pragmatic sociology lemieux

Upload: guille-loquito

Post on 13-Jan-2016

18 views

Category:

Documents


1 download

DESCRIPTION

.

TRANSCRIPT

  • Pragmatic Sociology: A Users Guide

    Yannick BARTHE, Damien DE BLIC, Jean-Philippe HEURTIN, ric LAGNEAU, Cyril LEMIEUX, Dominique LINHARDT, Cdric MOREAU DE BELLAING, Catherine RMY, Danny TROM

    Translation of Sociologie pragmatique: mode d'emploi , Politix. Revue des sciences sociales du politique, n103, 2013, p. 175-204.

    Summary:

    During the last thirty years, the researchers working within the orientation known as pragmatic sociology have produced a considerable amount of empirical investigations relating to all areas of social life. In accordance with the theoretical and methodological assumptions they intended to defend, they have developed significantly new ways to conduct their inquiries, to collect data, to explore their fields, to think through the cases and controversies they used as entry points to explore the social order and its always problematic reproduction. The aim of this paper is to characterize the pragmatic style in sociology by highlighting ten points and to specify its methodological requisites and practical implications in the conduct of research.

    Over the last thirty years, the researchers who identify with pragmatic sociology (also known as sociology of preuves1) have produced empirical surveys relating to all areas of social life. In accordance with the theoretical assumptions they intended to defend, they have developed significantly new ways to conduct surveys, collect data, explore their fields, think in terms of case, as well as use controversies to understand social order and its problematic reproduction. This paper aims to highlight ten characteristics of the pragmatic style in sociology and specify its methodological requisites and practical implications on the conduct of research.

    In the mid-1980s, as P. Bourdieus critical sociology and R. Boudons methodological individualism prevailed, a new sociological movement surfaced. It was coined pragmatic sociology. It will fall to the disciplines historians to determine how this label emerged, who identified with it, and how it came to designate a set of heterogeneous yet somehow related approaches, which can be unified only retrospectively and not without difficulty. This movement drew on interactionism, ethnomethodology, situated action theories, and later the American philosophical tradition known as pragmatism2. Thus we dont at all aim to gloss on

    1 The latter is sometimes translated as sociology of tests or sociology of trials [N. d. T.].2 The label pragmatic we borrow here doesnt imply that the designated kind of sociology is directly inspired by pragmatist philosophers such as Charles S. Pierce, John Dewey, William James, George H. Mead. First, this sociology doesnt claim to consist in a philosophical approach to the social and physical world, but in a kind of sociology indeed: this implies in particular that the empirical survey, which follows tried and tested social science methodologies, has a central and irreplaceable role. Second, while pragmatisms influence is crucial to it (especially through the bridges built by the Interactionist and Goffmanian sociological traditions, as well as ethnomethodology), its sources of inspiration are nevertheless varied. Indeed, certain pragmatic sociologists significantly draw on Durkheimianism, Weberianism, phenomenology, and Science Studies.

  • the use of the term. Nor do we claim exclusive rights on it. Rather, we intend to outline a sociological practice, indifferently called pragmatic sociology or sociology of preuves3.

    We think that two approaches form the backbone of pragmatic sociology, despite their significant differences: the anthropology of science and technology, developed by Michel Callon and Bruno Latour, and the sociology of action regimes, initiated by Luc Boltanski and Laurent Thvenot. In thirty years, they have led to empirical researches relating to all areas of social life: from factories to religious communities, from educational institutions to worlds of art, from scientific controversies to political and financial scandals, from political institutions to charity movements, from the media to transformations in the medical world, including the new mobilizations related to health and environmental risks, the changes in management, the political and social effects of statistical measures, the functioning of financial markets, or the practices of policing and surveillance. Classic sociological objects were therefore grasped in a new light, while other phenomena so far considered illegitimate or simply misunderstood, like music amateurs practices, the presence of nonhumans at the heart of social activities, or popular beliefs deemed irrational (such as those related to Marian apparitions or UFOs), could be taken seriously, as objects in their own right.

    Throughout these studies, proper methodological postures were identified, discussed, and revised. In accordance with the theoretical assumptions they intended to defend, pragmatic sociologists have developed significantly new ways to conduct surveys, collect data, explore their fields, think in terms of case, as well as use controversies to understand social order and its problematic reproduction. This know-how shares some of the techniques and practices used by the whole social science community. Yet it also partly differs from them. We identify with pragmatic sociology and try, in our work, to use its methods and develop them. We rely on its theoretical assumptions and its conceptual frameworks to analyze the social world. This paper primarily aims to clarify what the practice of pragmatic sociology requires in a technical sense first. In short, the goal is to characterize the pragmatic style in sociology and to specify its methodological requisites and practical consequences on the conduct of the research4.

    The notion of style matters. Needless to say, it refers to a style of survey, reasoning, and rendering to a style of sociological practice. A style involves points

    3 Due to the crucial importance of the notion of preuve in this approach, see in particular: Latour (B.), Pasteur : guerre et paix des microbes. Followed by Irrductions, Paris, La Dcouverte, 2011 [1st ed. 1984]; Boltanski (L.), Thvenot (L.), De la justification. Les conomies de la grandeur, Paris, Gallimard, 1991; Boltanski (L.), Chiapello (.), Le nouvel esprit du capitalisme, Paris, Gallimard, 1998. Pour un essai de prsentation synthtique de la notion, Lemieux (C.), Jugements en action, actions en jugement. Ce que la sociologie des preuves peut apporter ltude de la cognition , in Clment (F.), Kaufmann (L.), eds, La sociologie cognitive, Paris, Orphys-ditions de la Maison des sciences de lhomme, 2011.4 For more introductory texts on pragmatic sociology, see in particular: Brviglieri (M.), Stavo-Debauge (J.), Le geste pragmatique de la sociologie franaise , Antropolitica, 7, 1999; Cantelli (F.), Genard (J.-L.), tres capables et comptents : lecture anthropologique et pistes pragmatiques , SociologieS, 2008 [online: http://sociologies.revues.org/1943]; Dodier (N.), Lespace et le mouvement du sens critique , Annales, 60 (1), 2005; Nachi (M.), Introduction la sociologie pragmatique, Paris, Armand Colin, 2006; Lemieux (C.), Jugements en action, actions en jugement art. cit.

  • of convergence. But by no means does it involve a perfect homogeneity throughout all the affiliated work. Likewise, although a style is identified by a set of quite distinctive features, it can show a certain level of variability even disagreement or conflict. This paper aims to offer a ten-point clarification of the requisites for a sociological survey in the pragmatic style. The approach is therefore deliberately retrospective. It intends to assess the progress of pragmatic sociology and publicize its common ground, which we view as dynamic and open to reformulations and orientations. Thus this paper is primarily meant for young sociologists and political scientists, so that they get a better idea of what this sociology entails.

    How pragmatic sociology bridges the micro and macro levels

    Pragmatic sociologys view on macrosociological facts can be summarized as follows: it never dissociates these facts from the operations and processes that enable them to be described. This implies that sociologists focus on settings and activities in which sets are aggregated, totalities assembled, collectives established, and structures made tangible. Thus pragmatic sociology strives never to leave the situations level, that is, the micro level. Yet the micro level isnt seen as opposed to the macro level. On the contrary, it is viewed as the level where, from situation to situation, the macro level itself is achieved, produced, and objectivated through practices, devices, and institutions, without which it could certainly be deemed to exist, but could no longer be observed and described.

    In the early Eighties, this approach prevailed in the studies on socioprofessional categories5. Their focus on the formation and composition of statistical aggregates aimed to account for certain ways of structuring social space. But there was an explicit methodological stance: the duality between the objectivation processes and the objectivated structure should be suspended, while the double movement of stabilization and extension of the statistical forms and practices should be analyzed. Pragmatic sociologists used this approach to analyze the various formats of summation, enlargement, and totalization whereby collective realities are established as such and certain beings are relegated to smallness, invisibility, or exceptionality6. In trying to account for procedures and instruments whereby actors assess the size of social phenomena, trace causal links, and establish collective entities, they systematically connected in situ observations to considerations relating to the state of macrosocial configurations (on a city-wide or national scale), and vice versa7.

    Thus pragmatic sociology doesnt focus only on face-to-face situations. On the contrary, as the work accumulated over the past thirty years shows, it is also concerned with large beings whether types of economic organization (capitalism, markets, companies8), political institutions (the State, its administrations9),

    5 For a review of this line of research, see: Desrosires (A.), Thvenot (L.), Les catgories socioprofessionnelles, Paris, La Dcouverte, 2002.6 Boltanski (L.), Les cadres. La formation dun groupe social, Paris, Minuit, 1982; Thvenot (L.), Les investissements de forme , Cahiers du CEE, 29, 1986.7 See: Hermant (E.), Latour (B.), Paris, ville invisible, Paris, Les empcheurs de penser en rond-La Dcouverte, 1998; Didier (E.), En quoi consiste lAmrique ? Les statistiques, le New Deal et la dmocratie, Paris, La Dcouverte, 2009.

