pascal's feather bed (2009)

Upload: craig-duncan

Post on 07-Apr-2018

220 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/6/2019 Pascal's Feather Bed (2009)

    1/29

    1

    Pascals Featherbed

    Happiness, Truth, and Pragmatic Arguments for Theistic Belief

    Abstract: Recent social scientific research suggests religious belief leads to favorable

    health and happiness outcomes. This article explores whether such outcomes can justify

    adopting religious belief on pragmatic grounds; it uses as a test case Jeff Jordans recentreworking of William Jamess pragmatic argument, and concludes that this argument, for

    two reasons. First, the wager fails to consider whether the falsity of religious belief

    (should this be the case) would make any resulting happiness illusory, and thus, less

    ethically worthy. Second, the wager fails in its attempt to exclude the potential harms of

    religious belief from its decision matrix. In the course of defending these criticisms, it is

    furthermore argued that false beliefper se can lower individual well-being, and thatconsiderations of individual responsibility for the unintended effects of ones beliefs mustcomplicate any simple attempt to weigh religions benefits against its harms.

    Word count: 9355

    Recent years have seen the emergence of much fascinating social scientific research into

    the causes and consequences of religious beliefs of various types. Prominent examples of this

    research include Ronald Ingleheart and Pippa Norriss global study finding a correlation between

    religious belief and existential insecurity (the more vulnerable people of a given country are to

    health and financial threats, the higher the level of religiosity those people exhibit) (Ingleheart

    and Norris 2004); Harold Koenig, Michael McCullough and David Larsons massive study

    linking religious belief with favorable health outcomes, such as lower rates of heart attacks

    (Koenig et al. 2001); and David Sloan Wilsons evolutionary account of religious belief, which

    stresses religions utility for producing feelings of group cohesion and solidarity (Wilson 2002;

    cf. Haidt 2007). These studies suggest that religious belief has a good deal of secular utility

    that is, that it has significant beneficial consequences for human happiness in this life (as

    opposed to the afterlife). Not unexpectedly, philosophical defenders of religious belief have

    pointed approvingly to some of these studies: if religious belief enhances ones happiness in this

  • 8/6/2019 Pascal's Feather Bed (2009)

    2/29

    2

    life, these defenders ask, is that not a sufficiently good reason for attempting to inculcate

    religious belief in oneself (or to hang on to it, if one already possesses it)? That question is the

    subject of this essay.

    In fact it is a complex question, and in order to make tackling this question a more

    manageable task, I will narrow my focus to evaluating one recent defense of religious belief on

    pragmatic grounds, namely, Jeff Jordans defense of (what he calls) the Jamesian wager. The

    name is an allusion to William Jamess famous paper, The Will to Believe (James 1956) ,

    which defends the legitimacy of religious belief on account of its ability to improve ones life in

    this world. Jordan presents himself as working in the Jamesian tradition, and indeed, it is fair to

    say that Jordan is currently the leading philosophical defender of pragmatic arguments for

    theistic belief. Moreover, the Jamesian wager is the centerpiece of Jordans recent book-length

    study of pragmatic arguments for theistic belief (Jordan 2006).1

    Thus, it is a good test case for

    the prospects of pragmatic arguments that stress religions secular utility.

    In this essay, I will argue that the Jamesian wager is unsound, for two main reasons. First,

    Jordan fails to consider whether the falsity of religious belief (should this in fact be the case)

    detracts from the ethical worth of the happiness that stems from such belief (in such a case the

    happiness is an illusory happiness, one might say). The relationship between happiness and

    truth is an important issue, albeit one that has yet to be given its due in the philosophical

    literature on happiness. My discussion of this issue should thus be of interest to ethicists

    generally, not just philosophers of religion. My second reason for rejecting the Jamesian wager is

    that despite an explicit effort on his behalf to do so, Jordan fails to give adequate consideration to

    the potential harms of religious belief. I will reveal this inadequacy, and explore some of the

    1 Unless otherwise indicated, subsequent parenthetical page references will be to this work.

  • 8/6/2019 Pascal's Feather Bed (2009)

    3/29

    3

    subtleties involved in the important task ofrationally weighing religions potential harms against

    its potential benefits.

    Notwithstanding my conclusion that Jordans Jamesian argument fails, however, I do in

    this essay not go so far as to conclude that all such pragmatic arguments for theistic belief are

    bound to fail. I do not have such a powerful argument; and indeed, my criticisms of Jordans

    argument will identify potentially fruitful avenues of argument that pragmatic defenders of

    religion would be wise to explore, in order to move the debate forward.

