

    In the controversies between Pagans and Christians at the end of Greco-Roman

    Antiquity, as exemplified by the debate between Philoponus and the Neoplatonist philosopherSimplicius, these two positions were usually considered both exhaustive and mutually

    exclusive1. On the one hand, one could agree with the pagans represented by Simplicius, and

    maintain that the world comes into being through eternal emanation (in Greek, aei), usually

    conceived as originating in the supreme principle (designated as the One, the Good, or God),

    and continuing through the intermediaries of hypostasized Intellect and Soul until it reaches

    the stage of Soul's insertion of forms into matter, thereby bringing about the formation of the

    sensible world. Or else one could believe, with the Christians, that God created the world in

    time or at a specific moment (Greekpote), including matter, out of nothing by a one-time act

    of his benevolent will2. According to Philoponus at least, although this act took place at a

    1 As they continued to be for Kant, in his first antinomy of pure reason ( Critique of Pure Reason,

    Transcendental Doctrine of Elements, Transcendental Logic, 2nd division, Transcendental Dialectic, book two :

    Dialectical Inferences of Pure Reason).

    2Cf. Philoponus, Against Aristotle, fr. 115 Wildberg = Simplicius, In Phys., 1141, 22 : !!"!#"$#!$%%&&!''#()!"*+(),-!!"!%'".; Hierocles, De prov., apud Photius, Bibl. cod. 251, p. 461a-23 : !!"!*/#01('2

    (...) !!"!#%&3$4)'2: Proclus, Investigation of Aristotle's objections to the Timaeus, ap. Philoponus, De aet.mundi, VI, 7, p. 138, 24-25 Rabe : "516#+)47!)')1+389,.#!:&*+ ;#

  • 8/13/2019 Taylor.talk.Paris.may.2012.as Given

    2/33

    2

    specific moment it time (pote), it was nevetheless instantaneous in the sense that various

    kinds of change were held to be so in Aristotelian natural philosophy : acts of intellection and

    touching, the flash of a bolt of lightning, and the freezing of water, the curdling of milk and

    other phase transitions as they're known to modern science, to mention just a few of the

    standard examples3.

    This debate had an important impact on Islamic philosopy, with al-Kindi, the

    Plotiniana Arabica, al-Ghazali and the Kalam basically adopting the broad outlines of

    Philoponus' approach to the question of creation, while Farabi, Ibn Bajja, Avicenna, and

    Averroes (at least in some phases of his thought) maintained different variations of the

    position defended by Simplicius.

    Eternal emanation or temporal creation ex nihilo : the battle lines seem to have been

    drawn, and all that's left is to choose one's camp.

    Very recently, however, Richard Taylor4 has argued that these two seemingly

    incompatible viewpoints can be reconciled, and that both can rightly be called instances of

    creation. This view has a long and exemplary pedigree, including no less an authority that

    Thomas Aquinas. In what follows I will try to contribute some elements toward an evaluation

    of this claim.

    1.0 Taylor on creation

    In his article, Taylor, following Hasker, sets forth a definition of what he calls

    creation1 or Abrahamic creation (I will henceforth call it the latter). This type of creation,

    opposed to Neoplatonic-style emanation (which Taylor designates as creation2), is

    characterized by the following features.

    1. It is ex nihilo, rather than being either a fabrication out of pre-existing material or an

    outflow from God's own nature.

    2. It is a free act of God, who was not obliged to create but did so out of love and

    generosity.

    3. God not only creates the world in the beginning, but continues to sustain it at every

    moment of its existence.

    3On all this, see M. Chase 2011.4R. Taylor 2012.

  • 8/13/2019 Taylor.talk.Paris.may.2012.as Given

    3/33

    3

    Summing up this notion of Abrahamic creation, Taylor writes5that it

    involves a single primary cause or First Cause originating all reality other than itself by bringing forth allex nihilo as ontologically after absolute nothingness in an action somehow including freedom, will andchoice such that there is neither external nor internal necessity compelling creation1.

    What Taylor calls creation2 or emanative origination, and I will henceforth simply call

    Neoplatonic emanation, is, he claims, characteristic of such Medieval Arabic works as the

    Plotiniana Arabica that is, the so-called Theology of Aristotle, the Sayings of the Greek

    Sage, and other such works, which are based largely on extracts from the work of Plotinus

    and the Liber de Causis, based mostly on propositions from Proclus' Elements of Theology.

    Here, Taylor explains, the creation or origination of reality takes place from the First Cause,

    or God, without any act of will or any other intermediary, but by the very being of that Cause(Greek auti ti einai, Arabic bi-ann!yati-hi). The existence of that Cause immediately and

    automatically entails, by a process of emanation, the existence of all subsequent levels of

    reality. This form of creation, Taylor writes6,

    ... entails the negation of will, choice, the necessity of nature characteristic of things having nature orform (which is necessity2), and also external compulsion (which is necessity3).

    Taylor7 thus introduces a distinction between three kinds of necessity. Proceedingfrom the lower to the higher forms, we have (Table 1) :

    Necessity3, which takes place by external compulsion.

    Necessity2, which indicates what follows for a thing on the basis of its nature or form.

    Finally, there is

    Necessity1, or transcendent necessity, in which the effect follows immediately upon

    the positing of the cause.

    Now Neoplatonic emanation, Taylor wants to claim, is free from necessity3 (nothingexternal can force the First Cause to create) ; and from necessity2(the first cause has no form

    or nature8 that might compel it to do something), but not from necessity 1, or transcendent

    5Taylor 2012, 115.

    6Taylor 2012, 130.

    7Taylor 2012, 130 ff.

    8This seems highly questionable in the case of Plotinus, for whom the first Cause, otherwise known as the

    One or the Good, may have no form, but can be, and quite often is, said to have a nature. See the numerous

    attestations in Sleeman-Pollet, Lexicon Plotinianum, s.v. ?@:+9 b6, col. 1095. Already in an early Christian

  • 8/13/2019 Taylor.talk.Paris.may.2012.as Given

    4/33

    4

    necessity. Thus, in Neoplatonic creation, the emanation of all reality follows immediately

    upon the being of the First Cause qua Good. This conceptual scheme, Taylor argues,

    characterises the thought of Plotinus, Proclus, the PA, the LDC, al-Farabi, and Avicenna.

    Abrahamic creation, by contrast, is free from all three types of necessity.

    Basing himself on no less an authority than Thomas Aquinas9, Taylor now goes on to

    make what might be deemed to be his most controversial move : both Abrahamic creation and

    Neoplatonic emanation can, he claims, be considered as creation tout court. Let us recall that,

    according to Taylor, the main difference between Abrahamic creation and Neoplatonic

    emanation is that the former involves a free choice of will on God's part, and the latter does

    not. In Taylor's words10:

    It appears then that it is quite appropriate to consider creation to be of at least two sorts, creation2which isbased on the notion of primary causality involving necessity1 resulting from the First as the Good, andcreation1 which is also based on primary causality but adds the Abrahamic understanding that the Firstcreates without any sort of necessity, need not have created at all, and acts by will, in some understandingof that term.

    Let me begin my critical discussion of Taylor's theses by saying that I find his paper

    exceptionally dense, profound, and stimulating, so much so that I have been wrestling with it

    since I first heard an initial version of it last Fall. My initial reaction was that there is

    something wrong with the final conclusion, or at least missing in the argumentation leading

    up to it. I must confess, however, that the more I think about the issues involved, the less sure

    I am of my position. In what follows, therefore, is by no means intended as a definitive

    refutation of Taylor's position, but more as a Confessioof the doubts I have had about it, and

    continue to have to some degree.

    I'll group these doubts under three headings.

    context, Clement of Alexandria (Strom. I, 86, 3) speaks of doing good (to agathopoein) as as it were, the nature

    (phusis) of God, as it is the nature of fire to heat and of light to illuminate. Cf. Drrie-Baltes 1998, 472 n. 47.

    That the First Cause lacks a nature does not even seem to be true of the Liber de Causis, which, in proposition 8

    as cited by Taylor (2012, n. 36) says of the Good or First Cause that its individual nature is the Pure Good

    emanating all goodnesses upon the intellect and upon the rest of the things through the mediation of the

    intellect. As in Plotinus, then, it is precisely because the One is good that it creates. Taylor seems to assume that

    at least as far as the Neoplatonic One is concerned, having nature is equivalent to having a form. I do not believe

    that is the case.

    9Commentary on the Sentences of Peter Lombard (1252-56), at Book 2 d. 1, q. 1, a. 2, resp. See below.10Taylor 2012, 132.

  • 8/13/2019 Taylor.talk.Paris.may.2012.as Given

    5/33

    5

    1. How solid are Taylor's initial axioms and definitions ? Do his categories of creation1

    (Abrahamic creation) and creation2(Neoplatonic emanation) accurately designate two clearly

    identifiable positions, neither neglecting any essential element nor including anything

    superfluous ?

