rayo, agustin - neo-fregeanism reconsidered.pdf

Upload: armando-lavalle

Post on 03-Jun-2018

239 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/12/2019 Rayo, Agustin - Neo-fregeanism reconsidered.pdf

    1/32

    Neo-Fregeanism Reconsidered

    Agustn Rayo

    March 11, 2009

    1 Platonism

    Mathematical Platonism is the view that mathematical objects exist. Traditional Pla-

    tonists believe that one can make sense of a world with no mathematical objects; subtle

    Platonists disagree.

    The easiest way of getting a handle on traditional Platonism is by imagining a creation

    myth. On the first day God created light; by the sixth day, she had created a large and

    complex world, including black holes, planets and sea-slugs. But there was something left

    to be done. On the seventh day she created mathematical objects. Only thendid she rest.

    On this view, it is easy to make sense of a world with no mathematical objects: it is just

    like the world we are considering, except that God rested on the seventh day.

    The crucial feature of this creation myth is that God needed to do something extra

    in order to bring about the existence of mathematical objects: something that wasnt

    already in place when she created black holes, planets and sea-slugs. According to subtle

    Platonists, this is a mistake. A subtle Platonist believes that for the number of the Fs

    to be eight just is for there to be eight planets. So when God created eight planets she

    therebymade it the case that the number of the planets was eight. More generally, subtle

    For their many helpful comments I am grateful to Roy Cook and Matti Eklund, and to audiences at

    the University of Connecticut and the University of St Andrews.

    1

  • 8/12/2019 Rayo, Agustin - Neo-fregeanism reconsidered.pdf

    2/32

    Platonists believe that there is no sense to be made of a world without numbers. Suppose,

    for reductio, that there are no numbers. The subtle Platonist thinks that for the number

    of numbers to be zero just is for there to be no numbers. So the number zero must exist

    after all, contradicting our assumption.

    Essential to the subtle Platonists position is the acceptance ofnon-objectual identity

    statements: identity statements in which the identity-predicate takes formulasrather than

    singular terms in its argument places. For instance:

    For the number of the planets to be eight just isfor there to be eight planets.

    [In symbols: #x(Planet(x)) = 8 !8x(Planet(x)).]

    This is the sense of identity whereby most of us would wish to claim that for a wedding

    to take place just is for someone to get married [i.e. x(Wedding(x) TakesPlace(x))

    x(Married(x))], that for something to be hotjust isfor it to have high mean kinetic energy

    [i.e. Hot(x)x HMKE(x)], and that for two people to be siblings just isfor them to share a

    parent [i.e. Siblings(x, y)x,y z(Parent(z, x)Parent(z, y))]. It is also the sense of identity

    whereby some philosophers (but not all) would wish to claim that for there to be a table just

    is for there to be some particles arranged table-wise [i.e.x(Table(x)) X(ArrTw(X))].

    The non-objectual identity symbol (or its natural-language correlate just is) is

    meant to express a form ofidentity. So it had better be reflexive, transitive and symmetric.

    In particular, there should be no difference between saying, on the one hand, that for a

    wedding to take place just isfor someone to get married and saying, on the other, that for

    someone to get married just isfor a wedding to take place.

    From this it follows that isnotmeant to capture a relation of metaphysical priority.

    If you think that for a wedding to take place just isfor someone to get married, you should

    think that there is a feature of reality that can be fully and accurately described by saying

    a wedding took place and can also be fully and accurately described by saying someone

    2

  • 8/12/2019 Rayo, Agustin - Neo-fregeanism reconsidered.pdf

    3/32

    got married. But you have notthereby committed yourself to the view that one of these

    descriptions is, in some sense, more fundamental than the other.

    First-order identities can be regarded as a special case of non-objectual identities. The

    standard first-order identity-statement a= b is equivalent to the conjunction of the non-

    objectual identity-statement to be a just isto be b [i.e. x= a x x= b] and a sentence

    asserting the existence ofa [i.e. x(x = a)]. (The Kripkean reading of a = b, whereby

    a= b can be true at a world in which a fails to exist, is equivalent to x= a x x= b.)

    Semi-identitystatements, such as part of what it is to be scarlet is to be red [in symbols:

    Scarlet(x)xRed(x)], can also be regarded as a special case of non-objectual identities.

    In general, Fx x Gx is equivalent to Fx x (Gx Fx). In light of these connections,

    I will use identity-statement in what follows to refer to any statement equivalent to a

    sentence of the form (x1, . . . , xn)x1,...,xn (x1, . . . , xn) (n 0).

    Identity-statements pervade our pre-theoretic, scientific and philosophical discourse.

    Yet they have been given surprisingly little attention in the literature, and are in much

    need of elucidation. I think it would be hopeless to attempt an explicit definition of

    ,not because true and illuminating equivalences couldnt be foundI will suggest some

    belowbut because any potential definiens can be expected to contain expressions that

    are in at least as much need of elucidation as . The right methodology, it seems to

    me, is to explain how our acceptance of identities interacts with the rest of our theorizing,

    and use these interconnections to inform our understanding of . (I make no claims

    about conceptual priority: the various interconnections I will discuss are as well-placed to

    inform our understanding of on the basis of other notions as they are to inform our

    understanding of the other notions on the basis of .)

    3

  • 8/12/2019 Rayo, Agustin - Neo-fregeanism reconsidered.pdf

    4/32

    1.1 Identity

    In this section I will suggest four different ways in which our acceptance of identity-statements interacts with the rest of our theorizing. (I have developed these connections in

    far greater detail, and addressed some potential objections, in An Account of Possibility

    and Towards a Trivialist Account of Mathematics.)

    1.1.1 Truth-conditions

    A sentences truth-conditions are usefully thought of as imposing a requirement on the

    world. Specifically: the requirement that the world be such as it would need to be in

    order for the truth-conditions to be satisfied. The truth-conditions of snow is white, for

    example, impose the requirement that snow be white, and the truth conditions of grass is

    green the requirement that grass be green.

    Suppose you think that for something to be composed of water just is for it to be

    composed of H2O. Then you should think that what is required of the world in order for

    the truth-conditions of the sentence Ais composed of water to be satisfied is precisely what

    is required of the world in order for the truth-conditions of the sentence A is composed

    of H2O to be satisfied. In particular, you should think that all that is required of the

    world in order for the truth-conditions of A is composed of water to be satisfied is for A

    to be composed of H2O, and that all that is required of the world in order for the truth

    conditions of A is composed of H2O to be satisfied is that A be composed of water.

    Conversely: suppose you think that what is required of the world in order for the truth-

    conditions of A is composed of water to be satisfied is precisely what is required of the

    world in order for A is composed of H2O to be satisfied. Then you should think that for

    something to be made of water just isfor it to be made of H2O.