  • socioprofessional groups (managers, doctors, teachers, journalists10), or public issues11. It doesnt neglect the comparative approach for it compares national societies12 through combinatory ethnographies, which account for certain social operations (doing science, evaluate, care, put to death, and so on) observed in various contexts13. Thus how pragmatic sociology tames the great Leviathan doesnt lead to relativize let alone deny the existence of sociological realities beyond the here and now of observable situations14. This sociology would otherwise renounce the basis of all sociological approaches: viewing society as a total phenomenon to be grasped as such15.

    Pragmatic sociology is original in that it distances itself from other approaches that view situations as determined by structures, which only sociologists could bring to light. Indeed, according to pragmatic sociology, the refusal of this kind of structural analysis doesnt equate with a lack of consideration for structural phenomena, much less with a failure to take account of macrosociological facts. Pragmatic sociologys main contributions is to offer an alternative conception of the connection between situational and structural realities, and therefore to bridge the micro and macro levels.

    8 Callon (M.), ed., The Laws of the Markets, Oxford-Malden (MA), Blackwell, 1998; Callon (M.), Millo (Y.), Muniesa (F.), eds, Market Devices, Oxford-Malden (MA), Blackwell, 2007; Boltanski (L.), Chiapello (.), Le nouvel esprit du capitalisme, op. cit.9 Linhardt (D.), Ltat et ses preuves. lments dune sociologie des agencements tatiques , Clio@Thmis, 1, 2009; Linhardt (D.), Muniesa (F.), Du ministre lagence. tude dun processus daltration politique , Politix, 95, 2011; Lemoine (B.), Les valeurs de la dette. Ltat lpreuve de la dette publique, PhD dissertation in political science, Mines ParisTech, 2011; Moreau de Bellaing (C.), Ltat, une affaire de police ? , Quaderni, 78, 2012; Cantelli (F.), Pattaroni (L.), Roca (M.), Stavo-Debauge (J.), eds, Sensibilits pragmatiques. Enquter sur laction publique, Berne, Peter Lang, 2009; Normand (R.), Expertise, Networks and Tools of Government: The Fabrication of European Policy in Education , European Educational Research Journal, 9 (3), 2010.10 Boltanski (L.), Les cadres, op. cit.; Dodier (N.), Les mutations politiques du monde mdical. Lobjectivit des spcialistes et lautonomie des patients in Tournay (V.), ed., La gouvernance des innovations mdicales, Paris, Presses universitaires de France, 2007; Normand (R.), La profession enseignante lpreuve du Nouveau Management Public. La rforme anglaise de la Troisime Voie , Sociologie du travail, 53 (3), 2011; Lemieux (C.), Existe-t-il quelque chose comme une profession journalistique ? , in Lemieux (C.), ed., La subjectivit journalistique. Onze leons sur le rle de lindividualit dans la production de linformation, Paris, ditions de lEHESS, 2010.11 Charvolin (F.), Linvention de lenvironnement en France. Chronique anthropologique dune institutionnalisation, Paris, La Dcouverte, 2003; Barthe (Y.), Le pouvoir dindcision. La mise en politique des dchets nuclaires, Paris, Economica, 2006; Cefa (D.), Terzi (C.), eds, Lexprience des problmes publics, Paris, ditions de lEHESS, 2012.12 For instance: Lamont (M.), Thvenot (L.), eds, Rethinking Comparative Cultural Sociology: Repertoires of Evaluation in France and the United States, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2000; Kovenova (O.), Les communauts politiques en France et en Russie. Regards croiss sur quelques modalits du vivre ensemble , Annales, 66 (3), 2011; Debourdeau (A.), De la solution au problme. La problmatisation de lobligation dachat de lnergie solaire photovoltaque en France et en Allemagne , Politix, 95, 2011.13 Dodier (N.), Baszanger (I.), Totalisation et altrit dans lenqute ethnographique , Revue franaise de sociologie, 38 (1), 1997; Rmy (C.), La fin des btes. Une ethnographie de la mise mort des animaux, Paris, Economica, 2009.14 Callon (M.), Latour (B.), Le grand Lviathan sapprivoise-t-il ? , in Akrich (M.), Callon (M.), Latour (B.), Sociologie de la traduction. Textes fondateurs, Paris, Presses des Mines, 2006.15 On this technical necessity of sociology, see: Kaufmann (L.), Trom (D.), eds, Quest-ce quun collectif ? Du commun la politique, Paris, ditions de lEHESS, 2010.

  • What does this alternative conception consist in? It is based on the need to grasp macrosociological realities within the social reality in which they unfold. Thus the macro level is viewed as the result of performances that can be empirically observations. This holds for the sociological reasoning itself, which isnt unique in this respect: social science deserves to be understood and analyzed as a contribution to the processes whereby societies grasp themselves16. Such a statement doesnt constrain them to renounce the objectivation of aggregated realities. But it requires them to view the objective knowledge they produce or use as a practical achievement, and therefore to break with certain nave forms of objectivism.

    How pragmatic sociology integrates phenomenas historical temporality

    Pragmatic sociology seeks to grasp phenomena in their concrete observability. This is why the situation the present of the action as it unfolds forms the basis of surveys. Whether the studied situations are recent or belong to a distant past doesnt matter. Pragmatic sociology isnt confined to the study of our societies present. Rather, it aims to study any action, past or present, as it unfolds. In doing so, this approach is very similar to that of certain historians, who endeavor to account for past actions within the effective horizon of their authors expectations17. In line with these historians, pragmatic sociology tries not to project onto past facts the knowledge of their repercussions. Likewise, it tries to account for the relative indeterminacy that prevailed in past actions and was often erased by them18. Such presentism deserves to be described as methodological. Indeed, it doesnt presuppose that present phenomena are of greater analytical interest than past ones. It only requires that the latter be examined using the same methodology as present ones, that is for a pragmatist researcher in accordance with their relative indeterminacy and internal dynamism.

    For all that, pragmatic sociologists analyses dont neglect longer temporalities, which go beyond the here and now of the actions they study. In this respect, two non-mutually-exclusive stances can be distinguished within pragmatic sociology. The first is more strictly presentist. It sticks to the ethnomethodological principle that, when analyzing action, researchers shouldnt take account of any element external to the order resulting from the action being achieved. Thus the historical past can be included in the survey only if the situations participants call for it. The researcher then determines when, how, and by means of which material and organizational supports actors themselves refer to the past, reinterpret it, and produce its factuality19. Far from marginal, this highly pragmatist topic is similar albeit

    16 See: Latour (B.), Changer de socit, refaire de la sociologie, Paris, La Dcouverte, 2006.17 For a discussion on this comparison: Cerrutti (S.), Pragmatique et histoire. Ce dont les sociologues sont capables , Annales, 46 (6), 1991; Boureau (A.), La croyance comme comptence , Critique, 529-530, 1991; Lepetit (B.), ed., Les formes de lexprience. Une autre histoire sociale, Paris, Albin Michel, 1995; Van Damme (S.), Lpreuve libertine. Morale, soupon et pouvoirs dans la France baroque, Paris, CNRS ditions, 2008; Offenstadt (N.), Van Damme (S.), Les pratiques historiennes au risque de la sociologie pragmatique , in Brvigliri (M.), Lafaye (C.), Trom (D.), eds, Comptences critiques et sens de la justice, Paris, Economica, 2009.18 On the importance of this stance, see: Callon (M.), Latour (B.), eds, La science telle quelle se fait, Paris, La Dcouverte, 1990; Latour (B.), Pasteur, op. cit.19 See the issue edited by: Heurtin (J.-Ph.), Trom (D.), Se rfrer au pass , Politix, 39, 1997.

  • different to a research area now popular among historians: the social and political uses of the past20. It contributes to the study of historical phenomena by bringing in an analytical reflexivity that forces the researcher not only to acknowledge its contemporaries abilities to produce their presents historicity, but also to specify the degree to which these shared abilities differ from his/her own, as well as how they both derive from the same processes of conflicting objectivation of the past.

