steve helmling - 'immanent critique' and 'dialetical mimesis' in adorno &...

21
‘‘Immanent Critique’’ and ‘‘Dialectical Mimesis’’ in Adorno and Horkheimer’s Dialectic of Enlightenment Steven Helmling Given the ubiquity of the phrase ‘‘immanent critique’’ in Theodor Adorno’s oeuvre, both early and late, it is surprising that what Adorno might have meant by it has received such perfunctory attention from commenta- tors, most of whom treat it as a self-evident premise to dispose of on the way to weightier matters. 1 Yet in this phrase, Adorno comes as close as he does anywhere to naming something like a programmatic ambition for his work, its distinctive method as well as its more comprehensive aims. The accomplishment it proposes is meant not only to distinguish Adorno’s work (and that of his Frankfurt School colleagues) from the conventional critical 1. Most valuable for my purposes have been Susan Buck-Morss, The Origin of Nega- tive Dialectics: Theodor W. Adorno, Walter Benjamin, and the Frankfurt Institute (Sussex: Harvester Press, 1977), 66–69 (especially useful in delimiting some crucial differences between Adorno and Horkheimer); Robert Hullot-Kentor, ‘‘Introduction to Adorno’s ‘Idea of Natural History,’’’ Telos 60 (1984): 105–7; and J. M. Bernstein, Adorno: Disenchant- ment and Ethics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001), 87–90. For a special- ized argument for immanent critique as a method at once of interpretation and of aesthetic evaluation, see Christopher Menke, The Sovereignty of Art: Aesthetic Negativity in Adorno and Derrida (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1998), 136–43. boundary 2 32:3, 2005. Copyright © 2005 by Duke University Press.

Upload: rebecca-garcia

Post on 27-Dec-2015

15 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Steve Helmling - 'Immanent Critique' and 'Dialetical Mimesis' in Adorno & Horkheimer's Dialectic of Enlightenment

‘‘Immanent Critique’’ and ‘‘Dialectical Mimesis’’ in Adornoand Horkheimer’s Dialectic of Enlightenment

Steven Helmling

Given the ubiquity of the phrase ‘‘immanent critique’’ in Theodor

Adorno’s oeuvre, both early and late, it is surprising that what Adorno might

have meant by it has received such perfunctory attention from commenta-

tors, most of whom treat it as a self-evident premise to dispose of on the

way to weightier matters.1Yet in this phrase, Adorno comes as close as he

does anywhere to naming something like a programmatic ambition for his

work, its distinctive method as well as its more comprehensive aims. The

accomplishment it proposes is meant not only to distinguish Adorno’s work

(and that of his Frankfurt School colleagues) from the conventional critical

1. Most valuable for my purposes have been Susan Buck-Morss, The Origin of Nega-tive Dialectics: Theodor W. Adorno, Walter Benjamin, and the Frankfurt Institute (Sussex:Harvester Press, 1977), 66–69 (especially useful in delimiting some crucial differences

between Adorno and Horkheimer); Robert Hullot-Kentor, ‘‘Introduction to Adorno’s ‘Idea

of Natural History,’ ’’ Telos 60 (1984): 105–7; and J. M. Bernstein, Adorno: Disenchant-ment and Ethics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001), 87–90. For a special-

ized argument for immanent critique as a method at once of interpretation and of aesthetic

evaluation, see Christopher Menke, The Sovereignty of Art: Aesthetic Negativity in Adornoand Derrida (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1998), 136–43.

boundary 2 32:3, 2005. Copyright © 2005 by Duke University Press.

Page 2: Steve Helmling - 'Immanent Critique' and 'Dialetical Mimesis' in Adorno & Horkheimer's Dialectic of Enlightenment

98 boundary 2 / Fall 2005

practices of his era, but to model a riskier, more comprehensive range of

critical effort, and thus to challenge criticism-as-usual to enlarge its scope,

to take on greater burdens, to aim, even at the price of failure, at ever-more

daunting tasks. Adorno means to bring critique itself into the critical cross-

hairs, to enlarge or arouse the very self-consciousness—even the ‘‘bad con-

science’’—of critique, and he means the consequences to bear not merely

on the kinds of objects critique might target, or the kinds or method or scope

of the arguments it might mount, but on the very writing practice in which

critique performs itself, in which it accomplishes as much of its program as

it manages to deliver on.

So rather than take ‘‘immanent critique’’ as a given, I want in this

essay to try to focus fault lines and contradictions in Adorno’s theory and

practice of immanent critique that seem to me suggestive and illuminating

for the antithetical or dialectical uses to which Adorno turns it, or, better,

allows or suffers it to turn his writing. I aim to set the ‘‘performative contradic-

tion’’ (as Jürgen Habermas calls it) of Adorno’s immanent critique in relation

to other constructions (Walter Benjamin’s) and/or critiques (Georg Lukács’s,

Habermas’s) of it, in ways that I think illuminate from a novel angle all these

figures and the issues at stake in their disagreements over what critique is

and how it should conduct itself. I mean to expound Adorno’s immanent cri-

tique as not only a critical program but also a performative one, that is, a

reflexive self-consciousness about his own writing practice as well, and thus

a considerable motivation of the flair and drama that are so distinctive to the

energetic carriage of his ‘‘dialectical’’ sentences.

Since, in what follows, I want to foreground the implication of Adorno’s

writing practice as enactment of the varied ambitions connoted by the

phrase ‘‘immanent critique,’’ it is with some chagrin that I report that I can-

not read Adorno in German without a trot. In writing about Adorno, I have

tried to subject knotty passages to readings as detailed as I can make them

but which nevertheless do not claim to be offering a specifically ‘‘stylistic’’

response; if I have shied away from quoting the German, it is precisely in

order not to seem tomake such claims. I have been careful, in the process of

composition, to consult the German when it has seemed prudent; and when

the German has raised doubts about my argument, I have backed off, or

sought a different way of pursuing my point. I am trying to say that I am wary

of the pitfalls my poor German lays for me, and have done my cautious best

to avoid them. That said, I think that in an increasingly global culture, critical

discourse must increasingly rely—indeed, it had better admit the extent to

which it always has relied—on translations. (Even ourmost enviably polyglot

Page 3: Steve Helmling - 'Immanent Critique' and 'Dialetical Mimesis' in Adorno & Horkheimer's Dialectic of Enlightenment

Helmling / ‘‘Immanent Critique’’ and ‘‘Dialectical Mimesis’’ 99

colleagues—George Steiner, Paul de Man, Fredric Jameson—must rely on

translations for the Koran, Orhan Pamuk, Dostoyevsky, The Tale of Genji . . .)And I think it would be a shame if critics stimulated by work from all over

the planet felt disqualified from comment on anything in languages in which

they lack ‘‘literary competence.’’ In resolving to write on Adorno, I have had

to overcome considerable hesitation, but my keen interest in him, and my

conviction that I could illuminate problems that others had overlooked, have

obviously gotten the better of my scruples.

‘‘Immanent critique,’’ then: by this usage, Adorno clearly intends to do

more than merely take sides in the long contention over what critique is, or

should, or can, be. Rather, he means his own practice to enact a critique of

the debate itself, and to model larger possibilities and challenges beyond it.

A chronic ambition of critique has been to get outside the critical object, to

achieve ‘‘objectivity’’ about it, or ‘‘critical distance’’ from it. Both in its Kantian

and its Marxist senses, critique has turned on issues of inside/outside; and

the pursuit of the inside track has largely belonged to ‘‘hermeneutic,’’ as

opposed to ‘‘critique.’’ ‘‘Hermeneutic’’ sanctions the interpreter’s sympathy,

or even identity with the object—precisely the stance ‘‘critique’’ rejects as

imperiling objectivity. As usual, when confronted with a dichotomy in our cul-

ture’s way of conceptualizing its problems, Adorno takes the dichotomy itself

as an ideological problem or wound—his code word is chorismos (Greek

‘‘separation’’)—that his own critical labor will attempt to overcome or heal.