    4

  • 8/12/2019 Rayo, Agustin - Neo-fregeanism reconsidered.pdf

    5/32

    1.1.2 De re intelligibility

    Let a story be a set of sentences in some language we understand. I shall assume thatstories are read de re: that every name used by the story is used to say of the names

    actualbearer how it is according to the story, and that every predicate used by the story

    is used to attribute the property actuallyexpressed by the predicate to characters in the

    story. Accordingly, in order for a story that says Hesperus is covered with water to be

    true it must be the case that Venus itself is covered with H2O. (I shall ignore names that

    are actually empty, such as Sherlock Holmes, and predicates that are actually empty, such

    as . . . is composed of phlogiston or . . . is a unicorn.)

    Sometimes we describe a story as unintelligible on the grounds that it is too complicated

    for us to understand. That is not the notion of unintelligibility I will have in mind here.

    I will say that a story is de re unintelligiblefor a subject if her best effort to make sense

    of a scenario verifying the story would yield something she regards as incoherent. (De re

    intelligibility is the contradictory ofde re unintelligibility.)

    Here is an example. Consider a story that says Hesperus is not Phosphorus. My best

    effort to make sense of a scenario verifying this story ends in incoherence. For a scenario

    in which the story is true would have to be a scenario in which Hesperus itself (i.e. Venus)

    fails to be identical with Phosphorus itself (i.e. Venus), and the nonselfidentity of Venus is

    something I regard as incoherent. Another example: consider a story that says a wedding

    took place, but nobody got married. For a wedding to take place just is for someone to

    get married. So a scenario verifying a wedding took place, but nobody got married would

    have to be a scenario in which a wedding takes placei.e. a scenario in which someone

    gets marriedbut nobody gets married, which is something I regard as incoherent. (Of

    course, it would be easy enough to make sense of a scenario in which language is used in

    such a way that the expression Hesperus is not Phosphorus or a wedding took place, but

    nobody got married is true. But that wont help with the question of whether the original

    5

  • 8/12/2019 Rayo, Agustin - Neo-fregeanism reconsidered.pdf

    6/32

    story is de reintelligible.)

    There is an intimate connection between identity and de re intelligibility: a story is

    de reunintelligible for a subject just in case she is in a position to derive something she

    regards as incoherent from the result of adding the story to the set of identities she accepts,

    using inferences she takes to be logically valid.

    Three clarifications: (1) The notion ofde reintelligibility is deeply non-a priori. For

    whether or not one takes a story to be de reintelligible will depend on whether one believes

    that, say, Hesperus is Phosphorusand this is not the sort of thing that one could come

    to know a priori. (2) Perhaps you think there is a sense of intelligibility (distinct from

    de re intelligibility) with respect to which it would be right to say that Hesperus is not

    Phosphorus is an intelligible story. You could claim, for example, that Hesperus is not

    Phosphorus is intelligible in the following sense: it would be verified (in a special sense of

    verify) by a scenario in which the first heavenly body to be visible in the evenings is not

    the last heavenly body to be visible in the mornings. I myself am skeptical that the needed

    notion of verificationwhich is, in effect, an implementation of the idea that our sentenceshave primary intensionsis in good order. But nothing in this paper will turn on my

    skepticism. If you think you can understand a notion of intelligibility distinct from de re

    intelligibility, thats fine. Just keep in mind that its not the notion under discussion here.

    (3) So far we have talked about the intelligibility of stories, but not the intelligibility of

    the scenarios that the stories depict. When a scenario is picked out by a story, we shall say

    that the scenario is intelligible just in case the story used to pick it out is de reintelligible.

    1.1.3 Why-closure

    Suppose someone says: I can see that Hesperus is Phosphorus; what I want to understand

    is why. It is not just that one wouldnt know how to comply with such a requestone

    is unable to make senseof it. The natural reaction is to reject it altogether. One might

    6

  • 8/12/2019 Rayo, Agustin - Neo-fregeanism reconsidered.pdf

    7/32

    reply, for instance, What do you mean why? Hesperus just isPhosphorus.

    Contrast this with a case in which someone says: I can see that the window is broken;

    what I want to understand is why, or I can see that the radioactive isotope decayed

    at time t rather than a second later; what I want to understand is why, or even I can

    see that there is something rather than nothing; what I want to understand is why. In

    all three of these cases, one can at least make sense of the request. In the first case, one

    may even have a satisfying reply (e.g. The window is broken because it was hit by soccer

    ball). In the second case, it is harder to think of a goodreply, but one can at least think

    of a bad one (e.g. because God willed it so). Potential replies are even scarcer in the

    third case (even bad ones), but one can at least state that there is no good answer to be

    given without refusing to make sense the question (e.g. Well, thats just the way things

    turned out.). Contrast this with the initial Hesperus/Phosphorus case, where it isnt even

    appropriate to say Well, thats just the way things turned out.

    Say that a sentence is treated as why-closedjust in case one is unable to make sense

    of

    Why is it the case that

    ?

    . (Here it is important to stipulate that the question is notto be read as a groundingquestion. In other words: (1) it is not to be read as a request

    for justification, as when someone asks Why is Hesperus is Phosphorus? in an effort to

    acquire grounds for believing that Hesperus is Phosphorus; (2) it is not to be read as a

    request for insight about what the truth of would consist in, as when one reads Why are

    elephants mammals? as a request for better understanding what it takes to be a mammal;

    and (3) it is assumed not to be a case in which someone is able to see that has the

    truth-conditions that it actually has, but does not fully understand why this is so, as when

    one reads Why are there infinitely many primes? as a request for a more illuminating

    proof of the theorem.)

    There is an intimate connection between identity and why-closure: the sentences one

    treats as as why-closed are those one regards as logical consequences of the identity-

    7

  • 8/12/2019 Rayo, Agustin - Neo-fregeanism reconsidered.pdf

    8/32

    statements one accepts.

    1.1.4 Possibility

    When one looks at the philosophical literature on possibility (or metaphysical possibility,

    as it is sometimes called), one is left with the impression that there are two schools of

    thought. According to the metaphysicalschool of thought, there is a gap between intelli-

    gibility and possibility. It might be thought to be intelligible, for instance, that Hesperus

    fail to be Phosphorus, or that I be a sea-slug. But such rogue scenarios are to be counted

    as impossible nonetheless, on the grounds that they are, in some sense, metaphysically

    untoward. They violate the metaphysical laws, as it were. (For an example of this sort

    of approach, see Kment (2006); for useful discussion, see Rosen (2006).)

