should we save nature’s hidden gems? - ned...

21
1 Should we Save Nature’s Hidden Gems? Abstract Aesthetic preservation is the idea of sparing natural areas from development because of their aesthetic value. In this essay I discuss a problem for aesthetic preservation that I call the ‘hidden gems problem’: in certain cases, the natural area under consideration is so remote and/or fragile that very few people can actually experience its aesthetic value. In these cases, it becomes unclear how nature’s aesthetic value can serve as a logical justification for its preservation, when development promises practical human benefits. After rejecting three potential responses to the hidden gems problem, I offer a different solution. I argue that we have an aesthetic reason to preserve nature’s hidden gems because they are required to produce ‘true judges’ of aesthetic value, who are capable of improving the general quality of taste for landscape. In developing this argument, I offer a critique of some recent preservationist efforts to save the isolated landscape of Sable Island, Nova Scotia. Aesthetic preservation is the idea that, although the development of some natural area could provide economic benefits, we should forgo these benefits and preserve the area in its natural state because of its aesthetic value. Many preservationists and environmental philosophers have found this an appealing idea. 1 However, the notion of aesthetic preservation faces difficulty when the natural area in question is inaccessible or fragile, preventing all but a few from aesthetically appreciating it. In this paper, I aim to lend some support to the idea of aesthetic preservation, by arguing that it can be extended to these difficult cases. I begin by introducing, in a general way, the concept of aesthetic preservation, discussing some of its attractions and also some potential problems with it (§§1-2). Then, in the main part of the paper (§§3-5), I discuss the aforementioned cases, which I call cases of ‘hidden gems’ in nature, which present special difficulties for aesthetic preservation. Drawing on some aesthetic theory, and particularly on some of the ideas of David Hume, I argue that even in these cases it makes sense to consider preserving nature on aesthetic grounds. I conclude by discussing a potential objection to my argument (§6).

Upload: others

Post on 28-Jan-2020

4 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Should we Save Nature’s Hidden Gems? - Ned Hettingerhettingern.people.cofc.edu/Env_Aes_2012/Parsons_Should we save natures... · Should we Save Nature’s Hidden Gems? Abstract

1

Should we Save Nature’s Hidden Gems?

Abstract

Aesthetic preservation is the idea of sparing natural areas from development because of their aesthetic value. In this essay I discuss a problem for aesthetic preservation that I call the ‘hidden gems problem’: in certain cases, the natural area under consideration is so remote and/or fragile that very few people can actually experience its aesthetic value. In these cases, it becomes unclear how nature’s aesthetic value can serve as a logical justification for its preservation, when development promises practical human benefits. After rejecting three potential responses to the hidden gems problem, I offer a different solution. I argue that we have an aesthetic reason to preserve nature’s hidden gems because they are required to produce ‘true judges’ of aesthetic value, who are capable of improving the general quality of taste for landscape. In developing this argument, I offer a critique of some recent preservationist efforts to save the isolated landscape of Sable Island, Nova Scotia.

Aesthetic preservation is the idea that, although the development of some natural area

could provide economic benefits, we should forgo these benefits and preserve the area in its

natural state because of its aesthetic value. Many preservationists and environmental

philosophers have found this an appealing idea.1 However, the notion of aesthetic preservation

faces difficulty when the natural area in question is inaccessible or fragile, preventing all but a

few from aesthetically appreciating it. In this paper, I aim to lend some support to the idea of

aesthetic preservation, by arguing that it can be extended to these difficult cases.

I begin by introducing, in a general way, the concept of aesthetic preservation,

discussing some of its attractions and also some potential problems with it (§§1-2). Then, in the

main part of the paper (§§3-5), I discuss the aforementioned cases, which I call cases of ‘hidden

gems’ in nature, which present special difficulties for aesthetic preservation. Drawing on some

aesthetic theory, and particularly on some of the ideas of David Hume, I argue that even in

these cases it makes sense to consider preserving nature on aesthetic grounds. I conclude by

discussing a potential objection to my argument (§6).

Page 2: Should we Save Nature’s Hidden Gems? - Ned Hettingerhettingern.people.cofc.edu/Env_Aes_2012/Parsons_Should we save natures... · Should we Save Nature’s Hidden Gems? Abstract

2

1. The Appeal of Aesthetic Preservation

As mentioned, aesthetic preservation is the idea of sparing natural areas for their

aesthetic value, or their beauty.2 In actuality, debates over the preservation of natural areas

are rarely, if ever, couched solely in aesthetic terms. To make their case, preservationists

typically appeal to a range of factors: economic, ecological, moral, and so on. Nonetheless, the

aesthetic value of nature is a recurrent theme in preservation debates. As the environmental

philosopher Holmes Rolston once put it, ‘Ask people, “Why save the Grand Canyon?” and the

ready answer will be “Because it is so beautiful. So grand!” ‘3 So although it is by no means the

only rationale for preserving nature, aesthetic value is an important one.

As an illustration, consider the case of the Arctic National Wildlife Refuge (ANWR) in

northern Alaska. ANWR is located on the northeast coast of Alaska, bordering on the Yukon

Territories of Canada. The refuge was designated a protected area by the United States

government in 1960, and today spans over seven million hectares (roughly the area of

Belgium). It is home to many animal and bird species, including the large, migratory Porcupine

Caribou herd. The refuge has virtually no human inhabitants, although a native group, the

Gwich’in people, live near the refuge and have traditionally relied on the Porcupine herd for

food and clothing. The refuge also contains oil deposits, which has led to proposals to open it to

petroleum development. Opponents of drilling in ANWR have appealed to many

considerations, including potential harm to the Porcupine Caribou herd and, thereby, to the

Gwich’in who depend upon it. But aesthetic motivations are front and centre in their

campaigns: the various “save ANWR” websites all prominently feature striking photographs of

the refuge. One group’s website speaks of ‘the unique beauty’ of the area, calling it ‘a crown

jewel’ of the North.4 The National Resource Defense Council’s website describes it as a ‘one of

our true wilderness gems’.5 Another website calls it ‘a wilderness jewel… one of the most

beautiful and breathtaking places on Earth.’6 Indeed, not only preservationist advocacy groups

find this idea appealing. When asked why he opposed drilling in ANWR, during the 2008

Presidential election, Republican candidate John McCain replied: ‘This is one of the most

pristine and beautiful parts of the world.’7 Aesthetic preservation, then, is clearly an attractive

notion to many people.