Hence his ‘‘immanent critique,’’ which encodes the ambition to get the criti-

cal ‘‘subject’’ inside what we might then no longer so simply be able to call

critique’s ‘‘object’’; Adorno frequently contrasts it with ‘‘external’’ critique,

critique ‘‘from outside,’’ or even, if rarely, ‘‘transcendent critique.’’2Adorno’s

most sustained contrast of ‘‘immanent’’ with ‘‘transcendent’’ criticism comes

in the peroration of the 1949 essay ‘‘Cultural Criticism and Society’’ (it is this

peroration that rises to the climax of ‘‘To write poetry after Auschwitz is bar-

2. See especially Theodor W. Adorno, Prisms, trans. Samuel and Shierry Weber (Cam-

bridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1981), 33; and Theodor W. Adorno, Kant’s Critique of PureReason, trans. Rodney Livingstone (Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press, 2001), 20.Twice, Adorno characterizes his own work as ‘‘metacritique’’—in the subtitle to his book

on Husserl (Against Epistemology: A Metacritique), and in the opening section, on Kant,

of Part III of Negative Dialectics (‘‘A Metacritique of Practical Reason’’). In both cases, the

word amounts to a kind of sarcasmat the expense of philosophical systems founded on the

premise that certain problems can be ‘‘bracketed off’’ from, or declared to be ‘‘transcenden-

tal’’ to, others. Adorno affronts these ‘‘transcendent critiques’’ by dilating to encompass,

and thus reintroduce, all that Husserl and Kant have tried to exclude. In this application,

there appears a family resemblance of ‘‘immanent critique’’ with deconstruction.

Page 4: Steve Helmling - 'Immanent Critique' and 'Dialetical Mimesis' in Adorno & Horkheimer's Dialectic of Enlightenment

100 boundary 2 / Fall 2005

baric’’): ‘‘The alternatives—either calling culture as a whole into question

from outside under the general notion of ideology, or confronting it with the

norms which it itself has crystallized—cannot be accepted by critical theory.

To insist on the choice between immanence and transcendence is to revert

to the traditional logic criticized in Hegel’s polemic against Kant. . . . The

position transcending culture is in a certain sense presupposed by dialectics

as the consciousness which does succumb in advance to the fetishization of

the intellectual sphere.’’ Whereas, says Adorno, ‘‘dialectics means intransi-

gence toward all reification’’3—in particular, the ‘‘spurious harmony’’ of what

he elsewhere calls, in condemnation of Lukács, ‘‘Extorted Reconciliation’’4

(observe how, as the passage develops, immanent criticism and dialecticsbegin to operate as functionally convertible terms):

[Immanent criticism] pursues the logic of its aporias, the insolubility of

the task itself. In such antinomies criticism perceives those of society.

A successful work, according to immanent criticism, is not one which

resolves objective contradictions in a spurious harmony, but one

which expresses the harmony negatively by embodying the contra-

dictions, . . . in its innermost structure. Confronted with this kind of

work, the verdict ‘‘mere ideology’’ loses its meaning. At the same

time, however, immanent criticism holds in evidence that the mind

has always been under a spell. On its own it is unable to resolve the

contradictions under which it labours. Even the most radical reflec-

tion of the mind on its own failure is limited by the fact that it remains

only reflection, without altering the existence to which its failure bears

witness. Hence immanent criticism cannot take comfort in its own

idea. It can neither be vain enough to believe that it can liberate the

mind directly . . . nor naïve enough to believe that unflinching immer-

sion in the object will inevitably lead to truth by virtue of the logic of

things. . . . The less the dialectical method can today presuppose

the Hegelian identity of subject and object, the more it is obliged to

be mindful of the duality of the moments. . . . The very opposition

between knowledge which penetrates from without and that which

bores from within becomes suspect to the dialectical method, which

sees in it a symptom of precisely that reification which the dialectic is

obliged to accuse. . . . No theory, not even that which is true, is safe

3. Adorno, Prisms, 31.4. Theodor W. Adorno, Notes to Literature, trans. Shierry Weber Nicholsen, vol. 1 (New

York: Columbia University Press, 1991), 216–40.

Page 5: Steve Helmling - 'Immanent Critique' and 'Dialetical Mimesis' in Adorno & Horkheimer's Dialectic of Enlightenment

Helmling / ‘‘Immanent Critique’’ and ‘‘Dialectical Mimesis’’ 101

from perversion into delusion once it has renounced a spontaneous

[i.e., ‘‘immanent’’] relation to the object. Dialectics must guard against

this no less than against enthrallment in the cultural object. It can sub-

scribe neither to the cult of the mind nor to hatred of it. The dialectical

critic of culture must both participate in culture and not participate.

Only then does he do justice to his object and to himself.5

If ‘‘the very opposition between knowledge which penetrates from without

and that which bores from within’’ is itself a symptom of the problem, then

the logic of that aporia requires a method that aspires to do both, and ‘‘the

insolubility of the task’’ is not its disqualification but an attestation of its

necessity. Adorno’s practice thus assumes for immanent critique burdens

both critical and hermeneutic: making each immanent to the other and, at

the same time, making each the other’s critique.

And thereby Adorno implies as well an ideological critique of each—

of critique and of hermeneutic—as usually practiced: critique’s ‘‘distance’’

from the object now appears as not an objectivity to be striven for but

an alienation to be overcome; while hermeneutic’s ‘‘inwardness’’ with the

object, attesting the interpreter’s sympathy with the interpreted text (a moti-

vation extending through belles lettres ‘‘appreciation’’ back to biblical exege-

sis), now appears as an ideological entrapment that critique must struggle,

however vainly, to breach. (Immanent critique, then, is critique of critique,

and not merely in the sense of autocritique.) At stake, needless to say,

is not the critic’s mere decision in advance between two menu items, two

kinds of critique, internal and external. Adorno’s premise is that all critique is

from ‘‘inside’’—inside of history, of economy, of culture, politics, ideology—

and that ‘‘external critique’’ is ideologically deluded, or self-blinded, or self-

trivializing, if it supposes that it has gotten, or can or should get, ‘‘outside’’

the determinations of the social. Immanent critique, then, is less a program

that critique should aspire to than a predicament that critique must try not

to flinch from.

An immanent critique thus conceived incurs complex burdens—and

since Adorno resists generalization, let us begin with consideration of a par-

ticular instance: a section ofNegative Dialectics that proposes an immanentcritique of Heideggerian ‘‘ontology.’’ Adorno concedes that the Spirit in our

age has a legitimate ‘‘ontological need,’’ to which Heidegger and others are

offering, so to speak, ‘‘an imaginary [i.e., ideological] solution.’’ His imma-

nent critique means to interpret the genuine (and symptomatic) need or

5. Adorno, Prisms, 32–33.

Page 6: Steve Helmling - 'Immanent Critique' and 'Dialetical Mimesis' in Adorno & Horkheimer's Dialectic of Enlightenment