    2. Subsidiary to this first question : how cut-and-dried are the positions of the various

    thinkers Taylor assigns to the two camps ? I will leave aside the case of the Plotiniana

    Arabicaand theLiber De Causis, assuming that Taylor, one of the world's leading experts on

    both works, knows what he's talking about and has given an unimpeachable account of their

    doctrines. But is it really the case, as Taylor claims with regard to creation 2or Neoplatonic-

    style emanationism, that Plotinus, Proclus, Farabi and Avicenna accept the causing by the

    primary cause of the existence of something after nothing11 ? With regard to Abrahamic

    creation : it is really so straightforwardly clear that God's creative act, for Thomas Aquinas, is

    the result of a completely free act of will ? And as far as Neoplatonic emanation is

    concerned : is it quite so certain as Taylor asserts that it involves noelement of will ?

    3. Finally, with regard to Taylor's conclusion, if there really is not that much of a

    difference between Abrahamic creation and Neoplatonic emanationism, a large chunk of the

    history of philosophy, and of the Pagan-Christian debate of Late Antiquity in particular,

    becomes incomprehensible. The Christian Church fathers virulently opposed the Neoplatonic

    doctrine of emanation for centuries, as can be seen, for instance, in the 6th-century debate

    between the Christian John Philoponus and the pagans Proclus and Simplicius in their debate

    over the eternity of the world, while the pagans opposed, with equal violence, the Christian

    doctrine of creation within time. Yet if these two views are really so close as to be ultimately

    compatible, what was all the fuss about12?

    1.2 Taylor's definitions

    11Taylor 2012, 131. The key word here, is, of course, after : in what sense are we to understand it ? There

    is, after all, a difference in Latin between ex nihiloandpost nihil, as Bonaventure points out (Commentary on the

    Sentences, II, d. 1, p. 1, a. 1, q. 2, II, p. 19 ff. Quaracchi), and the formulas of Catholic orthodox enshrine the

    formula ex nihilo,notpost nihil.

    12 Likewise, on Taylor's hypothesis it becomes hard to understand the conflict between Avicenna and

    Ghazali, and between the latter and Averroes, to say nothing of the debate between Bonaventure and Aquinas

    himself on the question of creation, which is inseparable from the question of the eternity of the world ; cf.Michon et al. 2004, 35 f.

  • 8/13/2019 Taylor.talk.Paris.may.2012.as Given

    6/33

  • 8/13/2019 Taylor.talk.Paris.may.2012.as Given

    7/33

    7

    goodness manifests itself in His creation, then it seems to follow that God can never not

    create, on pain of acting contrary to His essence, and this seems to rule out, or at least render

    problematic, the notion of a one-shot creation in time. This, at any rate, was the conclusion

    Origen drew, and it led him and many of his correligionaries to be condemned for heresy19.

    Such considerations would seem to shed at least some doubt on whether the Abrahamic God

    really is unconditionally free to create or to refrain from creating.

    Let us re-read Taylor's summarizing statement : Abrahamic creation, he writes,

    involves a single primary cause or First Cause originating all reality other than itself by bringing forth all

    ex nihilo as ontologically after absolute nothingness.

    At first glance, this statement seems to come close to tautology : if divine creation isex nihilo, then it cannot help but be ontologically after absolute nothingness. Surely

    everything that exists is automatically ontologically after absolute nothingness, since

    absolute nothingness could be defined as that beneath which nothing is ontologically. But one

    suspects the addition of the term ontologically is here to rule out another possible sense in

    which created reality might be later than nothingness : the temporal sense.

    I do not believe, however, that what Taylor describes is in fact the standard Abrahamic

    position, although it may be the standard Thomistic position. For the former, the sense in

    which creation is after nothingness is not, or not merely, ontological, but temporal. It is the

    Abrahamic tradition, or at least the great majority of its representatives20, that argues

    relentlessly for the temporal or chronological nature of the divine act of creation, and the

    Neoplatonists who argue for a version of ontologicalposterity, in the sense that for them, as

    19On this, cf. M. Chase, in press ; M. Wacht 1969.

    20

    Excluding Thomas Aquinas, of course. Cf. Oxford Dictionary of the Christian Church, 3rd ed. 1997,p. 429 : Though a doctrine of Creation does not as such require that the world took its beginning in or with

    time, Christian theologians in general have decisively rejected the eternity of the universe. But they have

    commonly held that its temporal origin is capable of being established only through revelation. This, of course,

    was the position of Aquinas (Cont. Gent. 2, 38, etc.). See also First Vatican Council, Sess. 3, can. 1 : Hic solus

    verus Deus bonitate sua et omnipotenti virtute non ad augendam suam beatitudinem, nec ad acquirendam, sed ad

    manifestandam perfectionem suam per bona, qu creaturis impertitur, liberrimo consilio simul ab initio temporis

    utramque de nihilo condidit creaturam, spiritualem et corporalem, angelicam videlicet et mundanam, ac deinde

    humanam quasi communem ex spiritu et corpore constitutam. The formula ab initio temporisdates back at least

    to the Fourth Council of the Lateran of 1215, according to which God is creator omnium visibilium et

    invisibilium, spiritalium et corporalium : qui sua omnipotenti virtute simul ab initio temporisutramque de nihilo

    condidit creaturam, spiritualem et corporalem (Denzinger, Enchiridion Symbolorum, no. 800). Michon et al.(2004, 353) translate ab initio temporisas au commencement du temps.

  • 8/13/2019 Taylor.talk.Paris.may.2012.as Given

    8/33

    8

    we shall see, the world is created or generated (Greek genton) not temporally but in the sense

    of causation (kat'aitian). This omission, or at least downplaying, of the temporal nature of

    Abrahamic creation is, I believe, perhaps the most questionable element in Taylor's

    argumentation21.

    1.3 What iscreation, anyhow ? Taylor on St. Thomas

    As good philosophers we ought, insofar as is possible, to define our terms at the

    outset. Taylor does not fail to do so, of course : for him, the word creation primarily

    translates the Arabic ibd", itself a rendering of the Latin creare. Taylor does not discuss the

    Greek equivalent of creare/ibd", but I think there can be little doubt that these terms

    correspond to the Greek verb gignesthai/genesthaiand to the verbal adjective genton, which

    one could render either as generated or as generable, subject to generation. This will

    prove to be of some importance as we proceed.

    One of the texts on which Taylor bases his claim that Abrahamic creation and

    Neoplatonic emanationism can both be called creation is a text from St. Thomas'

    commentary on the Sentences22. Famously, Peter Lombard had written :creare proprie est de

    nihilo alquid facere23. While Thomas sometimes seems to be willing to accept this

    definition24, in the text quoted by Taylor he brings in important qualifications :

    21In Taylor's paper, mentions of time as a factor in either Abrahamic creation or Neoplatonic emanation are

    restricted to a couple of footnotes and a brief mention at the very end of the article. At p. 131 n. 38, we read that

    al-Kindi's understanding of Divine creation as willed and as creation in time separates him from the others

    listed above, where the others include the PA, LDC, al-Kindi and al-Farabi. One could deduce from this, I

    suppose, that in Taylor's view these last-named philosophers do notview creation as taking place in time, but

    Taylor has, at least here, no more to say on the subject. At n. 39, Taylor writes that The criterion of temporal

    creation indicated in the third [variety of creation mentioned by Thomas] is shared with al-Kindi, though hereAquinas considers it something known only through Christian faith. Finally, in the very last parapraph of his

    article (p. 136), Taylor again points out that al-Kindi embraced not an eternal emanative creation2 but a

    doctrine of temporal creation by a divine willing in accord with Islamic religious teaching . This is, unless I'm

    mistaken, the only explicit acknowledgement in the entire article that Neoplatonic creation2 or emanation is

    eternal, while Abrahamic creation/creation1is temporal. Yet this point is of absolutely fundamental importance,

    as I shall try to show.

    22Commentary on the Sentences of Peter Lombard (1252-56), Book 2, dist. 1, q. 1, a. 2, solutio.

    23Sententiae lib. II, dist. 1, c. 2, vol. 1/2 p. 330.

    24 Other Thomistic definitions of creation include producere simpliciter ens and producere totum ens

    subsistens, nullo praesupposito (De pot. deiIII, I, c ; In VIII Phys. 974 f.). Yet the Angelic Doctor can also

    simply identify creation with emanation (hanc quidem emanationem designamus nomine creationis [S. th. I, 45,

  • 8/13/2019 Taylor.talk.Paris.may.2012.as Given

    9/33

    9

    the notion of creation involves two things. The first is that it presupposes nothing in the thing which is

    said to be created . . . creation is said to be from nothing because there is nothing which preexists creation

    as uncreated. The second is that in the thing which is said to be created non-being is prior to being, not by

    a priority of time or duration . . . but by a priority of nature in such a way that, if the created thing is left

    to itself, non-being would result. For it has being only from the influence of a superior cause.