Page 3: Should we Save Nature’s Hidden Gems? - Ned Hettingerhettingern.people.cofc.edu/Env_Aes_2012/Parsons_Should we save natures... · Should we Save Nature’s Hidden Gems? Abstract

3

But why is this idea so attractive? Clearly, one reason is simply that we care about

aesthetic value in general: it can be as disturbing to think about sacrificing an aesthetically

outstanding natural area, such as the ANWR, for oil as it is to think of burning Da Vinci’s

canvases for firewood. A second reason involves the fact that aesthetic value presents itself to

our senses, and is something we can see. Because of this, appeals to aesthetic value can have a

strong rhetorical impact in preservation debates. Photographs showing beautiful nature, and

images showing the potential aesthetic impact of proposed developments, have an immediate,

visceral impact that isn’t generated by generated by talk of moral duties to nature or charts and

tables detailing long-term ecological impacts. This is surely why the websites mentioned earlier

feature such images so prominently in their preservation campaigns.

But there is also a deeper, more philosophical motive for appealing to aesthetic value, if

you are a preservationist. As mentioned, there are other reasons why we might preserve

nature—the economic, the ecological, and so on—but it can be argued that these must boil

down, in the end, to practical human interests. For instance, someone might insist that we

preserve a forest because it houses a species that is vital to some local ecosystem. But then the

question is: Why do we need to preserve the integrity of this ecosystem? It seems that some

connection to the maintenance of practical human interests, such as health or resource

sustainability, must eventually be established. And some environmentalists think this approach

won’t be enough to prevent widespread destruction of nature. They believe that we must

recognize that nature has a sort of value that does not rest upon its serving practical human

interests. But what could this value be?

One possibility is to take into account the practical interests of other living organisms.

We might argue, for instance, that creatures such as caribou have practical needs and interests

(food, water, space), as humans do. As we take human practical interests into account when

deciding what is valuable and worth preserving, perhaps we ought also to take into account the

practical interests of non-human organisms such as caribou. Such organisms can suffer and be

harmed, in some sense, when these interests are frustrated, as human beings can. This line of

thought might provide a basis for attempting to preserve some natural areas. Thus, we might

Page 4: Should we Save Nature’s Hidden Gems? - Ned Hettingerhettingern.people.cofc.edu/Env_Aes_2012/Parsons_Should we save natures... · Should we Save Nature’s Hidden Gems? Abstract

4

say that we shouldn’t drill for oil in ANWR because it would harm the animals that live there,

such as the Porcupine caribou.

However, this line of thought seems not to take us far enough. For those who oppose

development in ANWR, for example, would surely not be satisfied if the oil companies agreed

to move the Porcupine caribou herd to some safe location, and then drill for oil in ANWR. Nor

would they be happy even if it could be shown that building roads, erecting oil platforms and

drilling would not substantially harm the caribou, or the other flora and fauna in the reserve, at

all. It is the place itself, in addition to the well-being of the creatures it shelters, that they see as

valuable and that, accordingly, they want to see preserved.

But at this point the preservationist is confronted with a very difficult question: if some

area isn’t really needed to satisfy the practical interests of any relevant creatures (human or

non-human), why should we see it as valuable, and worth preserving? In response to this

question, some philosophers have tried to argue that the mere fact that something is natural

confers value on it. But the injunction to value nature is not likely to be compelling unless we

are given further reasons for doing so. For much in nature simply seems bad, or at least

regrettable: think about the omnipresent suffering and death that is a regular part of the

animal world. If something in the—frankly, often quite horrific—realm of the natural is good

and worth saving, surely there is a reason why.

This is where aesthetic value comes into the picture, promising to offer us a neat

solution. If we say that nature should be preserved for its aesthetic value, we are offering a

familiar and compelling human reason for saving nature. But at the same time, the aesthetic

value of natural things does not reduce to the practical or economic benefits that they bring us.

Their aesthetic value does not arise from our manipulating or using them, but only from our

looking and listening to them. Aesthetic value, then, seems to be just what the preservationist

wants: it is a good reason to preserve nature even when we gain no practical benefit from

doing so. So if you are an environmentalist, you might think that this idea is, well—bliss!

Page 5: Should we Save Nature’s Hidden Gems? - Ned Hettingerhettingern.people.cofc.edu/Env_Aes_2012/Parsons_Should we save natures... · Should we Save Nature’s Hidden Gems? Abstract

5

2. Limitations of Aesthetic Preservation

As a rationale for preserving nature, however, aesthetic preservation also has its

problems.8 In this section, I consider five of these. As I have discussed them in detail

elsewhere, I will not treat them in depth, or try to offer solutions to all of them here.9 Rather, I

will briefly table them in order to bring idea of aesthetic preservation into better focus and to

introduce some ideas that will later play a role in the main argument of the paper.

The most obvious and immediate concern involves weighing aesthetic value against

practical benefits. Say that an area is aesthetically excellent, but that developing it would

deliver three hundred well-paying jobs for the next fifty years. Aesthetic preservation requires

that the aesthetic value here outweigh the economic benefit. But is this really so? How do we

weigh aesthetic pleasure against food on the table for families? The very idea of such a

comparison raises many difficult issues.

A second problem with aesthetic preservation is the worry that aesthetic value is

subjective, and that people will therefore have conflicting opinions about the aesthetic value of

any given natural area. If this is true, then environmentalists may find that aesthetic value is not

a very effective tool for convincing others that nature must be spared from development. A

nice example of this disagreement in taste occurred during a debate about drilling in ANWR

several years ago. Responding to calls to save the beauty of the area, the late Senator Ted

Stevens from Alaska thundered: ‘I defy anyone to say that that is a beautiful place that has to

be preserved for the future. It is a barren wasteland, [a] frozen wasteland ….it is just constant,

constant, constant tundra, no trees, no beauty at all.’10

Stevens’ comment nicely illustrates the worry about disagreement over the beauty of

nature, even the so-called ‘wilderness jewels’. But perhaps his comment also answers it as well.