102 boundary 2 / Fall 2005

problem as well as to expose the ideological mystification of the proposed

solution. ‘‘We have no power over the philosophy of Being if we reject it gen-

erally, from outside, instead of taking it on in its own structure—turning its

own force against it.’’ Thus critique must confront not merely Heidegger’s

own ‘‘thought movements’’ but all the philosophical concepts and systems

that precede and surround Heidegger. ‘‘The thought movement that con-

gealed in them,’’ Adorno explains, ‘‘must be reliquified, its validity traced, in

repetition.’’6

Let us unpack some of this.What is ‘‘congealed’’ must be ‘‘reliquified’’:

this figuration is frequent in discussions of ideology and reification, and not

just in Adorno; indeed, we find it in Hegel himself. (Observe the contrast with

reactionaries, who typically figure the disgraced world as ‘‘soft’’ or ‘‘liquid,’’

in need of an order to ‘‘stiffen’’ or ‘‘harden’’ it.) Adorno typically figures ‘‘reifi-

cation’’ as a hardening or freezing or rigidifying, which a de-reifying critique

seeks to undo—to soften, thaw, loosen or, in his figure here, ‘‘reliquify.’’ As a

program, however, this is more easily proposed than executed. The critical

object ‘‘must be reliquified, its validity traced, in repetition.’’ Observe first that

this is a critique concerned as much to validate what is valid in its object as

to discredit or expose what is not. But the real trouble is repetition, a word

in all critical usages (including Adorno’s) virtually always connoting ideol-

ogy itself, everything that forecloses the (utopian) promise of future deliver-

ance from the fated repetition of the past. As part—or as ‘‘moment’’—of its

effort to ‘‘reliquify’’ the ideological rigidities it suffers, immanent critique must

‘‘repeat’’ these rigidities, which is to say, must suffer, indeed, inflict, the fate

of repetition upon itself deliberately. Adorno is Hegel’s disciple in holding

that the past cannot be merely disowned, or gotten ‘‘outside’’ of: escaping

its cycle of repetition requires a working-through that confronts, immanently,

all the horror of what we would escape. So solving a problem requires, first,

the evocation of the problem, in all its problematicalness. We cannot over-

come ideology without a full acknowledgment—and more: a full experience,

in the writing, in the reading—of the power of ideology.

As writing, therefore—and Adorno never lets a reader (or a critic)

forget that critique is, by reason of its written-ness, ineluctably, ‘‘a kind of

writing’’—critique must labor as mightily to evoke its object as to sublate or

move beyond it. And hence the ‘‘unhappy consciousness’’ imperative that

is palpable in every word Adorno ever wrote. For a dramatic shorthand,

6. Theodor W. Adorno, Negative Dialectics, trans. E. B. Ashton (New York: Continuum,

1973), 97.

Page 7: Steve Helmling - 'Immanent Critique' and 'Dialetical Mimesis' in Adorno & Horkheimer's Dialectic of Enlightenment

Helmling / ‘‘Immanent Critique’’ and ‘‘Dialectical Mimesis’’ 103

we might call it the ‘‘after-Auschwitz’’ imperative, keeping in mind that this

intellectual-affective imperative of Adorno’s writing long predates Auschwitz

itself. (One way of registering the angst of Dialectic of Enlightenment mightbe the reminder that the moment of its composition was, literally, during-Auschwitz.) What I am trying to stress here is the place of affect both in

Adorno’s theory of critique and in his practice of it. Adorno’s insistence on

‘‘the labor of conceptualization’’ also involves a labor of what I will call here

affectualization—the labor of apprehending our ideological condition not

only (to recall Hegel again) as thought but also as feeling—with the caveat

that Adorno refuses the conventional antithesis, or as he would rather call it,

the ideological chorismos, between concept and affect: he wants (and this,too, is part of the problem his immanent critique means both to ‘‘repeat’’ and

to ‘‘reliquify,’’ part of the breach he wants to close, the wound he wants to

heal, even if doing so must begin by reopening it) to make affects concep-

tual, and tomake the concept affective, to overcome the chorismos by whichEnlightenment has, in separating thought from feeling, impoverished both.

Only thus can the wound, and the healing (if any: at any rate, the need for

it), be made concrete.

This ambition puts large demands on the writing of critique: the critic

must be a writer of peculiar brilliance to meet them. (This is partly why com-

mentary on Dialectic of Enlightenment discounts the coauthorship of Hork-heimer, and so often lapses, faute de mieux, into treating the book ‘‘as if’’

Adorno were its [sole] author.) It also makes for a finished text that will be

peculiarly challenging, peculiarly difficult, for its reader—a text whose self-

conscious expressive difficulty is motivated by the historical, cultural, social,

and political difficulties of its subject matter, difficulties it must ‘‘repeat,’’ must

evoke as inescapable preliminary to any other hoped-for transitive (‘‘reliqui-fying’’) effect upon them. And that imperative, familiar in our period from

the great radical innovations of modernism, incurs the dangers that Lukács

reprehends as ‘‘the ideology of modernism’’: that to ‘‘repeat ’’ the problem

will be merely to replicate it, so that the radical new work will present merely

a symptom of the problem rather than a critical negation of it. Hence the

subtext, lifelong, of the debates between Lukács and Adorno over the mer-

its of realism versus modernism. For Lukács, a Joyce or a Proust is merely

an example of bourgeois decadence, not, in any useful way, an anatomist

or critic of it. For Adorno, a Kafka or a Beckett has a critical value far out-

stripping any more conventionally conceived critique, because they make

the contemporary predicament and its anguish real, or perhaps we had

better say concrete—they convey its ‘‘objectivity.’’ Adorno praises the plays

Page 8: Steve Helmling - 'Immanent Critique' and 'Dialetical Mimesis' in Adorno & Horkheimer's Dialectic of Enlightenment

104 boundary 2 / Fall 2005

of Beckett precisely because they ‘‘arouse the anxiety that existentialism

only talks about’’7—and they do so without offering any narrative resolution,

such as would be, for Lukács, the sine qua non of any critical prospect of

release from the predicaments they portray: the failure of any such enact-

ment is what makes them, for Lukács, merely symptomatic of the bourgeois

ideology, and to that extent, ideological themselves. For Adorno, any such

narrative release could be only ‘‘imaginary’’ release, and hence itself not

merely ideological but virtually the epitome of ideology as such. It is not

merely that Lukács and Adorno disagree on what is critical and what is ideo-

logical: it is that precisely what determines the question for one determines

it the other way for the other.

Lukács cannot have approved of Dialectic of Enlightenment—either

as a set of theses (assuming such could be extorted from its motivatedly

anti-thetic prose) or as a piece of rhetoric, or writing. Dialectic of Enlight-enment violates the norms established for critique in the century and morepreceding it as radically as Ulysses violates the norms of realist fiction. It

avows a historicizing and dialectical consciousness, but builds itself around

binary pairs—Odysseus as bourgeois, myth as Enlightenment—that would

seem to be staged as anything but: asserted, rather, as transhistorically or

unhistorically homogeneous, as well as ‘‘equivalent’’ or fungible in a way to

eschew the need, even foreclose the possibility, of their ‘‘dialectical’’ media-

tion, let alone negation or sublation, altogether. They conjoin historically dis-

junct pairs but in a way to dispense with, even to preempt or foreclose, any

narrative leading from one to the other: conjoin them, that is, in what Adorno

elsewhere calls a ‘‘constellation,’’ a term and practice with obvious affini-

ties to cubist collage, Eisenstein’s ‘‘montage,’’ Pound’s ‘‘ideogram,’’ Joyce’s

‘‘epiphany,’’ and other modernist devices in which Lukács sees only symp-

toms of bourgeois decadence.

If Lukács refrains from spelling this out, a more recent figure, namely

Habermas, epigone of the Frankfurt School generally and protégé of Adorno

in particular, has done something close to it for him. In Lecture V of ThePhilosophical Discourse of Modernity, Habermas warns that Dialectic ofEnlightenment risks incurring the sin it avowedly condemns, namely, elabo-rating and enforcing the myth/Enlightenment binary so insistently as to

threaten a lapse into a ‘‘mythic thinking’’ of the very kind the book charges

against Enlightenment itself. (Habermas is concerned lest the gains of mo-

7. Theodor W. Adorno, Notes to Literature, trans. Shierry Weber Nicholsen, vol. 2 (New

York: Columbia University Press, 1992), 90.

