scientific expert evidence in the uk: proposing an abridged daubert

26
1 Scientific expert evidence in the UK: Proposing an Abridged Daubert Professor Jane L. Ireland*, School of Psychology, University of Central Lancashire, Preston, UK; and Ashworth Research Centre (ARC), High Secure Forensic Psychiatry, Mersey Care NHS Trust. Professor John Beaumont Lancashire Law School, University of Central Lancashire, Preston, UK. *Authors note Correspondence should be addressed to Jane L. Ireland, University of Central Lancashire, Preston, PR1 2HE, Lancashire, UK; E-mail: [email protected]

Upload: others

Post on 12-Sep-2021

3 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Scientific expert evidence in the UK: Proposing an Abridged Daubert

1    

Scientific expert evidence in the UK: Proposing an Abridged Daubert

Professor Jane L. Ireland*,

School of Psychology, University of Central Lancashire, Preston, UK; and Ashworth Research Centre

(ARC), High Secure Forensic Psychiatry, Mersey Care NHS Trust.

Professor John Beaumont

Lancashire Law School, University of Central Lancashire, Preston, UK.

 

*Authors note

Correspondence should be addressed to Jane L. Ireland, University of Central Lancashire, Preston, PR1

2HE, Lancashire, UK; E-mail: [email protected]

Page 2: Scientific expert evidence in the UK: Proposing an Abridged Daubert

2    

ABSTRACT

Expert evidence is a contentious area with some high profile cases highlighting unreliable ‘scientific’

expert evidence. This commentary argues for improvement in the assessment of expert evidence

reliability. The history of developing legal criteria for admitting ‘scientific’ evidence will be considered.

An alternative to current approaches is proposed, including a Daubert application for generally accepted

physical sciences and Abridged-Daubert for novel and social/behavioural sciences. Also proposed is

increased involvement by experts in critically reviewing their own evidence and in providing statements

of limitations. The commentary concludes by outlining the importance of developing such an approach

for the UK legal system.

Key Words: Expert evidence; Admissibility; Scientific Evidence; Daubert

Page 3: Scientific expert evidence in the UK: Proposing an Abridged Daubert

3    

Imagine being convicted on the basis of ear-print evidence for an offence you have not committed, even

when such evidence is known to be unreliable and not accepted by the wider scientific community.

Alternatively, consider being placed in prison for murder on the sole basis of a dog detecting your scent

after an article of your clothing has been placed in a coffee can. Or what of being accused and placed on

remand for allegedly bringing a giraffe and elephant into a Sunday school as part of suspected ritual

abuse of children; later killing these animals and hanging the children upside down from chandeliers on

the (incorrect) basis that children as young as three or four have intact memories and are not

suggestible? These may sound like plot lines from movie scripts, but they are not, having already been

played out in courts, leading to convictions later questioned or overturned (i.e. Dallagher1; Winfrey2;

Akiki3 respectively). In all cases, experts proffered their evidence to be reliable, rigorous, scientific, and

of the highest quality.

Such evidence from experts is commonly considered under the broad definition of ‘opinion evidence’4.

This fails to allot such evidence the focused attention it requires, particularly considering the increased

significance of expert scientific evidence in courts5. Expert evidence is known to appreciably influence

decision-making, particularly if considered ‘scientific’6. Science though is a fluid concept, where new

techniques and approaches are constantly evolving7 and where it can be perceived to hold definitive and

reliable answers when this is not the case8. It is further assumed that it can be easily communicated9 to

                                                                                                                         1 [2002] EWCA Crim 1903 2 [2010] Tex Crim Ap No PD-0987-09 3 San Diego County Grand Jury Report of 1993-1994: Families in Crisis. Dale Akiki case. 4 C Tapper, Cross and Tapper on Evidence (12th Edition, OUP, Oxford, 2010), ch 11. 5 P Roberts, A Zuckerman, The Principles of Criminal Evidence (2nd ed, OUP, Oxford, 2010) 467. 6 D Omerod, A Roberts, ‘Expert evidence: Where now? Where next?’ Archbold (2006), June, 5 - 9 7 (n 5) 8 ( n 6) 9 (n 6)

Page 4: Scientific expert evidence in the UK: Proposing an Abridged Daubert

4    

lay audiences, when in reality the evaluation of scientific evidence is complex10 and challenging to

test11.

Methods for testing the reliability of expert opinion evidence are crucial, with particular focus on what is

termed ‘evidential reliability’ or rather ‘trustworthiness’12 . Evidential reliability concerning the

scientific opinion evidence offered by expert witnesses will form the focus of this commentary as

opposed to other areas of concern such as expert qualification and evidence relevance13.

By exploring expert opinion evidence and its evidential reliability14, the commentary will set the scene

by first reviewing difficulties with unreliable expert evidence before progressing onto a critical review

of how courts have attempted to determine the quality of such evidence. This review will focus on two

sets of criteria that have featured prominently in the US court system, Frye15 and Daubert16, 17. The

benefits and challenges of attempting to develop criteria for admitting expert evidence will then be

considered, followed by suggestions for what could be included in a UK legal test of reliability. The

importance of maintaining a pragmatic approach18,19 will nonetheless remain at the centre of any

suggested procedure.