    Taylor goes on, somewhat rashly I'm afraid, to claim25that

    These two criteria [ sc. that creation presupposes not-being and that the non-being of the created thing is

    not temporal but ontological - MC] are precisely those found in the account of primary causality in the

    LDC derived from Proclus and common to the teachings of Plotinus, Proclus, the PA, theLDC, al-Farabi,

    and Avicenna.

    I'm afraid that as far Plotinus and Proclus are concerned, this statement requires a good

    deal of qualification. Quite apart from the question of whether or not these Neoplatonists had

    a concept of creation at all this is of course the thesis that needs to be established it seems

    at first glance false that they would assent to Thomas' assertion that creation nihil

    praesupponat in re quae creari dicitur. Indeed, this seems to amount to imputing to them a

    doctrine of creatio ex nihilowhich neither Greek philosopher would have accepted, although,

    as Endress has shown, the Arabic adapter of Proclus' Elements of Theologydoes interpolate

    the doctrine into his version of Proclus' Proposition 7626.

    Thomas' notion that creation presupposes nothing in the thing which is said to be

    created is, however, similar to one of the seven meanings of creation distinguished by Greek

    Middle- and Neoplatonists, where it is attributed to Aristotle and denied of Plato. The second

    sense of creation mentioned here by Thomas here, moreover, corresponds another of the

    I, c] ; ...productio universalis entis a Deo non sit motus nec mutatio, sed sit quaedam simplex emanatio [In VIII

    Phys.no. 974]). Cf. Kremer 19712, 419 n. 46 ; 421.25Taylor 2012, 132.

    26Cf. Endress 1973 and Chase, in press, where I also suggest that Porphyry may have accepted some variety

    of the doctrine of creationex nihilo. Another interpretation may be possible, however : perhaps by his use of the

    verbpraesupponatThomas may be referring to the Greek idea that the Demiurge's creation of the world in time

    in the Timaeus is merely kath'hupothesin (by hypothesis) or didaskalias heneka (for the sake of instruction).

    That is, as the Neoplatonists held, Plato may have meant to present eternal realities as occurring within time

    after all, Plotinus informs us that this is always the function of myth like geometers describe the construction

    of geometrical figures although their existence is eternal, in order to show what great benefits the world receives

    from the World Soul. See, for instance, Enn. IV 8 [6] 38-42 : B #

  • 8/13/2019 Taylor.talk.Paris.may.2012.as Given

    10/33

    10

    seven senses in which Greek exegetes of Plato explained the gegonen at Timaeus28B7f. I

    therefore propose a brief return to the land of Hellas, so that we may better understand the

    background of Thomas' conception.

    1.4 Calvisius Taurus and Porphyry on the meanings of genton

    In commenting on the Timaeus, the Middle Platonist Calvinus Taurus27of Beirut (fl. c.

    145AD) distinguished four meanings of the Greek word generated (gentos).

    As we can see in Table 3, these meanings include (1) what is not generated but has the

    same genus as generated things ; such things are gentain the sense that an object hidden in

    the center of the earth can still be said to be visible (Greek horaton), even if it will never

    actually be seen. The second meaning (2) covers what is notionally but not actually

    composite : things, that is, that can be analysed in thought into their component parts. The

    third meaning (3) of gentos concerns what's always in the process of becoming ; that is,

    according to Platonic philosophy, the whole of the sublunar world, which is subject to

    constant change. Finally (4), gentos can mean what derives its being from elsewhere ; in

    other words from God. In a similar sense, the moon's light may be said to be generated by the

    sun, although there has never been a time when this was not the case. Note that the important

    feature here is that cause and effect are simultaneous and co-eternal (Greek sunaidios).

    Slightly more than a century later, the Neoplatonist philosopher Porphyry (c. 234-c.

    310) added additional meanings of gentos(Table 4) : these include (5) : what has the logos

    of generation, i.e. what can be analysed in thought28. Meaning no. (6) covers sensible objects

    like houses, ships, plants and animals, which obtain their being through a process of

    generation. Finally, the seventh and last meaning (7) of gentosis what begins to exist in time

    after not having existed. It's this last meaning of generated that Porphyry denies is

    applicable to Plato's creation story in the Timaeus29.

    27Cf. W. Baltes 1976, 105-121 ; M.-L. Lakmann 1995.

    28 It must be admitted that it's not terribly clear what the difference is between this meaning and Taurus'

    meaning no. 2, except that Porphyry adds the crucial example of what is composed out of matter and form.

    29 If one can judge from the fragments cited by Philoponus, Porphyry himself believes that constituted

    (suntheton) of form and matter is the most appropriate interpretation of gentosin Plato's Timaeus ; cf. Drrie-Baltes V, 1998, 440.

  • 8/13/2019 Taylor.talk.Paris.may.2012.as Given

    11/33

    11

    It seems clear, then, that in the passage just cited, Thomas first takes up Porphyry's

    definition no. 7 (What begins to exist in time, after having not existed), and then, when

    discussing the second meaning of creation in the text cited above, he follows Calvisius

    Taurus' meaning no. 4 : the world is created (Greek genton) in the sense that it derives its

    being from elsewhere (Thomas : For it has being only from the influence of a superior

    cause). According to Proclus, this sense is equivalent to being generated causally

    (kat'aitian)30. This idea, originating in the interpretation of Timaeus 29E4-30A1 and

    formulated by Plotinus31and then by Porphyry (see Text A below)32, amounts to claiming that

    the world is not autonomous as far as its existence is concerned, but always implies a causal

    principle superior to itself33. To say the word is generated kat'aitianis equivalent to saying it

    has its being in becoming, as was held by a number of Middle Platonists 34, and by Plotinus

    himself35. The kat'aitian interpretation is, moreover, equivalent to the interpretation of

    gentonas designating that which is composite or at least analysable into its parts (Tauros'

    meaning no. 2 = Porphyry's meaning no. 5), insofar as what is compound implies the

    existence of a higher cause (aitia) that put it together36.

    By adopting meanings no. 4 and 7, Thomas Aquinas is thus picking up on the tradition

    of the Late Antique Neoplatonic commentators, as exemplified by Simplicius. According to

    the latter in his Commentary on the Physics37, by generated (genton) Aristotle means what

    previously does not exist, but later comes into existence or is generated (i.e., meaning no. 7).

    30 Proclus, apud Philop., De aet. mundi, VI, 8, p. 148, 5-7 'G"D9#*H"49?-:+) "5)I,F"D)*#!)-"5),.#!+)"5)E4:7') ... E*>J"+#!)-"5)K9L%5&!'M#!)47!)')E*>'HE*H"5)N*2"O"'M!P)*+*Q"+')R)"*, #$%&'()*+),-.) ./)0.+1%+2),+%3+.4. Proclus is probably, here as often, following Porphyry,who declares in his Sentence 14 that everything generated has its the cause of its generation from something

    else (IS)#!)-"5)=% T,,'2"U)*V"(*)"W9#!).:!D9J3!+).

    31EnneadsII 4 [12], 5, 25 ff. ; IV 3 [27] 8, 30 ff. ; V 2 [11], 1, 5 ff. ; V 6 [24], 5, 5 ff. Cf. W. Baltes 1976,126 ff. ; Drrie-Baltes V, 1998, 428.

    32Ap. Philop.,De aet. mundi6, 17, p. 172, 5 ff. Rabe ; ap. Proclus,In Tim., I, 277, 10 ff. Diehl. Cf. Porphyry,

    Sent. 14 ; fr. 459 Smith ; Baltes 1976, 143 ff.

    33On this view, which goes back to Xenocrates' student Crantor of Soli, see Drrie-Baltes V, 1998, 437 ff.

    34 Philo, Plutarch, Tauros, Alcinoos, the anonymous Plationists cited by Alexander of Aphrodisias and

    Philoponus. For references cf. Drrie-Baltes V, 1998, 438 and notes.

    35E.g., VI 7 [38] 3, 1 ff.

    36 Baltes 1976, 144, who points out the Middle Platonic antecedents to this view (Albinus, Tauros,

    Hippolytus).37Simpl.,In Phys., 1154, 2 ff.

  • 8/13/2019 Taylor.talk.Paris.may.2012.as Given

    12/33

    12

    Plato, in contrast, means by generated what has its being in becoming (meaning no. 6) and

    derives its being from another cause (meaning no. 4).

    What follows from these considerations, then, as far as the legitimacy of the

    conclusion reached by Taylor, following Thomas, is concerned, viz. that both Abrahamic

    creationism and Neoplatonic emanation can legitimately be considered forms of creation ?