For Stevens’ claim seems wildly idiosyncratic, a bit like the claim that Shakespeare couldn’t

write. It is hard to deny that wilderness, such as the landscape of ANWR, has become a

paradigm of beauty for our culture. Perhaps aesthetic value is subjective, but even if it is, there

is probably enough agreement on the beauty of wilderness to make aesthetic preservation a

viable strategy.11

Page 6: Should we Save Nature’s Hidden Gems? - Ned Hettingerhettingern.people.cofc.edu/Env_Aes_2012/Parsons_Should we save natures... · Should we Save Nature’s Hidden Gems? Abstract

6

This leads us on to a third problem, however, which is that we find this sort of general

agreement only about the aesthetic excellence of some parts of nature (ANWR, for example).

Other parts of nature seem to be commonly viewed as aesthetically bad. Of wetlands, for

instance, Rolston goes so far as to suggest that, in our minds, these places ‘have ‘ugliness’ built

into them’: phrases like ‘beautiful bog’ and ‘pleasant mire’ are, he notes, ‘almost a

contradiction in terms’.12 Yuriko Saito describes such parts of nature, with tongue in cheek, as

the ‘scenically challenged’.13 The existence of the ‘scenically challenged’ means that, if we base

preservation on aesthetics, we will tend to get a skewed selection of protected landscapes.

What we get is the preservation of ‘nature’s crown jewels’, but not of more homely

environments that might need preserving, such as wetlands.

A fourth concern arises in regard to the aesthetic appreciation of development that

replaces nature. Aesthetic preservation assumes that there will be a gain in aesthetic value

from saving nature, rather than exploiting it. But this assumption is open to question. Might

one not argue that strip mines, urban sprawl, and massive dams are actually as aesthetically

good as—perhaps better even—than the nature they replace?

At a first glance, a strip mine might appear aesthetically bad—a huge gash in the earth,

emitting a terrible din and spewing black smoke into the sky. But if we consider it not simply as

a gash in the earth, but as a large industrial mechanism, it might look quite different. The

billowing smoke, loud noise and roaring fires, rather than looking obtrusive and jarring, may

seem indicative of its power and vitality. Such developments could also be viewed as expressive

of certain positive values: hard work, ingenuity, determination and vision, for instance. If we

see them in these ways, strip mines and their ilk might not look so bad after all.14

A fifth and final worry about aesthetic preservation involves its relation to natural

change. In some cases, a natural area is threatened with destruction, not from human

development, but by nature itself. A nice example of this sort of case, which has been well-

described by Keekok Lee, is Yew Tree Tarn, a small lake in the English Lake District.15 Several

years ago, it was discovered that this particular lake happened to be draining due to the

(natural) opening of an underground fault. The National Trust, a charitable organization that

protects important natural areas in the United Kingdom, intervened in order to prevent this

Page 7: Should we Save Nature’s Hidden Gems? - Ned Hettingerhettingern.people.cofc.edu/Env_Aes_2012/Parsons_Should we save natures... · Should we Save Nature’s Hidden Gems? Abstract

7

draining from occurring. The Trust described its actions as aiming to preserve the beauty of the

lake and the surrounding area; in their words, ‘the area has been landscaped to ensure its

beauty is permanent’. The worry here is that in preserving a natural thing or area against

natural destruction, in this way, we effectively turn it into something that is no longer natural.

In the case of Yew Tree Tarn, blocking the natural geological processes that were destroying the

lake turned it into something that exists because of the voluntary and intentional actions of

human beings – that is, an artefact. So in this case, aesthetic preservation perhaps did not

deliver what it promised: it preserved the beauty, but it failed to preserve the nature.

These, then, are some of the challenges facing the idea of aesthetic preservation. They

are important, and much more could be said about them. But rather than discuss them further,

I will assume here that we can address them. Let us assume, then, that the natural area we

want to preserve is widely agreed to be aesthetically outstanding, and is threatened, not by

natural change, but by human development. Let us assume that its aesthetic value outweighs

whatever economic benefits might be reaped by developing it, and that the development that

would replace it is aesthetically inferior. Let us imagine that we have, in other words, an ideal

case for implementing aesthetic preservation. There is an additional problem that can arise

even in such ideal cases, and it is to this difficulty that I now turn.

3. The Hidden Gems Problem

The problem I want to discuss is this: the natural area that we want to preserve is so

inaccessible and/or fragile that actually visiting it to enjoy its aesthetic value is either impossible

or else imprudent, because it would irrevocably harm or destroy the area. Since no one can

actually enjoy the aesthetic value of the natural area, this aesthetic value seems to become

useless as a justification for its preservation. This is what I call the ‘hidden gems problem’ for

aesthetic preservation. No doubt the problem rarely, if ever, occurs in the simple form I have

described. But I think that the general problem is a feature of many real life instances of

aesthetic preservation.

Page 8: Should we Save Nature’s Hidden Gems? - Ned Hettingerhettingern.people.cofc.edu/Env_Aes_2012/Parsons_Should we save natures... · Should we Save Nature’s Hidden Gems? Abstract

8

Consider, for example, the case of Sable Island, a small sandy outpost, barely 25 miles

long, about 180 miles off the coast of Nova Scotia. Its fame rests chiefly on the threat it poses

to shipping: Atlantic storms drive ships onto its treacherous shoals, and there are more than

three hundred known shipwrecks off the island’s coast. But it is also a starkly beautiful place. A

mariner who came to the island in 1916 said ‘[It was] the most striking landscape I had ever

seen; the island appeared to be made of burnished gold and the hills, which faced me, had the

angularity of waves in a storm’.16 The sailor had the impression that the island was made of

gold because it is composed entirely from sand (hence the name ‘sable’, derived from the

French word for sand). Adding to its mysterious allure is a continual shroud of fog, populations

of rare migrating sea birds, and perhaps most famously, the island’s population of wild horses.