    Another way pragmatic sociology brings in temporalities that go beyond the here and now of the situations can be described as genealogical. It consists in inquiring into the past of a society, group, or organizational device, so as to account for the fact that, throughout their actions and judgments, contemporary actors are faced with constraints they inherit, but can also use certain resources passed on by their predecessors (already pioneered means of action, justifications already formed, etc.). Whether it focuses on pilgrims waiting for Marian apparitions, anti-AIDS activists calling out to the authorities, elected representatives cursing one another in the National Assembly, slaughterhouse workers struggling with the animals they have to put to death, foremen claiming manager status within their companies, or journalists seeking to verify the information they came across, the observation of practices must be compared with the way forms of collective life and professional worlds were historically structured21. This can lead the researcher to inquire into the historical formation of certain shared action forms and reasoning patterns which have become a common and even sometimes socially compulsory focus of study such as those that help publicly formulate accusations22 or collectively react to a suffering23 or the beauty of a landscape24. These genealogical surveys will enable the researcher to explain and, to a certain extent, predict the lack of mobilization prompted by the denunciation of certain scandals25 or the lack of emotion inspired by certain kinds of suffering or certain landscapes26. Sometimes, a diagnostic on current

    20 See: Hartog (F.), Revel (J.), eds, Les usages politiques du pass, Paris, ditions de lEHESS, 2001; Hartog (F.), Rgimes dhistoricit. Prsentisme et expriences du temps, Paris, Seuil, 2002. The difference between this work and pragmatic sociology is that the latter doesnt consider the past accomplished once and for all and therefore ready to be used. On the contrary, it sees it as always in the making, each of its new mobilizations necessarily leading to its partial reinterpretation and reconfiguration.21 See respectively: Claverie (.), Les guerres de la Vierge. Une anthropologie des apparitions, Paris, Gallimard, 2003; Dodier (N.), Leons politiques de lpidmie de sida, Paris, ditions de lEHESS, 2003; Heurtin (J.-Ph.), Lespace public parlementaire. Essai sur les raisons du lgislateur, Paris, Presses universitaires de France, 1999; Rmy (C.), La fin des btes, op. cit.; Boltanski (L.), Les cadres, op. cit.; Lemieux (C.), Mauvaise presse. Une sociologie comprhensive du travail journalistique et de ses critiques, Paris, Mtaili, 2000.22 See: Boltanski (L.), Claverie (.), Offenstadt (N.), Van Damme (S.), eds, Affaires, scandales et grandes causes. De Socrate Pinochet, Paris, Stock, 2007; as well as the issue edited by: Blic (D.), Lemieux (C.), lpreuve du scandale , Politix, 71, 2005.23 Boltanski (L.), La souffrance distance. Morale humanitaire, mdias et politique, Paris, Mtaili, 1993.24 Trom (D.), Voir le paysage, enquter sur le temps. Narration du temps historique, engagement dans laction et rapport visuel au monde , Politix, 39, 1997.25 De Blic (D.), Le scandale financier du sicle, a ne vous intresse pas ? Difficiles mobilisations autour du Crdit Lyonnais , Politix, 52, 2000.26 Boltanski (L.), Godet (M.-N.), Messages damour sur le Tlphone du dimanche , Politix, 31, 1995; Cardon (D.), Heurtin (J.-Ph.), Martin (O.), Pharabod (A.-S.), Rozier (S.), Les formats de la gnrosit. Trois explorations du Tlthon , Rseaux, 95, 1999; Trom (D.), Zimmerman (B.), Cadres

  • situations will lead the researcher to reconstruct the conflicting dynamics that generated them how the social critique of capitalism gradually became questioned in France in the twentieth centurys last decades or how at the same time an issue seen as strictly technical, namely nuclear waste disposal, was politicized27.

    In this respect, pragmatic sociology is similar to traditional historical sociology for it also tries to reconstruct the historical dynamics that shape current situations. However, they differ in that pragmatic sociology doesnt only seek to understand how the dead seize the living, but equally and, in a way, primarily examines how the living seize the dead. Thus pragmatic sociology analytically prioritizes the actions present and restores its relative indeterminacy. The aim of the historical survey therefore isnt so much to trace lines of historical continuity as it is to made current situations more intelligible, particularly by considering the fact that the numerous legacies these situations inherit arent equally claimed and seized by actors, which should be explained. Thus researchers should observe the present before turning to the past, rather than the contrary28. But then, they should take another fresh look at the present with the past in mind, asking new questions29.

    Pragmatic sociologists introduce the historical past in their analyses in various ways. Certain studies take account of this past only if actors themselves refer to it explicitly, whether to celebrate it or to confront one another about it. Thus they tend to analyze how our societies produce their histories and historicize the present, as well as how researchers are themselves involved in this process. In other studies, researchers try to reconstruct the historical past of the studied situations in a genealogical (that is, regressive) approach. Thus they aim not only to explain the constraints on present situations or, inseparably, the resources available to actors, but also to observe such situations in a different way, by asking why certain legacies of the past arent being activated. In any case, a methodological presentism prevails, which constitutes one of the main forms of unity and coherence of the pragmatic approach. It is based in particular on the idea that no action can simply or mechanically be inferred from the past for it always entails its own indeterminacy. Far from rejecting the historical perspective or the genealogical survey, this approach is just another way of practicing them.

    How pragmatic sociology reexamines the questions of interests

    Pragmatic sociology doesnt aim to disclose vested interests supposedly concealed behind more general arguments. Nor does it aim to track down hidden agendas or more or less conscious ulterior motives behind certain actors universalist,

    et institutions des problmes publics. Les cas du chmage et du paysage , in Trom (D.), Cefa (D.), eds, Les formes de laction collective. Mobilisations dans des arnes publiques, Paris, ditions de lEHESS, 2001.27 See respectively: Boltanski (L.), Chiapello (.), Le nouvel esprit du capitalisme, op. cit.; Barthe (Y.), Le pouvoir dindcision, op. cit.28 The approach is then more similar to the explanation model Philippe Descola calls regressive history, as opposed to the idea of mythical genesis. Descola (P.), Pourquoi les Indiens dAmazonie nont-ils pas domestiqu le pcari ? , in Latour (B.), Lemonier (P.), eds, De la prhistoire aux missiles balistiques. Paris, La Dcouverte, 1994.29 Trom (D.), Situationnisme et historicit de laction. Une approche par induction triangulaire , in Laborier (P.), Trom (D.), eds, Historicits de laction publique, Paris, Presses universitaires de France, 2003.

  • altruist, or disinterested statements. Does this mean that pragmatic sociology doesnt deal with the question of interests? Quite the opposite: the formation of interests is the focus of many studies affiliated to pragmatic sociology. Yet interests arent conceived as an explanatory factor of action or speech, but as one of their products. Rather than being a convenient and inexhaustible resource that enables the sociologist to explain actors behaviors, interests become a focus of research in their own right. The sociologist should therefore explain how they are defined, stabilized, and transformed throughout controversies, polemics, and other studied preuves30 (tests, trials).

    This is why pragmatic sociology so often focuses on the figure of the unveiling of hidden interests in public controversies31. Actors frequently use unveiling as a way to define and impute interests to their opponents: what they claim to be a just war, based on humanitarian grounds, is really motivated by the States or a lobbys oil interests; your commitment as an artist to Kosovo actually conceals your professional ambition and your desire to achieve peer recognition, and so on. Thus highlighting hidden interests is a common figure of public denunciation, whose conditions of effectiveness should be studied, particularly in relation to the shared normative constructions whose history can be sketched out32. The denunciation of hidden interests can therefore be viewed as one of the most important modes of disqualification in public arenas33.

    Yet the figure of denunciation is far from being the only way actors strive to produce interests and manifest them to one another. The reference to interests isnt limited to a denunciation; it can also correspond to a protest, so as to build alliances, alter positions, or recruit other actors to support a cause by showing them that it is in their own interest34. In such situations, the identification of interests and their reformulation which go hand in hand are operations whereby actors define one another, either by creating distance or by pointing out similarities.

    To that effect, we need to keep in mind that referring to interests is but one way of distancing oneself or coming closer. This is why a certain number of pragmatic sociologists refuse to equate all social actions with strategic behaviors indexed to the pursuit of individual or collective interests35. These authors seek to distinguish various regimes of engagement in which actors define each other and relate to one another in a quite different way36. In some regimes, actors activity consists in explicitly expressing or stating their interests and in considering others from an often

    30 Callon (M.), lments pour une sociologie de la traduction : la domestication des coquilles Saint-Jacques et des marins pcheurs dans la baie de Saint-Brieuc , LAnne sociologique, 36, 1986; Bidet (A.), La gense des valeurs : une affaire denqute , Tracs, 15, 2008.31 Boltanski (L.), La dnonciation , Actes de la recherche en sciences sociales, 51, 1984.32 See previous section.33 Sociology runs the risk to lose track of this from the moment it also resorts to this kind of critical operation. See: Trom (D.), De la rfutation de leffet NIMBY considre comme une pratique militante. Notes pour une approche pragmatique de lactivit revendicative , Revue franaise de science politique, 49 (1), 1999.34 Callon (M.), Law (J.), On Interest and Their Transformation: Enrolment and Counter-Enrolment , Social Studies of Science, 12 (4), 1982.35 See for instance: Corcuff (P.), Sanier (M.), Politique publique et action stratgique en contexte de dcentralisation. Aperus dun processus dcisionnel aprs la bataille , Annales, 55 (4), 2000.