Page 9: Steve Helmling - 'Immanent Critique' and 'Dialetical Mimesis' in Adorno & Horkheimer's Dialectic of Enlightenment

Helmling / ‘‘Immanent Critique’’ and ‘‘Dialectical Mimesis’’ 105

dernity be lost in the crossfire between antimodern reactionaries on the

Right and postmodern radicals on the Left; he more charitably concedes

Adorno andHorkheimer’s commitment to ‘‘reason’’ in the interviews, roughly

contemporaneous with Philosophical Discourse of Modernity, collected as

Autonomy and Solidarity.)8 But Habermas argues that to the extent that

Enlightenment is critique, Horkheimer and Adorno undercut their own criti-cal project, as well as the modern project at large, and that Dialectic ofEnlightenment is therefore entoiled in what Habermas thrice calls a ‘‘perfor-mative contradiction’’

9—a contradiction, he argues, that vitiates the whole

project.

I am arguing the contrary here, that just this performative contradic-

tion is what gives Dialectic of Enlightenment its force and its weird power. IfHabermas puts the stress on the contradiction, I want to put it on the perfor-

mativity. The point of the performativity is precisely to perform that histori-

cally specific contradiction, a contradiction, Adorno would say, not merely

incidental to a particular critical rhetoric but a contradiction ‘‘objectively’’

there in the cultural predicament the critique means, immanently, to take on,

to suffer or ‘‘repeat’’ as well as to negate or ‘‘reliquify.’’ And an irony, or dialec-

tic, that might seem to vindicate the book against Habermas is that Haber-

mas’s indictment itself can contrive to do no other than ‘‘repeat’’ the offense it

protests—for consider: according to Dialectic of Enlightenment, Enlighten-ment denounces every precedent episteme as ‘‘myth.’’ Repeating that ges-ture, Dialectic of Enlightenment denounces Enlightenment as ‘‘myth.’’ Andnow, here is Habermas, denouncing Dialectic of Enlightenment as ‘‘myth’’(PDM, 125, 127). Habermas usually makes Adorno and Horkheimer’s unfor-tunate fall into myth sound unwitting, but not always—and indeed, his brief

against the ‘‘paradox’’ of Dialectic of Enlightenment is compounded by the

reflection that it is not unconscious: ‘‘Adorno was quite aware of this per-

formative contradiction’’ (PDM, 119). What is further ironic is the question

of Habermas’s own awareness of his own implication in the tangle. It is

like an Escher drawing, a fractal-recursive, self-replicating structure into

which Habermas’s reading has conducted itself despite itself—which attests

that Dialectic of Enlightenment has indeed tapped some ‘‘objective’’ sys-

temic virus, so to speak, or structural meme, so pervasively active and self-

8. Jürgen Habermas, Autonomy and Solidarity: Interviews, ed. Peter Dews (London:

Verso, 1986), 98, 154–55.

9. Jürgen Habermas, Philosophical Discourse of Modernity, trans. Frederick G. Lawrence(Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1987), 119, 127, 185; for the same charge leveled at Derrida,

see 197. Hereafter, this work is cited parenthetically as PDM.

Page 10: Steve Helmling - 'Immanent Critique' and 'Dialetical Mimesis' in Adorno & Horkheimer's Dialectic of Enlightenment

106 boundary 2 / Fall 2005

activating in the sociocultural DNA of Enlightenment—a.k.a. modernity, late

capitalism, the administered world—that neither Horkheimer and Adorno’s

own critique of Enlightenment nor Habermas’s critique of their critique can

quarantine the infection ‘‘inside’’ a boundary or secure itself safely ‘‘outside’’

the zone of contamination. Thus the Horkheimer/Adorno QED: the absence

of any way to get ‘‘outside’’ the ideological dilemmas of ‘‘Enlightenment’’

and/as ‘‘myth.’’

Habermas, I should point out, never quite charges ‘‘mythical think-

ing,’’ in those words, against Horkheimer and Adorno; rather, he makes

the case implicitly, but unmistakably, via a kind of guilt by association, in

the section of the essay assimilating Dialectic of Enlightenment to Nietz-

sche’s ‘‘cynical consciousness’’ and his fundamentally ‘‘aesthetic’’ attitude,

by which Habermas means, à la Kierkegaard, Nietzsche’s abrogation from

questions of truth or falsity (PDM, 119–26). (Compare Habermas’s open-

ing paragraph, which places Dialectic of Enlightenment among the ‘‘black

books’’ of Nietzsche, de Sade, and other ‘‘ ‘dark’ writers of the bourgeoi-

sie, such as Machiavelli, Hobbes, and Mandeville’’ [PDM, 106].) On the

truth/falsity score, Habermas scrupulously maintains a distinction between

Dialectic of Enlightenment and Nietzsche, but the distinction turns on the

‘‘paradox’’ produced by the book’s adherence, cynical consciousness not-

withstanding, to the truth-claim: and precisely that—a cynical truth-claim—

is, I take it, what produces the ‘‘performative contradiction’’ Habermas pro-

tests. But even more ironically, the allegedly ‘‘cynical consciousness’’ of

Dialectic of Enlightenment—the fact that ‘‘Adorno was quite aware of this

performative contradiction’’—would seem to be, for Habermas, all that can

redeem the book from a wholesale lapse into naïvely mythic thinking.

Now I hasten to grant the power of Habermas’s critique ofDialectic ofEnlightenment—he puts that case as well as it can be put—but: Horkheimer

and, especially, Adorno as exemplars of cynical reason? That seems to mea judgment so wrongheaded as to approach the perverse. Peter Sloterdijk’s

diagnosis of Adorno’s ‘‘sensitive critique,’’ and his prescription (at need) of

a dose of ‘‘cheekiness,’’ seems to me much closer to the mark; indeed, his

formula—that Adorno ‘‘tried, by a conceptual balancing act, to construe a

knowledge that would not be power’’10—seems to me to capture both the

forlornness and the defiance of Adorno’s refusal of every variety of cynical

consciousness.Which is to say that Sloterdijk’s formula praises Adorno rele-

10. Peter Sloterdijk, Critique of Cynical Reason, trans. Michael Eldred (Minneapolis: Uni-versity of Minnesota Press, 1987), xxxv.

Page 11: Steve Helmling - 'Immanent Critique' and 'Dialetical Mimesis' in Adorno & Horkheimer's Dialectic of Enlightenment

Helmling / ‘‘Immanent Critique’’ and ‘‘Dialectical Mimesis’’ 107

vantly—and it is praise, not the cynical ‘‘unmasking’’ it could be mistaken for.(Compare Lutz Niethammer’s asperities regarding the ‘‘will to powerless-

ness’’ of Adorno and other modern intellectuals.)11That Sloterdijk himself

elects to fight the fight with satire and laughter—‘‘kynicism’’—rather than,

à la Adorno, from the position of ‘‘unhappy consciousness,’’ might be read

as variously qualifying his praise, but I do not see how it could be taken to

undo it. That Habermas, on the other hand, can find for Dialectic of Enlight-enment no better alternative than the either/or of naïve myth versus cynicalconsciousness, cannot see that the book aspires, quite the reverse of cyni-

cally, to open a utopian alternative to that binary, seems to me an index in

Habermas of a surprising limitation.12

Pace Habermas, I would put it that Dialectic of Enlightenment ’s bril-liance is to have sustained a fertile and high-voltage rhetoric not despite,but precisely because of, the contradictoriness of what seem initially quite

ahistorical, undialectical, even ‘‘mythical’’ conjunctions. The measure of its

success is how effectually it manages to communicate those contradictions.