    This picture strikes me as doubly objectionable. Firstly, I think one should be weary

    of a notion of intelligibility according to which it is intelligible that Hesperus fail to be

    Phosphorus or that I be a sea-slug. It is certainly not de reintelligibilitynot, at least, on

    the assumption that one believes that Hesperus is Phosphorus and that part of what it is tobe me is to be a human and not a sea-slug. The view, presumably, is that is intelligible

    is to be cashed out in terms of something along the lines of is not analytic or has a

    non-empty primary intension. Notice, however, that each of these proposals relies on the

    assumption that one can factor the requirement that a sentences truth-conditions impose

    on the world into two parts: an a prioricomponent and a non-a prioricomponent. And I

    see no good reason for thinking that this is true in general, even if it seems plausible when

    one focuses on toy examples such as Hesperus is Phosphorus.

    Secondly, and more importantly, the notion of a metaphysical law strikes me as both

    obscure and unhelpful. It strikes me as obscure because I have never been able to find

    a use for it outside Deep Metaphysicsmetaphysics of the kind only a metaphysician

    would understand (and only a metaphysician would care about). It strikes me as unhelpful

    8

  • 8/12/2019 Rayo, Agustin - Neo-fregeanism reconsidered.pdf

    9/32

    because it drives a wedge between the notion of possibility and one of its most useful

    applications: the representation of content. For in stating a metaphysical law one would

    presumably be saying something non-trivial about the way the world is. But if every

    possible scenario is a scenario which verifies the metaphysical laws, one cannot hope to

    represent the non-trivial requirement that the world must meet in order for a metaphysical

    law to hold by dividing up the possibilities into those that meet the requirement and those

    that do not.

    The right way of thinking about possibility, it seems to me, is by refusing to allow a gap

    between possibility and intelligibility: possibility just is de reintelligibility. To see a de re

    story as describing a possible world is to take the story to be de re intelligible. By appealing

    to de reintelligibility, one is able to steer clear of the analytic/synthetic distinction and

    its siblings. One works with a notion which is non-a priori to begin with, rather than

    construing necessity as a marriage between a priori truths and non-a priori Kripkean

    necessities. The result is that one gets a distinction between necessity and contingency

    without having to forego the Quinean insight that conceptual questions cannot be cleanlyseparated from questions of fact.

    In addition, the alternative strategy has the advantage of not severing the connection

    between possibility and content. To see this, think of a sentences truth-conditions as a

    requirement imposed on the world: a requirement that the world be a certain way. Knowing

    whether a scenario we regard as intelligible must fail to obtain in order for the requirement

    to be met is valuable because it gives us an understanding of how the world would need

    to be in order for the requirement to be satisfied. But knowing whether a scenario we

    dont regard as intelligible must fail to obtain in order for the requirement to be to be

    met is not very helpful. For when one is unable to describe a scenario in a way one finds

    intelligible, the claim that the scenario must fail to obtain gives one no understanding

    of how the world would need to be in order for the requirement to be satisfied. The

    9

  • 8/12/2019 Rayo, Agustin - Neo-fregeanism reconsidered.pdf

    10/32

    result is that one can model a sentences truth-conditions as a partition of the space of

    scenarios one regards as intelligible. So the notion of possibility that is useful for modeling

    truth-conditions is precisely the notion that is correlated with intelligibility. (Earlier I

    had described connections between truth-conditions and identity, on the one hand, and

    identity and intelligibility, on the other. The present connection between truth-conditions

    and intelligibility closes the circle.)

    A third advantage of the alternative way of thinking about possibility is that it re-

    moves some of the mystery surrounding modal knowledge. For if the stories we regard

    as describing a possible world are the stories we regard as de re intelligible, and if the

    stories we regard as de reintelligible are the stories we take to be logically consistent with

    the identities we accept, then our modal knowledge should be no more mysterious than

    our knowledge of identities. And, in some cases at least, our knowledge of identities is

    relatively unmysteriouswitness our knowledge of the fact that to be hot just is to have

    high mean kinetic energy.

    I would like to end this section by mentioning a complication that I have been ignoringto simplify the exposition. In discussing the connections between identity, truth-conditions,

    intelligibility, why-closure and possibility, I have tacitly assumed that attention is restricted

    to the sorts of sentences that are best formalized in a (non-modal) first-order language. I

    am happy to the claim, for example, that one will treat Agustn has a mustache as possibly

    true (andde reintelligible) just in case one takes it to be logically consistent with the set of

    identities one accepts. But I do not wish to be committed to the claim that one will treat,

    e.g. mustached individuals are essentially mustached [in symbols: (x(Mustached(x)

    (y(y= x Mustached(x)))))] as possibly true (and intelligiblede re) just in case one

    takes it to be logically consistent with the set of identities one accepts. For mustached

    individuals are essentially mustached will only be true if different worlds are in agreement

    about who has a mustache and who does not, and two worlds can fail to display such

    10

  • 8/12/2019 Rayo, Agustin - Neo-fregeanism reconsidered.pdf

    11/32

    agreement even if each of them, taken in isolation, is consistent with the set of identities one

    accepts. Happily, there is a way of extending the proposal to encompass every sentence of

    a first-order modal language. And when the enriched proposal is combined with a suitable

    list of identity statements, one gets a non-revisionary list of modal truths, including all

    of the standard Kripkean necessities. (The results are made possible by a supervenience

    theorem, which shows that by fixing the truth-value of every identity-statement, every

    conditional identity statement and every sentence in the language containing no boxes or

    diamonds, one fixes the truth-value of every sentence in the modal language. See my An

    Account of Possibility for details. )

    1.2 The Resulting Picture

    In the preceding section I suggested several different ways in which our acceptance of

    identity-statements interacts with the rest of our theorizing. In doing so, I hope to have

    shown that the notion of non-objectual identity is not a creature of Deep Metaphysics. It

    is at the center of our theorizing about content, intelligibility, explanation and possibility.

    The aim of the present section is to make some brief remarks about the philosophical

    picture that emerges from these theoretical connections.

    In theorizing about the world, we do three things at once. First, we develop a language

    within which to formulate theoretical questions. Second, we endorse a family of identity-

    statements, and thereby classify the questions that can be formulated in the language into

    those we take to be worth answering and those we take to be pointless. (For instance, by

    accepting to be composed of water just isto be composed of H2O, we resolve that why

    does this portion of water contain hydrogen? is not the sort of question that is worth

    answering; had we instead accepted to be composed of water just is to be an odorless,

    colorless liquid with thus-and-such properties, we would have taken why does this portion

    of water contain hydrogen? to be an interesting question, deserving explanation.) Third,

    11

  • 8/12/2019 Rayo, Agustin - Neo-fregeanism reconsidered.pdf

    12/32

    we set forth theoretical claims that address the questions we take to be worth answering.