    I think we can say that Simplicius would not have been impressed. He would have

    objected against T&T that they are committing the same error, or tactical ruse, as Philoponus.

    By playing on the ambiguity of the term created/genton, they are conflating two quite

    different meanings of the term and claiming that these meanings are, caeteris paribus, the

    same thing. In a sense, of course, they arethe same thing, or rather they are closely related.

    The two meanings of genton : coming into existence after not having existed (Aristotle)

    and owing its existence to a higher causal principle (Plato) do in fact bear a kind of

    Wittgensteinian family resemblance, which is why they can both be designated by the same

    term. But to go on to deduce from this that the two phenomena have anything substantial in

    common besides their name is to commit a fallacy of equivocation. Plato and Aristotle do

    *not* mean the same thing by genton, Simplicius would say, and it is *not* the same thing

    for a thing (a) to exist after having not existed (Latin post nihil), and for it (b) to owe its

    existence to a higher causal principle. Pagan Neoplatonists would assert (b) and deny (a) ;

    orthodox Christians, such as Thomas, might very well assert both (a) and (b) conjointly.

    Finally, before leaving the passage from Thomas cited and analysed by Taylor, it is

    worthwhile returning to the continuation of the passage quoted above :

    However, if we take a third to be required for the notion of creation so that in duration

    the thing created has non-being before being so that it is said to be from nothing because it is temporally

    after nothing, creation cannot be demonstrated in this way nor is this conceded by the philosophers, but is

    supposed by faith.

    I take it that Thomas is acknowledging here that there is a third definition of creation

    in addition to the two he has just enumerated. This one insists that the sense in which created

    things are after nothing is temporal, and this meaning, as Thomas acknowledges, rejected

    by the philosophers. Yet this third definition, which Thomas mentions almost in passing, is

    surely the standard Abrahamic position : it is the one Philoponus defended at great length,

    first against Proclus, then against Aristotle, and which Simplicius in turn attempted to refute

  • 8/13/2019 Taylor.talk.Paris.may.2012.as Given

    13/33

    13

    in his commentaries on the De Caeloand the Physics. It is also the position of Bonaventure,

    against whom Thomas may well be reacting here.

    Thomas' position, then, seems to amount to saying that Christian creation and

    Neoplatonic emanation are compatible if we leave the question of time out of consideration.

    This also seems to be Taylor's position. Whether or not such a bracketing is legitimate is,

    however, quite another question38.

    2. 1 Free will and necessity

    We have not yet dealt with the question of free will and necessity ; yet we must, for

    we recall that according to Taylor, although both Abrahamic creation and Neoplatonic

    emanationism are forms of creation, they are distinguished, presumably exclusively, by the

    fact that Abrahamic creation is a free act of divine will, free of every kind of necessity, while

    Neoplatonic emanationism involves no act of will at all, and is subject to at least one of

    Taylor's three kinds of necessity.

    As far as Neoplatonist creation is concerned, Taylor stresses, as we have seen, that

    created reality emanates directly from the First Principle without any act of will or any other

    intermediary, but by the very being of that Cause (Greek auti ti einai, Arabic bi-ann!yati-

    hi) . He concludes from this that the very existence of the first cause immediately and

    automatically entails, by a process of emanation, the existence of all subsequent levels of

    reality.

    We are on very slippery territory here, for there are clearly tensions within the

    Neoplatonism itself, and especially Plotinus, as far as the question of will is concerned, so my

    discussion will make even less claim here than elsewhere to be definitive. On the one hand, it

    cannot be denied that creation auti ti einaiis a key element in post-Plotinian Neoplatonic

    thought, not just since Proclus and the Pseudo-Dionysius, as Cristina D'Ancona has often

    38The Taylor/Aquinas position would seem to amount to one of the doctrines identified as heretical, or at

    least dangerous, by tienne Tempier and condemned in 1277 (vol. I, p. 549, no. 99 Denifle/Chatelain = 83

    Mandonnet/Hissette) : Quod mundus, licet sit factus de nichilo, non tamen est factus de novo ; et quamvis de

    non esse exierit in esse, tamen non esse non precessit esse duratione sed natura tantum (The world, although

    created out of nothing, was nevertheless not originated ; and although it emerged from not-being to being, yetnot-being did not precede being with regard to duration, but only with regard to nature.

  • 8/13/2019 Taylor.talk.Paris.may.2012.as Given

    14/33

    14

    argued, but since Porphyry39. Plotinus does indeed sometimes speak as if the One, the Good,

    or the First lacked will40. It is just as undeniable, however, that the Neoplatonists, following

    Plato himself in the Timaeus, devote a great deal of discussion to the role of the Demiurge's

    will in the process of the world's creation41.

    At this juncture, it is perhaps worthwile studying in detail a couple of very densely

    argued pages of Taylor's paper42, which I believe are key to his entire thesis. In what follows I

    will quote selections from these passages and intersperse them with my responses.

    Transcendental necessity or necessity1, argues Taylor, is beyond the nature of will

    where will might denote deliberation, choice, or weighing of alternatives, characteristics of

    human will and action. It then does not involve a selection between alternatives.

    MC : So far, so good. For Plotinus and Proclus, the One clearly does not deliberate or

    hesitate. Yet all we are entitled to conclude from this, I would argue, is that if the One has a

    will, it does not resemble human will, any more than human intellection resembles the

    hypernosis (EnneadsVI 8, 16, 32) of the Good43. This does not, however, prove that the

    One/Good/First lacks any and everykind of will.

    Rather, Taylor continues,

    reality under necessity1involves what cannot be otherwisethan the overflowing of reality from the Firstas the Good (...) This form of origination or ibd"(creatio) then, does not allow for the possibility of astopping or denialof the emanation of reality from the First.

    39See Chase 2011 ; in press ; Drrie-Baltes 1998, 472 and n. 46. Creating through being what a thing is is

    characteristic of entities whose being is pure actuality (energeia).

    40V 1, 6, 15-27 ; VI 9, 6, 40. With regard to the latter passage, however, Georges Leorux (1990, 57) specifiesthat ce n'est donc qu'une volont de besoin et de dsir, volont de fins particulires, qui est nie. For Leroux,

    the will that can be attributed to the One, in a positive theology that provides the necessary counterpart to the

    negative theology that denies it, is a will that is intransitive, i.e. that has itself as its primary object.

    41The role of the will of the Demiurge is accentuated even more in Plotinus's successors that it is in Plotinus.

    Porphyry and Iamblichus (ap. Proclum,In Tim., 1, 382, 18 ff. Diehl) reject the doctrine of Atticus and Plutarch

    because, among other reasons, it completely eliminates the Demiurge's benevolent will ( tn agathoeid boulsin

    autou to parapan anairousan).

    42Taylor 2012, 129-130.

    43 According to Iamblichus, De Myst. I, 12, the divine will of the Good surpasses the life of ordinary

    deliberation and choice (h t'agathou theia boulsis ts proairetiks huperekhei zs), translationClarke/Dillon/Hershbell, who remark (p. 51 n. 76) on the difficulty of translating this phrase.

  • 8/13/2019 Taylor.talk.Paris.may.2012.as Given

    15/33

    15

    MC: Cannot, does not allow, and possibility are the key terms here ; we shall

    investigate their possible meanings more closely below.

    After adding that the First Cause, since it lacks form, does not act through the

    necessity of a nature or form44, Taylors goes on to add :

    To this extent, then, it [sc. causal activity under necessity1, and hence Neoplatonic-style emanation] does

    not fit under Hasker's conception of creation1, which he characterizes as common to the monotheistic

    religions of Judaism, Christianity and Islam [...] a free act on God's part ; he has no need to create but

    has done so out of love and generosity.

    M.C. A couple of remarks seem in order here. Hasker, whom Taylor is following here,

    seems to be presupposing that eitherGod has a need to create orhe does so out of love and

    generosity ; only in the latter case would God's act be free. Now, for Taylor, the fact that ittakes place auti ti einaiexcludes Neoplatonic emanation from this category of creation1.

    This must be because he considers that such emanation is not free, or, in Hasker's

    terminology, that it implies or entails a needto create on the part of the First Principle.

    For Plotinus, however, there can be no question of the First Principle's having any

    need to create. As perfect and self-sufficient, the One has no needs at all, not even the need

    to reveal or manifest itself, and not even to create. Plotinus consistently describes the

    One/Good as anendeswithout need45. Indeed, the One can be described as that which is

    most without need (anendeestaton)46. And as Augustine reminds us, where there is no need,

    there can be no necessity47. Perhaps, then, the dichotomy free act of creation vs. necessitated

    act of creation is more complex that Hasker thought.

    As far as the alleged absence of divine will in Neoplatonic emanation is concerned, for

    Plotinus, God's boulsis is the cause of the eternal world48, or of the nous49. The difficult

    paradox that creation occurs automatically and at the same time through the will of the First

    Principle is, of course, the subject of Plotinus' EnneadVI.8, and the role of the Demiurge's

    44See my objections to this claim, above n. 00.