The origin of the herd is uncertain, but it is thought that domesticated horses were brought

there at some point in the eighteenth century, and their feral descendants have roamed the

island ever since.

Although it seems odd to think of such a deadly place as fragile, the island’s landscape is

very sensitive to human activity. Lighthouse keepers who manned the island found that the

removal of even small amounts of the native vegetation could cause entire sand dunes to be

washed away by storms. To date, human intrusion hasn’t posed much threat to the island, due

to its remote location and the fact that the Canadian government has strictly restricted access.

However, this is changing. Well-heeled tourists have recently been spotted on sightseeing

excursions to the island. Also, in the 1970s it was discovered that Sable Island sits directly on

top of one of the largest natural gas fields in North America. Development of the field began in

the 1990s, and currently there are several drilling platforms operating just off the island,

pumping gas onshore via an underwater pipeline.17

Apparently in response to these developments, in October of 2011 the Canadian

government announced that it was turning Sable Island into a national park.18 The move,

however, was greeted tepidly by Sable enthusiasts, with many taking issue with Parks Canada’s

stated intention to ‘manage the current and likely increased interest and ability of the public to

access the Island with programs to facilitate visitor experience.’19 Canada’s parks, after all, have

a mandate to ‘facilitate visitor experience’ in natural areas, by creating trails, accommodation,

Page 9: Should we Save Nature’s Hidden Gems? - Ned Hettingerhettingern.people.cofc.edu/Env_Aes_2012/Parsons_Should we save natures... · Should we Save Nature’s Hidden Gems? Abstract

9

and so on. The ‘Hands off Sable Island’ Facebook group, however, insists on precisely that: a

complete ban on sightseers, whose presence would jeopardize its unique landscape.

‘Hands off Sable Island’ might be right that allowing visitors will irreparably damage the

island. But in their position lies precisely the hidden gems conundrum. This is brought out nicely

by two online comments on a recent news story reporting the decision to turn the island into a

park. One commenter remarked that the island ‘sounds very beautiful ....our government made

the right decision to protect it.’ But another said ‘So the government will spend millions of

taxpayer dollars establishing and maintaining a park, but no taxpayers will ever be able to see

and enjoy it. Not much of a deal for the taxpayers.’20 This last remark hits the nail on the head:

it seems impossible to say ‘Save Sable Island for its beauty!’ when no one, outside a handful of

government-approved scientists, will ever experience this beauty. Doesn’t the fact that no one,

or only a very few people, can enjoy it aesthetically destroy the logic of preserving it on

aesthetic grounds? This is the question I now want to explore.

4. Three responses

One reply that the proponent of aesthetic preservation might give to the hidden gems

problem is that the amount of enjoyment we get from Sable’s aesthetic value is irrelevant,

since the aesthetic value of natural areas is independent of such enjoyment, and indeed of any

of the area’s effects on human beings. We can call this the ‘non-anthropogenic value solution’

to the hidden gems problem. If this claim is true, then a part of nature can have aesthetic value

even if it is unable to produce any actual aesthetic enjoyment.

Unfortunately, this view has the serious drawback of making the idea of aesthetic value

difficult to grasp. A more common approach takes all value to be anthropogenic: on this

approach, value is not ‘out there in the natural world’, so to speak, but rather attaches to things

only in virtue of their relations to desirable human experiences. This is the more common view

about value, surely, because it is fairly easy to understand. If it isn’t right, and aesthetic value is

‘out there in the natural world’, then many uncomfortable questions loom. What exactly is

aesthetic value? Is it a property that, like other natural qualities, we can measure in some

Page 10: Should we Save Nature’s Hidden Gems? - Ned Hettingerhettingern.people.cofc.edu/Env_Aes_2012/Parsons_Should we save natures... · Should we Save Nature’s Hidden Gems? Abstract

10

objective fashion? How does aesthetic value fit into the scientific picture describing the rest of

the natural world?

Of course, these questions have not deterred some philosophers from trying to inject

value into the natural world.21 But this move is a particularly awkward one for the proponent of

aesthetic preservation to make. The reason is that, as mentioned earlier on, one of the most

attractive things about aesthetic preservation is that aesthetic value—the capacity to produce

aesthetic enjoyment—is familiar and easy to understand. Turning aesthetic value into a

creature of darkness destroys one of its main virtues as a rationale for nature preservation.

Thus, I will assume that the proponent of aesthetic preservation will not favour this rather

radical response to the hidden gems problem.

A less radical response than the ‘non-anthropogenic value response’ would hold that

value is anthropogenic, but that nature’s hidden gems have value, not because they give us

aesthetic enjoyment, but because they afford us a different satisfaction: the satisfaction that

comes just from knowing that such beautiful places still exist. Thus, although very few get to

enjoy Sable Island’s beauty, we can all enjoy the thought that the island exists. We could call

this the ‘just knowing solution’ to the hidden gems problem.

The trouble with this response is that rather than providing a solution to the hidden

gems problem, it presumes one. For according to the just knowing response, what we enjoy (or,

perhaps, take solace in) is the fact that, in certain cases at least, our species has not been selfish

or wantonly destructive, but rather has been wise, and has made a good decision. But

ascertaining this ‘fact’ takes us back to the fundamental question of preservation: Is it wise to

spare nature rather than reap the practical benefits that developing it could provide? Of course

the aesthetic preservationist will say that the decision to forego development on Sable Island is

wise because the area is extremely beautiful. But now we only find the hidden gems problem

emerging again. Why is it wise to forego real material benefits to safeguard something that will

give no aesthetic benefit at all? Without an answer to this question, we cannot know that we

have, in fact, made a wise decision in choosing preservation, and thus the satisfaction of ‘just

knowing’ that Sable Island still exists evaporates into nothing.