                                                                                                                         10 The Law Commission Consultation Paper No 190. The admissibility of expert evidence in criminal proceedings in England and Wales: A new approach to the determination of evidentiary reliability: A consultation paper. 2009; and Law Commission Paper No 325. Expert Evidence in Criminal Proceedings in England and Wales. 2011. 11 M Redmayne, Expert Evidence and Criminal Justice (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2001). 12 (n 10) and reference to evidential reliability as ‘trustworthiness’ as opposed to consistency. 13 Keane, A. The Modern Law of Evidence (8th ed, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2010). It is recognised that there are a broader range of issues in the arena of expert work (see n 5) but the focus of the current paper is reliability and admissibility of proffered ‘scientific’ evidence. 14 As opposed to validity or issues concerning consistency. 15 Frye v. United States [1993] 293 F 1013 16 Daubert v Merrell Dow Pharmaceuticals [1993] 509 US 579 17 Both of which are being considered for application to the UK system. 18 I Dennis, The Law of Evidence (4th Edition, London, Sweet & Maxwell, 2010) 850 19 (n 5)

Page 5: Scientific expert evidence in the UK: Proposing an Abridged Daubert

5    

This commentary will therefore concern itself with three questions:

• Is there cause for concern about evidence reliability which suggests criteria are necessary?

• Are criteria already in existence that is relevant and has support?

• What can be proposed to determine evidence reliability, if required?

ANALYSIS OF EVIDENTIAL RELIABILITY OF EXPERT OPINION EVIDENCE

Problems arising from admitting unreliable expert evidence

Evidence from experts is admitted on the grounds that it meets the ‘helpfulness’ test20, 21 and assists

decision makers on issues outside ordinary experience (i.e. Turner Rule22). Once deemed helpful, focus

then shifts to evidence reliability. Complications can arise here for expert evidence23 presented as

scientific which is accepted with little or no question as to its reliability. A plethora of cases exist where

such evidence has significantly influenced final judgements but has later been considered unreliable or

requiring special consideration24. Example cases from the last decade25 include Clark (Sally)26,

Cannings27, Dallagher28, Winfrey29, Luttrell30, Jenkins (Siôn)31,George (Barry)32, and most recently

Knox and Sollecito33.

                                                                                                                         20 (n 18) and thus bringing value to the case and assisting the jury with details outside ordinary experience. 21 (n 5) 22 [1975] QB 834 841 23 The focus in this commentary is opinion evidence and thus use of the term ‘expert evidence’ is specifically referring to opinion evidence and not factual evidence such as that offered by other witnesses. 24 (n 10) 25 Not just including the UK but some pertinent recent cases. 26 [2003] EWCA Crim 1020 27 [2004] 2 Cr App R 7 28 (n 1)

Page 6: Scientific expert evidence in the UK: Proposing an Abridged Daubert

6    

In Clark (Sally)34 appeal evidence focused on the admission of statistical data on cot deaths. The Court

of Appeal considered the data flawed and the expert to have misrepresented statistics. This led to the

overturning of a murder conviction for the defendant. Similarities were also drawn with Cannings, with

this involving three infant deaths and the same expert misrepresenting statistics. The defendant in this

case also had their conviction overturned.

Dallagher35contrasted to these cases in its use of untested methods being admitted as reliable. As noted

earlier, this case involved the use of ear prints, but it failed to account for this representing a novel

scientific advance without general scientific acceptance36. The defendant was convicted but released on

appeal when it was demonstrated that the ear print belonged to someone else. The evidence was further

criticised on the grounds that a decision for conviction included over-focus on a single element of

scientific evidence, an issue which will be returned to later37.

Whereas Dallagher focused on the use of a novel method and the problems associated with this, Winfrey

was applying a method considered routine38 but where scientific testing and application was poor.

                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                     29 (n 2) 30 R v Gerrard Francis Luttrell and others [2004] EWCA Crim 1344 31 R v Jenkins (Siôn) [2004] EWCA Crim 2047 32 R v George (Barry) [2007] EWCA Crim 2722 33 A recently overturned case (3rd October 2011) involving the death of Meredith Kercher, which led to the conviction of Amanda Knox and Raffaele Sollecito in Italy in 2009. See N Squires, ‘Amanda Knox freed: tears of joy as four-year nightmare is over – Telegraph’ (The Daily Telegraph, London, 3rd October 2011). 34 (n 26) 35 (n 1) 36 C Champod, B Kuchler, I Evett, ‘Earmarks as evidence: A critical review’ Journal of Forensic Sciences (2002) 46/6, 1275-1284. 37 (n 31, 32, 33) 38 (n 10) where it is discussed how knowledge may become generally accepted even without robust examination of its methodology. It lacks, however, the methods required to deem it scientific.