    (For instance, having accepted to be composed of water just isto be composed of H2O,

    we set forth theoretical claims as an answer to the question why is this portion of water

    an odorless, colorless liquid with thus-and-such properties?.)

    In light of the connection between identity and possibility, when one endorses a set of

    identity-statements one is, in effect, endorsing a space of possible worlds. And in light of the

    connection between possibility and intelligibility, a space of possible words can be regarded

    as a framework for ascertaining the limits of intelligibility. In other words: by endorsing

    a set of identity-statements one is, in effect, endorsing a framework for ascertaining the

    limits of intelligibility.

    It is against the background of such a framework that it makes sense to distinguish

    between factual sentencesi.e. sentences that are verified by some intelligible scenarios

    but not othersand necessary truthsi.e. sentences that are verified in every intelligible

    scenario. What one gets is a post-Quinean revival of the position that Carnap advanced

    in Empiricism, Semantics and Ontology. Carnaps frameworks, like ours, are devices fordistinguishing between factual sentences and necessary truths. The big difference is that

    whereas Carnaps distinction was tied up with the analytic/synthetic distinction, ours is

    not.

    (Is there an objective fact of the matter about which choice of identity-statements

    i.e. which choice of frameworkis correct? Nothing in the paper will turn on the answer

    to this question. My own view, for what its worth, is that there is not. All one can

    say is that different choices are more or less amenable to the development of a successful

    articulation of ones methods of inquiry, given the way the world is. The empirical facts

    make it the case that acceptance of to be composed of water just is to be composed of

    H2O leads to particularly fruitful theorizing, and one has strong reasons to accept it on

    this basis. But there is no more to be said on its behalf. And when it comes to other

    12

  • 8/12/2019 Rayo, Agustin - Neo-fregeanism reconsidered.pdf

    13/32

    identity-statements, the empirical pressures are even milder. For example, whether it is a

    good idea to accept to be a reptile is to have a certain lineage rather than to be a reptile is

    to have a certain phenotype might to a large extent depend on the purposes at hand. But,

    to insist, nothing in this paper turns on whether one favors a pragmatic attitude towards

    identity-statements. And if you think there is an objective fact of the matter about which

    identities are true you can use it to convert the subject-relative characterizations of de

    reintelligibility, why-closure and possibility that I set forth in the preceding section into

    objective ones: a story is de re intelligible just in case it is logically consistent with the

    true semi-identity statements; is why-closed just in case it is a logical consequence of the

    true semi-identities; a story describes a possible world just in case it is de reintelligible.)

    1.3 Back to Platonism

    I introduced the difference between traditional and subtle Platonism by saying that whereas

    traditional Platonists believe that one can make sense of a world with no mathematical

    objects, subtle Platonists think one cannot. But if one is prepared to identify possibility

    and intelligibility, as I suggested in section 1.1.4, one can also state the difference as

    follows: traditional Platonists believe that mathematical objects exist contingently; subtle

    Platonists believe that they exist necessarily.

    This way of characterizing the debate might strike you as suspect. If so, it may be

    because you have a different conception of possibility in mindsomething akin to the

    metaphysical conception of possibility I described in section 1.1.4. (See also Rosen (2006).)

    You may be thinking of necessary existence as a special kind of metaphysical status. It is,

    of course, open to traditional Platonists to claim that numbers enjoy necessary existence

    in this sense. But notice that in doing so they would be engaging in Deep Metaphysics.

    For whether or not an object enjoys this special metaphysical status is the sort of question

    that only a metaphysician would be in a position to ascertain, and only a metaphysician

    13

  • 8/12/2019 Rayo, Agustin - Neo-fregeanism reconsidered.pdf

    14/32

    would care about.

    In contrast, the claim that numbers exist necessarily in the sense of necessity that is

    at issue here has consequences far beyond metaphysics. It delivers the result that the

    existence of numbers is no longer a factual question: nothing is required of the world in

    order for the truth-conditions of a truth of pure mathematics to be satisfied. Satisfaction

    is guaranteed by the framework with respect to which we have chosen to carry out our

    theoretical investigation of the world. And this, in turn, has non-trivial epistemological

    consequences.

    Non-factuality, in our sense, does not entail a priori knowability. (To be composed

    of water just isto be composed of H2O will count as non-facutal even though it is not

    knowable a priori.) But there is still room for mathematical truths to enjoy a privileged

    epistemological status. For in adopting a frameworki.e. in adopting a family of identity-

    statementsone makes decisions that are closely tied to empirical considerations, but

    also decisions that are more organizational in nature. This is because a delicate balance

    must be struck. If one accepts too many identities, one will be committed to treating asunintelligible scenarios that might have been useful in theorizing about the world. If one

    accepts too few, one opens the door to a larger range of intelligible scenarios, all of them

    candidates for truth. In discriminating amongst these scenarios one will have to explain

    why one favors the ones one favors. And although the relevant explanations could lead to

    fruitful theorizing, they could also prove burdensome.

    Logic and mathematics play an important role in finding the right balance between

    these competing considerations. Consider, for example, the decision to treat p p

    as a logical truth (i.e. the decision to accept every identity-statement of the form for pto

    be the case just is for p to be the case). A friend of intuitionistic logic, who denies

    the logicality of p p, thinks it might be worthwhile to ask why it is the case that

    p even if you fully understand why it is not the case that p. In the best case scenario,

    14

  • 8/12/2019 Rayo, Agustin - Neo-fregeanism reconsidered.pdf

    15/32

    making room for an answer will lead to fruitful theorizing. But things may not go that

    well. One might come to see the newfound conceptual space between a sentence and its

    double negation as a pointless distraction, demanding explanations in places where there

    is nothing fruitful to be said.

    The result is that even if none of the decisions one makes in adopting a family of

    identity-statements is wholly independent of empirical considerations, some decisions are

    more closely tied to empirical considerations than others. And when it comes to identity-

    statements corresponding to logic and mathematics, one would expect the focus to be less

    on particular empirical matters and more on questions of framework-organization. So there

    is room for a picture whereby an epistemically responsible subject can believe that numbers

    exist even if her belief isnt grounded very directly in any sort of empirical investigation.

    2 Neo-Fregeanism

    Humes Principle is the following sentence:

    FG(#x(F(x)) = #x(G(x)) F(x)x G(x))

    [Read: the number of the Fs equals the number of the Gs just in case the Fs

    are in one-one correspondence with the Gs.]

    Neo-Fregeanism is the view that when Humes Principle is set forth as an implicit definition

    of #x(F(x)), one gets the following two results: (1) the truth of Humes Principle is know-

    ablea priori, and (2) the referents of number-terms constitute a realm of mind-independent

    objects which is such as to render mathematical Platonism true. (Neo-Fregeanism was first

    proposed in Wright (1983), and has since been championed by Bob Hale, Crispin Wright

    and others. For a collection of relevant essays, see Hale and Wright (2001).)