Page 11: Should we Save Nature’s Hidden Gems? - Ned Hettingerhettingern.people.cofc.edu/Env_Aes_2012/Parsons_Should we save natures... · Should we Save Nature’s Hidden Gems? Abstract

11

A third, and perhaps more promising response might be based on the idea that we can,

in fact, enjoy nature’s hidden gems, despite not being able to directly experience them. We can

call this the ‘Indirect experience solution’. For instance, one might say that it doesn’t matter

that we can’t actually get to Sable Island, since we can aesthetically appreciate it indirectly via

the imagination. Even based on my rudimentary description of it, you could probably construct

some version of the island in your imagination. Perhaps in this way we can aesthetically

appreciate Sable Island in our imaginations without actually going there.

No doubt the exact nature of this appreciation would require some clarification. But

however exactly we understand it, the problem with this response is that it proves too much: if

we can appreciate Sable Island via the imagination, it no longer seems to matter, so far as

aesthetic enjoyment goes, whether it actually exists or not. We can also use imagination to

aesthetically appreciate Tolkien’s Middle-Earth, or Dante’s Hell, and not only do these places

not exist now, they never existed at all. What the indirect experience solution really requires,

then, is a way of aesthetically appreciating Sable Island that doesn’t require going there, but

does require the island’s continued existence.

The obvious candidate here is appreciation via visual representations produced through

some suitable causal chain terminating with Sable island: films or photographs of the island, for

instance. The Nova Scotia Museum of Natural History maintains a website on the island which

states: ‘As it is a place most of us will never visit, this web site brings Sable Island to you.’22 So it

does, in a way, by displaying photographs of the island. There’s no question that these

photographs have some aesthetic value. Perhaps, then, we should preserve Sable Island in its

natural state because it is needed to produce a set of visual representations that can provide

widespread aesthetic enjoyment.

Some will object here that experiencing the aesthetic value of photographs of Sable

Island is not the same as experiencing the aesthetic value of the Island itself. More strongly, it

may be said that such representations do not allow us to experience the location’s aesthetic

value at all. For example, Allen Carlson has argued that photography is incapable of adequately

capturing the aesthetic qualities of natural environments, which are three-dimensional and

multi-sensory environments, in which we are immersed as active viewers.23 To appreciate a

Page 12: Should we Save Nature’s Hidden Gems? - Ned Hettingerhettingern.people.cofc.edu/Env_Aes_2012/Parsons_Should we save natures... · Should we Save Nature’s Hidden Gems? Abstract

12

photograph of a natural area is, therefore, not to appreciate that area. These claims may be

true, but they need not destroy our suggested rationale for aesthetic preservation. For even if

these claims are true, it remains true also that such photographs do bring aesthetic enjoyment

of some kind, and given that they do, the enjoyment they provide might be a basis for

preserving the ‘raw material’, as it were, for their production: namely Sable Island.

Nonetheless, this response to the hidden gems problem seems ultimately

unsatisfactory. One difficulty lies in the threat of diminishing returns. It may be worthwhile to

spare a natural area so that its aesthetic excellence can used to produce an aesthetically

excellent set of photographs. For instance, some years ago the New York photographer Roberto

Dutesco received permission to go to Sable Island and photograph its wild horses: his striking,

deeply moving images are indeed aesthetically excellent.24 But once such a visual record has

been produced, and is made available for enjoyment, is it worthwhile to preserve the area in

question so that additional visual records can be produced? This depends, obviously, on how

comprehensive a photo record we possess, but at some point we must ask: How many different

pictures do we need? There may come a point at which the new visual records generated no

longer produce sufficient aesthetic payoff to justify foregoing the practical benefits of

developing the area.

A deeper problem with the indirect experience response, though, lies in the assumption

that the continued existence of the natural area is required to produce these visual

representations. This probably was true in the past, when techniques for ‘doctoring’ and

enhancing visual representations were limited. But with current technology, it seems highly

doubtful that the only way we could produce beautiful Sable Island photos and films is by

photographing or filming Sable Island. To return to the Tolkien example, Peter Jackson’s

popular Lord of the Rings films provided a stunning visual record of Middle Earth, contrived

largely through digital effects. There seems no principled reason why the nature photography

industry could not employ similar techniques to produce photos of Sable island after the island

itself has been destroyed. One could argue that these images would not really be images of

Sable Island, and that’s fair enough: we could call them ‘Sable-ish’ images instead. Indeed, we

might come to regard these representations as a new form of Art: ‘imaginary landscape

Page 13: Should we Save Nature’s Hidden Gems? - Ned Hettingerhettingern.people.cofc.edu/Env_Aes_2012/Parsons_Should we save natures... · Should we Save Nature’s Hidden Gems? Abstract

13

representation’, as opposed to nature photography. The point is that they can apparently yield

as much aesthetic pleasure as real photos of Sable Island can.

One might deny this, however. One might insist that Sable-ish images just wouldn’t be

the same: we wouldn’t respond to them as we would respond to actual photos of Sable Island.

This may be true; many philosophers have argued that we have different aesthetic responses to

representational images when we have different beliefs concerning their causal history. Dennis

Dutton, for instance, argued that when we know that a painting is a forgery, our appreciation

shifts from the artistic elements of the work toward its technical aspects.25 When you think that

a particular work is a Vermeer, you might approach it in a certain way, focusing on what

Vermeer was expressing in his composition of a certain biblical scene, for example. But when

you learn it is a forgery, your attention shifts to technical matters such as: How did the painter

imitate Vermeer’s treatment of light so effectively? How did he know which elements to copy

and which to change, in order to fool the experts? Perhaps a similar shift in appreciation would

occur when we move to imaginary landscape representations, as opposed to traditional nature

photography.

But even if this is the case, the hidden gems problem remains unsolved. For our

question then becomes: Why should we insist upon appreciating nature photography rather

than appreciating imaginary landscape representations? The reason for insisting on the former

seems not to be purely aesthetic, since we can obviously derive aesthetic satisfaction, albeit a

different aesthetic satisfaction, from imaginary landscape representations, such as computer

generated Sable-ish images or Peter Jackson’s digital depiction of Mordor. The purely aesthetic

case for preservation has, once more, slipped between our fingers.

