priest - non transitive identity

13
LP 1 2 1 2 Abstract Non-Transitive Identity 1 Problematising Identity Graham Priest Departments of Philosophy Universities of Melbourne and St Andrews In this paper I shall concentrate on issues concerning change, and shall have nothing to say concerning intentionality. A discussion of identity in intentional contexts can be found in Priest (2002a) and ch. 2 of Priest (200+a). See, e.g., Miller (1969), p. 413 ff. The paper denes a notion of identity in the second-order paracon- sistent logic . The notion does not have the properties of transi- tivity or substitutivity, but these may be regained in consistent con- texts. The paper then discusses applications of this notion of identity, especially to entities involved in change, including sorites-generating changes. The notion of identity has always been a problematic notion, especially when considerations of intentionality and change are around. And though there is now a standard theory of identityidentity in classical rst or- der logicthis can appear as unproblematic as it does only because it is normally presented in a way that is sanitised by the disregarding of such considerations. For example, suppose I change the exhaust pipes on my bike; is it or is it not the same bike as before? It is, as the traffic registration department and the insurance company will testify; but it is not, since it is manifestly dif- ferent in appearance, sound and acceleration. Dialecticians, such as Hegel, have delighted in such considerations, since they appear to show that the bike both is and is not the same. A standard reply here is to distinguish between the bike itself and its properties. After the change of exhaust pipes the bike is numerically the same bike; it is just that some of its properties are different. Perhaps, for the case at hand, this is the right thing to say. 1

Upload: pautei

Post on 29-Dec-2015

13 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Priest - Non Transitive Identity

LP

1

2

1

2

Abstract

Non-Transitive Identity

1 Problematising Identity

Graham PriestDepartments of Philosophy

Universities of Melbourne and St Andrews

In this paper I shall concentrate on issues concerning change, and shall have nothingto say concerning intentionality. A discussion of identity in intentional contexts can befound in Priest (2002a) and ch. 2 of Priest (200+a).See, e.g., Miller (1969), p. 413 ff.

The paper de�nes a notion of identity in the second-order paracon-sistent logic . The notion does not have the properties of transi-tivity or substitutivity, but these may be regained in consistent con-texts. The paper then discusses applications of this notion of identity,especially to entities involved in change, including sorites-generatingchanges.

The notion of identity has always been a problematic notion, especiallywhen considerations of intentionality and change are around. And thoughthere is now a standard theory of identity�identity in �classical� �rst or-der logic�this can appear as unproblematic as it does only because it isnormally presented in a way that is sanitised by the disregarding of suchconsiderations.For example, suppose I change the exhaust pipes on my bike; is it or is it

not the same bike as before? It is, as the traffic registration department andthe insurance company will testify; but it is not, since it is manifestly dif-ferent in appearance, sound and acceleration. Dialecticians, such as Hegel,have delighted in such considerations, since they appear to show that thebike both is and is not the same. A standard reply here is to distinguishbetween the bike itself and its properties. After the change of exhaust pipesthe bike is numerically the same bike; it is just that some of its propertiesare different. Perhaps, for the case at hand, this is the right thing to say.

1

Page 2: Priest - Non Transitive Identity

3

4

3

4

↖ ↗

b c

b c

b

0 1

1

1

0

1

= =

= = =

=

= ==

dingan sich

it

else

a a a a

a b ca b b c a c

a b b c a c

t t ab c t b l c l

t l l

b c

t a

a b c

a c b c t b al c a c

See, e.g., Priest (1987), 5.3.For references and discussion, see Par�tt (1984), p. 204 ff.

But the categorical distinction between the thing itself and its propertiesis one which is difficult to sustain; to suppose that the bike is somethingover and above all of its properties is simply to make it a mysterious