    Just like one can distinguish between two different varieties of mathematical Platonism,

    one can distinguish between two different varieties of neo-Fregeanism. Traditional and

    15

  • 8/12/2019 Rayo, Agustin - Neo-fregeanism reconsidered.pdf

    16/32

  • 8/12/2019 Rayo, Agustin - Neo-fregeanism reconsidered.pdf

    17/32

    a thought can be split up in many ways, so that now one thing, now another, appears as

    subject or predicate (Frege (1892) p. 199), it is natural to interpret him as embracing the

    identity-statement:

    For the concept square root of 4 to be realized just isfor there to be at least

    one square root of 4.

    And when he claims, in Grundlagen 64, that in treating the judgement line a is parallel

    to line b as an identity, so as to obtain the direction of line ais identical to the direction

    of line b, we carve up the content in a way different from the original way, it is natural

    to interpret him as embracing the identity-statement:

    For the direction of line a to equal the direction of line b just is for a and b to

    be parallel.

    In both instances, Frege puts the point in terms of content-recarving, rather than as an

    identity-statement. But, as emphasized above, ones views about truth-conditions are

    tightly correlated with the identities one accepts.

    Neo-Fregeans are evidently sympathetic towards Freges views on content-recarving.

    (See, for instance, Wright (1997).) And even though talk of content-recarving has become

    less prevalent in recent years, with more of the emphasis on implicit definitions, a version

    of neo-Fregeanism rooted in subtle Platonism is clearly on the cards. In the remainder

    of the paper I will argue that such an interpretation of the program would be decidedly

    advantageous.

    2.1 Objects

    Suppose you introduce the verb to tableize into your language, and accept for it to

    tableize just isfor there to be a table (where the it in it tableizes is assumed to play

    17

  • 8/12/2019 Rayo, Agustin - Neo-fregeanism reconsidered.pdf

    18/32

    the same dummy role as the it in it is raining). Then you will think that it tableizes

    and there is a table have the same truth-conditions. In each case, what is required in

    order for the truth-conditions to be satisfied is that there be a table (equivalently: that

    it tableize). So you will think thatfor the purposes of stating that there is a table

    object-talk isoptional. One can state that there is a table by employing a quantifier that

    binds singular term positionsas in there is a tablebut also by employing an essentially

    different syntactic structureas in it tableizes.

    If object-talk is optional, what is the point of giving it a place in our language? Ac-

    cording to the non-metaphysical view, as I shall call it, the answer is compositionality.

    A language involving object-talkthat is, a language including singular terms and quan-

    tifiers binding singular term positionsis attractive because it enables one to give a recur-

    sive specification of truth-conditions for a class of sentences rich in expressive power. But

    there is not much more to be said on its behalf. If one could construct a language that

    never indulged in object-talk, and was able to do so without sacrificing compositionality

    or expressive power, there would be no immediate reason to think it inferior to our own.Whether or not we choose to adopt it should turn entirely on matters of convenience. (For

    an example of such a language, and illuminating discussion, see Burgess (2005).)

    Proponents of the non-metaphysical view believe that it takes very little for a singular

    term to be in good order. All it takes is a compositional specification of truth-conditions

    for whichever sentences involving the term one wishes to make available for use. The reason

    there is nothing more that needs to be done is that there was nothing special about using

    singular terms to begin with. In setting forth a language, all we wanted was the ability to

    express a suitably rich range of truth-conditions. If we happened to carry out this aim by

    bringing in singular terms, it was because they supplied a convenient way of specifying the

    right range of truth-conditions, not because they had some further virtue.

    Proponents of themetaphysical view, in contrast, believe that that object-talk is subject

    18

  • 8/12/2019 Rayo, Agustin - Neo-fregeanism reconsidered.pdf

    19/32

    to a further constraint: there needs to be a certain kind of correspondence between the

    semantic structure of our sentences and the metaphysical structure of reality. In partic-

    ular, they presuppose the following: (1) there is a particular carving of reality into objects

    which is more apt, in some metaphysical sense, than any potential rivalthe one and only

    carving that is in accord with realitys true metaphysical structure; (2) to each legitimate

    singular term there must correspond an object carved out by this metaphysical structure;

    and (3) satisfaction of the truth-conditions of a sentence of the form P(t1, . . . , tn) re-

    quires that the objects paired witht1, . . . , tn bear to each other the property expressed by

    P. (For an example of this sort of view, see Sider (typescript).)

    A consequence of the metaphysical view is that one cannot accept for it to tableize just

    isfor there to be a table. (Since it tableizes and there is a table have different semantic

    structures, there cant be a single feature of reality they are both accurate descriptions of

    when it is presupposed that correspondence with the one and only structure of reality is a

    precondition for accuracy.) For similar reasons, one cannot accept for some things to be

    arranged tablewisejust is

    for there to be a table, or for the property of tablehood to be in-stantiatedjust isfor there to be a table, or, indeed, any identity statement where

    and are atomic sentences with different semantic structures. Accordingly, proponents

    of the metaphysical view takes themselves to be in a position to make distinctions that

    a proponent of the non-metaphysical view would be unable to understand. For instance,

    they might take themselves to be in a position to make sense of a scenario in which some

    things are arranged tablewise but there is no table.

    I am ignoring a complication. Friends of the metaphysical view might favor a moderate

    version of the proposal according to which only a subset of our discourse is subject to the

    constraint that there be a correspondence between semantic structure and the metaphysical

    structure of reality. One could claim, for example, that the constraint only applies when

    one is in the ontology room. Accordingly, friends of the moderate view would be free to

    19

  • 8/12/2019 Rayo, Agustin - Neo-fregeanism reconsidered.pdf

    20/32

    accept a version of, e.g. for there to be some things arranged tablewise just is for there

    to be a table by arguing that only there are some things arranged tablewise is to be

    understood in an ontology-room spirit. Ignoring this version of the view allows me to

    simplify the exposition with no loss in generality: everything I will say about the non-

    moderate view applies to the moderate view when attention is restricted to ontology-room

    discourse.