    Pascal vs. James

    Jordan judges the Jamesian wager to be more convincing in the final analysis than

    Pascals own, much better-known wager, which defends religious belief as a rational bet to make

    given the chance that it leads to infinite happiness in the next life. While Jordan is keen to

    defend Pascals wager against what he considers to be the most important objections, he

    recognizes that many critics judge these objections to be fatal to wager. In particular, many

    philosophers invoke the so-called Many Gods objection against Pascal: these critics (for

    example, Mackie 1982, p. 203, and Martin 1983) note that as long as there is some non-zero

    chance that a deviant God exists who punishes religious believers (for being too credulous,

    say) and rewards skeptics (for their carefulness of belief, say), then in such a case non-belief

    carries a chance of infinite happiness, just as religious belief carries a chance of infinite

    happiness in the case of a more traditional god. The result is that Pascals wager ends in a

    stalemate, since both belief and non-belief each carry a chance of gaining salvation and a risk of

    losing salvation.

    Although Jordan is not himself convinced by the Many Gods objection (see his lengthy

    reply to it on pp. 73-101), he considers a chief advantage of the Jamesian wager to lie in its

  • 8/6/2019 Pascal's Feather Bed (2009)

    4/29

    4

    ability to escape the stalemate that results from adding a deviant God to the Pascalian decision

    matrix. Essentially, the Jamesian wager breaks the otherworldly tie between a deviant and

    traditional God by invoking the beneficial this-worldly consequences of traditional religious

    belief; according to Jordan, these benefits tip the decision-theoretic balance back in favor of

    religious belief.

    Before describing in some detail the structure of this alternative Jamesian wager,

    however, one final point of comparison between Pascals wager and the Jamesian wager is in

    order. In particular, I wish to note the modest ambitions of the Jamesian wager compared with

    its Pascalian predecessor. For starters, according to Jordan, the Jamesian wager applies only if a

    very specific condition obtains, namely, the arguments for and against Gods existence are fairly

    balanced in rational force, so that there is roughly an evidential tie. Additionally, the wager

    concludes only that belief in God is rationally permissible, not that it is rationally required.

    Although when laying the argument out Jordan states its conclusion simply as one should

    believe in God (p. 29), his detailed defense of it relies on a premise asserting only that it is

    rationally and morallypermissible to believe some propositionp(such as God exists) in

    certain cases where large benefits are in the offing (pp. 51 and 52, my emphasis). Hence, we

    must interpret Jordans Jamesian wager as concluding only that religious belieffor pragmatic

    reasons is rationally and morallypermissible, in the case of an evidential tie between the

    arguments for and against Gods existence.

    This is a far cry from the version ofPascals wagerthat is now canonical in the literature,

    according to which, even if there is a strong preponderance of evidence againstGods existence,

    each person still has a prudential duty, not just permission, to inculcate religious belief in himself

    or herself. This is because even if Gods existence is on balance unlikely, so long as there is at

  • 8/6/2019 Pascal's Feather Bed (2009)

    5/29

    5

    least a speck of a chance that God exists and requires theistic belief for salvation, it follows that

    theistic belief carries infinite expected utility, and thereby becomes rationally obligatory belief.

    Reflecting on the difference between this strong canonical conclusion and the much more modest

    conclusion of the Jamesian wager, I am reminded of a remark by Erasmus Darwin (Charles

    Darwins grandfather), who once referred to Unitarianism as a feather-bed to catch a falling

    Christian.2

    I am tempted to judge the Jamesian wager similarly, and refer to it as a featherbed

    for a falling Pascalianthat is, as an argument that will appeal to people who might like Pascals

    wager to be sound, but who cannot bring themselves to embrace its more grandiose ambitions

    and otherworldly focus. All the same, even the Jamesian wagers less grandiose claim that

    religious belief is morally and rationally permissible, provided the evidence for and against God

    is tied in strength, is still a grander claim that many philosophers will antecedently accept.

    Hence, it is worth exploring whether the Jamesian wager establishes its conclusion.

    The Jamesian Wager

    Key to the Jamesian wager is what Jordan calls the Next Best Thing rule (pp. 14-15).

    According to this proposed rule of rational choice, if in a case of decision under uncertainty,

    some optionxhas a best case outcome at least as good as all rival options best case ou tcomes,

    and a worst case outcome at least as good as all rival options worst case outcomes, and

    furthermore,x has better outcomes than its rivals in all other cases, then it is rational to choose x.