And by ‘‘communicate’’ I here mean to evoke not the model of transmission

of message from sender to receiver but the ambition of the text to make the

pain of all this contradiction common, a kind of ideological communion of

suffering that, Adorno insinuates, is as close to a binding agent, a legitimate

solidarity, as our alienated culture may presently allow us. ‘‘The need to lend

a voice to suffering,’’ as he elsewhere puts it, ‘‘is the condition of all truth.’’13

The level of affect—the ‘‘after- [or during-] Auschwitz’’ anger and fear that

is the specific felt or lived ‘‘unhappy consciousness’’ of Dialectic of Enlight-enment—remains potent throughout, and this affective or moral difficulty

attests, expresses, the philosophical, political, social, cultural (etc.) difficul-

ties the book protests.Dialectic of Enlightenment is a text in which all the dif-ferent kinds of difficulty motivate, indeed, overdetermine each other; hence

the difficulty of the text is irreducible, and by design: it cannot, it should not,

11. Lutz Niethammer,Posthistoire, trans. Patrick Camiller (NewYork: Verso, 1992), 138–42.

12. For a scathing critique of Habermas on this score, see Robert Hullot-Kentor, ‘‘Back to

Adorno,’’ Telos 81 (1989): 9–14. If Hullot-Kentor argues that Habermas misses the point

of the ‘‘immanence’’ of Adorno’s ‘‘immanent critique,’’ Axel Honneth takes the opposite

tack, sidestepping immanent critique altogether to argue for the ‘‘transcending’’ or ‘‘disclos-

ing’’ power—i.e., critique of the type Habermas should approve—of Dialectic of Enlighten-ment ; see Axel Honneth, ‘‘The Possibility of a Disclosing Critique of Society: The Dialecticof Enlightenment in Light of Current Debates in Social Criticism,’’ Constellations 7, no. 1(2000): 116–27.

13. Adorno, Negative Dialectics, 17–18.

Page 12: Steve Helmling - 'Immanent Critique' and 'Dialetical Mimesis' in Adorno & Horkheimer's Dialectic of Enlightenment

108 boundary 2 / Fall 2005

be rendered lucid by any paraphrase or commentary. And this un-lucidity

has the further specific ‘‘textual effect’’ (or affect) of feeling, in the reading,

always a direct function of the general apprehension of contradiction as the

motivation of the writing. It is the very point of Adorno’s immanent critique

that we are not merely shown this contradiction or that, but that we feelcontradictoriness, feel, indeed, what Adorno elsewhere calls the ‘‘Objectivity

of Contradiction’’14in our very experience of the reading throughout. Contra-

diction is realized, or concretized, in its very concept, and as feeling: amodelof the ‘‘labor of conceptualization’’ and the ‘‘labor of affectualization,’’ as well

as the chorismos of the ideological will to separate them, to diminish the

force, to numb the pain, of each—all concretized or even—why not?—‘‘con-

stellated’’ in the medium of Adorno’s writing practice.

The power and contradictoriness of this effect, or affect, are what

entitle Adorno’s immanent critique to call itself ‘‘dialectical.’’ In fact, in one

place (in his immanent critique of Edmund Husserl), Adorno makes explicit

the connection—indeed, the virtual convertibility—of these terms: ‘‘Dialec-

tic’s very procedure is immanent critique. It does not so much oppose

[Husserlian] phenomenology with a position or ‘model’ external and alien to

phenomenology, as it pushes the phenomenological model, with the latter’s

own force, to where the latter cannot afford to go. Dialectic exacts the truth

from it through the confession of its own untruth.’’15Immanent critique, that

is, ‘‘repeats’’ Husserl’s ‘‘phenomenological model,’’ and its ‘‘untruth’’—but

with the effect of not merely ‘‘repeating’’ the ‘‘untruth’’ but forcing a critical

‘‘confession’’ from the ‘‘untruth’’ itself. The problematic implicit here of the

mere repetition of the Husserlian ‘‘symptom’’ versus its ‘‘reliquified’’ critical

‘‘negation’’ is made explicit on a later page: ‘‘Dialectics is the quest to see

the new in the old instead of just the old in the new. As it mediates the new,

so it also preserves the old as the mediated. If it were to proceed accord-

ing to the schema of sheer flow and indiscriminate vitality (Lebendigkeit ),then it would degrade itself to a replica of the amorphous structure of nature,

which it should not sanction through mimicry, but surpass through cogni-

tion. Dialectic gives its own to the old as reified and consolidated, which dia-

lectic can move only by releasing the force of its own weight.’’16Dialectics,

a.k.a. ‘‘immanent critique,’’ must ‘‘not sanction through mimicry, but surpass

through cognition’’: this usefully enlarges the ‘‘repeat and reliquify’’ motif,

14. Adorno, Negative Dialectics, 151–53.15. Theodor W. Adorno, Against Epistemology: A Metacritique, trans. Willis Domingo (Ox-

ford: Blackwell, 1982), 5.

16. Adorno, Against Epistemology, 38–39.

Page 13: Steve Helmling - 'Immanent Critique' and 'Dialetical Mimesis' in Adorno & Horkheimer's Dialectic of Enlightenment

Helmling / ‘‘Immanent Critique’’ and ‘‘Dialectical Mimesis’’ 109

but more to my present point is the preemption of the Lukács complaint

in the warning lest critique ‘‘degrade itself . . . to a replica of . . . nature’’

(this last, the signifier here of the ‘‘naturalizations’’ of the cultural that are

the specific work and effect of ideology as such, the mystifying will to ‘‘sanc-

tion through mimicry’’). The point I want to bring out—and it is a cautionary

one—is the liability of ‘‘immanent [or ‘‘dialectical’’] critique’’ to such dangers:

because it must ‘‘repeat’’ in order to ‘‘reliquify’’ or ‘‘surpass,’’ it must per-

force risk approaching a ‘‘replica[tion]’’ or ‘‘mimicry’’ of its ideological object.

It must risk appearing as an example or symptom, as Lukács charged, or

as itself ‘‘mythical,’’ as Habermas warned. It cannot contest what Dialecticof Enlightenment calls ‘‘the power of repetition over reality’’ 17 without riskingthe danger of succumbing to it, or at least of appearing to. Which, for critique

‘‘as a kind of writing,’’ means something in the realm of the critical like the

property the German philosophical tradition ambiguously or polysemously

denominates, in the realm of the aesthetic, as ‘‘Schein’’—appearance or illu-

sion: the artful contrivance, variously concealing its own art or, in modern

times, more critically baring its own device(s), whereby any composition,

whether of art or of critique, hesitates between the aesthetic as ideology

and (Adorno’s burden in Aesthetic Theory) the aesthetic as bearer of truth.So immanent critique must pursue, in the writing, and less as pre-

scription than as inevitable burden, a strategy of something like whatDialec-tic of Enlightenment seems to indict: ‘‘mimesis.’’ This word signals one of themost unstable, most conflicted—why not say most ‘‘dialectical’’?—motifs in

the book.18For most of us, the word’s primary association will probably be

with Aristotle’s Poetics—themirror held up to nature—but this is an associa-

tionDialectic of Enlightenment studiously avoids. In the Horkheimer/Adornotext, mimesis is primarily a synecdoche for the mythic and even premythic

habitus of archaic consciousness and the proto-Enlightenment attempt, at

first to propitiate nature, then to dominate it, by means of ‘‘sympathetic

magic.’’ (This context, opening Aristotle’s ‘‘mimesis’’ to its archaic foretime,

can quite eclipse its sequels in the more familiar and more recent cultural

past of Europe, and, indeed, I suspect Horkheimer and Adorno mean to

estrange or defamiliarize those meanings, so complicit in the ideology of

the aesthetic in the West, and thereby to expose the degree to which West-

17. MaxHorkheimer and TheodorW. Adorno,Dialectic of Enlightenment, trans. JohnCum-ming (New York: Continuum, 1988), 12.

18. For the most interesting discussion of Adorno’s ‘‘mimesis’’ I know, see Fredric Jame-

son, Late Marxism (London and New York: Verso, 1990), 63–69, 101–5. See also Hullot-

Kentor, ‘‘Introduction to Adorno’s ‘Idea of Natural History,’ ’’ 107–8.