. Thus, suppose that I change, not just the exhaust pipes, but, insucceeding weeks, the handle bars, wheels, engine, and in fact all the parts,until nothing of the original is left. It is now a numerically different bike,as even the traffic office and the insurance company will concur. At somestage, it has changed into a different bike, i.e., has become a differentmachine: the bike itself is numerically different. (This is a variation on theold problem of the ship of Theseus.)True sentences of the form and are standard fare in para-

consistent theories of identity; but there is more to the matter than this.What is it for an object to be the same object over a period of time in whichchange occurs? The answer is, plausibly, different for different kinds of ob-jects; for many kinds of objects, the answer is also likely to be contentious.But it is not uncommon so appeal to some kind of continuity condition.Thus, for example, Locke took personal identity to be given by continuityof memory. I am the same person that I was yesterday since I can recallmost of what I could recall then, and some more as well. But continuityconditions of this kind are naturally non-transitive. Memories can be lostin trauma, or even in the simple process of ageing. There can thereforebe objects, say people, , and , such that there is sufficient continuitybetween and , and between and , but not between and . Thus, wehave and , but not . Identity fails to be transitive.Cases of �ssion and fusion can also give rise to similar problems. Sup-

pose that between and , an amoeba, , divides into two new amoebas,and ; at , occupies location , and occupies a distinct location .We may depict the situation as follows:

At least arguably, . (If were to die on �ssion, this would be clear; andhow can the identity of two things depend on what exists?). Similarly,

. But it is not the case that . Moreover, at , �that is, �is at; but is not, even though . We have a failure of the substitutivity of

2

Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Page 3: Priest - Non Transitive Identity

LP

LP

( ) ( )

5

6

7

8

5

6

7

8

by �at

∧ ∨ ¬∀ ∃

� ¬ ∨ � ∧ �

2 Second-Order

LP

� � � � � � � � � �

LP

The example comes from Prior (1968), p. 83. See also Priest (1995).There are certainly other non-classical theories of identity to be found in the literature,

even ones based on a paraconsistent logic. Thus, e.g., in Krause (1992) and Bueno (2000)there is to be found a theory in which substitutivity of ideniticals fails. The notion ofidentity of these papers is still an equivalence relation, however. In particular, identity istransitive. This makes the notion very different from that to be given here, and unsuitablefor the major applications at issue.See, e.g., Priest (1987), ch. 5.For second-order , see section 7.2 of Priest (2002b).

identicals, where the property in question has nothing to do with identity.There is, of course, much more to be said about all of these examples.

But the discussion at least shows that various properties standardly takento be possessed by identity (consistency, transitivity, substitutivity) are notto be taken for granted philosophically. One can, of course, simply specify

that identity has these properties. But this is hardly satisfactory.The notion so produced will then certainly have those properties�and callit identity if you like; but it is all too obvious that the behaviour of therelationship involved in the above examples�and which we used to callidentity before the word was usurped�still cries out to be understood.In what follows, I will provide a theory of a relationship that is naturally

enough thought of as identity, but for which the properties that we havejust seen to be problematic fail, though in a controlled and recoverableway. In the next few sections we will look at a formal speci�cation of therelation. We will then return to the above examples.

The theory in question is based on a paraconsistent logic, . For reasonsthat will become obvious, we willwork with the second-order version of this,though there are other ways to proceed, as we shall see in due course. Letus start, then, with a speci�cation of the logic.The language has the connectives , and , and the �rst- and second-

order quanti�ers and . The material conditional and biconditional arede�ned in the usual way: is ; is .There are predicates and function symbols, but we will suppose, for thesake of simplicity, that they are all monadic. First order variables are lowercase, and monadic second-order variables are upper case. I will avoid freevariables.There are various forms that the semantics of second-order may

take; importantly, there are various possible ranges for the second-ordervariables. I will choose one appropriate way here. An interpretation for the

3

Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Page 4: Priest - Non Transitive Identity

=9

9

� �

� �

d

d

d

� �

1

2

2

1

2 2

〈 〉 ∪

〈 〉 ∈ ⇒ ∈

extension

A,B A B DD

D

DA,B D B,A D

1 2 1

2+ +

1+

1

1 2

2

1 2

1 1+

+

1 2 1 2

1

1

〈 〉

〈 〉 ∪�

� 〈 〉 ∈

{ } { } { }

∈ ∈

∈ ∈

∈ ¬ ∈

∈ ¬ ∈

∈ ∧ ∈ ∈

∈ ∧ ∈ ∈

∈ ∨ ∈ ∈

∈ ∨ ∈ ∈

∈ ∪

∈ ∃ ∈ ∈

∈ ∃ ∈ ∈

=

( )( ) ( )

( ) = ( )( ( ))1 0 1 0

1 ( ) ( ) ( )

0 ( ) ( ) ( )

1 ( ) 0 ( )

0 ( ) 1 ( )

1 ( ) 1 ( ) 1 ( )

0 ( ) 0 ( ) 0 ( )