    45I 8, 2, 4 ; III 8, 11, 42 ; V 6, 4, 1 ; VI 7, 23, 8 ; VI 9, 6, 35 ; VI 8, 6, 35.

    46VI 9, 6, 18

    47Aug.De div. quaest. 83, quaest. 22, p. 26 Mutzenbecher : Ubi nulla indigentia, nulla necessitas : ubi nullus

    defectus, nulla indigentia. Nullus autem defectus in Deo ; nulla ergo necessitas.

    48II 1, 1 (40), II 1, 1, 2-4 ; II 1, 1, 34-37 ; III 8, 9, 16 ff.49VI 8, 17, 20 ff. ; VI 8, 18, 38-43.

  • 8/13/2019 Taylor.talk.Paris.may.2012.as Given

    16/33

    16

    will as a factor in creation is stressed even more in such fifth-century pagan Neoplatonists as

    Hierocles and Proclus50. For Plotinus, in a word and here one cannot avoid betraying the

    subtlety and complexity of a truly profound work the will of God or the One is identical to

    his substance, essence, and freedom51. The One does not exist just any old way, but as it

    wills ; likewise, it produces not randomly, but as it wills52.

    The role of divine will in Neoplatonic emanation can probably not be stated with more

    clarity than it was by the late Matthias Baltes :

    The Will of God is nothing other than the fulfillment [teleisis, one might also translate by perfection or

    completion - MC] of his essence (ousia), that is, his goodness (agathots), which realizes itself

    (energei) in willing (boulsis) and creation (poisis). For God is goodness that wills to communicate

    itself, and does so53.

    As far as the Abrahamic tradition is concerned, although God creates through a free

    decision of his will, uninfluenced by any kind of necessity, he must still, like every rational

    being, have a motive for his actions. Thomas' master Albertus Magnus makes this clear 54:

    when something is produced not by natural necessity, but through freedom of will, the knowledge and

    power of the agent do not suffice for production (...) but it is necessary that the appetitite of the will be

    inclined toward the production of the thing (...) but that by which the will is inclined to action is the

    goodness of the first agent ; and therefore it is proper to his goodness to educe things by creation.

    For Thomas Aquinas as well, as for the Neoplatonists, it is of the nature of the Good to

    communicate itself55. Ultimately, for Plotinus, God wished to produce the world precisely

    50Already for Plotinus' assistant Amelius (ap. Proclus, In Tim., I, 361, 25), one of the three Demiurges acts

    by will alone (boulsei monon) ; Proclus corrects him by affirming that one and the same Demiurge makes

    everything through his goodness by means of his will (X#

  • 8/13/2019 Taylor.talk.Paris.may.2012.as Given

    17/33

    17

    because he was good and was without any kind of need, and this motivation is ultimately not

    terribly far removed from that adduced by Thomas56. It is true that Plotinus often says that

    creation takes place by the nature of necessity57but he may be referring58by this only to the

    law that all that is perfect produces an image similar to itself : natural things necessarily,

    spiritual beings consciously and deliberately on the basis of purely moral necessity.

    2.2 Leibniz on free will and necessity

    We recall that for Richard Taylor, Abrahamic creation is free of all the three kinds of

    necessity, while Neoplatonic emanation, although free from the necessity of external

    compulsion (necessity3) and the necessity characteristic of things having a nature or form

    (necessity2), is still subject to transcendent necessity (necessity1), in the sense that no

    possibility exists of stopping or denying the emanation of reality from the First.

    Klaus Kremer has an alternative discussion of necessity, which he takes from Leibniz.

    For Leibniz, there is logical or metaphysical necessity in the fact that the angles of a triangle

    are equal to two right angles, and this is the way God produces the world according to

    Spinoza59. Unlike such absolute necessity, physical necessity, the kind by which fire warms

    and ice cools, does allow its contrary. Finally, moral necessity does not eliminate freedom,

    but presupposes it. It is this kind of necessity according to which the most perfect beings,

    since they act in the most perfect way, must choose what is best, and wise, virtuous people

    must act in accordance with their wisdom and virtue. Such necessity, although it

    presupposes knowledge and will, is not opposed to freedom. If what is contrary to God's

    choice implied a contradiction, then this would imply metaphysical necessity and eliminate

    His freedom. In the words of Leibniz :

    55Cf. Kremer 1965, 262-263, citing In DN nr. 136 ; 36 ; nnr. 213 ; 227 ; 229 ; 269 ; S. th. 1 11 1, 4 ad 1um ;

    2 II 117, 6 ad 2um; I 106, 4, c. l C.G. II ; I 37 (fin.) ; III 24 ; I Sent. IV 1, 1, so. ; II 1, 4 contra ; S. th. III 1, 1, c.

    56Kremer 1965, 264, citingDe pot. DeiI 5 ad 14 um : Optima ratio, qua Deus omnia facit, est sua bonitas et

    sua sapientia, quae manerent, etiam si alia vel alio modo faceret. Cf. Kremer 1987, 1029, citing S. th. I 19, 4 ad

    3um : bonitas est ei ratio volendi omnia alia.

    57phuses anankiIII 2, 2, 8 ff. ; III, 2, 3, 35 ; II 9, 8, 20-29 ; II 9, 8, 3.

    58Kremer 1987, 1015.59Spiniza,Ethics, note to prop. 17.

  • 8/13/2019 Taylor.talk.Paris.may.2012.as Given

    18/33

    18

    Il y a donc en Dieu une libert, exemte non seulement de la contrainte, mais encore de la ncessit. Jel'entends de la ncessit mtaphysique ; car c'est une ncessit morale, que le plus sage soit oblig dechoisir le meilleur60.

    (...) c'est la bont qui porte Dieu crer, afin de se communiquer ; et cette mme bont jointe la sagesse

    le porte crer le meilleur : cela comprend toute la suite, l'effect et les voyes. Elle l'y porte sans lenecessiter, car elle ne rend point impossible ce qu'elle ne fait point choisir.

    Applied to Plotinus, then, Leibniz's thesis would mean that the One, as highest good,

    mut communicate its goodness to other things in a way analogous to that in which a moral

    person must behave morally, but this must does not mean absolute necessity or

    necessitation, since there would be no contradiction in supposing that God did not choose to

    communicate himself61. Plotinus' One, argues Kremer, is free in the same sense as Thomas'

    God : since it is already perfect and without no need, it creates non-necessarily.

    3.0 Conclusion : Porphyrian Neoplatosism on temporal vs. causal creation

    Finally, since I've often stressed, throughout this presentation, that Taylor

    underestimates the importance of the distinction between temporal and timeless creation, I'd

    like to briefly discuss a few Neoplatonic texts to back up my claim. They all interpret Plato's

    account of the Demiurge's creation in the Timaeusas occurring in a causal, not a temporalsense. The first one is explicitly attributed to Porphyry, and Matthias Baltes 62 has argued

    persuasively that the others go back to him, too. In Text A, Porphyry denies that Plato gives

    the world a temporal origin. In things that are causally dependent (i.e., presumably,

    everything except the First Cause, and therefore including the world), existence need not

    presuppose a temporally pre-existent state of nothingness ; note the direction contradiction

    here with the claim of Thomas Aquinas as cited by Taylor). This is another way of asserting,

    as in our texts from Augustine and Philoponus, that in the sensible world some effects co-exist eternally with their causes. In turn, this amounts to claiming that the world is generated

    in a causal, not a temporal sense (kat' aitian, all' ou kata khronon).

    60Leibniz, Thodice, 230.

    61 Indeed, in at least one passage (Ennead IV 8 [6] 6, 1-8), Plotinus, says not that the procession of beings

    cannotbe stopped, but that it ought notto be stopped (ouk edei stsai), as if it were circumscribed by jealousy.

    Again, the impossibility of stopping or refraining from creation is moral, not logical or metaphysical in nature.62Baltes 1976, 163 ff.

  • 8/13/2019 Taylor.talk.Paris.may.2012.as Given

    19/33

    19

    In Text B, taken from the same book of the City of God in which he summarizes

    Porphyry'sLetter to Anebo, Augustine affirms that some Platonists interpret Plato as saying

    that the creation of the world takes place not in time, but from eternity, just as an eternal foot

    might leave an eternal footprint : both would exist simultaneously, and yet it would be clear

    that one was a cause, the other an effect. It is thus quite possible for a cause to be co-eternal

    with its effect63.

    In our Text C, Philoponus, who believes God did create the world in time, explains

    how God can always be good even if he does not always create. If he does not do so, it is not

    because of God's unwillingness or inability, but because the very nature of creation requires it

    to come into existence after not having existed. He attests the Neoplatonic image of sun

    emitting light and bodies casting a shadow, an image, probably deriving from Porphyry,

    intended to illustrate the simultaneity or co-eternity of cause and effect64.