Page 14: Steve Helmling - 'Immanent Critique' and 'Dialetical Mimesis' in Adorno & Horkheimer's Dialectic of Enlightenment

110 boundary 2 / Fall 2005

ern aesthetics, having retrojected its own detached, alienated, enlightened,

‘‘instrumentalized’’ purposes—the emotional self-management of cathar-sis—back on Aristotle, has distorted its reading of him ever since.)

‘‘Mimesis’’ thus reoriented to the consciousness of ‘‘before Aris-

totle’’—that is, to the thematics evoked in Dialectic of Enlightenment by wayof such terms as ‘‘[sympathetic] magic,’’ ‘‘ritual,’’ ‘‘myth,’’ as well as ‘‘mimesis’’

itself, and via allusion, to the figure of Odysseus and the Sirens—summa-

rizes a complex of devices and practices, indeed ruses, akin to the Nietz-

schean imaginary and to the Marxist and modernist senses of ideology. To

that extent, ‘‘mimesis’’ would seem to figure as a virtual epitome of what

immanent critique aims to subvert. But as we have seen, immanent cri-

tique itself must ‘‘repeat’’ its object, must incur the risk of ‘‘replicating’’ it or

‘‘mimicking’’ it—and to that extent, ‘‘mimesis’’ is critique’s ownmost potent, if

also most treacherous, device: indeed, the potency and the treachery must

be its very condition. If ideological ‘‘mimesis’’ is the problem or danger, the

solution or program involves a ‘‘mimesis’’ that I will here call ‘‘dialectical’’—

in justification of which I might cite the analogy with Benjamin’s usage of

‘‘image’’ and, or against, ‘‘dialectical image,’’ a usage Adorno expounds in

numerous places.19With Sloterdijk again in mind, we might say that ‘‘dia-

lectical mimesis’’ enacts a kind of satirical parody, but with affects of angst

and rage rather than the Sloterdijkian ‘‘cynical’’ or ‘‘cheeky’’ (Bergsonian)

laughter of mockery. (Readers familiar with Michael Cahn’s rich essay ‘‘Sub-

versive Mimesis’’ will recognize a family resemblance between his refunc-

tioning of Adorno’s ‘‘mimesis’’ and mine here.20Cahn pursues the argument

with much more grounding in and reference to philosophy than I could do,

and his discussion aims to illuminate Adorno’s aesthetic theory—or indeed

his Aesthetic Theory—rather than, as I hope to do here, Adorno’s writing

practice and the difficulties it poses for readers.)

My suggestion now is that we take Dialectic of Enlightenment itselfas a test or probe of this ‘‘dialectical mimesis’’ I am proposing. We may take

the book as a kind of historical narrative, and therefore, like (presumably)

any historical analysis or explanation, to that extent a dialectical mimesis of

Western history or civilization itself. But a more concrete grasp of the text’s

19. For our present point, see especially Theodor W. Adorno, Kierkegaard: Constructionof the Aesthetic, trans. Robert Hullot-Kentor (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press,1989), 54.

20. Michael Cahn, ‘‘Subversive Mimesis: Theodor W. Adorno and the Modern Impasse of

Critique,’’ inMimesis in Contemporary Theory, ed. Mihai Spariosu, vol. 1 (Philadelphia andAmsterdam: John Benjamins, 1984), 27–64.

Page 15: Steve Helmling - 'Immanent Critique' and 'Dialetical Mimesis' in Adorno & Horkheimer's Dialectic of Enlightenment

Helmling / ‘‘Immanent Critique’’ and ‘‘Dialectical Mimesis’’ 111

ambitions may be allowed by considering its relation to a precedent textu-

alization of that ambition—and it is my suggestion here that we consider

Dialectic of Enlightenment for a moment ‘‘as if’’ it were a parodic rescript ofHegel’sPhenomenology of Spirit. Notice I said ‘‘as if’’—or I might use the old

Hegelian/Marxist (and Adorno) word, objectively : the point being that the

resonances are significant, whether Adorno and Horkheimer intended them

or not, although I will go on the record with my conviction that they did. How-

ever that may be, the resonances are there, simply as part of the vast social

and historical fact Horkheimer and Adorno mean to confront—which turns

out to entail, besides Hegel himself, the whole debased Hegelian aftermath

in the conventions or ideology of historicist explanation in the bourgeois age,

from fascism’s reactionary fantasias of racialist agon, through the progres-

sive or meliorist story of liberalism, to its revolutionary variants extending

to ‘‘official’’ Soviet orthodoxies of ‘‘dialectical materialism’’ (‘‘diamat,’’ in the

neologistic party-speak Adorno so loathed) and the providential historical

happy endings they were fashioned to underwrite.

The affinities of Dialectic of Enlightenment with Phenomenology ofSpirit are numerous and suggestive. Both books were written in a moment

of crisis perceived by their authors as world-historical, and both aim to diag-

nose and even to prescribe for the cultural pathologies, extending back into

an immemorial foretime, of their respective cultural moments. The table of

contents of Dialectic of Enlightenment discloses a narrative and historical

arc broadly similar to Hegel’s, orchestrating a passage from Greek antiquity

to the period of the Enlightenment proper, and thence to the present-day

moment at the height of World War II in which Horkheimer and Adorno are

writing. This historicizing organization, the antique and modern instances

chosen for elaboration, and the proportions allotted to them, all invite us to

take Dialectic of Enlightenment as a production, albeit on a smaller scale,

on the model of Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit. Horkheimer and Adornorenew Hegel’s terminology and supplement it with newer ones—Marxist,

Nietzschean, Weberian, Freudian—that have emerged since Hegel; but

their account of the devolution of philosophy into a mere handmaiden of

(positivist) science, and the attendant reification of thinking as instrumen-

talized to serve the purposes of scientific and technological ‘‘rationaliza-

tion,’’ is recognizably a continuation of Hegel’s story, although, of course, an

ironic one: a nightmare sequel to an overture (a terminal overture, Hegel

had supposed) that, in Hegel’s enthusiastic afflatus, had promised a con-

siderably happier finale. Indeed, this issue—‘‘optimism’’ versus ‘‘pessimism’’

was the mid-century topos—marks the fundamental dissent or ‘‘contradic-

Page 16: Steve Helmling - 'Immanent Critique' and 'Dialetical Mimesis' in Adorno & Horkheimer's Dialectic of Enlightenment

112 boundary 2 / Fall 2005

tion’’ or ‘‘negation’’ that Horkheimer and Adorno’s ‘‘unhappy [critical] con-

sciousness’’ operates on Hegel. Hegel diagnosed unhappy consciousness

and prescribed for it in ways anticipating the morale-management counsels

of Nietzsche andWilliam James, in the faith that modernity would eventually

enable a universal ‘‘happy consciousness.’’ The ‘‘textual effect’’ or affect ofDialectic of Enlightenment joins the darker tone of Sigmund Freud, OswaldSpengler, Thomas Mann, T. S. Eliot, and many other moderns whose drift,

especially post-1914, is that the current situation and prospects are grim.

(Dialectic of Enlightenment thereby not only contravenes the bien-pensant

liberal hopes of the day but defies the ‘‘official’’ party-line ‘‘optimism’’ of

the Soviet bloc, the Stalinist Comintern of that period, in which ‘‘defeatism’’

could be a capital [thought-] crime.)