Page 7: Scientific expert evidence in the UK: Proposing an Abridged Daubert

7    

Winfrey applied osmological evidence (Wojcikiewicz, 199939), specifically dog scent analysis40, to

secure a murder conviction. The defendant was sentenced after bloodhounds located his scent on the

victim’s clothing and matched it to a sample of the defendants scent placed in a coffee can. The expert

evidence was considered compelling by the jury and represented the primary evidence in the original

trial, but was overturned on appeal due to poor reliability41.

A willingness to admit expert evidence despite queries over its reliability, contrasts to Gilfoyle42 where a

‘psychological autopsy’ was conducted on the deceased. The courts rejected this evidence on the basis

that its reliability was unknown; there was no means by which the opinions could be tested, an absence

of academic support for the methods, and no database that could be drawn upon. In addition the expert

had never conducted such an assessment previously. Gilfoyle is distinguished from the other cases

presented, since expert opinion was not permitted admissible. This indicates existence of a threshold in

some cases, where evidence can be rejected on the basis it is not sufficiently reliable. Despite existence

of a threshold there appears inconsistency with which it is applied.

This is captured well in the case of Luttrell43. Here, expert evidence focused on admissibility of lip-

reading evidence using videos. Defendants were convicted of conspiracy on the basis of such evidence.

On appeal it was held lip reading met the criteria for evidence reliability and was thus admissible.

However, it was deemed such evidence could be admitted only if it carried a warning as to its limitations

                                                                                                                         39 J Wojcikiewicz, ‘Dog scent line-up as scientific evidence’ (1999) accessed via http://www.forensic-science.com on 04.07.2011. 40 See State v Cross [2009] 681 S E 2d 566 WL 2177766 as a further example of courts considering such evidence. 41 (n 39) 42 [2001] 2 Cr App R 5. Where ‘psychological autopsy’ refers to completing a psychological assessment on a deceased individual. 43 (n 30)

Page 8: Scientific expert evidence in the UK: Proposing an Abridged Daubert

8    

and likely error rates44. In this instance courts appeared to be submitting potentially unreliable evidence

with caution. This contrasts to the earlier cited cases of Clark (Sally), Cannings, Dallagher and Winfrey.

Finally, are cases such as Jenkins (Siôn)45, George (Barry)46, Knox and Sollecito47where limited forensic

evidence was focused on without commentary on its reliability. In Jenkins (Siôn), the defendant was

convicted of the murder of his foster daughter due to 158 microscopic bloodspots on his clothing. The

forensic evidence was later deemed unsafe. An alternative explanation was indicated, namely the

bloodspots were the product of a blood clot and release of air as the victim, Billie-Jo, died whilst he was

tending to her injuries. Following two subsequent retrials, juries failed to reach a verdict and Jenkins

was released.

A more extreme example of narrow unreliable evidence, convincingly argued by expert witnesses,

occurred in George (Barry)48 where a single microscopic particle of what was supposed to be gunshot

residue, and a single fibre on his clothing, linked him to the murder of a TV presenter, Jill Dando. He

was acquitted after seven years, when it was successfully argued that this residue could have been

transferred from armed officers attending the scene and via a mannequin that the defendants clothing

was placed on to take the forensic photographs.

The key issue in the George (Barry) case was the jury failing to be advised by the expert witnesses of

the risk for contamination of evidence, and thus failing to critically review the evidence they offered.

                                                                                                                         44Also referred to as ‘margins of error’ or ‘confidence intervals’. These represent an indication of how confident you can be that the evidence is accurate and where the ‘true’ data is likely to fall within a range. 45 (n 31) 46 (n 32) 47 (n 33)  48 (n 32)

Page 9: Scientific expert evidence in the UK: Proposing an Abridged Daubert

9    

Similar issues were raised in the recent case of Knox and Sollecito49 following the murder of a student in

Italy. The evidence used to convict the defendants focused on DNA tests which linked them to a knife

(later noted to be incompatible with the murder weapon), the bra clasp of the victim (which was left at

the scene for six weeks, untouched) and bloodstained footprints. The appeal case focused again on the

reliability of the expert testimony presented at the original trial, and the failure of experts to recognise

and report the contamination caused to the forensic evidence. What Knox and Sollecito indicates, is the

continuing significant difficulties in the application of expert ‘scientific’ evidence, despite a wealth of

preceding high profile cases, and apparent failure to learn from previous miscarriages of justice50.

This brief review illustrates how problems can arise when expert evidence is admitted without

consideration of its reliability, particularly if it has become the focus of a case and there has been a

failure to disclose errors. The UK legal system has not, until recently, considered reliability in any

detail51. Complexity remains, with the question not simply one of determining the reliability of

evidence but also how reliability can be assessed and how limitations on reliability should be

communicated. This point is essential. As noted by Roberts and Zuckerman (2010), the benefits of

expert evidence should not be minimised as it undoubtedly has value. Rather, the issue is one of the

problems that can arise when the evidence is misrepresented or its reliability over-emphasised52.