1 ( ) 1 ( ) 1 ( )

0 ( ) 0 ( ) 0 ( )

1 ( ( )) 1 ( ( ))

0 ( ( )) 0 ( ( ))

I D ,D ,� DDA ,A A A D A

A A DB D A,B D

D �D D

D D P � P� P , � P�

� ft � f � t �,

� P t � t � P

� Pt � t � P

� � � �

� � � �

� � � � � � �

� � � � � � �

� � � � � � �

� � � � � � �

D D d D D

� x� x d D � �

� x� x d D � �

In particular, we do not assume that every pair of the form , where ,is in . This fact is, in itself, sufficient to give failure of substitutivity for molecularformulas. One might suggest that the only pairs that are in are those which representspecial properties of some kind, such as natural or intrinsic properties. Depending on thehow one interprets the notion, it may be natural to add extra closure conditions on ,such as closure under negation: .

language, , is a triple . is the non-empty domain of �rst-order quanti�cation. is the domain of second-order quanti�ers, and is aset of pairs of the form , where . I will call an

, and a co-extension. We require that for every , thereis a such that , but otherwise make no assumptionsabout how extensive is. assigns every individual constant a memberof , every predicate constant a member of , and every function symbola (monadic) function from to . If is a predicate, I will writeas .

can be extended to assign every closed term a denotation by thefamiliar recursive clause: . An evaluation, , is a functionthat maps each formula to (true only), (false only), and (bothtrue and false), according to the following recursive clauses:

iff

iff

iff

iff

iff and

iff or

iff or

iff and

To give the truth and falsity conditions for the quanti�ers, we assume, forthe sake of simplicity, that the language is expanded if necessary to giveeach member of and a name. If , I will write its nameas . The conditions may now be stated as follows.

iff for some ,

iff for all ,

4

Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Page 5: Priest - Non Transitive Identity

:

d

d

d

d

d

d

1

1

2

2

2

2

1 2

= 1 2

3 De�ning Identity

∈ ∀ ∈ ∈

∈ ∀ ∈ ∈

∈ ∃ ∈ ∈

∈ ∃ ∈ ∈

∈ ∀ ∈ ∈

∈ ∀ ∈ ∈

¬ ¬

¬ ¬

¬

¬ ¬

1 ( ( )) 1 ( ( ))

0 ( ( )) 0 ( ( ))

1 ( ( )) 1 ( ( ))

0 ( ( )) 0 ( ( ))

1 ( ( )) 1 ( ( ))

0 ( ( )) 0 ( ( ))

1 ( ) �� �

( )

=

( )

� x� x d D � �

� x� x d D � �

� X� X d D � �

� X� X d D � �

� X� X d D � �

� X� X d D � �

I � � � I�

�LP

� �

� � � �

�,� � �

�, � � �

�, � � �

�, � � �

� � � �

� �,� � � � �

t t

Def X Xt Xt

iff for all ,

iff for some ,

iff for some ,

iff for all ,

iff for all ,

iff for some ,

Finally, validity: is a model of iff ; if is a set of formulas, isa model of iff it is a model of every member; and iff every modelof is a model of .The �rst-order part of in the above semantics is entirely standard.

The second-order part is the natural extrapolation. I merely pause, there-fore, to note a few of the properties of the material biconditional that willfeature in what follows. In particular, is easy to check the following. (Iomit set braces in the premises.)

(Make both true and false.)

With this background, we can now come to identity. Taking its cue fromLeibniz� Law, identity may be de�ned in second-order logic in the standardfashion. Thus, let us de�ne as:

5

Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Page 6: Priest - Non Transitive Identity

10

10

i i

��

� �

== =

∈ ∪∩

2+

1+

3

A D A A D FDEt t A A � K

A A A AB B B B

A A

A A

A A A A

= = =

=

( ) = = 1 2 3

=

=

( ) ==

( ) = = = =

=

( )( ) ( ) =

� { }

� 〈{ } { }〉 ∈

� ∈

∧ ¬ ∈¬ ∧ ¬ ∀

∧ ¬ ¬ ∃ ¬ ¬∀ �

1 2 2 1

1 1 2 3

1 2 2 3 2

2 1

2 2 1 2 2

1 2 1 2 1 2 1 2

2 3 1 3

1 3 1 3 1 2 2 3 1 3

2 3 2 3

2 2 2 2

2 2 2 2 2 2

=

1 2

t t t t t t

D a ,a ,a

� t a i , ,

a , a , a ,a A D

B D B D

t t t t B Dt t t t X Xt Xt t t

t t t tX Xt Xt t t t t , t t t t

t t , t t

t t t tX Xt Xt X Xt Xt t t

Def

P Pt Pt

LP � �� �

It is perhaps worth observing that if we drop the condition on interpretations that forall , , and so base the theory of identity on , then the Law ofIdentity, , also fails. If we insist that , and so base the theory on ,the Law still fails, but transitivity and substitutivity hold.