But Dialectic of Enlightenment enacts a more corrosive ‘‘dialecti-

cal mimesis’’ of Hegel-and-after on the level of narrative itself. The book

organizes its argument around binary pairs that link disjunct historical phe-

nomena—most saliently, ‘‘myth’’/‘‘Enlightenment’’ and ‘‘Odysseus’’/‘‘bour-

geois.’’ These binaries initially seem the conventional constituents of a famil-

iar modernizing historicism, but they turn out to act in the book not as

opposed (historical) pairs but as virtual transhistorical equations or (to make

the ideological baggage more explicit) ‘‘identities’’: in the latter instance,

exposing nineteenth-century philology’s fetishization of the Homeric pro-

tagonist as ‘‘universal’’ hero; in the former, deconstructing (if you’ll permit

the anachronism) the binary terms of Enlightenment’s own self-constituting

ancients/moderns narrative. Both work to activate the downside, as it were,

of ‘‘equivalence’’ or ‘‘exchange’’ logic: in the one case, offering a ‘‘dialecti-

cal image/mimesis’’ of the equivalence that bourgeois modernity wants to

embrace; in the second, enforcing an equivalence it seeks to disown. And

in both cases, and in many other instances passim, we get not the his-

torical narrative that mediates the development from one to the other but

a sequence of nonnarrative juxtapositions—what Adorno probably learned

from Benjamin to call ‘‘constellations’’—enforcing the point that the narra-

tive of progress has not only stalled but now (1944) looks to have been a

deception or ‘‘ruse of history’’ all along, insofar as it has masked history’s

chronic steady-state or (the same thing?) cycle of ‘‘repetition,’’ blocking our

recognition that the history we are living out is not a narrative of progress,

reason, and freedom, but a stasis, or even a regress, of violence and domi-

nation. Recall here Benjamin’s aphorism that every document of civilization

is also a document of barbarism. In Dialectic of Enlightenment, the progres-sive world story becomes the failure of the narrative to realize not only its

Page 17: Steve Helmling - 'Immanent Critique' and 'Dialetical Mimesis' in Adorno & Horkheimer's Dialectic of Enlightenment

Helmling / ‘‘Immanent Critique’’ and ‘‘Dialectical Mimesis’’ 113

thematic or programmatic telos, human liberation, but, more fundamentally,its generic or formal constitutive sine qua non, narrativity itself.

J. M. Bernstein coolly scorns this way of reading Dialectic of Enlight-enment, summoning earlier scholars, from Susan Buck-Morss to Robert

Hullot-Kentor, to his aid, citing, however, passages that do not, at least to my

reading eye, quitemake his case for him.21Bernstein wants to see the critical

force ofDialectic of Enlightenment as trained not on Enlightenment’s histori-cist narrative investments but rather on the ‘‘conceptual dualism’’ underlying

them—and to that extent his reading can be brought to square with mine.

Where Bernstein seems to me to misplace the emphasis is in the assump-

tion that in the face of an apparent dichotomy in Adorno, a reader’s task is to

decide on one side or the other; my own experience learning to read Adorno

is that he is almost always looking for ways to reinforce the dichotomy, to

exploit its dichotomousness—its ‘‘contradictoriness’’—to critical (i.e., dialec-

tical) effect. I would, rather, put it that Dialectic of Enlightenment expressesits critique of the West’s detemporalized, nonnarrative, ‘‘conceptual dual-

ism’’ by deconcealing the petrification or ‘‘standstill’’ that dualism wreaks

on its own narrative categories: that in Adorno, the horns of the dichotomy

are mobilized precisely in order to im -mobilize each other, to perform the

ways in which our culture’s fundamental contradictions, and their ideologi-

cal denial, can disclose themselves only in the condition—or the ‘‘dialectical

mimesis’’—of ‘‘dialectic at a standstill’’: conceptual dualities arresting, freez-

ing, petrifying the very narrative progress and movement they were meant

to release.

‘‘Dialectic at a standstill’’: that watchword of Benjamin’s is often cited

by Adorno as evocation of the modern condition—and hence another moti-

vation for the failed narrativity of Dialectic of Enlightenment, as ‘‘dialecti-

cal mimesis’’ of the stalled or arrested dialectic of history itself. Recall, to

begin with, that in Hegel, dialectic is ineluctably temporalized, historicized,narrativized. Hence a (large) degree of commutativity between narrativeand dialectic in the ideological constellation Dialectic of Enlightenment con-structs: if the Enlightenment narrative is rendered non- or even antinarra-

tively, the conventions of dialectic are likewise contravened in usages pro-

vocatively non- or antidialectical. If binaries like ‘‘myth/Enlightenment’’ or

‘‘Odysseus/bourgeois’’ elide narrativity and history, they equally elide dia-

lectic, for the conjoined terms are rather identified than mediated, dedif-

ferentiated as we now say, as if the point is their ‘‘essential’’ homogeneity

21. Bernstein, Adorno: Disenchantment and Ethics, 84–86; see esp. 86n18.

Page 18: Steve Helmling - 'Immanent Critique' and 'Dialetical Mimesis' in Adorno & Horkheimer's Dialectic of Enlightenment

114 boundary 2 / Fall 2005

rather than their qualitative, mutually negating differences. And likewise for

the other kind of binary the book mobilizes, the kind that conjoins contem-

poraneous pairs, like de Sade and Kant, or anti-Semitism and Hollywood.

In our present-day academic subculture, this would already be a politically

incorrect enough way of putting it; in 1944, with Stalin’s assassins patrolling

the globe for ‘‘class enemies,’’ it was a provocation of potentially dire conse-

quence (recall the fate of Trotsky [August 1940] just a few years before the

publication of Dialectic of Enlightenment [May 1944]).Part of my point in summarizing the aims of Dialectic of Enlighten-

ment in these terms is to foreground how very different is Horkheimer and

Adorno’s (in)version of Hegel from Marx’s. Marx claimed to have turned

Hegel right-side up, putting his idealist headstand squarely back where it

belongs, on its materialist feet—but Marx’s figure owns that he and Hegel

are talking about the same biped, and the same configuration of posture

(vertical) andmobility (ambulatory). In Marx, as in Hegel, we have a forward-

moving story, an indisputably narrative dynamic; the coloration of particu-

lar episodes and themes varies between the two—the story of alienation,

of Aufhebung, of human beings rendered thing-like, but achieving the self-

consciousness of the ‘‘für Sich’’ in the end—but the happiness of the provi-

dential ending and the kinetic momentum of the whole progress to it are

macrofeatures that Hegel andMarx have toomuch in common to allow them

to appear as anything other than variants of a shared set of themes and

(more fundamentally) of presuppositions regarding the use of historical nar-

rative in works of social interpretation, explanation, diagnosis, and critique.

Dialectic of Enlightenment asserts its own place in the array by way ofa much more radical refunctioning of its terms and its operations—most tell-

ingly, in the extent to which the Horkheimer/Adorno retelling of the Enlight-

enment/Hegelian/Marxist metanarrative is so little narrative in its effect.