    This analogy also shows an important difference from Christian notions of creation, as

    we see in Text D. Here, Aeneas of Gaza confirms, that the Platonists hold the world is

    generated causally (genton kat'aitian). They deny, however, that the Demiurge made

    (pepoiken) the world, any more that my body makes its shadow : on the contrary, as a

    shadow follows upon or accompanies (sunakolouthsen) my body, so the sensible world

    follows upon the Demiurge65. Here, at any rate, Abrahamic creationism and Neoplatonic

    emanationism seem far apart, so much so that it does not seem licit to speak of the latter as

    creation at all.

    63Origen also held that God's creation was sunaidioswith him, a position that was duly anathematized. See

    Chase, in press.

    64This analogy of divine emanation or creation to such natural processes as the sun emitting light or bodies

    casting shadows was dangerous for the Neoplatonists, in that it could tend to imply the kind of automatic andnecessary nature of emanation with which the Christians reproached them. On the Neoplatonic use of this image,

    see M. Wacht 1969, 73-74. W. Theiler 1966 traces it back to Porphyry.

    65Basil of Caesarea comes dangerously close to this view when he speaks (Homiliae in hexaemeron, I, 6-7)

    of how the world comes into existence timelessly, together with the will of God (X7'M "\Y'2,Z:!+ "'M]!'M=3$4)D9:2)2?!:"F)*+"5)E4:7')). Yet Basil comes down hard on those who refuse to concede thatthe world was generated by Him, but came into existence as a kind of shadow of his power, as it were

    automatically (^*>E*&4"+%',,'>"8)?*)"*:&.)"D):2)2%F$3!+)C/=01('2"O]!O"5)E4:7'), 'H3>#!#!)W:&*+%*$ *H"'M:2)!3_$-:*), =,, '`')!>=%':E(*:7*"W912)F7!D9*H"'MR)"**H"'7F"D9%*$2%':"W)*+). Basil's text was translated more or less word for word in Ambrose's Hexaemeron (I, 1, 5, 18),

    whence it was no doubt known to Augustine.

  • 8/13/2019 Taylor.talk.Paris.may.2012.as Given

    20/33

    20

    Our Text E, from the dialogue Ammonios by Zacharias of Mytilene, gives reasons

    why God's creation cannot be co-eternal with Him : if it were, it would be equally worthy of

    worship (homotimos).

    Finally, our Text F, from a lost work On Providenceby the Alexandrian Neoplatonist

    Hierocles, a contemporary of Proclus, is interesting in that Hierocles raises against the Middle

    Platonists who gave a literal interpretation of the creation story in the Timaeusthe same, or at

    least very similar, arguments that Proclus and Simplicius raised against the Christine doctrine

    of creation within time. If the Demiurge, according to Timaeus42E, remains in his customary

    state (en ti heautou thei kata tropon menn), then he must remain unchanging66, which rules

    out any temporal act of creation, since this would imply a change or shift on his part from

    non-creation to creation67. If it was better not to create, then how could could the Demiurge

    shift (metabainein), as it were, into creation mode ? If it were better to create, why didn't he

    create from perpetuity68?

    In conclusion, then, I have to say that I disagree with Taylor's assertion that both

    Christian creation and Neoplatonic emanation and usefully and legitimately be called

    creation. Creation, as it is usually understood in the Abrahamic world, is usually understood

    as ex nihilo and temporal. For the Neoplatonists in contrast, as for virtually the entire

    millenium-long Greek philosophical tradition, ex nihilo nihilfit, and emanation neither takes

    place within time nor does it begin from a temporal starting-point. Finally, the role Taylor and

    many others assign to divine will in creation as a specific difference between Abrahamic

    creation and Neoplatonic emanation is a bit of a red herring. It is doubtful that God's will is

    entirely free for thinkers like Thomas Aquinas, and it is false that will plays no role in

    Neoplatonic emanation. It does indeed seem paradoxical to maintain, as does Plotinus, that

    the First Principle creates both by free will and by its own being or essence. In fact, however,

    as long as we recall that we are not talking about the same kindof will in the case of the First

    as in the case of human beings, this paradox can be understood : for in the case of the One or

    the Good, will and being are simply identical69.

    66 For this doctrine in Plotinus, cf. Kremer 19712 4-5, with references n. 18. Only the soul is altered as it

    creates.

    67Drrie-Baltes 1998, 470 ; Baltes 1996.

    68Cf., with Drrie-Baltes ad loc., Augustine, Conf. 11, 10, 12, probably following Porphyry.69Drrie-Baltes 1998, 472 n. 46.

  • 8/13/2019 Taylor.talk.Paris.may.2012.as Given

    21/33

    21

  • 8/13/2019 Taylor.talk.Paris.may.2012.as Given

    22/33

    22

    Tables

    Table 1 : Taylor on types of necessity

    Type of necessity characteristics applicability to

    Abrahamic creation

    applicability to

    Neoplatonicemanation

    3 external compulsion no no

    2 necessity of nature,

    characteristic of

    things that possess a

    nature or form

    no no

    1 transcendent ; effectfollows necessarily

    upon positing ofcause

    no yes

    Table 2: Athanasius on the generation of the Son and the creation of the world

    Type of creation relation to God'sessence

    relation to God's will relation to time

    poima(world) outside divine

    essence

    dependent in time

    gennma(Son) idion ts ousias

    gennma/ex autou

    phusei gennmemon

    not dependent eternal

    Table 3

    Calvinus Taurus apud Philoponum aet. mundi, p. 145, 13-147, 25 Rabe on the

    meanings of genton :

    Meanings of gentos examples

    1. what was not generated, but

    belongs to same genus as generated things

    body in center of the earth (visible,

    but will never actually be seen)

  • 8/13/2019 Taylor.talk.Paris.may.2012.as Given

    23/33

    23

    2. what is composite by virtue of a

    thought experiment, even if not composite in

    actuality

    middle note of the musical scale from

    the highest and the lowest, flowers, animals

    3. what is always in a process of

    becoming

    sublunar elements

    4. what derives its being from

    elsewhere (viz., from God)

    moon derives its light from the sun

    (although there's never been a time when it

    did not do so)

    Table 4

    Porphyry apud Philoponum aet. mundi, VI, 8, p. 148, 7 ff. Rabe on the meanings of

    gentos :

    meanings of gentos examples

    5. That which has the logos of

    generation

    (= Taurus meaning 2?)

    words, syllables (decomposable into

    letters) ; geometrical figures (rectilinear

    figures decomposable into triangles),

    compounds of matter and form

    6. What receives its being through

    generation and becoming

    house, ship, plant, animal (snap of

    fingers, flash of lightning : come into

    existence without any process of generation)

    7. What begins to exist in time, after

    having not existed

    most familiar meaning, but Plato

    didn't apply it to the world

  • 8/13/2019 Taylor.talk.Paris.may.2012.as Given

    24/33

    24

    Chase, Abrahamic creation and Neoplatonic emanation

    in Greek, Arabic and Latin.

    Texts

    Text A

    Porphyry ap. Sharastani p. 492 = t. II,

    p. 357-358 Jolivet-Monnot

    Porphyry, fr. 459, p. 529-351 Smith70.

    wa yadaa anna allaai yubkc an

    AflAden min al-qawl bi-budefal-Alam ghayr

    gabcbqAl fcrisAla ilAAnAbAne: wa-ammAmA

    faraqa bihi AflAden71 indakum min annahu

    yahau li-l-Alam ibtidA zamAniyyan72 fa-

    dawAkAaiba. wa-aalika anna AflAden laysa

    (yarA) anna li-l-Alam ibtidA zamAniyyan

    lakinna ibtidA alAjiha al-alla, wa yazamu

    anna alla kawnihi ibtidAuhi73, wa-qad raa

    anna al-mutawahhim alayhi fcqawlihi anna

    al-Alam maileq wa-innahu badafa lA min

    jay, wa-innahu iaraja min lA nikAm ilA

    nikAm fa-qad aida wa lalida, wa-aAlika

    annahu lAyagabbu dAimAn, anna kull adam

    And he claimed that the statement

    attributed to Plato concerning the world's

    coming into being is not correct. He said in

    his letter to Anebo76 : what separates Plato

    from you, viz. that he gives the world a

    temporal beginning, is a mendacious

    assertion. This is because Plato did not think

    that the world has a temporal origination77,

    but an origination with regard to a cause ;

    and he claimed that the cause of its existence

    is its origination78. He was of the opinion that

    whoever had the illusion that his view was

    that the world was created and that it had

    come into being ex nihilo, and that it had

    70I have considerably modified the translation by Wasserstein (in Smith, Porphyrius Fragmenta), in the light

    of the alternative versions by Jolivet-Monnot (Livre des religions et des sectes, trad. avec introd. et notes par

    Daniel Gimaret, Jean Jolivet et Guy Monnot, 2. vols., Leuven : Peeters Paris : Unesco, 1986-1993 [Collection

    Unesco d'oeuvres reprsentatives. Srie arabe, vol.1]) (J/L) and by Gabrieli (in A. R. Sodano, ed., Porphyrii in

    Platonis Timaeum commentariorum fragmenta, Napoli 1964) (G).