  • efficiency-oriented perspective. In others, however, actors denounce the interests they attribute to others, particularly by highlighting their incompatibility with the general interest or with certain impartiality and equity requirements. In still others, actors dont point out interests as such neither others, nor their own for the course of action doesnt let them bring this figure out. Developed in particular in the sociology of the regimes of engagement, this perspective aims to closely observe how individuals collectively produce their interests, which requires taking account of the situations of social life in which such interests havent formed yet. In some respects, this approach is very similar to that developed by other movements within pragmatic sociology such as, in particular, the anthropology of science and technology which invite us to consider the importance, in the formation of the interests, of the presence or lack of interest-producing devices. For instance, the success of a technical innovation can be analyzed as being due to its ability to enable social groups to identify and recognize themselves, by instilling new interests into their members or shifting preexisting ones37.

    How pragmatic sociology treats what actors say

    An important characteristic of pragmatic sociology consists in taking seriously actors justifications and critiques. What does this entail? It entails both accounting for their practical foundations and analyzing their social effects. First, accounting for their practical foundations: it is important to understand how critiques and justifications are generated from a certain kind of social practices, that is, faced with a certain kind of practical contradictions actors have to deal with. This is why, in pragmatic sociology, taking justifications and critiques seriously involves inquiring into practices and, more specifically, reconstructing the contradictory logics of practice, which give rise to actors critical activity38. Second, analyzing their social effects: it is important to account for the kind of efficiency or relative inefficiency attached to actors critical operations and justifications within the social world in which they live or act. Their arguments, justifications, and critiques are certainly not, as such, able to transform the state of social relations. However, the actions consisting in arguing, justifying, and criticizing can do so, if only marginally (for instance, making a leader justify him/herself should be viewed as altering the preexisting political and social relations, if only minimally). Thus, in pragmatic sociology, taking justifications and critiques seriously entails exploring the possible effects of critiques on the reshaping of collectives, the transformation of sociotechnical devices, and the reform of institutions39.

    36 See in particular: Thvenot (L.), Laction au pluriel. Sociologie des rgimes dengagement, Paris, La Dcouverte, 2006.37 Akrich (M.), Callon (M.), Latour (B.), quoi tient le succs des innovations ? 1. Lart de lintressement , Annales des Mines. Grer et comprendre, 11, 1988.38 Relating to various objects, see: Chateauraynaud (F.) La faute professionnelle. Une sociologie des conflits de responsabilit, Paris, Mtaili, 1991; Doidy (E.), (Ne pas) juger scandaleux. Les lecteurs de Levallois-Perret face au comportement de leur maire , Politix, 71, 2005; Lagneau (.), Ce que Sgolne Royal na pas assez vu. LAFP entre ralismes politique et conomique , Rseaux, 157-158, 2009.39 See: Chiapello (.), Artistes versus managers. Le management culturel face la critique artiste, Paris, Mtaili, 1998; Boltanski (L.), Chiapello (.), Le nouvel esprit du capitalisme, op. cit.; de Blic (D.), Moraliser largent. Ce que Panama a chang dans la socit franaise (1889-1897) , Politix, 71, 2005; Fillion (E.), lpreuve du sang contamin. Pour une sociologie des affaires mdicales, Paris, ditions de lEHESS, 2009.

  • Pragmatic sociology involves systematically analyzing the practical

    foundations and social effects of critical operations and justifications. By doing so, with regard to what actors say, it emphasizes a quite different kind of epistemological break from that advocated by the critical sociology of domination. The goal is neither to reveal the underlying strategies in general arguments, nor as previously stated to reveal particular interests. Since this task is usually carried out by actors themselves as any researcher studying controversies or cases can observe the pragmatic sociologist seeks to examine how actors do so, with what kind of proof and material supports, and whether they succeed or not. Thus the sociologist isnt quite at the level where actors themselves tend to spontaneously explain their mutual actions and judge them. He/she makes an additional effort, not only because, most often unlike actors, he/she tries to grasp all viewpoints involved in the fight (treating them symmetrically), but also because he/she inquires into the practical foundations of critical operations and justifications as well as into their social effects. This amounts to identifying the elements actors (and the researcher) arent immediately aware of: the kind of practical contradictions that generates the studied critical process or the kind of social or institutional mechanisms that limits the publicization and the social effects of critiques40.

    Thus taking seriously what actors do to account for their practices and justify their behaviors doesnt mean simply recording their viewpoints or translating them into a scientific language. Nor does it mean simply considering that actors are right to say what they say: it means taking into account that there are reasons for them to say it reasons related to the real contradictions of their practices41. Likewise, it doesnt mean considering that what actors say adequately describes what they do: it means considering that what they say is an integral part of the way they describe what they do their discursive practices coming with a form of efficiency, which varies according to the individuals and the situations.

    How pragmatic sociology does justice to actors reflexivity

    Pragmatic sociology refuses to analyze action from a perspective that contrasts practical activities with reflexive ones. It assumes that it is impossible, when analyzing action, to isolate a level totally lacking actors reflexivity on their own actions or on others. This refusal to dissociate the analysis of practices from the analysis of the corresponding forms of reflexivity results from the following observation: no action is ever devoid of reasons. The latter are made describable in the course of actions, and are therefore both material and observable42. Thus the sociological description of the interaction must be based on them to make them intelligible. Let us elaborate on these two statements.

    40 See: Stavo-Debauge (J.), En qute dune introuvable action antidiscriminatoire. Une sociologie de ce qui fait dfaut , Politix, 94, 2011.41 Callon (M.), Rabeharisoa (V.), La leon dhumanit de Gino , Rseaux, 95, 1999.42 The pragmatic approach breaks away from mentalism on this point. The researcher endeavors to describe actors reasons for acting only through what makes them observable in situation, that is: the interaction itself, its actors mobilization of certain material supports, their reaction to their partners attitudes, and their possible verbal exchanges. See: Dodier (N.), Les appuis conventionnels de laction. lments de pragmatique sociologique , Rseaux, 62, 1993; Lemieux (C.), Mauvaise presse, op. cit., p. 116-117.

  • Pragmatic sociologists dont assume that actors are always fully aware of the reasons for what they do, nor that they could, if needed, clearly express them to themselves or others. Rather, they consider that actors reflexive relation to their own actions or to others should be considered in gradual terms. At the upper end of this gradation, there are forms of maximal reflexivity, characteristic of the public situations in which they are expressed as justifications opposable to third parties. True, at first, pragmatic sociology looked into these situations because it initially examined the moments of quarrels during which the participants reasons for acting the way they do become the object of a collective explanation requiring a high level of detachment43.

    Yet pragmatic sociology doesnt claim to outline a general model of action based on the analysis of the actions characteristic of these most public configurations. It would be mistaken to consider that in all circumstances actors act as if they were subject to strong constraints of publicity. On the contrary, pragmatic sociology has been lead to take account of the formats of action below the public action format. These formats dont rely on rules of public justification or detachment, but on rules similar to what the notions of practice and routine usually involve44. However, the situations that characterize them arent a-reflexive, that is, devoid of reasons. But the reflexive relation then takes on minimal, non-opposable, and often nonverbal forms. They can sometimes be observed only through details a hesitation, a readjustment of the body, a glance, etc. indicative of a misalignment however tenuous and fleeting it may be of the action in relation to itself45.

    Thus pragmatic sociology is aware that, in many social situations, action can be very little reflexive. Some of its supporters have even tried to restore the notion of the unconscious or, more precisely, to explore the idea that any action, like any judgment, necessarily involves an unconscious part.46 But this sociology does dispute the idea that a practice, whatever it be, can be completely devoid of reflexivity. It therefore distances itself from the conception that our most empirical practices proceed from a mechanical adjustment to others and to the environment a relation that excludes any kind of reflexive mediation. Indeed, such conception of practice, which establishes action only in the regularity of habits, doesnt explain the interactional dynamics that make it possible and spark an increased reflexivity among actors. Conversely, considering the reasons actors actions are based on helps

    43 For an analysis of several empirical cases of this kind of rise in generality, see: Boltanski (L.), Thvenot (L.), eds, Justesse et justice dans le travail, Cahiers du CEE, 33, 1989.44 See in particular: Thvenot (L.), Le rgime de familiarit. Des choses en personne , Genses, 17, 1994; Thvenot (L.), Laction au pluriel, op. cit.; Breviglieri (M.), Lusage et lhabiter. Contribution une sociologie de la proximit, PhD dissertation in sociology, cole des hautes tudes en sciences sociales, 1999.45 Observing such dynamic misalignments of an individual or collective action requires a high level of descriptive accuracy and sharpness. See: Piette (A.), Le mode mineur de la ralit, Louvain-la-Neuve, Peeters, 1992; Rmy (C.), Activit sociale et latralisation , Recherches sociologiques, 34 (3), 2003; Datchary (C.), La dispersion au travail, Toulouse, Octares, 2011.46 Boltanski (L.), La condition ftale. Une sociologie de lengendrement et de lavortement, Paris, Gallimard, 2004; Rmy (C.), Quand la norme implicite est le moteur de laction , Dviance et Socit, 29 (2), 2005; Lemieux (C.), Du pluralisme des rgimes daction la question de linconscient : dplacements in Breviglieri (M.), Lafaye (C.), Trom (D.), eds, Comptences critiques, op. cit.