Because the material biconditional is re�exive and symmetric, it followsthat identity is too: and . The material bicon-ditional is not, however, transitive; identity inherits this property. Thus,consider the interpretation where:

( )

For every other ,

Since is true, so is ; and for every other ,is true, so . Hence, , that is

is true. Similarly, . But is not true; hence, neither is, that is, is not true. Thus, .

Since transitivity of identity is a special case of substitutivity of identicals,this, too, fails. For another counter-example, note that .In the above interpretation, the premises are true, but the conclusion isnot. Finally, note that identity statements may not be consistent. Thus, inthe above interpretation, since is true, so is . Itfollows that , so , i.e., .It might be objected that the account of identity just given is inade-

quate since what is required in is not a material biconditional, but agenuine (and detachable) conditional, such as the conditional of an appro-priate relevant logic. We would then have transitivity and substitutivity ofidentity (though maybe not consistency). However, this would be too fast.It is not at all clear that what is required for an expression of Leibniz� Lawis a genuine conditional. For example it is not clear that there is a relevantimplication between, e.g., Mary Ann Evans was a woman� and George El-liot was a woman��at least, not without the suppressed information thatMary Ann Evans was George Elliot. What is required for Leibniz� Law isthat for every predicate, , and have the same truth value; andthis is what the material biconditional delivers.It might still be objected that this is not the case in , since is

true (and false) if is true only but is both true and false. But again, thisis too fast. Though the semantics are formulated formally as three-valued,

6

Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Administrador
Resaltado
Page 7: Priest - Non Transitive Identity

m

m

11

12

11

12

∧ ∨ ¬ ∧¬

∈ ∩

{ ∈ ∃ ∈∈ ∩ }

{ }

( ) ( )

=

! = :!

! ! �� �

� �

= = = = =

4 Identity and Consistency

2+

1 2+

1

1 2 1 2 1 2

1 2

1 2 2 3 1 2 2 3 1 3

� �� �

� � � � � � � �

A D A A �

LP

I I d D A Dd A A I DI I I I I I

I I I IJ I J

� �

t t , t t t t , t t t t

true false

both

classical

minimally inconsistent

minimally inconsistent consequence

This comes out most clearly in the relational semantics for the logic. See Priest (2001),ch. 7.See Priest (1987), 8.4.

there are, in fact, really only two truth values, and . It is just thatsentences may have various combinations of these. In particular, istrue iff and are both true, or both false. It is easy enough to check that

is logically equivalent to . If is true only andis both true and false, are true, hence one should expect the materialbiconditional to be true�and since one is true and the other is false, oneshould expect it to be false as well.

Call an interpretation iff for every , . Theclassical interpretations are simply those where no atomic sentence�andhence no sentence at all�behaves inconsistently. The classical interpreta-tions are, in fact, just the interpretations of classical second-order logic.And, restricted to those, the de�nition of identity just employed gives theclassical account of identity. Thus, though some of the features of theclassical account fail, they do hold when we restrict ourselves to classicalmodels. Provided that we are reasoning about consistent situations, then,identity may be taken to behave in the orthodox fashion. I have arguedelsewhere that consistency should be taken as a default assumption. Ifthis is right then the classical properties of identity may be invoked unlessand until that default assumption is revoked.The idea may be turned into a formal non-monotonic logic, minimally

inconsistent . The details for the �rst order case are given in Priest(1991). How best to modify the idea so that it works in the second-ordercase, and so for identity, is not obvious. Here is one way. (I do not claimthat it is the best.) If is an interpretation, let ,

. is the set of elements in that behave inconsistently. Ifand are interpretations, de�ne ( is more consistent than )

to mean that . is a (mi) model of iffis a model of and there is no such that is a model of . Finally,

can be de�ned thus:

iff every mi model of is a model of

If is classically consistent, its mi models are its classical models.Hence, its mi consequences are simply its classical consequences. In par-ticular, since is consistent, .