5. Another approach

No doubt there is more to say about these responses, but perhaps enough has been said

to motivate a different approach. A problem with the responses covered so far is that all of

them focus only on the impact of natural destruction on the quantity of aesthetic enjoyment

produced. The basic problem is that, since so few people can take aesthetic enjoyment from

the island, its destruction seems not to have a significant impact on the total amount of

Page 14: Should we Save Nature’s Hidden Gems? - Ned Hettingerhettingern.people.cofc.edu/Env_Aes_2012/Parsons_Should we save natures... · Should we Save Nature’s Hidden Gems? Abstract

14

aesthetic enjoyment. Perhaps we would do better to focus instead on the impact of the loss of

the island on the quality of aesthetic enjoyment.

In switching focus in this way, we will need to introduce into the framework of aesthetic

preservation a stronger assumption than we have been using so far. I have been assuming that

aesthetic appreciation is subjective, but if we are to discriminate between aesthetic responses

not just in terms of their intensity (or the quantity of pleasure they involve) but in terms of their

quality–in terms of how correct or appropriate they are—then we must see aesthetic responses

as having an element of objectivity. We need not hold that aesthetic value is present in objects

in the way that mass and shape are. But we do need to see aesthetic responses as objective in

sense that some responses to a particular object will be better or more correct than others. A

useful analogy is with colour—colours are subjective in that they involve certain perceptual

experiences, but they are also objective insofar as some colour responses to a particular object

are better or more correct than others. Thus we say that stop signs are really red, even if colour

blind individuals, or people who have taken LSD, see them as green.26

So let us adopt as our assumption, then, that some aesthetic responses to an object can

be said to be better or more correct than other responses. My claim is that we should preserve

nature’s hidden gems because, if we do, we will be more likely to have better or more correct

aesthetic responses to nature in general. We can develop an argument for this claim by turning

to a classic text on the quality of aesthetic responses: David Hume’s essay ‘Of the Standard of

Taste’.27 In that essay, Hume singles out those with superior taste—in our terms, those who

tend to have aesthetic responses of superior quality—whom he calls the ‘true judges’. Hume

describes these ‘rare characters’ thus: ‘Strong sense, united to delicate sentiment, improved by

practice, perfected by comparison, and cleared of all prejudice, can alone entitle critics to this

valuable character; and the joint verdict of such, wherever they are to be found, is the true

standard of taste and beauty.’28

In this passage, Hume lists a number of qualities required for making correct aesthetic

judgements. For our purposes here, the pertinent characteristic of the true judge is the fourth:

being experienced in making comparisons between the different ‘species and degrees of

excellence’. Hume says that ‘a man, who has had no opportunity of comparing the different

Page 15: Should we Save Nature’s Hidden Gems? - Ned Hettingerhettingern.people.cofc.edu/Env_Aes_2012/Parsons_Should we save natures... · Should we Save Nature’s Hidden Gems? Abstract

15

kinds of beauty, is indeed totally unqualified to pronounce an opinion with regard to any object

presented to him’.29 The basic idea is plausible enough: someone who only ever read drug store

romance novels would probably have a rather skewed standard of literary excellence, being

unaware of many of the more impressive things that can be achieved with the novel form.

Now in order for a true judge to engage in the sort of comparisons that Hume

recommends, that judge must have access to objects spanning the full range of ‘species and

degrees of excellence’. If someone has nothing to read but drug store romance novels, he will

be stuck with his skewed standard of literary excellence: he needs some masterpieces as a

contrast. And it is here that I propose to offer the initial justification for preserving nature’s

hidden gems: they can serve as masterpieces with which aspiring true judges can compare the

more common objects of appreciation. Thus, a man might come to over-rate the beauty of his

mediocre local landscape, but viewing an aesthetically outstanding landscape, such as Sable

Island, might jolt him out of his complacency, put his previous assessments into a better

perspective, and improve his judgement, just as reading Tolstoy or Austen might do for the

devotee of romance novels.

Of course, this point seems not much of an advance on our problem. For all we have

established is that the hidden gems can enhance the quality of aesthetic experience of the

happy few who get to experience them: these visitors are more apt to be true (or truer) judges

than they otherwise would be. But the whole problem of the hidden gems is that the benefits

to the few allowed to visit, real as they may be, are insufficient to outweigh the practical

benefits that would accrue to the larger society from development. What we lack is any

connection between the aesthetic benefit to the small group of visitors and the aesthetic

welfare of society at large. I think we can draw such a connection, however, by reflecting on the

question: What is so valuable about true judges, anyway?

In one sense, the question seems trivial. True judges are, well, true judges, and that is

precisely what is valuable about them. They make better appraisals of the features of objects

and of their aesthetic value—they are more able to get it right about such matters—and

perhaps this is just obviously a good thing.30 But there is another good thing about true judges:

they also play a useful role in helping the rest of us, who are not true judges, to improve our

Page 16: Should we Save Nature’s Hidden Gems? - Ned Hettingerhettingern.people.cofc.edu/Env_Aes_2012/Parsons_Should we save natures... · Should we Save Nature’s Hidden Gems? Abstract

16

taste. This happens in a number of ways, but the key one here is the true judge’s ability to

deliver informed verdicts on the aesthetic value of particular things. Good literary critics, for

instance, make appraisals of the aesthetic value of literary works that call our own preferences

into question, help us to see key things that we’ve missed, and draw us toward works we may

have unduly neglected. In doing these things, they lead us toward the improvement of our own

aesthetic judgement. My suggestion is that true judges of aesthetic value in nature can help

improve all of our tastes in landscape in a similar way. Since nature’s hidden gems are often

requisite training materials for true judges of aesthetic value in nature, we thus have an

aesthetic reason to preserve them.