  • bridge the gap between the categories of practice and reflexivity, by assuming that the situations are characterized by varying levels of reflexive intensity47. It is only by considering that the most intuitive and the least reflexive actions still (or more precisely, already) have reasons that we can analyze the fact that, in certain circumstances, their reflexivity can increase48. Conversely, this perspective brings all forms of reflexivity including sociological reflexivity back to their practical foundations49.

    This approach helps pragmatic sociology not overestimate actors reflexivity, while it avoids assigning them too much awareness of what they do and say. Indeed, this sociology is careful not to prejudge their level of reflexivity since it focuses on determining it and how it varies in time for a person. Thus it doesnt consider that actors are always at the highest level of their collective reflexive abilities. Nor does it consider, however, that they are constantly at their lowest level, let alone that this lower level corresponds to a degree zero reflexivity.

    How pragmatic sociology renews the question of socialization

    The last twenty years, in France, one of the main renewals in the studies on socialization has undoubtedly been the rediscovery of the plurality of self. As it is well known, the argument isnt new since it can be traced back to the pragmatism of the early twentieth century in particular50. In the early Nineties, L. Boltanski and L. Thvenot imported it into France. By defending the idea that social agents should no longer be presumed systematically coherent with themselves, their book On Justification argued that they should on the contrary be analyzed from the perspective of the plurality of the sometimes contradictory logics they are involved in51. This approach entails a conception of identity and socialization devoid of the emphasis that Bourdieus interpretation of the concept of habitus rather than Norbert Eliass puts on the coherence of self. Thus, according to pragmatic sociology, individuals tensions and internal contradictions, as well as their symptoms

    47 See: Breviglieri (M.), Trom (D.), Troubles et tensions en milieu urbain. Les preuves citadines et habitantes de la ville , in Cefa (D.), Pasquier (D.), eds, Les sens du public, Paris, Presses universitaires de France, 2003; Breviglieri (M.), Linsupportable. Lexcs de proximit, latteinte lautonomie et le sentiment de violation du priv , in Breviglieri (M.), Lafaye (C.), Trom (D.), eds, Comptences critiques, op. cit. For a theorization of the continuist hypothesis mentioned here, see: Lemieux (C.), Le devoir et la grce. Pour une analyse grammaticale de laction, Paris, Economica, 2009. 48 See the analysis of corporate recruiters practical judgements and intuitions by Eymard-Duvernay (F.), Marchal (E.), Faons de recruter. Le jugement des comptences sur le march du travail, Paris, Mtaili, 1996. For the case of physicians, see: Dodier (N.), Lexpertise mdicale. Essai de sociologie sur lexercice du jugement, Paris, Mtaili, 1993. For the case of journalists, see: Lagneau (.), Une fausse information en qute dauteur. Conflits dimputation autour dune annulation de dpches AFP , in Lemieux (C.), ed., La subjectivit journalistique, op. cit.49 See Bruno Latours analyses of the production of scientific and juridical reflexivities: Latour (B.), Woolgar (S.), La vie de laboratoire. La production des faits scientifiques, Paris, La Dcouverte, 1988; Latour (B.), Lespoir de Pandore. Pour une version raliste de lactivit scientifique, Paris, La Dcouverte, 2007 [1st US ed. 1999]; Latour (B.), La fabrique du droit. Une ethnographie du Conseil dtat, Paris, La Dcouverte, 2002.50 See in particular: Mead (G.), Lesprit, le soi et la socit, Paris, Presses universitaires de France, 2006 [1st US ed. 1934]. For a synthetic overview of this tradition, see: Elster (J.), ed., The Multiple Self, New York, Cambridge University Press, 1985.51 Boltanski (L.), Thvenot (L.), De la justification..., op. cit.

  • (disorders, hesitations, being unable to act, moral dilemmas, and sometimes inventiveness), help understand individuals in action, the judgments their partners make about them, and ultimately the construction of their selves52.

    This kind of pluralistic approach of self deeply renews the analysis of the socialization processes. It should be noted that numerous dispositional concepts, from habits (Peirce, Dewey) to tendencies to act (Mead), are central to pragmatist philosophy53. However, to remain within the orbit of pragmatic sociology, such concepts require to be handled in a way French sociologists may not be familiar with. The pragmatist perspective indeed doesnt grant the status of descriptive concept to dispositions since they dont describe actions: the former are made describable by the latter. (He has a middle-class disposition doesnt describe an action. The agents action makes him describable as having a middle-class disposition.) The sociologist should therefore at first describe action in situation, which will enable him/her to identify the dispositions it shows as opposed to deducing action from the dispositions attributed to the agent. Thus the researcher who acknowledges the plural and potentially contradictory character of actions, because he/she often has to describe them, must also acknowledge what derives from them: the plural and potentially contradictory character of dispositions and, therefore, what is usually referred to as learning or education. In consequence, he/she cant take actors coherence of their selves for granted. On the contrary, he/she should see it as a practical problem actors are trying to deal with54.

    Moreover, starting from the description of actions in situation helps precisely assess the practical mechanisms whereby learning occurs. The approach consisting in deducing agents actions from the dispositions attributed to them doesnt bother with this: according to it, statements such as the institution taught the agents or the actors internalized suffice. According to the pragmatist approach, on the other hand, these oversimplifications are insufficient. They dont tell us anything about the practical situations in which learning took place and the kind of preuves that occurred during learning. They dont tell us much about the places, objects, and ways of the socialization. In this respect, pragmatic sociology choses to carefully examine the actors bodily involvement in the material devices they intend to use or are ordered to master. This sociology is actually a pragmatic sociology of the body.

    52 Relating to various objects, see: Prilleux (T.), Les tensions de la flexibilit. Lpreuve du travail contemporain, Paris, Descle de Brouwer, 2001; Barbot (J.), Dodier (N.), Itinraires de rparation et formation dun espace de victimes autour dun drame mdical , in Cultiaux (J.), Prilleux (T.), eds, Destins politiques de la souffrance. Intervention sociale, justice, travail, Toulouse, Ers, 2009; Cefa (D.), Gardella (E.), Lurgence sociale en action. Ethnologie du Samu social de Paris, Paris, La Dcouverte, 2011; Breviglieri (M.), Cichelli (V.), eds, Adolescences mditerranennes. Lespace public petits pas, Paris, LHarmattan, 2007; Sourp (M.-L.), Une question de personnalit. Laccs linformation chez un rubricard de Libration , in Lemieux (C.), ed., La subjectivit journalistique, op. cit.53 Bourdieu (E.), Savoir-faire. Contribution une thorie dispositionnelle de laction, Paris, Seuil, 1998; Chauvir (C.), Ogien (A.), eds, La rgularit. Habitude, disposition et savoir-faire dans lexplication de laction, Paris, ditions de lEHESS, 2002.54 This approach was initiated by one of the GSPM founders, Michal Pollak, in his book Lexprience concentrationnaire. Essai sur le maintien de lidentit sociale, Paris, Mtaili, 1990. See: Lemieux (C.), De la thorie de lhabitus la sociologie des preuves : relire Lexprience concentrationnaire , in Isral (L.), Voldman (D.), eds, Michal Pollak. De lidentit blesse une sociologie des possibles, Paris, Complexe, 2007.

  • Basically, it can be seen as a sociology of the bodily involvement55. Its authors connected it with the ecological approaches in terms of situated cognition56. In particular, they sought to account for the fact that affordances are provided or withdrawn from actors by the sociotechnical devices they are involved in which has a direct impact on both actors differential abilities to learn and the kind of knowledge they acquire57.

    Therefore, these authors renewed the understanding of the link between the shows in situation of competence or virtuosity58 as well as the processes of (social, professional, institutional, etc.) integration and exclusion. Far from being a foregone conclusion, these processes derive from a series of preuves whose results are still uncertain although they may in part be predictable. During these preuves, actors performances or counterperformances may be judged by peers, supervisors, and so on even by themselves considering their ability, inability, normality, or abnormality. These preuves and the subsequent sanctions, whether positive or negative, force the researcher to view the question of individuals membership in a collective in a highly dynamic way. It renews the approach to what social science referred to as socialization. Unlike the perspectives that attribute a given status to actors (depending on what was up to then their status), pragmatic sociology reopens, on principle of method, the discussion on the persons present or future identity in a certain situation and on the status that will be attributed to them. Thus it doesnt prejudge what people are capable of59. Will this child be able to walk, work, or swim? It is precisely because this is uncertain that eighteenth-century and contemporary educationalists dont agree on what can reasonably and fairly be expected from a child or be done with him/her60. The principle that actors competences shouldnt be prejudged is of methodological nature. Although it should be followed, it absolutely doesnt mean that all social agents have the same abilities. Rather, it means their competences (and therefore also their dispositions, habits, tendencies to act, etc.) form a dynamic and adaptive system, whose limits cant be set in advance by the researcher.