    The difference between the non-metaphysical and the metaphysical view is subtle but

    important. First, the metaphysical view indulges in Deep Metaphysics where the non-

    metaphysical view does not. For the metaphysical structure of reality is a paradigm exam-

    ple of the sort of thing only a metaphysician could understand, and only a metaphysician

    would care about. (For arguments to the contrary, see Sider (typescript).) Second, and

    more importantly for our purposes, the non-metaphysical view leaves room for meaning-

    lessness where the metaphysical view does not. Suppose it is agreed on all sides that the

    singular terms t1 and t2 are both in good order, each of them figuring meaningfully in

    sentences with well-defined truth-conditions. A proponent of the metaphysical view is, onthe face of it, committed to the claim that it must be possible to meaningfully ask whether

    t1= t2 is true. For she believes that each oft1 and t2 is paired with one of the objects

    carved out by the metaphysical structure of reality. So the question whether t1= t2 is

    true can be cashed out as the question whether t1 and t2 are paired with the same such

    object. (Friends of the metaphysical view could, of course, deny that this is a meaning-

    ful question. But such a move would come at a cost, since it it would make it hard to

    understand what is meant by carving reality into objects.)

    For a proponent of the non-metaphysical view, in contrast, there is no tension between

    thinking that t1 and t2 figure meaningfully in sentences with well-defined truth conditions

    and denying that one has asked a meaningful question when one asks whether t1= t2is

    true. For according to the non-metaphysical view, all it takes for a singular term to be in

    20

  • 8/12/2019 Rayo, Agustin - Neo-fregeanism reconsidered.pdf

    21/32

    good order is for there to be a compositional specification of truth-conditions for whichever

    sentences involving the term one wishes to make available for use. And there is no reason

    one couldnt have a compositional specification of truth-conditions for a large range of

    sentences involving t1 and t2 without thereby specifying truth-conditions for t1= t2.

    Arithmetic is a case in point. The subtle Platonist has a straightforward way of spec-

    ifying a compositional assignment of truth-conditions to arithmetical sentences. (See ap-

    pendix A.) On this assignment, every arithmetical sentence a non-philosopher would care

    about gets well-definied truth-conditions, as does every sentence in the non-arithmetical

    fragment of the language, but no truth-conditions are supplied for mixed identity-statements,

    such as the number of the planets = Julius Caesar. And for good reason: there is no

    natural way of extending the relevant semantic clauses to cover these cases.

    Proponents of the metaphysical view will claim that something important has been left

    out. For in the absence of well-defined truth-conditions for the number of the planets =

    Julius Caesar, it is unclear which of the objects carved out by the metaphysical structure

    of reality has been paired with the number of the planets. But proponents of the non-metaphysical view would disagree: it is simply a mistake to think that such pairings are

    necessary to render a singular term meaningful.

    If the non-metaphysical view is rightyou might be tempted to askin what sense

    are we committed to the existence of numbers when we say that the number of the planets

    is eight? In the only sense of existence and numbers that non-metaphysicians are able

    to understand, say I. In order for the truth-conditions of the number of the planets is eight

    to be satisfied the number of the planets must be eight, and in order for the number of the

    planets to be eight there have to be numbers. What else could it take for someone who

    asserts the number of the planets is eight to be committed to the existence of numbers?

    Of course, the subtle Platonist will make a further claim. She will claim that it is also

    true that all it takes for the truth-conditions of the number of the planets is eight to be

    21

  • 8/12/2019 Rayo, Agustin - Neo-fregeanism reconsidered.pdf

    22/32

    satisfied is that there be eight planets. To think that this contradicts what was said in

    the preceding paragraph is to fail to take seriously the idea that for the number of the

    planets to be eight just is for there to be eight planets. It is true that the number of

    the planets is eight carries commitment to numbers, but it is also true that commitment

    to numbers is no commitment at all. (If you have trouble getting your head around this,

    consider the following. The subtle Platonist accepts For the number of the planets to be

    zero just isfor there to be no planets. She also accepts For the number of the planets to

    be distinct from zero just isfor there to be planets. Putting the two together, she accepts

    For the number of planets to be either identical to or distinct from zero just isfor there

    to be some planets or none; equivalently: For the number of the planets to exist just is

    for there to be some planets or none. But there are be some planets or none has trivial

    truth-conditionstruth-conditions whose non-satisfaction would be unintelligibleso the

    number of the planets exists must also have trivial truth-conditions.)

    Perhaps you think that even if the subtle Platonist is right and there is a single feature

    of reality that is fully and accurate described by both the number of the plants is eightand there are exactly eight planets, one of these descriptions is more fundamental then

    the other: one of them carves reality at the joints. Believe this if you wish, but keep

    in mind that the distinction you seek to make is a creature of Deep Metaphysics. You

    have, in effect, endorsed what I earlier called the moderate version of the metaphysical

    view whereby one of the two descriptions picks out objects that are carved up by the

    metaphysical structure of reality, and is thereby fit for the ontology room, and the other

    hooks up with the world in a way that has lesser metaphysical pedigree, and is therefore

    not fit for the ontology room.

    The moral I hope to draw from the discussion this section is that subtle Platonists

    have reason to adopt the non-metaphysical view of singular-terms. This goes, in par-

    ticular, for subtle neo-Fregeansneo-Fregeans who favor subtle Platonism. But once one

    22

  • 8/12/2019 Rayo, Agustin - Neo-fregeanism reconsidered.pdf

    23/32

    embraces the non-metaphysical view, there is no pressure for thinking that a mixed identity-

    statement such as the number of the planets = Julius Caesar should have well-defined

    truth-conditions. So there is no reason to thinkin spite of what Frege suggests in 66

    of the Grundlagen and what proponents of neo-Fregeanism tend to presupposethat a

    characterization of the concept of number will be unacceptable unless it settles the truth-

    value of mixed identity-statements. In short: if you are a subtle neo-Fregean, you should

    be resolute about it, and stop worrying about mixed identities.

    2.2 Abstraction Principles

    I have never been able to understand why a traditionalneo-Fregean would think it impor-

    tant to use Humes Princple to characterize the meaning of arithmetical vocabulary, instead

    of using, e.g. the (second-order) Dedekind Axioms. In the case ofsubtleneo-Fregeans, on

    the other hand, I can see a motivation. Humes Principle, and abstraction principles more

    generally, might be thought to be important because they are seen as capturing the dif-

    ference between setting forth a mere quantified biconditional as an implicit definition of

    mathematical terms:

    (f() =f() R(, ))

    and setting forth the corresponding identity-statement:

    f() =f(),R(, ).

    And this is clearly an important difference. Only the latter delivers subtle Platonism,

    and only the latter promises to deliver an account for the special epistemic status of

    mathematical truths.

    If thats whats intended, however, it seems to me that there are better ways of doing

    the job. Consider the case of Humes Principle. In order to convince oneself that it succeeds

    23

  • 8/12/2019 Rayo, Agustin - Neo-fregeanism reconsidered.pdf

    24/32

    in characterizing the meaning of our arithmetical vocabulary, one needs to prove a certain

    kind of completeness result: one needs to show that setting forth Humes Principle as an

    implicit definition of numerical terms is enough to pin down the truth-conditions of every

    arithmetical sentence one wishes to have available for use. This, in turn, involves proving

    the following two results:

    1. Given suitable definitions, every true sentence in the language of pure arithmetic is

    a logical consequence of Humes Principle.