This relates to a fundamental issue, particularly that involving new forms of evidence. Courts need to

distinguish between ‘accepted’ and ‘novel’ scientific evidence but to commit to critically reviewing both

                                                                                                                         49 (n 33) 50 (n 5) 51 (n 10) 52 (n 5)

Page 10: Scientific expert evidence in the UK: Proposing an Abridged Daubert

10    

and not assuming the former automatically has reliability53. Indeed, automatically excluding novel

evidence prematurely, before testing, can raise challenges54. This was captured in Clarke (RL)55 and

Harris and others56 where the court directed that evidence could not be restricted or refused solely on

the basis that it represented a novel scientific advance. Thus, ascertaining a means of determining

reliability for ‘generally accepted’ or ‘novel’ scientific expert opinion becomes crucial. This is the focus

of the ensuing section.

What can be applied to determine evidential reliability?

The cases noted thus far support a case for testing expert opinion for reliability. Until recently the UK

court system has been relaxed on this issue and criticised for the absence of specific criteria57.

Consequently, UK judges are provided with no guidance on how they should determine evidential

reliability. However, the absence of detailed admissibility criteria beyond very basic ‘relevance and

reliability’58 has been commended as pragmatic and a means of ensuring no inhibition of potentially

valuable expert evidence being admitted59. Thus a simple system, such as that found in the UK, is not

necessarily a poor one. Indeed, Roberts and Zuckerman (2010) argue for a retained simplistic approach

to admissibility, advocating solely for the ‘helpfulness’ element of Turner60, namely, if the evidence

does not assist and risks distraction then it should not be admitted regardless of its scientific rigour.

                                                                                                                         53 (n 5) 54 (n 6) 55 [1995] 2 Cr App R 425 56 [2005] EWCA Crim 1980 57 (n 10) 58 JA Dvoskin, LS Guy, ‘On Being an Expert Witness: It’s not about you’ Psychiatry, Psychology and Law, 2008, 15(2), 202-212. 59 (n 10) 60 (n 5)

Page 11: Scientific expert evidence in the UK: Proposing an Abridged Daubert

11    

Nonetheless, the series of cases noted earlier in which expert evidence was indicated to be unreliable,

suggests that more is required than a simple determination of ‘helpfulness’. There has been a focus

elsewhere on developing detailed admissibility criteria which has influenced practice in the UK and is

thus worthy of consideration. One influential case is the Australian case of Bonython61. Three factors

were considered relevant here to determining evidence admissibility; that the evidence was part of

specialised knowledge or experience; that opinion was derived from a reliable body of knowledge or

experience; and the witness had the required experience to express an expert opinion.

Then there is the US system, using the grounding case of Frye62, to deem testimony could only be

admitted if ‘generally accepted’ in the field. Unlike Bonython, this excluded admission of novel

evidence. Bonython has, however, been described as a simple restatement of Frye in part63, illustrating

the close cross-over between these tests. Frye though failed to propose a means of testing the evidence

once ‘general acceptance’ was reached. The previously described case of Winfrey64, for example, would

pass Frye on the ‘general acceptance’ principle concerning osmological [dog scent] evidence. However,

a lack of testing and failure to account for false positive rates65 would make this evidence unreliable,

thus illustrating the problems with Frye.

Due to mounting criticism66, Frye was superseded by a further US case, that of Daubert v Merrell Dow

Pharmaceuticals67 where the 1975 Federal Rules of Evidence68 took precedence. Here, admissibility of

                                                                                                                         61 [1984] 38 SASR 45, 46-47. This forms part of common law in England and Wales. 62 (n 15) which focused on the admissibility of polygraph evidence. 63 D Omerod ‘The Law Governing Reliability and Admissibility in Criminal Trials’ (2008) http://www.northeasterncircuit.co.uk/documents/Ormerod_CBA_lecture_experts_26_april.pdf accessed 10.07.2011. 64 (n 2) 65 Where an individual is falsely identified to have committed an act. 66 (n 10)

Page 12: Scientific expert evidence in the UK: Proposing an Abridged Daubert

12    

scientific knowledge focused on appropriately qualified experts, relevance and reliability69. The latter

criteria included evidence based on a testable theory or technique; evidence subjected to peer review;

inclusion of a known error rate70; standards in place to control its use; and a basis in generally relevant

science, with the latter an element clearly relating to Frye. Generally referred to as the Daubert

Criteria, they are being considered for application to the UK criminal law system71. They have also

been applied with some success to support the admissibility of non-scientific testimony (e.g. Kumho Tire

v. Carmichael72).

Criticisms of using criteria to determine reliability

In 2000, Federal Rule 702 was amended to include additional provisions whereby expert evidence could

be admitted only if based on sufficient facts or data; if it was the product of reliable methods; and if

these methods had been applied correctly and reliably73. Thus there appeared a move to how reliable the

witness was as an information-giver as opposed to how reliable the expert opinion was that they offered.

These improvements did not satisfy critics, with some arguing that what started as a “well-intentioned

attempt to ensure reliable and relevant evidentiary science has had troubling consequences”74 (p 3). One

of the most significant of these has been the exclusion of evidence from juries that did not pass the

                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                     67 (n 16) 68 Federal Rules of Evidence, Rule 702 69 (n 11) 70 (n 44) 71 (n 10) 72 [1999] 526 US 137 73 (n 68) 74 Tellus Institute, ‘Daubert: The most influential supreme court ruling you’ve never heard of’ (A publication of the Project on Scientific Knowledge and Public Policy, Boston, US, June 2003).