Granted Marx’s boast, that he had inverted Hegel’s story (stood it on its

head/feet), he still narrated it according to storytelling conventions recog-

nizably of the same type, bearing marked family resemblances, to Hegel’s

own. Horkheimer and Adorno’s narrative is much more ambiguously nar-

rative; it does not so much tell the story as elaborate chosen moments or

images (dialectical images?) from it; it presupposes the reader’s knowledge

of the story’s basic narrative, and turns the energy thus released from nar-

ration to eliciting resonances and potencies undeveloped in the narrative’s

earlier versions. Though the narrative interest of the precedent ‘‘story’’ nec-

essarily prolongs itself inDialectic of Enlightenment, the narrative impulse isclearly subordinate to the interpretive; and to that extent the book stands to

Page 19: Steve Helmling - 'Immanent Critique' and 'Dialetical Mimesis' in Adorno & Horkheimer's Dialectic of Enlightenment

Helmling / ‘‘Immanent Critique’’ and ‘‘Dialectical Mimesis’’ 115

Hegel-and-Marx in a relation in some ways like that of Midrash to Torah. But

that analogy needs qualification, to the extent that both scripture and com-

mentary minimize affect: the biblical narratives are terse as if precisely to

purge affective or aesthetic power, ‘‘textual effect’’ or affect. (On the theory

that the Torah narratives are prose synopses of originally much longer, and

more libidinally invested, oral narratives, intended precisely to deprive those

bardic narratives of the affective power pagans associated with divine inspi-

ration [the Muses], we might speculate that biblical narrative’s estrange-

ments of narrative effects or affects anticipate the Republic ’s expulsion of

the poets.)

By contrast, the affective program I have ascribed to Horkheimer

and Adorno here, to arouse Enlightenment to its chronically suppressed

‘‘fear,’’ to disturb Enlightenment’s ‘‘tranquility of mind,’’ to arouse Enlighten-

ment’s ‘‘bad conscience,’’ adds to the mode of Midrashic exposition an emo-

tionalism, a ‘‘labor of affectualization,’’ absent in the precursor text(s); here

the analogy that comes to mind is Aeschylus’s sensationalizing reconstitu-

tion of Homeric epos, in which the familiar epic story need not be retold—

the audience already knows the plot—so that the hypnagogic work of the

choral song can concentrate instead on a stroboscopic activation of the

story’s most horrific associations, as when the Chorus in the Agamem-non is beset by images from the curse-of-Atreus story (a boiling pot of

infant limbs! a mighty fleet becalmed at sea! a princess’s lovely neck bared

to the sacrificial knife!) so elliptically, but also so obsessively, as to moti-

vate the elision of their collectively known narrative context as a collec-

tive effort to repress collective anxieties that are recurring with the force of

nightmare. (Compare the similar impulse in a more contemporary instance,

Christopher Logue’s operatic workouts on the Iliad.) The nobility of the

Homeric grand style, idealized since antiquity, has much to do with what

Horkheimer and Adorno indict as its ‘‘narrative composure’’;22Aeschylus’s

rescript (and Logue’s) represses the narrative the better to distill from its

imageries the panic Homer’s ‘‘composure’’ composes—and however delib-

erately, Horkheimer and Adorno seem to me to stand in some such rela-

tion to Hegel, or at least to that side of him they most deplore, his Panglos-

sian, happy-consciousness, theodicy-mongering ‘‘optimism.’’ The intrusion,

into the quasi- or evenmock-Hegelian habitus ofDialectic of Enlightenment,of de Sade and Nietzsche, anti-Semitism and Hollywood, ‘‘motivates’’ this

gesture.

22. Horkheimer and Adorno, Dialectic of Enlightenment, 78–80.

Page 20: Steve Helmling - 'Immanent Critique' and 'Dialetical Mimesis' in Adorno & Horkheimer's Dialectic of Enlightenment

116 boundary 2 / Fall 2005

In doing so (again), Dialectic of Enlightenment projects a panoramaof catastrophe that mobilizes Marx as readily as Hegel, and without miti-

gating the force of its anti-Enlightenment indictments against either. But par-

ticular or ‘‘party’’ ideological provocations aside, Dialectic of Enlightenmentmeans to present a vision of global cultural catastrophe that challenges the

competing received partisan scenarios. It is addressed to readers of good

will—at least, potentially, of all ideological stripes. To loyal communists, it

says that their party-line optimism is fraudulent, that the revolution under

Stalin partakes of a barbarism every bit as savage as the alternatives. To

right-wingers short of outright fascism, conservatives like, say, Spengler, it

offers something like a ‘‘dialectical mimesis’’ of The Decline of the West, butone in which the catastrophe appears as present, not future, and is attended

by anguish rather than the paradoxically anodyne knowingness typical of

early-modern ‘‘cultural despair’’ reactionaries of the Spengler type. Most

complicatedly, it addresses liberals and non-Stalinist leftists, inheritors and

stewards of the ‘‘Enlightenment’’ tradition, whose received view of the catas-

trophe—that the bad guys, the forces of darkness, are winning—they affront

by diagnosing the failures and shortcomings of the good guys themselves,

of Enlightenment itself. In their account of Enlightenment’s devolution or

regression into barbarism, via positivism, scientism, ‘‘identity-thinking,’’ anti-

theorism, and literal-mindedness of all kinds, they enact the failure of the

Enlightenment narrative not only to achieve its narrative telos but also to

maintain its dialectical ethos—whether or not it is still telling itself that pro-

gressive or revolutionary story, or (as in the USSR) fetishizing the word

dialectic itself. They narrate the failure of the Enlightenment narrative to

achieve narrativity, as well as the failure of Enlightenment dialectic to be dia-

lectical. As if dialectic itself could be subject to ‘‘negation’’—and not ‘‘deter-minate negation,’’ the kind that alters quality, but an annihilation, that is

reduction ad nihil, to zero, that, in the terms of Horkheimer and Adorno’s

indictment of Enlightenment, liquidates ‘‘quality’’ altogether, and therefore

‘‘dialectic’’ itself, leaving only the ‘‘bad infinity’’ of the merely quantitative, the

domain in which the logic of equivalence/exchange has its limited but lethal

validity. This, as Dialectic of Enlightenment projects it, is the irony, or indeedthe peculiar ‘‘dialectic,’’ of the ‘‘dialectic of Enlightenment.’’

Horkheimer and Adorno’s evocation of the failure is the most potent

such book of the mid-century period, a period peculiarly rich in efforts at

cultural diagnosis—and I include here everything from prewar works such

as Freud’s Civilization and Its Discontents and Spengler’s Decline of theWest to such postwar productions as Norman O. Brown’s Life Against

Page 21: Steve Helmling - 'Immanent Critique' and 'Dialetical Mimesis' in Adorno & Horkheimer's Dialectic of Enlightenment

Helmling / ‘‘Immanent Critique’’ and ‘‘Dialectical Mimesis’’ 117

Death, Herbert Marcuse’s Eros and Civilization, and Erich Fromm’s Flightfrom Freedom. Dialectic of Enlightenment remains an epitome of critical

‘‘unhappy consciousness,’’ fully answering to the angst, rage, and despair

of the ‘‘during-Auschwitz’’ ordeal and, prophetically, to the ‘‘after-Auschwitz’’

prolongation, in which the fact that the killing at Auschwitz had ceased

offered so little comfort in view of the prospect of global murder opened by

the nuclear attacks against Hiroshima and Nagasaki. In the 1944 introduc-

tion, Horkheimer and Adorno explain that all rhetorics of ‘‘affirmation’’ are by

now so compromised as to make affirmation itself a lie—a premise that all

but forecloses any possibility of the utopian in the book itself. Yet the book

has its hints of utopian hope—a hope indissociable from a sense of the dia-

lectic simply as the historically unforeseeable but capable of horror as well

as blessings: not at all the providential stand-in for God, deus ex machina

all too familiarized in progressive and revolutionary storytelling. Against all

optimisms from Hegel to Stalin and beyond, Horkheimer and Adorno de-

conceal a historical dialectic leading to catastrophe rather than reconcilia-

tion, an Absolute of despair rather than exaltation, a Golgotha of the Spirit or

‘‘slaughterbench of history’’ more literal and more atrocious than any Hegel

could ever have imagined, projected indeed as the apparent liquidation of

dialectic itself. This is, in 1944, the look—the ‘‘dialectical mimesis’’—of the

dialectic very specifically of Enlightenment.