    It should therefore be noted that, while dispositional concepts dont describe actions, they contribute to make it partially visible and explainable. This is why they are specifically interesting for social science. Thus the researcher can relate an actors

    55 Bessy (C.), Chateauraynaud (F.), Experts et faussaires. Pour une sociologie de la perception, Paris, Mtaili, 1995; Hennion (A.), Music Lovers: Taste as Performance , in Warde (A.), ed., Consumption, vol 3: Appropriation, London, Sage, 2010; Rmy (C.), La fin des btes, op. cit.56 See in particular: Conein (B.), Dodier (N.), Thvenot (L.), eds, Les objets dans laction. De la maison au laboratoire, Paris, ditions de lEHESS, 1993.57 Relating to various fields, see: Hennion (A.), Comment la musique vient aux enfants. Une anthropologie de lenseignement musical, Paris, Economica, 1988; Conein (B.), Cognition situe et coordination de laction. La cuisine dans tous ses tats , Rseaux, 43, 1990; Winance (M.), Mobilits en fauteuil roulant. Processus dajustement corporel et darrangements pratiques avec lespace, physique et social , Politix, 90, 2010; Moreau de Bellaing (C.) Comment la violence vient aux policiers. cole de police et enseignement de la violence lgitime , Genses, 75, 2009.58 Dodier (N.), Les hommes et les machines. La conscience collective dans les socits technicises, Paris, Mtaili, 1995.59 Boltanski (L.), Lamour et la justice comme comptences. Trois essais de sociologie de laction, Paris, Mtaili, 1990.60 Garnier (P), Ce dont les enfants sont capables, Paris, Mtaili, 1995.

  • observable behavior to its past ones, so as to highlight how through which series of preuves and devices the tendencies or habits the actor now manifests have previously developed in him. This explanatory use of dispositionalism prevails in pragmatic sociology61. It is also in this predictive use of dispositional concepts that the question of the unequal distribution of opportunities to act or successfully pass a test may be raised afresh. In this respect, pragmatic sociology does nothing but insist on the importance for the researcher of describing actions in situation, insofar as the latter, although partially predictably, are never completely so. On no account can it be purely and simply deduced from the actors dispositions.

    How pragmatic sociology shifts the question of power

    To study a conflict or a controversy, the pragmatic approach supposes that sociologists suspend their knowledge about the initial distribution of the dominant/dominated roles or about the balance of power that eventually stemmed from the examined situation of confrontation. One of this stances underlying principles is that the social worlds asymmetries are all the better describable when observed from the standpoint of an epistemology of symmetry62. This doesnt mean that pragmatic sociologists imagine the social world symmetrical by default, but simply that, to correctly describe asymmetries, the latter shouldnt be prejudged and the possibility of their reversibility shouldnt be excluded a priori, even when it is the least probable.

    Thus, since the situations of domination arent totally closed most of the time, this sociology places particular emphasis on the fact that each of the two poles of the relationship plays an active role in the evolution of their relation although with a very different efficiency. From this perspective, no power can be unilaterally exerted since its exercise necessarily involves a reaction from the one who obeys or, if it be so, resists. In this sense, pragmatic sociologists all follow the methodological principle of the potential reversibility of the studied power relations, including when they appear the most stable and well-established. According to them, due to their very nature, such relations can fail even when they succeed. This has at least two implications. The first is to ensure that an analysis of a relation of dependency, power, and domination never erases the relative indeterminacy constitutive of it. The second is not to forget that power doesnt exist outside of the preuves it gives rise to, so that the latter are undoubtedly the first thing the researcher should describe and analyze63.

    These methodological presuppositions explain why pragmatic sociology focuses on actors critical competences. Indeed, only at this cost can the researcher measure the actual influence of power devices: by taking seriously the prospect of challenging the relation of domination, the researcher is in a better position to observe the effective limitations of the gestures, attitudes, and words that initiate such a challenge.

    61 For instance: Dodier (N.), Leons politiques sur lpidmie de sida, op. cit.; Lemieux (C.), Albert Londres. Le journalisme contre-cur , in Lemieux (C.), ed., La subjectivit journalistique, op. cit.62 Latour (B.), Pasteur, op. cit.63 See: Linhardt (D.), La force de ltat en dmocratie. La Rpublique fdrale dAllemagne lpreuve de la gurilla urbaine, PhD dissertation in sociology, cole nationale suprieure des Mines de Paris, 2004; as well as the issue edited by: Linhardt (D.), Vitale (T.), preuves dtat , Quaderni, 78, 2012.

  • Conversely, prejudging the unstoppable efficiency of domination makes it both useless and impossible to observe the dynamics whereby this domination is sometimes thwarted and sometimes strengthened. In this respect, pragmatic sociology requires a sufficiently fine and precise level of description of the situations, so that the researcher may observe and analyze actors smallest critical inclinations and the most immediate processes that hinder them.

    While pragmatic sociology considers that a situation whatever it is doesnt amount to a pre-established distribution of dominant/dominated roles, it doesnt fail to recognize the existence of power phenomena. It seeks a level of description where these phenomena can be seen and analyzed as practical accomplishments. Rather than attempting to account for observable actions with the help of the power relations black box, this sociology focuses on actions themselves, observable as they produce power relations64. The black box is then opened: power structures are no longer considered as causes, but as resulting from what is observed; and rather than pretending to exhaust the behaviors description and explanation by invoking a totem word (power, domination, etc.), the researcher begins to study the power effects and the arrangements that make them possible65.

    Pragmatic sociologys task is therefore to describe and understand how power devices actually work. It seeks to identify the concrete supports used in situation by those who manage to make others perform certain actions. It seeks to analyze how those who try to challenge the dependency or domination they suffer from go about it, as well as the limitations they face in doing so. Finally, it tries to account for the social work whereby power occurs and is actualized.

    How pragmatic sociology analyzes social inequalities

    As we have just said, as regards its methodological principles, pragmatic sociology values symmetry and equality of treatment between the conflicting parties, yet it doesnt deny the existence of asymmetries and inequalities as regards the realities it studies. It intends to provide the means to investigate how such asymmetries and inequalities are reproduced but also sometimes undone. In this respect, it is clearly different from the critical sociology of domination, according to which inequalities are somehow a starting point for analysis and are used as a resource to explain action. According to pragmatic sociology, on the contrary, inequalities should be considered a product of action66. Rather than an explanatory

    64 See: Chateauraynaud (F.), Les relations demprise, document de travail, GSPR-EHESS, 1999; Linhardt (D.), Moreau de Bellaing (C.), Lgitime violence ? Enqutes sur la ralit de ltat dmocratique , Revue franaise de science politique, 55 (2) 2005.65 As Bruno Latour states: The philosophers and sociologists of power flatter the masters they clam to criticize. They explain the masters actions in terms of the might of power, though this power is efficacious only as a result of complicities, connivances, compromises, and mixtures [] which are not explained by power. The notion of power is the dormitive virtue of the poppy which induces somnolence in the critics at just the moment when powerless princes ally themselves with others who are equally weak in order to become strong. Latour (B.), Pasteur, op. cit., p. 266. [Latour (B.), The Pasteurization of France , Harvard University Press, 1993, p. 175] . 66 Derouet (J.-L.), cole et justice. De lgalit des chances aux compromis locaux ?, Paris, Mtaili, 1992; Normand (R.), Gouverner la russite scolaire. Une arithmtique politique des ingalits, Bern, Peter Lang, 2011; Auray (N.), Sociabilit informatique et diffrence sexuelle , in Chabaud-Rychter (D.), Gardey (D.), eds, Lengendrement des choses. Des hommes, des femmes et des

  • resource, they are what should be explained. The consequences of this approach arent insignificant: analytically, the inequalities produced in earlier preuves can certainly have a predictive role (in terms of actors unequally distributed chances to act), but they dont enable us to mechanically deduce either the collective action or, subsequently, the state of inequalities that will result from the new preuve; politically, recognizing inequalities as the result of collective action and highlighting that its reproduction, if somewhat predictable, still isnt mechanical at all is a way to focus on our collective ability to further real equality in our social relations.