7

Page 8: Priest - Non Transitive Identity

m m

m

b

� �

5 Some Applications

1 2 1 2

1 2 1 2 2 2

2

2+

1

1+

1 1 2 1 2

2

1

1

∧ ¬

∈ ∩∈ ∈ ∀

¬

¬

¬ ¬ ∀ ¬ ¬ ¬∀ �

¬

¬ ¬ ¬ ¬

= ( ) ( )

=( )

( ) ( ) ( ) ( )( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( )

( ) =( ) ( ) =

= ==

kind consistency

Example 1

in addition

Example 2

Example 3

t t � t � t

t t ,P t ,Qt Qt PtI � t� t � Q � Q � t� t � P � t / � P X Xt Xt Pt Pt

PtP t

aP

Pb Qa Qb Q

Pa Pb Pa P b X Xa Xb a bPa Pb Pa Pb X Xa Xb a b a b

P Pc

a b b c a ca c

Bl t C Bb

Cb Bc Cc Ba Ba Ca Ca

Similarly, . More generally, is a consequence re-lation where irrelevant inconsistencies do not prevent classical inferencesfrom being employed. Thus: . For ifis a mi model of the premises, must behave inconsistently, since

. But nothing forces to behave inconsistently, soand . But is true, so .

Since the left hand side of this is true only, the right hand side must be atleast true. Hence, is true. The relation is non-monotonic, however. Inparticular, if we add as an extra premise, the left hand side is nowboth true and false, and the right hand side may simply be false.In closing this part of the discussion, it is perhaps worth pointing out the

following. It is not uncommon for logicians and philosophers to distinguisha class of predicates for which the substitutivity of identity holds and onesfor which it fails. Extensional predicates are usually taken to be amongstthe former; intentional predicates amongst the latter. For the notion ofidentity at hand, substitutivity may fail for all sorts of predicates, evenextensional ones. What determines whether substitutivity holds is not the

of predicate in question, but simply the of the situation.

So much for the theory. Let us now turn to some philosophical applications,including the topics in Section 1.

Let us start with an object that changes its properties. Con-sider some object, ; and suppose, for the sake of illustration, that itsproperties at some time are consistent. Let be one of these proper-ties. Suppose that at some later time it comes to acquire, , theproperty , all other properties remaining constant. Call the object thatresults . Then even after this time, for every . (Recall that

.) Hence, , that is, . But sinceand , ; thus . So . Thus, and

are both identical with each other and distinct from each other.Now extend the example. Suppose that at a subsequent

time again the object loses the property , maintaining the property .Call the object that results . Again, all other properties remain constant.Then, as before, ; similarly, . But has a property that lacks.Hence, it is not the case that . Transitivity has failed.

Next, consider the amoeba-�ssion case. Let be the predi-cate occupies at �; similarly for . Take it that�consistently� and; and that, similarly, and . Take it also that , , , .

8

Page 9: Priest - Non Transitive Identity

)

i i

13

14

13

14

t t aa a

0 6 3

0 6qua qua

Example 4

� �

� � � �

� � � �

6 Vagueness

== = =

0 6

= = = == = = =

= = = == = = =

= ==

= = ==

0 6

0 0 6

6

0 0 0 1 0 2 0 3

0 3 0 4 0 5 0 6

0 6 1 6 2 6 3 6

3 6 4 6 5 6 6 6

0

4 3 0

6 0 3 3 6

0 6

0 1 1 2 5 6

0 6

a ba c b c Ba a c

Bc

t tt a i

a a a

a

a a a a a a a aa a a a a a a a

a a a a a a a aa a a a a a a a

at t a

a a a a aa a

a a a a a aa a

See Hyde (1997).The transition stages are to be expected to have other contradictory properties as

well. Thus, if the bike is black at and red at then has the property of having beenblack ( , but also the property of not having been black ( ).