Page 13: Scientific expert evidence in the UK: Proposing an Abridged Daubert

13    

Daubert Criteria. This has served to limit prosecution evidence and strengthen defences75. It has also

excluded some legitimate novel or social/behavioural sciences from proceedings76. An example has

been the weight placed on peer review which serves to exclude novel scientific advances, even with

sound methodology77. Indeed, Daubert is liberal when the admitted evidence is well recognised and

researched but too strict when the science is novel or primarily social/behavioural. For the latter, Frye

offers a more relaxed application but has been duly criticised for its liberal nature78.

Despite criticisms of Daubert, it remains one of the most clearly outlined criteria for evidence

admissibility79. It has already had some application in the UK, namely in the case of Dallagher80 when

dealing with the concept of novel scientific evidence. Frye was not considered stringent enough for this

case, with the court opting for what they thought was a more lenient Daubert approach. This

misunderstanding of Daubert suggests that even in its limited application to the UK it has not been

accurately applied or understood81.

For example, in Dallagher, the court had actually applied the ‘general relevance’ element of Daubert

only, disregarding the Frye criteria of ‘general acceptance’. It is true that Frye is stricter on this single

issue but once you consider the additional criteria of Daubert it is apparent that Daubert has stricter

application. The interesting point from the application of Daubert in Dallagher is that even when

admissibility tests have been applied in the UK the focus has not been on reliability but relevance, e.g.

                                                                                                                         75 (n 74) 76 (n 74) 77 (n 10) 78 D Faigman, M Saks, J Sanders. ‘How good is good enough? Expert evidence under Daubert and Kumho’ Case Western Reserve Law Review (2000), 50, 645-647. See also (n 5). 79 (n 10)  80 (n 1) 81 (n 74)

Page 14: Scientific expert evidence in the UK: Proposing an Abridged Daubert

14    

‘why should we care’82. This is a result of the UK system continuing to apply only a rudimentary

principle for admissibility (i.e. Turner Rule) and focusing therefore on including expert evidence outside

typical knowledge. Turner does not have a role, however, in testing evidential reliability, representing

little more than a statement of how evidence should be included and not how it should be tested.

Thus there are a range of issues that require consideration when determining evidential reliability. The

UK system has largely avoided these, focusing more on basic issues, such as admissibility relevance

(Turner Rule), how experts should be used and when83,84. It has avoided the complexity and debate that

has developed around using criteria to determine evidence reliability. Nonetheless, UK Courts do need

some means of sufficiently testing the assertions of their experts85 and distinguishing between science

and junk-science86. The UK cases indicated earlier (e.g. Clark (Sally), Cannings, Dallagher, George

(Barry) and Jenkins (Siôn)) where admitted expert opinion has been deemed later to be unreliable,

provide a basis for ensuring this issue is fully considered across all breadth of legal proceedings.

The UK system needs to embrace these issues in their development of a more rigorous approach to

assessing the reliability of expert evidence87 whilst seeking to avoid difficulties evidenced in the

experiences of other court systems. Although there may be temptation to adopt what appears well-used

criteria from other countries (e.g. Daubert), it will be important to account for challenges in these

                                                                                                                         82 (n 58) 83 Civil Procedure Rules Pt 35; Criminal Procedure Rules, Pt 33 84 (n 5) 85 (n 6) 86 (n 18) 87 (n 63)

Page 15: Scientific expert evidence in the UK: Proposing an Abridged Daubert

15    

approaches88. The ensuing section will outline some proposals that could be considered by the UK legal

system.

WHAT CAN BE PROPOSED TO DETERMINE EVIDENTIAL RELIABILITY FOR EXPERT EVIDENCE

IN THE UK?

As illustrated in this commentary, action is required to improve the criteria for the admission of reliable

expert opinion evidence89, particularly in the UK where there is no detailed guidance on examining

reliability90. The importance of addressing this area is an accepted theme within the literature91, with

criterion approaches (such as Daubert) appearing to have value once correctly applied, particularly to

physical sciences92. Indeed, misapplication of these approaches is based on a poor understanding of

how they should be used93. Of the approaches presented the revised Daubert criteria94 has obtained the

most support, replacing Frye and applied more widely than Bonython. In broad terms, the Daubert

criteria to adopt would require the following components to be evidenced prior to the admission of

expert opinion, namely that it should be;

• Based on a testable theory or technique;

• Subject to peer review;

• Have a known error rate;

• Have standards in place to control its use;                                                                                                                          88 (n 6, 63) 89 (n 5) 90 ( n 10) 91 (n 10) 92 Physical sciences include physics, biology, astronomy etc; referred to generally as ‘hard’ sciences. 93 (n 6) 94 (n 16, 68)

Page 16: Scientific expert evidence in the UK: Proposing an Abridged Daubert

16    

• Have a basis in generally relevant science;

• Based on sufficient facts or data;

• The product of reliable methods;

• Used with a correct and reliably applied method by the expert.