It is worth noting that my claim is not that experiencing nature’s hidden gems is

sufficient to make one a true judge. The visitor must first of all take an aesthetic interest in the

landscape: a scientist who takes no such interest but only focuses on ecological matters may

not improve her aesthetic sensibilities at all. And other qualities, such as those Hume mentions,

will remain necessary for cultivating superior taste. My claim is only that experiencing nature’s

hidden gems is necessary for becoming a true judge of natural beauty: if this claim is true, then

we have a reason for holding onto these landscapes, even if there remains more to do in order

for us to reap their potential benefits. 31

6. An Objection

To conclude I’d like to consider an objection to my solution to the hidden gems

problem. It rests on the grounds that, when it comes to the role of true judges in improving the

aesthetic responses of the general population, there are important disanalogies between the

cases of art and nature. As mentioned, one of the main ways in which literary critics familiar

with the masterpieces help improve our literary taste is by moving us to read those

masterpieces for ourselves. To return to my earlier example, if the devotee of romance novels

is moved by a good literary critic, she will probably read Anna Karenina or Pride and Prejudice.

But when someone in a dreary corner of the Midwest reads a description of Sable Island, even

if she is moved to go see it, she cannot, precisely because it is a hidden gem. Thus, one might

Page 17: Should we Save Nature’s Hidden Gems? - Ned Hettingerhettingern.people.cofc.edu/Env_Aes_2012/Parsons_Should we save natures... · Should we Save Nature’s Hidden Gems? Abstract

17

doubt whether true judges versed in the beauties of nature’s hidden gems are capable of

improving the general taste in landscape, since the masterpieces that they know remain

inaccessible to us. However, I think that this does not follow, and we can see why by

considering a hypothetical case involving artworks.

Imagine that something bizarre happens to Vermeer’s paintings. One day, the images

mysteriously disappear: the canvasses are now simply black. At first it is suspected that the

canvasses have been stolen and replaced with black ones (perhaps as a joke), but this is ruled

out by scientific analysis showing the canvasses to be Vermeer’s. Furthermore, it soon comes to

light that the images have not truly disappeared at all, because a handful of people are still able

to view the images, in their original colour and condition: to them, the canvasses do not look

black, as they do to the rest of us. Upon further study, it is discovered that some chemical

oddity in Vermeer’s paints has caused this change, and that a rare genetic quirk in the visual

systems of a select few allows them to perceive the original image, despite the chemical

change. These lucky individuals are described as having been gifted with ‘Vermeer sight’.

Furthermore, scientists reveal that the chemical change is now causing the canvasses

themselves to rapidly deteriorate physically: although the original visibility of the image cannot

be restored, this physical deterioration of the canvasses can be prevented, but only by an

extremely costly treatment that must be applied to them continuously.

The question I mean to pose about this example is: Do we (the general public) have

good reason to pay the cost of maintaining Vermeer’s canvasses in existence, even though we

can never enjoy them? I think the answer is yes. The reason to preserve them is that the

opportunity to experience these masterpieces will allow the few afforded this opportunity—

those with Vermeer sight—to become truer judges, which is a boon to us all. It is true that

these critics will never get us to experience Vermeers for ourselves, since this is impossible for

those of us lacking Vermeer-sight. But these critics are a boon to us nonetheless: their greater

experience translates into more accurate and incisive verdicts about works we can appreciate.

Facilitating this experience for the lucky few is, therefore, a prudent investment for any society

that views as worthwhile the aesthetic dimension of life.

Page 18: Should we Save Nature’s Hidden Gems? - Ned Hettingerhettingern.people.cofc.edu/Env_Aes_2012/Parsons_Should we save natures... · Should we Save Nature’s Hidden Gems? Abstract

18

Notes

1 I discuss some examples of appeals to aesthetic considerations by preservationists in the

following sections. Philosophical defences of aesthetic preservation include: Eugene Hargrove,

Foundations of Environmental Ethics (Denton, Tex: Environmental Ethics Books, 1996); Eliot

Sober, ‘Philosophical Problems for Environmentalism’ in B.G. Norton (ed.) The Preservation of

Species: The Value of Biological Diversity (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1986), pp. 17-

194; Mark Sagoff, ‘On Preserving the Natural Environment’, Yale Law Journal, 84, (1974): 205-

267; Ned Hettinger, ‘Allen Carlson’s Environmental Aesthetics and Protection of the

Environment’, Environmental Ethics, 27, (2005): 57-76 and ‘Objectivity in Environmental

Aesthetics and Protection of the Environment’, in A. Carlson and S. Lintott (eds.) Nature,

Aesthetics, and Environmentalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 2008), pp. 413-438;

Janna Thompson, ‘Aesthetics and the Value of Nature’, Environmental Ethics, 17, (1995): 291-

305; Sheila Lintott, ‘Toward Eco-Friendly Aesthetics’, Environmental Ethics, 28, (2006): 57-76;

J.B. Callicot, ‘The Land Aesthetic’, Environmental Review, 7, (1983): 345-358, reprinted in , R. G.

Botzler and S. J. Armstrong (eds.) Environmental Ethics: Divergence and Convergence, 2nd ed

(Boston: McGraw-Hill, 1998); Holmes Rolston, ‘From Beauty to Duty: Aesthetics of Nature and

Environmental Ethics’, in A. Berleant (ed.) Environment and the Arts: Perspectives on

Environmental Aesthetics (Aldershot: Ashgate, 2002); Emily Brady, ‘Aesthetic Character and

Aesthetic Integrity in Environmental Conservation’, Environmental Ethics, 24, (2002): 75-91;

David Cooper, ‘Aestheticism and Environmentalism’ in D.E. Cooper and J.A. Palmer (eds.) Spirit

of Environmentalism: Religion, Value and Environmental Concern (New York: Routledge, 1998).