Again, assume that these are the only relevant properties. Then and, but it is not the case that ; moreover, and , but we do

not have .Finally, let us turn to the motor-bike of Theseus. Let us

suppose that the bike goes through seven stages, at times , ..., . Let themotorbike at time be ( ). Consider the predicate is identicalwith �. Arguably, this is a vague predicate. satis�es it; does not;and somehow its applicability fades out in between. In a sorites progressionof the kind produced by vague predicates, it is common enough to pointout that there are borderline cases, and claim that these are cases of truthvalue gaps. But intuition is satis�ed just as well by the thought that theseare truth value gluts. Symmetry, after all, is what seems to be required.If we take the borderline cases to be gluts, we may expect the predicateto behave as follows. The predicate is identical with � behaves inversely,and is also shown.

The bike undergoes various modi�cations, but it retains its identity asuntil , by which time it has already become (at ) distinct from , andidentical with . We also have a failure of transitivity. , ;but we do not have . More generally, we would expect to have

, , ..., ; the failure of transitivity of identity stops usfrom chaining these together to obtain .The Lockean example of personal identity, note, can be thought of as

similar. Two persons are the same if they have a sufficient psychologicalcontinuity. But sufficient psychological continuity� is a vague predicate. Soone should expect personal identity to be vague in just the required way.

Of course, there is a lot more to be said about sorites transitions. Vaguepredicates appear to be no more three-valued than two-valued. What is

9

Page 10: Priest - Non Transitive Identity

i

i

i i

Ra Ra 1 1 0 0

1 Ra

Ra Ra

0 6

0 1 2 3 4 5 6

0 1 2 3

3 4 5 6

0 6

1 0 6

0 0

2

+1

2 1

1 2

¬ ¬ ¬ ¬

{ } { } { }

{ { } { } { }}{ } { }

{ } � �{ }{ } � �{ }

= 1 1 0 0( ) = 1 ( ) = ( )

( ) = 1 0 2= 1 0 = 3= 0 4 6

( ) = 0

( ) = ( )

simply true both true and false both trueand false simply falsesimple truth simple falsity

a , ..., a

a a a a a a aRa Ra Ra Ra

Ra Ra Ra Ra

, ..., , , , ,�D Ra ... Ra ,

� � Ra � � f

f Ra i, i

if t t

Raf

D i� �

D DPt Pt

puzzling about sorites sequences is that there appear to be no semanticallysigni�cant cut-off points at all. Thus, suppose that is a sequenceof objects in transition from being red to not being red. Then if we treatborderline cases as semantic gluts, the associated truth values may go likethis:

And the cut-offs between and (orand ) are just as counter-intuitive as any betweenand .

In Priest (2003) I argued that versions of the forced-march sorites demon-strate that, one way or another, we are forced to admit the existence of somesort of cut-off points. All that is left for a solution to the sorites to do is totheorise the nature of the cut-off points and, crucially, explain why we �ndtheir existence so counter-intuitive. In that paper I suggested a solution interms of metalinguistic non-transitive identity. We �nd the existence of acut-off point counter-intuitive because whatever the semantic values of therelevant sentences on either side of the cut-off point, they are, in fact, thesame. The failure of the transitivity of identity prevents the value bleedingfrom one end to the other.The theory of non-transitive identity given in Priest (2003) is based on a

fuzzy logic. But the one outlined in this paper would do just as well. Con-sider a language that can describe the semantic properties of the languageof the red-sorites. The language has names ,and the one-place function symbol, (the truth value of�). Take an inter-pretation for the language in which , , , , , ,

, , etc., and is a function, such that:

ifififif is a truth value

The �rst three lines give an accurate description of the table for the s.(The last line is required since must have values for its other argumentstoo; what these are does not matter for what follows.)By a suitable choice of , we can ensure that for each , the sentence in

this language is true! A simple way to achieve this is toset the co-extension of every member of to be . Every sentence of theform is then (at least) true. Hence, every sentence of the form

10

Page 11: Priest - Non Transitive Identity

3 4

i i

15

16

15

16

, � �,

Ra Ra∀

∀ ∈ ∈

1 2 1 2

+1

= ( ) = ( ) ={ } { }∈ { }

∈ { }

7 Conclusion

( ) =( ) = ( )

= ( )

1 0 Ra Ra 01 1 0

1 0

X Xt Xt t t� �

LPLP

x y z x z y z

Note that it is true that . But even if we extendedthe language to be able to express the fact that , it would not follow that

, due to the failure of substitutivity. This provides a solution to the extendedsemantic paradox given by Smiley, different from the ones given by Priest, in Smiley andPriest (1993). See p. 30 f. and p. 50 f.As a matter of fact, identity is not de�ned in this way in that paper: it is taken as

primitive. But much the same construction goes through if identity is de�ned as indicated.