    This emphasizes that symmetry and equality arent merely methodological principles. Quite often, they also correspond to a claim made by actors. In On Justification, L. Boltanski and L. Thvenot attempted to account for this to consider the ideal of equality, as mobilized in social practices, to be an object of study67. But their approach didnt fail to generate misunderstandings. Their description of actors ideal of equality was sometimes taken as an affirmation of the egalitarian nature of the relations among these actors. They were also criticized for claiming that public authorities action should necessarily be egalitarian to have a chance to impose. Yet this isnt what they suggested. True, the axiomatic of the polities they describe is based on egalitarian principles, such as those they call common humanity (that is, a fundamental equality between members) and common dignity (that is, members equally shared right to be eligible for a higher status), the polities. The polities, however, dont describe the world as it is. It is even the exact opposite since, through this concept, the authors wanted to designate the ideal constructions actors use as external supports to criticize the current state of their social relations. From this point of view, if the polities are to play any role in collective action, it certainly isnt because the social world is egalitarian, but precisely because it isnt. Therefore, the fact that an unequal public action is socially needed doesnt refute the polity model. For this model predicts only that, in our societies, the less a public action respects the principles of common humanity and common dignity, the more it can be criticized. This doesnt mean that such action will be unanimously or massively criticized, insofar as, precisely, unequal mechanisms may limit both the visibility of its unequal nature and the public expression of its critique.

    We notice in passing that taking seriously the argumentative constraints and the rules of evidence that affect collective action in the most public situations leads us to shift our analysis towards the question of the socio-technical devices limiting or, on the contrary, enabling to discuss certain policies, initiatives, or behaviors, as well as the visibility of their effects68. In this respect, the program of pragmatic sociology doesnt assume that those who dont seem to rebel against the injustice and inequality they suffer from lack critical abilities. Rather, it looks into their relative lack of material and organizational supports making up for this lack would enable them to

    techniques, Paris, ditions des archives contemporaines, 2002.67 Boltanski (L.), Thvenot (L.), De la justification, op. cit.68 Callon (M.), Lascoumes (P.), Barthe (Y.), Agir dans un monde incertain. Essai sur la dmocratie technique, Paris, Seuil, 2001; Linhardt (D.), Lconomie du soupon. Une contribution pragmatique la sociologie de la menace , Genses, 44, 2001; Stavo-Debauge (J.), En qute dune introuvable action antidiscriminatoire , art. cit.; Richard-Ferroudji (A.), Limites du modle dlibratif : composer avec diffrents formats de participation , Politix, 96, 2011; Cardon (D.), Dans lesprit du PageRank. Une enqute sur lalgorithme de Google , Rseaux, 177, 2013; Benvegnu (N.), La politique des netroots. La politique lpreuve des outils informatiques de dbat public, thse pour le doctorat de sociologie, Mines ParisTech, 2011.

  • make more visible the unequal nature of certain social relations or policies. A sociology of mobilizations is here appealed to through the study of what (in many cases) limits the visibility and public discussion of issues and inequalities, as well as what (in some cases) enables and produces it69.

    How pragmatic sociology avoids relativism

    Any sociological movement and, more generally, any social science approach may be asked about its relativism. How indeed could a work in social science never resort to relativism? To understand how pragmatic sociology addresses this question, a commonly used preuve consists in asking how it would react if it had to deal with an object likely to raise a spontaneous moral condemnation from most of us (the issue of Nazism remains the most commonly used preuve, but we can also think of Al Qaedas terrorism, the perpetrators of the Rwandan Genocide, military torture during the Algerian War, the excision of girls, etc.). With such objects, pragmatic sociologists would force themselves to follow the actors, whether they are Nazis, terrorists, or excision practitioners, and to respect a principle of symmetry. They would therefore endeavor to analyze what the actors (Nazis, terrorists, or excisers, etc.) as well as those who condemn them and fight them do, without a priori assuming the formers lack of rationality in favor of the latter, and by ensuring that both sides respective arguments and points of view are treated with the same methodological indifference. Finally, pragmatic sociologists would respect the postulate of pluralism, in virtue of which they should admit that, despite appearances, the actors (Nazis, terrorists, or excisers, etc.) arent all of a piece and, like anyone else, are subject to internal contradictions. Such an approach could certainly be described as relativistic.

    However, pragmatist sociologists would remind us that these are methodological principles, which certainly dont prevent us from holding our own value judgments on the studied phenomena. Furthermore, two theoretical elements of pragmatic sociology enable it to be recognized as an anti-relativist enterprise. Derived from the work initiated by L. Boltanski and L. Thvenot, the first of these theoretical elements is linked to the idea of a sense of justice and to the principle that certain arguments, when expressed in public situations, can de facto be more criticized than others. What is recognized here is the existence of argumentative constraints and rules on the production of evidence. The more public the situation, the stronger the constraints. For actors, therefore, all actions cant be deemed equivalent, all behaviors arent equally acceptable, and some should be unanimously considered scandalous and degrading and shouldnt be tolerated. The challenge is to follow the actors to the end, in particular until they prove resolutely anti-relativist and allow themselves to produce value judgments and assess behaviors. These moments of moral reflexivity obey shared rules and refer to (more or less) common expectations: this is why the resulting judgments arent totally subjective or arbitrary.

    69 Barbot (J.) Les malades en mouvements. La mdecine et la science lpreuve du sida, Paris, Balland, 2002; Gramaglia (C.), Des poissons aux masses deau. Les usages militants du droit pour faire parler des tres qui ne parlent pas , Politix, 83, 2008; Lemieux (C.), Rendre visibles les dangers du nuclaire. Une contribution la sociologie de la mobilisation , in Lahire (B.), Rosental (C.), eds, La cognition au prisme des sciences sociales, Paris, ditions des archives contemporaines, 2008; Jobin (P.), Les cobayes portent plainte. Usages de lpidmiologie dans deux affaires de maladies industrielles Tawan , Politix, 91, 2010; Barthe (Y.), Cause politique et politique des causes. La mobilisation des vtrans des essais nuclaires franais , Politix, 91, 2010.

  • We see in passing that certain authors dont hesitate to describe the On Justification70 model as relativistic perhaps because they focus too exclusively on the postulate of pluralism implemented by the authors who defend in particular the idea that their different polities cant be organized along hierarchical lines. In doing so, they dont pay enough attention to the fact that, beyond their diversity, all polities obey the same egalitarian axiomatic, as reflected in each of them by the so-called common humanity and common dignity principles71.

    The second element that puts a brake on relativism is more closely linked to the notion of preuve as the anthropology of science and technology developed it. It consists in considering that the world provides resistances and practical denials of the definitions humans can give to reality. This is why, for instance, the success of Pasteurs theory on his opponent Pouchets spontaneous generation theory isnt arbitrary: Pasteur successfully passes the tests that Pouchet does not72 for instance, when the sterilizations Pasteur carries out prove effective. From this perspective, all definitions of reality arent equivalent. Their unequal values, however, shouldnt be reified or prejudged by the researcher but should, on the contrary, be understood as the result of preuves, remaining as such vulnerable to a new preuve. In other words, certain realities prove more real than others, in that they resist better the various preuves they are subjected to. For instance, if pragmatic sociology sought to provide a symmetrical analysis of the Galilean controversy between geo- and heliocentrism, it would probably demonstrate, through this analysis, that the geocentric evidence device couldnt pass (de facto, but not de jure) the tests of reality it was very systematically subjected to from the sixteenth century on.

    Taking into account both the lack of acceptability (which may border on illegitimacy) of certain arguments in public and the existence of reality tests ultimately outlines pragmatic sociologys normative orientation. This sociology stresses the importance of preuves for the collective production of truth tests and trials whereby the most established truths are verified, that is, confirmed or denied. It also highlights the need to develop public spaces where anyone can put to the test the acceptability of his/her own arguments with regard to egalitarian ideals, so as to collectively produce more justice. After all, through actions and through their ways of carrying out sociological surveys (following the actors, principle of symmetry, etc.), pragmatic sociologists express a preference for reviving critique and putting certainties to the test of their collective verification.

    How pragmatic sociology criticizes the social world

    Pragmatic sociology casts a critical eye on the social world. Yet, to do so, it is based on a conception quite different from those supported by the so-called critical sociology with regard to both sociology, social critique, and their mutual relations73. Pragmatic sociology stems precisely from the limits and impasses of the so-called

    70 Pharo (P.), Morale et sociologie, Paris, Gallimard, 2004.71 This non-relativistic stance allows L. Boltanski and L. Thvenot, for instance, to characterize the eugenic value as inherently illegitimate. (De la justification, op. cit., p. 104).72 Latour (B.), Pasteur et Pouchet : htrogense de lhistoire des sciences , in Serres (M.), ed., lments dhistoire des sciences, Paris, Bordas, 1989. See also: Lagrange (P.), Enqute sur les soucoupes volantes. La construction dun fait aux tats-Unis (1947) et en France (1951-54) , Terrain, 14, 1990; Rmy (.), Comment saisir la rumeur ? , Ethnologie franaise, 23 (4), 1993.

  • critical sociology and suggests trying out a new kind of critical engagement in sociology.