It is argued here, however, that more is required than a simple application of these components,

particularly if the aim is to ensure evidence is not unhelpfully restricted95 or that social/behavioural or

novel scientific advances are not excluded96. For example, peer review, error rates, standards in place,

and sufficient facts and data, will not necessarily be evidenced by new or some social/behavioural

sciences. For novel and some social/behavioural sciences97, therefore, this would leave the following

useable criteria:

• Based on a testable theory or technique;

• The product of reliable methods;

• Used with a correctly and reliably applied method by the expert.

It could also be suggested that the main weakness of a criteria based approach to evidential reliability is

its failure to define what it meant by ‘science’. Regardless of what approach is adopted, either for novel,

social/behavioural or physical sciences98, it needs to be a pragmatic99 and not overwhelmed by detail.

                                                                                                                         95 (n 78, 56) 96 (n 56) 97 Including social sciences such as psychology, politics, criminology and sociology; or behavioural sciences, such as anthropology. These are referred to generally as ‘soft’ sciences. 98 (n 92) 99 (n 18, 5)

Page 17: Scientific expert evidence in the UK: Proposing an Abridged Daubert

17    

Excessive detail will heighten the risk for individual interpretations, which has been one of the main

failings of Daubert100.

What the current commentary proposes instead is a two stage approach, a first stage where a series of

expectations should be met prior to the presentation of expert evidence, and a second where the evidence

is examined in court.

Stage one: Preparing for determining evidential reliability

It is proposed the core components of this stage include the following expectations:

• That the expert submits an information statement critically reviewing their opinions and

methods, further citing any recent advances in the field. This would allow experts to provide a

more balanced outline of their evidence to the Court and to distinguish between science with

considerable credentials, novel science, and common-sense evidence101. It should include

alternative explanations for opinions. Reference is made to the latter in Practice Directions102

but is rarely followed in practice where preference is for confident ‘absolute’ opinions103. The

information statement should also include content on what is needed to make the opinion

reliable, which in some instances may lead to a provisional opinion being indicated104. Experts

can also be invited to indicate, as noted later, exactly what category of science they believe they

are submitting under.                                                                                                                          100 (n 1) as a good example of Daubert being misinterpreted.  101 (n 2, 6) 102 (n 83) 103 (n 6, 63) 104 (n 63)

Page 18: Scientific expert evidence in the UK: Proposing an Abridged Daubert

18    

• That there is a clear definition of what type of evidence is being submitted. A rudimentary

definition of science has hampered the use of criterion approaches. This issue has been

completely missed by the various reviews into evidential reliability105. Even in the case of

Kumho Tire v. Carmichael this issue was not dealt with, where focus instead was on the

scientific method applied to physical (not social) evidence106. In order to determine how the

evidence can be tested for reliability there should be provisional agreement at this stage as to

which of the following categories the evidence primarily fits:

o Generally accepted physical sciences;

o Generally accepted social/behavioural sciences;

o Novel physical sciences;

o Novel social/behavioural sciences;

o Common-sense evidence.

What is not being suggested though is that stage one is equivalent to a Daubert Hearing107 where

advocates effectively test pre-hearing if the evidence can meet the criteria, rejecting its submission at

that stage if it does not. Such approaches have led, as noted earlier, to restrictions on the range of

evidence that a jury or decision-maker should be rightly exposed to108.

                                                                                                                         105 (n 4, 5, 6, 18, 10, 63). None of these sources make mention of this issue. 106 (n 72) where focus was on a damaged tire; the tire represents physical evidence and cannot be compared therefore to that indicated in some social/behavioural sciences. 107 (n 74) 108 (n 74)

Page 19: Scientific expert evidence in the UK: Proposing an Abridged Daubert

19    

Adopting a Daubert-style hearing approach is inconsistent with the UK system of relevance (i.e. Turner

Rule) and would unfairly restrict the admission of novel scientific advances 109 and some

social/behavioural sciences110. Stage one is suggested here merely as a preparation stage to allow

advocates to collect the evidence they require to prepare for a detailed examination of the expert

opinion.

Stage two: Evidence examination

Stage two should lead to the exclusion of common-sense evidence on the basis of the Turner Rule.

Focus then moves to generally accepted science versus novel science. The five categories indicated

earlier (i.e. generally accepted physical sciences, generally accepted social/behavioural sciences, novel

physical sciences, novel social/behavioural sciences and common-sense evidence) would allow stage

two to apply criteria differentially. It is suggested here that the Daubert criteria is automatically applied

to generally accepted physical sciences, with an Abridged-Daubert proposed by the current paper to

apply to generally accepted social/behavioural sciences, novel physical science, and novel

social/behavioural science.