    71 Ce dont on accuse Platon chez vous (J/L), quanto a ci di cui presso di voi si a torto accusato

    Platone (G)

    72 commencement temporel (J/L).

    73 la cause de son existence est son commencement (J/L), e che la causa del suo nascere debbaconsiderarsi come suo principio (G)

  • 8/13/2019 Taylor.talk.Paris.may.2012.as Given

    25/33

    25

    aqdamu min al-wujed fc-mA alla wujedihi

    jay Aiar layrihi74 wa lA kull se nikAm

    aqdam min al-nikAm wa-innamA yanc

    AflAden anna al-iAliq akhara al-Alam min al-

    adam ilA-l-wujed, wajada75 innahu lam

    yakun min /493/ aAtihi lakinna sabab

    wujedihi min al-iAliq.

    emerged from disorder into order79 - such a

    person has erred and been deluded. That is

    because it is not always true that all non-

    existence precedes existence in that which

    has the cause of its existence in something

    else80; nor is all lack of order prior to order.

    But by saying that the creator revealed the

    world from non-existence into existence,

    Plato merely meant that it does not exist by

    itself, but the cause of its existence is from

    the creator.

    Text B

    74 il n'est pas vrai toujours que toute sorte de non-tre prcde l'existence en ce qui a sa cause en une autre

    chose que lui (J/L).

    75 s'il est patent que... (J/L) ; Platone col dire che il Creatore trasse il mondo dal non essere all'essere

    volle solo intendere che il suo essere non fu di per s stesso (G). The latter is the interpretation I have followed.

    76 Sodano believed this reference was incorrect, and that the quotation in fact comes from Porphyry's

    Commentary on the Timaeus. Yet there seems to be no good reason to doubt mahrastAnc's express testimony. TheLetter to Anebowas well known in the Arabic-speaking world, as it was to Augustine, who gives an account of it

    in civ. Dei10, 11.

    77For the translation of ibtid"by origination I follow Zimmermann 1986, 198, who remarks on the term's

    frequency in the Theology of Aristotle. Cf. also al-Kindi, Epistle on the quantity of Aristotle's books, p. 410 f.

    Guidi-Walzer, who translate the term by creare dal nulla. Lizzini 2009 prefers far iniziare. Compare the

    Latin factum esse de novo, above, n. 00

    78 By this phrase, Porphyry may have meant something analogous to Augustine's non esse hoc videlicet

    temporis, sed substitutionis initium (see text B) : in the Timaeus, Plato depicts not a temporal origin for the

    world, but the origin of its hypostasis/substitutio : that is, its concrete existence. On this meaning of hypostasis,

    cf. Chase 2009-2010.79 A reference to Timaeus 30A, where Plato depicts the Demiurge's imposition of order on the disorderly

    motion of the khra. In Porphyry's preserved comments on this passage, Porphyry denies that what appears to be

    described as preceding and subsequent stages in Demiurge's creative activity can be understood as temporal :

    this is merely a pedagogical tactic on Plato's part to enhance the clarity of the exposition. As Baltes comments

    (1976, 152) : Es folgt daraus nichts fr ein reales Frher oder Spter im Schpfungs-geschehen : alles ist

    vielmehr immer zusammen.

    80In things that are causally dependent (i.e., presumably, everything except the First Cause), existence need

    notpresuppose a temporally pre-existent state of nothingness. This is another way of asserting, as in our texts

    from Augustine and Philoponus, that in the sensible world some effects co-exist eternally with their causes. In

    turn, this amounts to claiming that the world is generated in a causal, not a temporal sense (kat' aitian, all' oukata khronon).

  • 8/13/2019 Taylor.talk.Paris.may.2012.as Given

    26/33

    26

    Aug., civ. dei 10, 31.

    Cur ergo non potius divinitati

    credimus de his rebus, quas humano ingenio

    pervestigare non possumus, quae animam

    quoque ipsam non Deo coaeternam81, sed

    creatam dicit esse, quae non erat ? Ut enim

    hoc Platonici nollent credere, hanc utique

    causam idoneam sibi videbantur adferre,

    quia, nisi quod semper ante fuisset,

    sempiternum deinceps esse non posset ;

    quamquam et de mundo et de his, quos in

    mundo deos a Deos factos scribit Plato,

    apertissime dicat eos esse coepisse et habere

    initium82, finem tamen non habituros, sed per

    conditoris potentissimam voluntatem in

    aeternum mansuros esse perhibeat83. Verum

    id quo modo intellegant invenerunt, non esse

    hoc videlicet temporis, sed substitutionis

    initium84. Sicut enim, inquiunt, si pes ex

    aeternitate semper fuisset in pulvere, semper

    Why, then, should we not rather

    believe the divinity about these things which

    we cannot investigate with human ingenuity,

    that divinity which tells us the soul itself is

    not co-eternal with God, but that it was

    created after having not existed ? In order for

    the Platonists to refuse to believe this, they

    thought they adduced this adequate cause :

    unless something has always existed

    previously, it cannot be perpetual

    subsequently. However, Plato openly says

    both of the world and of what he writes as

    the gods in the world made by God, that they

    began to exist and have a beginning, but by

    the most powerful will of the creator he

    testifies they will remain for eternity. Yet

    they found a way to understand this, i.e. that

    this is not a beginning of time, but of

    subsistence85. Just as, they say, if a foot was

    81sunaidios.

    82Plato, Timaeus28B7 ff.

    83Ibid., 41B 2.

    84 A difficult phrase. Some translations : Combs : Les platoniciens, il est vrai, ont leur manire de

    comprendre : il s'agit videmment, disent-ils, non pas d'un commencement d'un temps, mais d'un

    commencement d'un tre sous-jacent un autre . Madec : Les platoniciens, il est vrai, ont leur manire de

    comprendre : il s'agit videmment, disent-ils, non pas d'un commencement temporel, mais d'un commencement

    constitutif . Allerdings haben sie einen Weg gefunden, wie sie das Gesagte verstehen : damit sei natrlich

    nicht ein Anfang der Zeit gemeint (initium temporis = arkh khronik), sondern das Prinzip der Existenz (initium

    substitutionis = arkh hupostases.

    85Cf. Augustine, civ. dei XI 4, I, p. 515, 18-24 Hoffmann (quoted by J. Ppin 1964, 90-91 n. 6) : Qui autem

    a deo quidem factum fatentur, non tamen eum temporis volunt habere sed suae creationis initium, ut modo

    quodam vix intellegibili semper sit factus, dicunt quidem aliquid, unde sibi deum videntur velut a fortuita

    temeritate defendere, ne subito illi venisse credatur in mentem, quod numquam ante venisset, facere mundum, etaccidisse illi novam voluntatem, cum in nullo sit omnino mutabilis.

  • 8/13/2019 Taylor.talk.Paris.may.2012.as Given

    27/33

    27

    ei subesset vestigium, quod tamen vestigium

    a calcante factum nemo dubitaret, nec

    alterum altero prius esset : sic, inquiunt, et

    mundus atque in illo dii creati et semper

    fuerunt, semper existente qui fecit, et tamen

    facti sunt.

    in dust from eternity, a footprint would

    always be under it86, yet no one would doubt

    that the footprint was made by someone

    treading, so, they say, both the world and the

    gods created within it always existed, since

    He who made them always exists, and yet

    they were made.

    Text C

    Philop.,De aet mundi, 4, p. 13, 12 ff.

    Rabe

    1n. ^*> T,,D9. !V X &!59 =#*&49,

    =#*&O16'H1!>9%!$>'H1!)59'H1.%'"!

    C##()!"*+ X ?&4)'9, K9 X :'?49 ?-:+

    I,F"D), E*>1+=#*&5)=?*+$'@7!&*

    'p"!=:&.)!+*)"W91-7+'2$-

    (5)

    #+EW9 *H"'M E*"-#'$'M7!)

    12)F7!D9, =,,

  • 8/13/2019 Taylor.talk.Paris.may.2012.as Given

    28/33

    28

    ?@:+)'HEJ3!+

    (...) B9#'p"!

    (25)

    "'Mo,('2"5?89'p"!"'M?D"59

    X v,+'9 'p"! %$4"!$49 C:"+) 'p&

    G:"!$'9 E*>"

  • 8/13/2019 Taylor.talk.Paris.may.2012.as Given

    29/33

    29

    "'H75):87*, =,, 'HE%!%'(-E!)*H"Z),

    =,, CE!()-"'@"z:2)-E','@&-:!).