, i.e., , is true. In particular, each sentence of theform is true. (There are, of course, more discriminatingways to obtain this result. The model is meant only as a simple proof thatthe trick can be turned.)The problem with which Priest (2003) ends is how to obtain a metathe-

ory for a vague object-language which has the same underlying logic as theobject language. For fuzzy logic, this is still an open issue. But for thetheory being deployed here, there are known solutions. In Priest (200+a),it is shown, using what the paper calls the model-theoretic strategy�, howto formulate the metatheory for a language with underlying logic in anaive set theory which itself has underlying logic . The logic is not asecond-order one, as is the case here, but the availability of sets gives thesame effect. In particular, may be de�ned as: .Because of the use of a material conditional, this identity has exactly thesame properties as the one we have been using here. Indeed, since thetheory is a naive one, in which every condition de�nes a set, there is verylittle conceptual difference between this and the second-order approach.We could, in fact, have avoided using second-order logic by deploying settheory and this de�nition of identity, instead of the second-order one. Ichose not to adopt that course here so as not to raise many important but,in this context, distracting questions.

In this paper I have outlined an account of identity and some of its ap-plications. The notion of identity does not have all the properties of theorthodox notion. Especially, transitivity fails. However, the notion may bethought of as a generalisation of the orthodox one, since, when restrictedto consistent situations, the orthodox account is obtained. The idea wasmade precise with the notion of minimally inconsistent consequence. Wehave also looked at various applications of the notion, especially those thatconcern change. I have not discussed other approaches to the problemsraised, which there certainly are; nor have I tried to mount a case that theapproach deployed here is the best. But I do hope to have shown both the

11

Page 12: Priest - Non Transitive Identity

LP

17

17

References

A version of this paper was given at the third World Conference on Paraconsistency,Toulouse, 2003. Versions have also been given at the Universities of Melbourne and StAndrews. I am grateful to the audiences on those occasions for comments and helpfulsuggestions.

Synthese

Mind

Notre Dame Journal of For-mal Logic

Hegel�s Science of Logic

Reasons and Persons

In Contradiction

Studia Logica

Logique et Analyse

Introduction to Non-Classical Logic

Journal of Philosophical Logic

Handbook of Philosophical Logic

Liarsand Heaps: New Essays on Paradox

technical viability of this notion of identity and its potential philosophicalfruitfulness.

[1] O. Bueno, Quasi-Truth in Quasi-Set Theory�, 125, 33-53

[2] D. Hyde (1997), From Heaps and Gaps to Heaps of Gluts�, 106,641-60.

[3] D. Krause (1992), On Quasi-Set Theory�,33, 402-11.

[4] A. F. Miller (trans.) (1969), , London: Allenand Unwin Ltd.

[5] D. Par�tt (1984), , Oxford: Clarendon Press.

[6] G. Priest (1987), , Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Pub-lishers; second edition, Oxford: Oxford University Press, forthcoming.

[7] G. Priest (1991), Minimally Inconsistent �, 50, 321-31; reprinted as ch. 16 of the second edition of Priest (1987).

[8] G. Priest (1995), Multiple Denotation, Ambiguity, and the StrangeCase of the Missing Amoeba�, 38, 361-73.

[9] G. Priest (2001), , Cambridge:Cambridge University Press.

[10] G. Priest (2002a), The Hooded Man�,31, 445-67.

[11] G. Priest (2002b), Paraconsistent Logic�, pp. 287-393, Vol. 6, of D.Gabbay and F. Guenthner (eds.), ,second edition, Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

[12] G. Priest (2003), A Site for Sorites�, pp. 9-23 of JC Beall (ed.),, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

12

Page 13: Priest - Non Transitive Identity

Towards Non-Being

et alEssays in Honour of John Bell

Papers on Time and Tense

Pro-ceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume

[13] G. Priest (200+a), , Oxford: Oxford UniversityPress, forthcoming.

[14] G. Priest (200+b), Paraconsistent Set Theory�, in M. Hallet .(eds.), , to appear; the paper is alsopublished as ch. 18 of the second edition of Priest (1987).

[15] A. Prior (1968), , Oxford: Clarendon Press.

[16] T. Smiley and G. Priest (1993), Can Contradictions be True?�,67, 17-54.

13