The only science that may cross Daubert and Abridged-Daubert would be generally accepted

social/behavioural sciences where occasions may arise where the science is closer in methodology to

physical sciences111. Adopting a pragmatic approach112, it is proposed this is submitted using Abridged-

Daubert with full Daubert used to supplement decisions. Abridged-Daubert is, admittedly, a lower                                                                                                                          109 (n 56) 110 (n 97) 111 Some elements of cognitive psychology, neuropsychology or anthropology, for example, may include evidence that appears more in keeping with physical sciences. 112 (n 5, 18)

Page 20: Scientific expert evidence in the UK: Proposing an Abridged Daubert

20    

level of reliability testing but would allow decision-makers to form their own view as to evidence

quality and avoid comparison to the more easily measurable physical sciences. Such an approach should

further reassure critics who argue for the removal of non-physical sciences from expert opinion

evidence113 because it cannot meet these prescribed criteria, even though this is inconsistent with the

importance of not restricting evidence114. Abridged-Daubert would at least allow for some evidence

testing.

Once evidence is deemed admissible on the basis of the criteria indicated here, the following principles

are then recommended;

• That all admitted evidence is accompanied by a statement of limitations, with this determined

largely on the basis of stage one. Precedents for this have already occurred in cases such as

Luttrell115. However, it is proposed this is not restricted to novel sciences but applied to all

evidence categories. This would allow all evidence to be tested equally without prejudice116.

The proposed statement of limitations should include a comment on the nature of the evidence,

namely if it is generally accepted science or a new advance.

• Disagreements between experts are acknowledged but not used to reject evidence.

Disagreements cannot be used as a basis to suggest that the science is flawed and all expert

                                                                                                                         113 See JT Richardson, GP Ginsburg, S Gatowski, S Dobbin, ‘The problems of applying Daubert to psychological syndrome evidence’ Judicature (1995) 79, 10; and M S Brodin, ‘Behavioural science evidence in the age of Daubert: Reflections of a skeptic’, Boston College Law School Faculty Papers (2004) 24, Berkley Electronic Press. Both outline problems in admitting non-physical science evidence. http://www.lacba.org/Files/Main%20Folder/Sections/Family%20law/Files/Shucart%202-2-05.pdf Accessed 29.06.2011. 114 (n 56) 115 (n 30) 116 (n 56)

Page 21: Scientific expert evidence in the UK: Proposing an Abridged Daubert

21    

opinions therefore should be rejected as they lack reliability117. Disagreements between experts,

does not reduce evidential reliability but allows for a more thorough testing of opinion.

Reliability criteria were not designed to compare and contrast experts118. The stage one critical

review proposed here should nonetheless assist with communicating these difficulties.

Importance of a two stage approach

Adopting a two stage approach where the starting point is the clear definition of the type of scientific

evidence and subsequent provision of a critical review, would allow courts to indicate what type of

criteria (i.e. Daubert; Daubert-Abridged) should be applied. The inclusion of an automatic stage two

allows for all expert evidence to be submitted and reliably tested using shared criteria to determine

admissibility. Adopting different criteria dependent on the nature of the science has value and supports

the commentary in cases such as Harris119 where it was thought a single test could not apply to all

evidence. The proposed approach supports this and protects against the exclusion of scientific advances

and non-physical sciences, whilst also allowing for more rigorous testing of ‘generally accepted’

sciences, whether physical or social/behavioural.

CONCLUSION

This commentary aimed to identify issues surrounding evidential reliability and difficulties with the lack

of criteria in the UK. It posed three initial questions; 1.) Is there cause for concern about evidential                                                                                                                          117 See R v Kai-Whitewind [2005] 2 Cr App R 31. A case involving the unexplained death of a child whom the mother had been accused of killing. The defence team noted disagreement between experts as a basis for their submission to argue for proceedings being unsafe. 118 (n 10) 119 (n 56)

Page 22: Scientific expert evidence in the UK: Proposing an Abridged Daubert

22    

reliability which suggests criteria are required? 2.) Are criteria already in existence that is relevant and

has support? 3.) What can be proposed to determine evidential reliability, if required?

The commentary aimed to answer the first two in the affirmative; there is cause for concern in the

absence of criteria120 and there appears a preferred criteria approach, namely Daubert. The problems

focus more on the overly strict application of such a criteria approach121. Such an approach also fails to

address the fundamental issue as to what type of science it is being applied to122. Problems have

occurred when its application has been beyond generally accepted physical sciences123, with the expert

evidence consequently being excluded124 on the basis that it does not meet criteria which it could never

actually meet. Thus although a criteria approach can assist in ensuring ‘junk’ science125 is excluded

from court, it may unfairly restrict evidence126, particularly that from social/behavioural and novel

sciences.

To answer the third question posed at the start of this commentary, it is argued that proposals can be

made to determine evidential reliability. The proposals focus on how criteria are applied as opposed to

their exact content. Proposed is a two stage approach whereby there is a classification and expert-

critique of the evidence (stage one), followed by an examination and limitation-giving component (stage

two). Common-sense or ‘junk’ science should be excluded by the process of stage one, allowing for

detailed and fairer consideration of a wider range of expert scientific opinion at stage two. In order to

                                                                                                                         120 (n 10) 121 (n 10) 122 (n 111) 123 (n 92) 124 (n 55, 74) 125 (n 18) 126 (n 55)

Page 23: Scientific expert evidence in the UK: Proposing an Abridged Daubert

23    

achieve this, it is argued that Daubert should apply for generally accepted physical sciences and an

Abridged-Daubert for social/behavioural sciences or novel scientific approaches.