The Carlson and Lintott anthology mentioned above (Nature, Aesthetics, and Environmentalism)

collects many of these essays and other relevant writings, and is an excellent introduction to

the topic. 2 I will use these terms interchangeably in this paper. Also, except in two instances that I will

note, I will make no assumptions regarding how we should understand or analyze nature’s

aesthetic value. For a recent survey of philosophical debates on this topic, see Allen Carlson,

‘Environmental Aesthetics’, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2010 Edition),

Page 19: Should we Save Nature’s Hidden Gems? - Ned Hettingerhettingern.people.cofc.edu/Env_Aes_2012/Parsons_Should we save natures... · Should we Save Nature’s Hidden Gems? Abstract

19

Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL =

<http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2010/entries/environmental-aesthetics/>. 3 Rolston, op cit., p.127. 4 See the Defenders of Wildlife sites at

www.defenders.org/programs_and_policy/habitat_conservation/federal_lands/national_wildlif

e_refuges/threats/arctic/index.php and www.savearcticrefuge.org/learnmore.html 5 www.nrdc.org/land/wilderness/arctic.asp 6 www.anwrphotography.com 7 McCain’s comment was recorded by Jim Geraghty in his blog ‘The Campaign Spot’, National

Review Online, January 16, 2008 http://www.nationalreview.com/campaign-spot/10699/john-

mccain-im-raising-hundreds-thousands-day-new-hampshire 8 Critics of aesthetic preservation include T.J. Diffey, ‘Arguing About the Environment’, British

Journal of Aesthetics, 40, (2000): 133-148; J. Robert Loftis, ‘Three Problems for the Aesthetic

Foundations of Environmental Ethics’, Philosophy in the Contemporary World, 10, (2003): 41-

50; Stan Godlovitch, ‘Aesthetic Protectionism’, Journal of Applied Philosophy, 6, (1989): 171-

180; and Keekok Lee, ‘Beauty for Ever?’ Environmental Values, 4, (1995): 213-215. 9 For further discussion, see [source deleted for blind review]. 10 Stevens’ comments were aired on the PBS New Hour, 2 November 2005. His speech can be

viewed online at http://www.pbs.org/newshour/bb/environment/july-dec05/anwr_11-2.html. 11 Or so it seems; as we’ll see, we will need to revisit the objectivity of aesthetic responses in

section five, below. 12 Holmes Rolston, ‘Aesthetics in the Swamps’, Perspectives in Biology and Medicine, 43, (2000):

584-597. 13 Yuriko Saito, ‘The Aesthetics of Unscenic Nature’, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 56,

(1998): 101-111. 14 The surprising (and somewhat disturbing) aesthetic power of industrial sites has been

brought home in recent years by the work of the Canadian photographer Ed Burtynsky; his

work can be viewed online at www.edwardburtynsky.com. That environmentally damaged

environmental sites can have significant aesthetic value is also argued by Maria Jose Alcaraz

Page 20: Should we Save Nature’s Hidden Gems? - Ned Hettingerhettingern.people.cofc.edu/Env_Aes_2012/Parsons_Should we save natures... · Should we Save Nature’s Hidden Gems? Abstract

20

Leon in “Morally Wrong Beauty as a Source of Value”, Nordic Journal of Aesthetics, 40-41,

(2010-11). 15 Lee, op cit.; on this issue, see also Godlovitch, op cit. 16 Quoted in Bruce Armstrong, Sable Island: Nova Scotia’s Mysterious Island of Sand (Toronto:

Doubleday, 1981), p. 9. 17 Current and historical information on the project is available at the Sable Offshore Energy

Project website (www.soep.com). 18 ‘Canada and Nova Scotia Reach Historic Agreement to designate Sable Island as a National

Park Reserve’. Canadian government press release, Halifax, Nova Scotia, October 17, 2011.

Available online at http://www.pc.gc.ca/apps/cp-nr/release_e.asp?id=1785&andor1=nr. 19 See Parks Canada’s ‘Sable Island FAQ’, online at www.pc.gc.ca/eng/progs/np-pn/cnpn-

cnnp/sable/faq.aspx 20 Kathryn Blaze Carlson, ‘Tiny Sable Island Canada’s newest national park’, National Post

Online, 18 October, 2011. 21 The most famous example is G.E. Moore, but a more recent instance in environmental

philosophy is Holmes Rolston: see, for example, his ‘Are Values in Nature Subjective or

Objective?’, in Philosophy Gone Wild (Buffalo, Prometheus Books, 1989), pp. 91-117. 22 www.museum.gov.ns.ca/mnh/nature/sableisland/ 23 Allen Carlson, ‘Appreciation and the Natural Environment’, Journal of Aesthetics and Art

Criticism, 37, (1979): 267-276; see also his essays ‘Formal Qualities and the Natural

Environment’, Journal of Aesthetic Education, 13, (1979): 99-114 and ‘On the Possibility of

Quantifying Scenic Beauty’, Landscape Planning, 4, (1977): 131-172. 24 On these images, see Richard Friswell, ‘Wild Things’, The Modern Estate, (2008): 1-14. Some

of Dutesco’s images, and the story behind them, can be viewed at his website:

http://www.dutescoart.com/gallery/sablehorses/index.html. 25 Dennis Dutton, ‘Artistic Crimes’, British Journal of Aesthetics, 19, (1965): 304-314. 26 On the analogy between judgements of colour and aesthetic judgements, see Frank Sibley,

‘Objectivity and Aesthetics’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplement 42, (1968): 31-

54.

Page 21: Should we Save Nature’s Hidden Gems? - Ned Hettingerhettingern.people.cofc.edu/Env_Aes_2012/Parsons_Should we save natures... · Should we Save Nature’s Hidden Gems? Abstract

21

27 Hume ‘Of the Standard of Taste’, (1757), in G. Sayre-McCord (ed.) David Hume: Moral

Philosophy (Indianapolis: Hackett, 2006), pp. 345-360. 28 Hume, op cit., p. 355. 29 Hume, op cit., p. 353. 30 Hume seems to have thought so, but for a different take on why we admire true judges, see

Jerrold Levinson, ‘Hume’s Standard of Taste: the Real Problem’, Journal of Aesthetics and Art

Criticism, 60, (2002): 227-238. 31 As mentioned earlier, in addition to the objectivity of aesthetic responses, this conclusion

requires a second assumption, which is that the appreciation of a photographic or cinematic

representation of a natural area, such as Sable Island, is not equivalent to aesthetically

appreciating that natural area itself. If this claim is false, then true judges could cultivate their

taste using such representations, which would remove the proposed reason for preserving the

actual area. For a detailed discussion and defence of the claim, see the references in note 23,

above.