    [This result has come to be known as Freges Theorem. It was originally proved in

    Frege (1893 and 1903), by making what Heck (1993) identified as a non-essential use

    of Basic Law V. That the result could be established without using Basic Law V was

    noted in Parsons (1965) and proved in Wright (1983).]

    2. Given suitable definitions, every true sentence in the (two-sorted) language of applied

    arithmetic is a logical consequence of Humes Principle, together with the set of true

    sentences containing no arithmetical vocabulary.

    Both of these results are true, but neither of them is trivial.

    Now suppose that one characterizes the meaning of arithmetical vocabulary by using

    the compositional semantics in appendix A. The assignment of truth-conditions one gets

    is exactly the same as the one one would get by setting forth the identity-statement corre-

    sponding to Humes Principle as an implicit definition of arithmetical termsbut with the

    advantage that establishing completeness, in the relevant sense, turns out to be absolutely

    straightforward. One can simply read it off from ones semantic clauses. (In fact, the

    easiest method I know of for proving the second of the two results above, and thereby es-

    tablishing the completeness of Humes Principle, proceeds via the appendix A semantics.)

    None of this should come as a surprise. When one uses the method in the appendix to

    specify truth-conditions for arithmetical sentences one avails oneself of all the advantages

    24

  • 8/12/2019 Rayo, Agustin - Neo-fregeanism reconsidered.pdf

    25/32

    of a compositional semantics. Not so when one sets forth Humes Principle as an implicit

    definition.

    There is, however, a much more important reason for preferring the method in the

    appendix over specifications of truth-conditions based on abstraction principles. Neo-

    Fregeans have found it difficult to identify abstraction principles that can do for set-

    theory what Humes Principle does for arithmetic. (For a selection of relevant literature,

    see Cook (2007).) But if one waives the requirement that the meaning-fixation work be done

    by abstraction principles, the difficulties vanish. The subtle Platonist has a straightforward

    way of specifying a compositional assignment of truth-conditions to set-theretic sentences.

    (See appendix B for details.) As in the case of arithmetic, one gets the result that every

    consequence of the standard set-theoretic axioms has well-defined truth-conditions. And,

    as in the case of arithmetic, one gets subtle Platonism. In particular, it is a consequence of

    the semantics that for the set of Romans to contain Julius Caesar just is for Julius Caesar

    to be a Roman.

    Perhaps there is some other reason to insist on using abstraction principles to fix themeanings of set-theoretic terms. But if the motivation is simply to secure subtle Platonism,

    it seems to me that neo-Fregeans would do better by using a compositional semantics

    instead.

    25

  • 8/12/2019 Rayo, Agustin - Neo-fregeanism reconsidered.pdf

    26/32

    A A Semantics for the Language of Arithmetic

    Consider a two-sorted first-order language with identity, L. It containsarithmetical vari-

    ables (n1, n2, . . .), constants (0) and function-letters (S, + and ), andnon-arithmetical

    variables (x1, x2, . . .), constants (Caesar and Earth) and predicate-letters (Human(. . . )

    and Planet(. . . )). In addition, L has been enriched with the function-letter #v(. . .) which

    takes a first-order predicate in its single argument-place to form a first-order arithmetical

    term (as in #x1(Planet(x1)), which is read the number of the planets).

    If is a variable assignment and w is a world, truth and denotation in Lrelative to

    and w can be characterized as follows:

    Denotation of arithmetical terms:

    1. ,w(ni) =(ni)

    2. ,w(0) = 0

    3. ,w(S(t)) =,w(t) + 1

    4. ,w((t1+ t2)) =,w(t1) + ,w(t2)

    5. ,w((t1 t2)) =,w(t1) ,w(t2)

    6. ,w(#xi((xi), nj)) = the number ofzs such that Sat((xi), z/xi, w)

    7. ,w(#ni((ni), nj)) = the number ofms such that Sat((ni), m/ni, w)

    Denotation of non-arithmetical terms:

    1. ,w(xi) =(xi)

    2. ,w(Caesar) = Julius Caesar

    3. ,w(Earth) = the planet Earth

    26

  • 8/12/2019 Rayo, Agustin - Neo-fregeanism reconsidered.pdf

    27/32

    Satisfaction:

    Where

    []w

    is read

    it is true at w that

    ,

    1. Sat(t1= t2,,w) ,w(t1) =,w(t2) (for t1, t2 arithmetical terms)

    2. Sat(t1= t2,,w) [,w(t1) =,w(t2)]w (for t1, t2 non-arithmetical terms)

    3. Sat(Human(t),,w) [,w(t) is human]w (for t a non-arithmetical term)

    4. Sat(Planet(t),,w) [,w(t) is a planet]w (for ta non-arithmetical term)

    5. Sat(ni ,,w) there is a number m such that Sat(, m/ni, w)

    6. Sat(xi ,,w) there is a zsuch that ([y(y= z)]w Sat(, z/xi, w))

    7. Sat( ,,w) Sat(,,w) Sat(,,w)

    8. Sat(,,w) Sat(,,w)

    Philosophical comment:

    As argued in the main text, a sentences truth-conditions can be modeled by a set of

    intelligible scenarios. Accordingly, when w is taken to range over intelligible scenarios

    as is intended abovethe characterization of truth at w yields a specification of truth-

    conditions for every sentence in the language.

    The proposed semantics makes full use of arithmetical vocabulary. So it can only be

    used to explain the truth-conditions of arithmetical sentences to someone who is already

    in a position to use arithmetical vocabulary. What then is the point of the exercise? How

    is it an improvement over a homophonic specification of truth-conditions?

    The first thing to note is that the present proposal has consequences that a homophonic

    specification lacks. Conspicuously, a homophonic specification would be compatible with

    27

  • 8/12/2019 Rayo, Agustin - Neo-fregeanism reconsidered.pdf

    28/32

    both traditional and subtle Platonism, but the present proposal is only compatible with

    subtle Platonism (since it entails that there is no intelligible scenario with no numbers).

    And unlike a homophonic specification, the present proposal can be used to go from the

    assumption that every sentence in the purely mathematical fragment of ones metalanguage

    is either true or false to the assumption that every sentence in the purely mathematical

    fragment of the object-language is either necessarily true or necessarily false.