What is suggested here is not an exact approach. For example, areas not addressed include the

importance of training advocates and decision-makers more thoroughly in the application of criteria

approaches and sciences more generally 127 , and training experts on what constitutes evidential

reliability128. What is clear is that the UK system requires some means of assessing evidential

reliability, with increased focus on the critical evaluation of all scientific expert evidence129. This

system should include evidence from a range of sciences and not exclude novel science130. It should

involve experts more in an assessment of their own evidence and qualification to use the methods they

apply in their evidence131, and place equal focus on the implementation of assessment criteria and

determination of its content. Underpinning the approach should be an acceptance that a range of science

can bring value to court, and that resolving all the problems associated with expert evidence is an

impossible goal to attain132.

                                                                                                                         127 (n 74) 128 (n 74, 18) 129 (n 5) 130 (n 56) 131 (n 6, 55, 74, 78) 132 (n 6)  

Page 24: Scientific expert evidence in the UK: Proposing an Abridged Daubert

24    

BIBLIOGRAPHY

Books, Journals, Reports

M S Brodin, ‘Behavioural science evidence in the age of Daubert: Reflections of a skeptic’, Boston

College Law School Faculty Papers (2004) 24, Berkley Electronic Press.

C Champod, B Kuchler, I Evett, ‘Earmarks as evidence: A critical review’ Journal of Forensic Sciences

(2002) 46/6, 1275-1284.

I Dennis, The Law of Evidence (4th Edition, London, Sweet & Maxwell, 2007).

JA Dvoskin, LS Guy, ‘On Being an Expert Witness: It’s not about you’ Psychiatry, Psychology and

Law, 2008, 15(2), 202-212, with ‘relevance’ referred to as ‘why should we care’.

D Faigman, M Saks, J Sanders. ‘How good is good enough? Expert evidence under Daubert and

Kumho’ Case Western Reserve Law Review (2000), 50, 645-647

Keane, A. The Modern Law of Evidence (8th ed, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2010).

Law Commission Consultation Paper No 190. The admissibility of expert evidence in criminal

proceedings in England and Wales: A new approach to the determination of evidentiary reliability: A

consultation paper. 2009.

Page 25: Scientific expert evidence in the UK: Proposing an Abridged Daubert

25    

Law Commission Paper No 325. Expert Evidence in Criminal Proceedings in England and Wales.

2011.

D Omerod, A Roberts, ‘Expert evidence: Where now? Where next?’ Archbold (2006) June, 5 – 9

M Redmayne, Expert Evidence and Criminal Justice (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2001).

JT Richardson, GP Ginsburg, S Gatowski, S Dobbin, ‘The problems of applying Daubert to

psychological syndrome evidence’ Judicature (1995) 79, 10.

P Roberts, A Zuckerman, The Principles of Criminal Evidence (2nd ed, OUP, Oxford, 2010).

N Squires, ‘Amanda Knox freed: tears of joy as four-year nightmare is over – Telegraph’ (The Daily

Telegraph, London, 3rd October 2011).

C Tapper, Cross and Tapper on Evidence (12th Edition, OUP, Oxford, 2010), ch 11.

San Diego County Grand Jury Report of 1993-1994: Families in Crisis.

Tellus Institute, ‘Daubert: The most influential supreme court ruling you’ve never heard of’ (A

publication of the Project on Scientific Knowledge and Public Policy, Boston, US, June 2003).

J Wojcikiewicz, ‘Dog scent line-up as scientific evidence’ (1999) accessed via http://www.forensic-

science.com on 04.07.2011.

Page 26: Scientific expert evidence in the UK: Proposing an Abridged Daubert

26    

Procedure

Civil Procedure Rules Pt 35

Criminal Procedure Rules, Pt 33

Cases

The Queen v Bonython [1984] 38 SASR 45, 46-47

R v Cannings [2004] 2 Cr App R 7

Kumho Tire v. Carmichael [1999] 526 US 137

R v Clarke (RL) [1995] 2 Cr App R 425

R v Clark (Sally) [2003] EWCA Crim 1020

State v. Cross [2009] 681 S E 2d 566 WL 2177766

R v Dallagher [2002] EWCA Crim 1903

R v George (Barry) [2007] EWCA Crim 2722

R v Jenkins (Siôn) [2004] EWCA Crim 2047

Daubert v Merrell Dow Pharmaceuticals [1993] 509 US 579

Frye v. United States [1993] 293 F 1013

R v Gerrard Francis Luttrell and others [2004] EWCA Crim 1344

R v Gilfoyle [2001] 2 Cr App R 5

R v Harris and others [2005] EWCA Crim 1980

R v Turner [1975] QB 834 841

R v Kai-Whitewind [2005] 2 Cr App R 31

Winfrey v The State of Texas [2010] Tex Crim Ap No PD-0987-09