    (kat'aitian), as my body is the cause of my

    shadow87, but it did not make the latter, but

    the latter followed from the former.

    Text E

    Zacharias Mytilenaeus Rhet.,

    Ammonius sive De mundi opificio disputatio,

    ed. M. Minniti Colonna, Zacaria Scolastico.

    Ammonio. Introduzione, testo critico,

    traduzione, commentario. Naples, 1973, sect.

    2, 508 ff. = p. 105 Boissonade

    {|}~. V :2)*s1+') "O &!O

    "5) E4:7') !P)*+ ?Z:'7!), J:"*+ %'2

    %F)"D9 E*"F #! "'M"' E*> X74"+7'9

    *H"O. ' "( ) #.)'+"' %$59 =:.Y!+*)

    7![u'), !V "5) %!$+#!#$*77.)') E*>

    X$*"5) E*> %"5) E*> :87* J3')"*

    L,+E5) C9 "*H"5) 14/-9 E*> "+7W9 "\

    =%!$+,Z%"z E*> ='$F"z E*> =)D"F"z

    %*:8)=)*#F#D7!)?@:!+;

    Christian: If we are to say that the

    world is co-eternal with God, it will

    necessarily, in that respect, be somehow

    equal in value to Him. [And what could be

    more impious], than if we were to raise what

    is circumscribed, visible, tangible, and

    possesses a material body to the same degree

    of glory and honor as the uncircumscribed,

    invisible nature which is above all natures ?

    Text F

    Hierocles, De prov., apud Photius,

    Bibl. cod. 251, p. 461a-23

    ^*> 7S,,') ) !Q- "W9 =,-&!(*9

    =?!:"_9, !V %$59 "O C)1!![ "W9 L,+EW9

    And it would be even farther from the

    truth if, in addition to making him needy of

    87Bonaventure (loc. cit.) uses the same image of God's production of creatures as the body's projection of ashadow, once again on the presupposition of the eternity of matter.

  • 8/13/2019 Taylor.talk.Paris.may.2012.as Given

    30/33

    30

    C)!$#!(*9E*>=%5 3$4)'2 "+)59E':7![)

    $/*"', q%!$'HEC7.)!+)*H"5)C)"O

    *L"'M &!+88. V #

  • 8/13/2019 Taylor.talk.Paris.may.2012.as Given

    31/33

    31

    Bibliography

    Baltes, Matthias, 1976. Die Weltentstehung des platonischen Timaios nach denantiken Interpreten, vol. I, Leiden : Brill.

    ____ , 1996. .#')!)(Platon, Tim. 28 B 7) : ist die Welt real entstanden oder nicht ?

    in Polyhistor : studies in the history and historiography of ancient philosophy presented to

    Jaap Mansfeld on his sixtieth birthday, ed. by Keimpe A. Algra, Pieter Willem Van der Horst,

    David T. Runia. Leiden : Brill. (Philosophia antiqua ; 72), 76-96.

    Chase, Michael, 2009-2010. La subsistence noplatonicienne. De Porphyre

    Thodore de Raithu, Chra : Revue d'tudes Anciennes et Mdivales (Bucharest-Paris)7-8,

    p. 37-52.

    _____ , 2011. Discussions on the Eternity of the world in Late Antiquity, in56789,

    A Journal of the Centre for Ancient Philosophy and the Classical Tradition, 5. 2. Special

    issue : Ancient Cosmology and Astronomy, p. 111-173.

    ____ , in press. Discussions on the eternity of the world in Antiquity and

    contemporary cosmology, I-II, to be published in 56789, A Journal of the Centre for

    Ancient Philosophy and the Classical Tradition.

    Drrie, Heinrich, & M. Baltes, 1998. Der Platonismus in der Antike : Grundlagen-

    System-Entwicklung. 5, Die philosophische Lehre des Platonismus. Platonische Physik (im

    antiken Verstndnis). 2, Bausteine 125-150 : Text, bersetzung, Kommentar, Stuttgart-Bad

    Cannstatt : frommann-holzboog.

    Kremer, Klaus, 1965. Das Warum der Schpfung : quia bonus vel/et quia

    voluit ? Ein Beitrag zum Verhltnis von Neuplatonismus und Christentum an Hand des

    Prinzips bonum est diffusivum sui. In: K. Flasch, ed., Parusia. Studien zur Philosophie

    Platons und zur Problemgeschichte des Platonismus. Festgabe fr J. Hirschberger.Frankfurt

    : Minerva-Verl., 241-264.

    ____ , 19712.Die neuplatonische Seinsphilosophie und ihre Wirkung auf Thomas von

    Aquin, Leiden : E. J. Brill, (Studien zur Problemgeschichte der antiken und mittealterlichen

    Philosophie, I).

    ____ , 1987. Bonum est diffusivum sui. Ein Beitrag zum Verhltnis von

    Neuplatonismus und Christentum, ANRW II.36.2, 994-1032.

  • 8/13/2019 Taylor.talk.Paris.may.2012.as Given

    32/33

    32

    Lakmann, Marie-Luise, 1995. Der Platoniker Tauros in der Darstellung des Aulus

    Gellius, Leiden etc. : Brill, (Philosophia Antiqua vol. LXIII).

    Leroux, Georges, 1990. Plotin. Trait sur la libert et la volont de l'Un [Ennade VI,

    8 (39)], Introduction, texte grec, traduction et commentaire par G. L., Paris : Vrin (Histoire

    des Doctrines de l'Antiquit classique 15).

    Lizzini, Olga, 2009 Il nulla, l'inesistente, la cosa : note intorno alla terminologia e alla

    dottrina del nulla e della creazione dal nulla nel pensiero islamico, in M. Lenzi & A. Maier,

    eds., Discussioni sul nulla tra Medioevo ed et moderna, Leo S. Olschki (Lessico

    Intellectuale Europeo), 63109.

    May, Gerhard. 1994. Creatio Ex Nihilo : the Doctrine of Creation Out of Nothing in

    Early Christian Thought. Trans. A. S. Worrall. Edinburgh : T&T Clark.

    Michon, Cyrille, et al., 2004. Thomas d'Aquin et la controverse sur l'ternit du

    monde. Traits sur l'ternit du monde de Bonaventure, Thomas d'Aquin, Peckham, Boce de

    Dacie, Henri de Gand et Guillaume d'Ockham, Traductions, prsentations et notes par C. M.,

    avec la collaboration d'Olivier Boulnois et de Nathanal Dupr La Tour, Paris : Flammarion

    (GF Flammarion).

    Narbonne, Jean-Marc, 2001. La mtaphysique de Plotin. Deuxime dition revue et

    augmente, suivi de Hensis et Ereignis : Remarques sur une interprtation heideggrienne

    de l'Un plotinien, Paris : Vrin (Bibliothque d'Histoire de la Philosophie. Nouvelle srie).

    Sorabji, Richard R. K., ed.. 2004. The philosophy of the commentators, 200-600 AD :

    400 years of transition : a sourcebook, London: Duckworth. 3 vol., 1, Psychology (with

    ethics and religion) ; 2, Physics ; 3, Logic and metaphysics.

    Taylor, Richard C., 2012. Primary Causality and Ibd! (Creare) in the Liber De

    Causis. In Wahrheit und Geschichte. Die Gebrochene Tradition Metaphysischen Denkens.

    Festschrift Zum 70. Geburtstag Von Gnther Mensching, ed. Alia Mensching-Estakhr and

    Michael Stdtler, 115. Knigshausen &Neumann.

    Theiler, Willy, 1966. Forschungen zum Neuplatonismus, Berlin : Walter de Gruyter &

    Co. (Quellen und Studien zur Geschichte der Philosophie, Band 10).

    Wacht, M., 1969.Aeneas von Gaza als Apologet. Seine Kosmologie im Verhltnis zum

    Platonismus, Bonn (Theophaneia 21).

    Wolfson, H. A., 1970. The identification of ex nihilo with emanation in Gregory of

    Nyssa,Harvard Theological Review63, 53-60 = 1973. Studies in the History of Philosophy

    and Religion. 1. Ed. Isadore Twersky and George H. Williams. Cambridge : Harvard

    University Press.

  • 8/13/2019 Taylor.talk.Paris.may.2012.as Given

    33/33

    33

    Zimmermann, Fritz W., 1986. The Origins of the So-Called Theology of Aristotle, in

    J. Kraye, W. F. Ryan, & C. B. Schmitt, eds. Pseudo-Aristotle in the Middle Ages: The

    Theology and other Texts, London : Warburg Institute, Univ. of London (Warburg Institute

    Surveys and Texts 11), 110240.