    The reason the present proposal has non-trivial consequences is that mathematical vo-

    cabulary never occurs within the scope of [. . .]w. So even though mathematical vocabulary

    is used to specify the satisfaction clauses, theworldsin the range ofw can be characterized

    entirely in non-mathematical terms. As a result, the formal semantics establishes a con-

    nection between mathematical and non-mathematical descriptions of the world. It entails,

    for example, that the intelligible scenarios at which the number of the planets is eight are

    precisely the intelligible scenarios at which there are eight planetsfrom which it follows

    that for the number of the planets to be eight just isfor there to be eight planets.

    Why not make this connection more explicit still? Why not specify a translation-function that maps each arithmetical sentence to a sentence such that (i) contains

    no mathematical vocabulary and (ii) the sublte Platonist would accept ? Al-

    though doing so would certainly be desirable, it is provably beyond our reach: one can

    show that no such function is finitely specifiable. (See Rayo (2008) for details.)

    Technical comments:

    1. Throughout the definition of dentation and satisfaction I assume that the range of

    the metalinguistic variables includes merely possible objects. This is a device to

    simplify the exposition, and could be avoided by appeal to the technique described

    in Rayo (2008) and Rayo (typescript b).

    2. In clause 5 of the definition of satisfaction I assume that number includes infinite

    28

  • 8/12/2019 Rayo, Agustin - Neo-fregeanism reconsidered.pdf

    29/32

    numbers. This is done in order to ensure that there are no empty terms in the

    language. If one wanted to restrict ones attention to the natural numbers one could

    do so by working in a free logic.

    B A Semantics for the Language of Set-Theory

    Consider a two-sorted first-order language with identity, L. It contains set-theoreticvari-

    ables (1, 2, . . .), and non-set-theoretic variables (x1, x2, . . .), and predicate-letters

    (Human(. . . ) and Planet(. . . )). If is a variable assignment and w is a world, truth in

    L relative to and w can be characterized as follows:

    1. Sat(xi= xj,,w) [(xi) =(xj)]w

    2. Sat(xi j,,w) (xi) (j)

    3. Sat(i j,,w) (i) (j)

    4. Sat(Human(xi),,w) [(xi) is human]w

    5. Sat(Planet(xi),,w) [(xi) is a planet]w

    6. Sat(i ,,w) there is a set such that (Goodw() Sat(, /xi, w))

    7. Sat(xi ,,w) there is a zsuch that ([y(y= z)]w Sat(, z/xi, w))

    8. Sat( ,,w) Sat(,,w) Sat(,,w)

    9. Sat(,,w) Sat(,,w)

    where a set is goodw just in case it occurs at some stage of the iterative hierarchy built up

    from objectsxsuch that [Urelement(x)]w. (For philosophical and technical comments, see

    appendix A.)

    29

  • 8/12/2019 Rayo, Agustin - Neo-fregeanism reconsidered.pdf

    30/32

    References

    Beaney, M., ed. (1997) The Frege Reader, Blackwell, Oxford.

    Benacerraf, P., and H. Putnam, eds. (1983) Philosophy of Mathematics, Cambridge Uni-

    versity Press, Cambridge, second edition.

    Black, M., ed. (1965) Philosophy in America, Cornell University Press, Ithaca, NY.

    Bueno, O., and . Linnebo (forthcoming) New Waves in Philosophy of Mathematics,

    Macmillan.

    Burgess, J. (2005) Being Explained Away, Harvard Review of Philosophy13, 4156.

    Carnap, R. (1950) Empiricism, Semantics and Ontology, Analysis4, 2040. Reprinted

    in Benacerraf and Putnam (1983), 241-257.

    Cook, R., ed. (2007) The Arche Papers on the Mathematics of Abstraction, The Western

    Ontario Series in Philosophy of Science, Springer, Dordrecht.

    Demopoulos, W., ed. (1995) Freges Philosophy of Mathematics, Harvard University Press,

    Cambridge, MA.

    Frege, G. (1884) Die Grundlagen der Arithmetik. English Translation by J.L. Austin, The

    Foundations of Arithmetic, Northwestern University Press, Evanston, IL, 1980.

    Frege, G. (1892) On Concept and Object, Vierteljahrsschrift fur wissenschaftliche

    Philosophie 16, 192205. The English translation by Peter Geach is reprinted in

    Beaney (1997).

    Frege, G. (1893 and 1903) Grundgesetze der Arithmetik. Vol 1 (1893), Vol 2 (1903).

    English Translation by Montgomery Furth, The Basic Laws of Arithmetic, University

    of California Press, Berkeley and Los Angeles, 1964.

    Hale, B., and C. Wright (2001) The Reasons Proper Study: Essays towards a Neo-Fregean

    Philosophy of Mathematics, Clarendon Press, Oxford.

    30

  • 8/12/2019 Rayo, Agustin - Neo-fregeanism reconsidered.pdf

    31/32

    Heck, R. (1993) The Development of Arithmetic in Freges Grundgesetze der Arithmetik,

    Journal of Symbolic Logic58, 579163. Reprinted in Demopoulos (1995).

    Heck, R., ed. (1997) Language, Thought and Logic, Clarendon Press, Oxford.

    Kment, B. (2006) Counterfactuals and the Analysis of Necessity, Philosophical Perspec-

    tives20, 237302.

    MacBride, F. (2003) Speaking with Shadows: A Study of Neo-Fregeanism, British

    Journal for the Philosophy of Science54, 103163.

    MacBride, F., ed. (2006) Identity and Modality, Oxford University Press, Oxford.

    Parsons, C. (1965) Freges Theory of Number. In Black (1965), pp 180203. Reprinted

    with a postscript in Parsons (1983), pp. 150175.

    Parsons, C. (1983) Mathematics in Philosophy, Cornell University Press, Ithaca, NY.

    Rayo, A. (2003) Success by Default? Philosophia Mathematica 305322.

    Rayo, A. (2005) Logicism Reconsidered. In Shapiro (2005), pp. 203235.

    Rayo, A. (2008) On Specifying Truth-Conditions, The Philosophical Review 117.

    Rayo, A. (forthcoming) Towards a Trivialist Account of Mathematics. In Bueno and

    Linnebo (forthcoming).

    Rayo, A. (typescript-a) An Account of Possibility.

    Rayo, A. (typescript-b) An Actualists Guide to Quantifying In.

    Rosen, G. (2006) The Limits of Contingency. In MacBride (2006), pp. 1339.

    Shapiro, S., ed. (2005) The Oxford Handbook for Logic and the Philosophy of Mathematics,

    Clarendon Press, Oxford.

    Sider, T. (typescript) Writing the Book of theWorld.

    Wright, C. (1983) Freges Conception of Numbers as Objects, Aberdeen University Press,

    Aberdeen.

    31

  • 8/12/2019 Rayo, Agustin - Neo-fregeanism reconsidered.pdf

    32/32

    Wright, C. (1997) The Philosophical Significance of Freges Theorem. In Heck (1997),

    201-244.