    What are these limits and impasses? It is often believed that pragmatic sociologists disagree with the so-called critical sociologists on the content of the latters critiques of the social world or on the vehemence and intensity of these critiques. This interpretation of the contrast between these two sociologies is reassuring in that it places them on a political axis, the one representing the radical pole, the other the compromising one. However, it should be noted that pragmatic sociology reproaches the so-called critical sociology not so much for its political radicalism as for its lack of sociological radicalism. In other words, critical sociology is blamed for not being able to offer an analytical viewpoint that would enable sociologists to produce a critique different from their actors, that is, for no longer being able to provide an added value to their contemporaries critical work.

    Critical sociology no doubt lost its sociological radicalism and therefore its critical originality because the societies we live in are increasingly sociological (to borrow Anthony Giddens phrase) and increasingly critical, as evidenced by the spread of the previously mentioned vocabulary of interests, strategies, symbolic domination, or inequalities. Thus the power of revelation that once gave the so-called critical sociology a prominent place in the practice of social critique has become considerably dull74.

    Based on this observation, pragmatic sociology suggests making an additional analytical and reflective effort to bring sociological analysis to the level where it can again say something other than what some actors say. This effort can be divided into three stages. 1 It starts with a survey that describes precisely what actors say and do, so as to explain their critical competences and follow the latter in situation. Throughout this survey, it is important to follow all the sides or, at least, not to a priori credit one with competences the other supposedly hasnt (principle of symmetry); furthermore, the material supports each side relies on to prove or publicly justify what it says should be described (principle of rationality). 2 Then comes an analysis of the way the studied actors competences are eased or hindered by the devices whereby they act or which leave them grappling with one another: which preuves do these devices enable? Which dont they enable? What kind of contradictions come to light? At this stage, the survey should reveal any possible asymmetries between the actors competences and capacities to rely on certain material and organizational supports to act, judge, and prove. 3 It ends or may

    73 Barthe (Y.), Lemieux (C.), Quelle critique aprs Bourdieu ? , Mouvements, 24, 2002; Trom (D.), propos de la dignit de la sociologie , Sociologie, 3 (1), 2012; Dodier (N.), Ordre, force, pluralit. Articuler description et critique autour des questions mdicales , in Haag (P.), Lemieux (C.),eds, Faire des sciences sociales, vol. 1 : Critiquer, Paris, ditions de lEHESS, 2012.74 This diagnosis echoes what certain pragmatist sociologists investigating on critical compentences in France in the mid-Nineties identified as the critique crisis (Cardon (D.), Heurtin (J.-Ph.), La critique en rgime dimpuissance , in Franois (B.), Neveu (.), eds, Espaces publics mosaques, Rennes, Presses universitaires de Rennes, 1999; Boltanski (L.), Chiapello (.), Le nouvel esprit du capitalisme, op. cit.; Parasie (S.), Une critique dsarme. Le tournant publicitaire dans la France des annes 1980 , Rseaux, 150, 2008). This term aimed to show that a political radicalism no longer empirically supported is doomed to critical inability or to a radicalism increasingly dissociated from the sociological preuve (Trom (D.), La crise de la critique sociale, vue de Paris et de Francfort , Esprit, July 2008). Thus pragmatic sociologys critical aim can be understood as an effort to ensure that the exercise of critique regains his grip of the social world.

  • end with the disclosure of the points which, if they were modified in the studied devices, would decrease actors chances of understating the importance of certain contradictions or avoiding certain preuves (which they currently do), and/or would increase their critical competences or access to certain material and organizational supports75.

    The three stages we have just distinguished for greater convenience redefine sociologys critical scope in three ways. 1 Critique of the intellectual-centrism and the intellectual powers undue claims. For the aim is, first of all, to show critiques work as it is always already there, by describing its operations and understanding it in the sociological sense (that is, without immediately criticizing it for being defective, groundless, illusory, etc.). This allows the sociologist to criticize sociologists more generally, intellectuals unjustified claim to the monopoly of the social worlds legitimate critique. 2 Critique of conservatism and of the refusal of public confrontation. For the aim is, secondly, to show how critiques work is always limited for actors because the material and organizational devices whereby they operate or oppose dont enable them to fully use their critical competences, reveal certain contradictions, and/or access certain judgment and action supports or the ways of producing some. This allows the sociologist to disagree with the actors who claim that, concerning the objects of interest to them, critique is already there and doesnt need to be done; is not (or no longer) useful; and/or that those who keep criticizing have no good reasons to do so (they are irrational, they didnt understand the guarantees they were given, etc.). As previously stated, sociologists show their preference for reviving critique and putting certainties to the test of their collective verification. 3 Critique of sociologys refusal to accept its practical consequences. For, given the analyses on an object, the aim is, finally, to suggest or at least to be able to suggest the material and organizational changes making the devices more likely to help actors deploy critique by themselves and uncover the contradictions have to deal with in practice76. This triple redefinition of sociologys critical scope stresses that a real political radicalism requires sociological radicalism, not the contrary.

    *

    All in all, do we know more about the specificity of the pragmatic style in sociology? We hope at least to have dispelled certain misunderstandings. When we focus on it, pragmatic sociology is both much more ordinary in some respects and much more original in others. It is more ordinary because a very large number of its assumptions, survey methodologies, and ambitions are anchored in the most classical sociological tradition mainly American, but also very often including continental influences, mostly Durkheimian and Weberian. Pragmatic sociology is also more

    75 See for instance the conclusions of books such as: Callon (M.), Lascoumes (P.), Barthe (Y.), Agir dans un monde incertain, op. cit.; Boltanski (L.), Chiapello (.), Le nouvel esprit du capitalisme, op. cit.; Latour (B.), Politiques de la nature, Paris, La Dcouverte, 1999; Lemieux (C.), Mauvaise presse, op. cit., or J. Stavo-Debauges article Les vices dune inconsquence conduisant limpuissance de la politique franaise de lutte contre les discriminations (published in two volumes, Carnets de Bord, 6, 2003, et 7, 2004).76 Sociologys political effect expresses itself in terms of actors empowerment and self-clarification of the critical processes in which they are involved. Such an effect derives from the preferred figure of internal critique, that is, a critique based on actors own sense of morality rather than confronting them with normative ideals unfamiliar to them, as does the figure of external critique.

  • original because, in the French context where it emerged, it challenges the most dominant sociological doxa which takes it for granted that the micro contrasts with the macro, that interest explains action, that behaviors can be deduced from dispositions, or that reality is nothing but a social construction. Pragmatic sociology is dominated in the French sociological research insofar as even respected journals regularly happen to publish the most misinformed remarks about it. Often greeted with concern and caution, its quite subversive project is readily attributed to traditional opponents better identified such as methodological individualism, idealism, anti-rationalism, or relativism, stances it is however diametrically opposed to, as shown in this paper. In this respect, this sociology is above all a critique of conservatism and of the refusal of public confrontation. It intends to carry on this fight with the social world through the way it grasps its objects of study and, in its analysis, takes into account, in its analysis, the postulates of pluralism and relative indeterminacy. But it also intends to carry it on within the professional sociology, by tackling its dominant forms of dogmatism and its almost inevitable processes of thought routinization, which openly threaten it.

    The kind of sociology discussed in this paper whether we call it pragmatic sociology or sociology of preuves is aware of its imperfections for it still is in the making. It tries to fully assess the existence of social regularities without feeling the need to mechanize action. It seeks to account for the influence of the established (institu) on practices without feeling obligated to underestimate the strength of the establishing (instituant) resulting from these very practices. It identifies with social sciences critical ambition without thinking it necessary to devaluate actors critical competences. Since we cant say where this sociology finishes, if we were to say where it begins, we should probably emphasize the double reversal of perspective whereby it continually strives to revive the sociological project: on the one hand, rather than seeing actions or social activities as the necessary result of determinism or rationality, by seeing them as the practical achievement of social obligations or shared expectations; on the other hand, by ceasing to consider classical notions such as power, interest, or domination to be explanatory resources and by considering them above all to be the observable and thus describable effects of the situations and practices in which and with regard to which each of us is engaged.

    Yannick BARTHE, Damien DE BLIC, Jean-Philippe HEURTIN, ric LAGNEAU, Cyril LEMIEUX, Dominique LINHARDT, Cdric MOREAU DE BELLAING, Catherine RMY, Danny TROM are researchers or lecturers-researchers in sociology or in political science.

    Their work spans a wide range of objects and themes. But they all agree on the methodological options advocated in this paper.

    Pragmatic Sociology: A Users GuideDuring the last thirty years, the researchers working within the orientation known as pragmatic sociology have produced a considerable amount of empirical investigations relating to all areas of social life. In accordance with the theoretical and methodological assumptions they intended to defend, they have developed significantly new ways to conduct their inquiries, to collect data, to explore their fields, to think through the cases and

  • controversies they used as entry points to explore the social order and its always problematic reproduction. The aim of this paper is to characterize by highlighting ten points the pragmatic style in sociology and to specify what are its methodological requisites and practical implications in the conduct of research.