    In other words, in a case where options are tied at extremes, but one option is superior in all

    middle ranges, the Next Best Thing rule says to choose that option. This is quite relevant, for as

    we have seen, a decision-theoretic tie results (according to many critics of Pascals wager) from

    2 As reported by Charles Darwin. See Letter 2461of The Darwin Correspondence Project

    (http://www.darwinproject.ac.uk/darwinletters/calendar/entry-2461.html [accessed September 20, 2007]).

  • 8/6/2019 Pascal's Feather Bed (2009)

    6/29

  • 8/6/2019 Pascal's Feather Bed (2009)

    7/29

    7

    will set aside these empirical controversies for present purposes, however, in order to focus on my

    two main philosophical objections to the Jamesian wager, which I believe to be decisive against it

    in its current form.

    Before describing these two objections, however, it is worth briefly mentioning that I am

    also choosing to set aside a third possible objection. This is an objection to one of the Jamesian

    wagers conditions of application, namely, the condition that supposes there is an evidential tie

    between arguments for and against Gods existence. Jordan judges it reasonable to believe such a

    tie obtains (p. 110), but many readers will demur. Still, I believe it would be unwise of such

    readers to rest their case against the Jamesian wager on doubts regarding this supposed evidential

    tie. The question whether such an evidential tie obtains is a large question, and to answer it in a

    thorough fashion would require a time-consumingand contentiouscomparative survey of the

    most important arguments for and against Gods existence. More narrowly targeted objections to

    the Jamesian wager are preferable to this, and it such objections that I intend to defend. Thus, for

    purposes of this paper I am prepared to grant Jordan the supposition that an evidential tie obtains,

    and ask whether, given this supposition, the Jamesian wager succeeds in justifying belief in God

    despite the evidential tie.

    Prior to moving forward in this fashion, though, I do wish briefly to make one critical

    point. For we must ask which religious doctrine Jordan has in mind when he claims there exists an

    evidential tie. Jordan says theism (p. 110), which he defines this as follows: Theism is the

    proposition that God exists. Godwe will understand as that individual, if any, who is omnipotent,

    omniscient, and morally perfect (pg. 1; emphasis in the original). In other words, theism is the

    belief that the god of natural theology exists. However, even following Jordan and supposing that

    the philosophical arguments for and against this sort of divine individual are evenly balanced, we

    Comment [CD1]: Move to footnote

    Comment [CD2]: Compress or eliminate this.

  • 8/6/2019 Pascal's Feather Bed (2009)

    8/29

    8

    would have to go on to ask whether bare belief in such an individualbare belief in natural

    religion, we might sayis enough to bring with it the pragmatic health and happiness benefits

    that the Jamesian wager emphasizes.

    I doubt this. The alleged benefits of religious belief cited by the studies in question most

    likely come from immersing oneself within the richly detailed ritual, worship, community, and

    lifestyle of a revealedreligionChristianity, in the case of the majority of individuals taking

    part in the studies. If so, then the Jamesian wagerer must wager on behalf of a revealed religion.

    Given his claim that the Jamesian wager is used only in the case of an evidential tie, however,

    Jordan is thereby committed to claiming that the evidence for and against the truth of a particular

    revealed religion is evenly matched. That is a much stronger claim than the corresponding claim

    regarding the god of natural theology. For in this case, it is not simply general arguments against

    Gods existence (such as the argument from evil) that must either be defused or matched with

    opposing pro-God arguments of equal force; the same must also be done with respect to

    specifically anti-Christian arguments, such as objections to the coherence of traditional key

    doctrines such as the Trinity, the Atonement, and Original Sin; skeptical arguments that point

    toward the Bibles seeming approval of genocide, slavery, the subjugation of women, and the

    eternal punishment of non-believers; and skeptical arguments that question the reliability of the

    Bibles historical claims (see Martin 1993 for a book-length presentation of arguments such as

    these, and others). It is far from clear that these arguments can be either defused or matched with

    opposing pro-Christianity arguments of equal force, and to that extent it is far from clear whether

    the conditions of applicability for Jordans Jamesian wager in fact obtain. However, rather than

    get embroiled in theological debates specific to Christianity, in what follows I will waive this

    concern and focus on more philosophically-minded objections to the Jamesian wager.

  • 8/6/2019 Pascal's Feather Bed (2009)

    9/29

    9

    Objection 1: The Value of Fantastical Happiness

    The Threat of a Fantasy Discount

    My first philosophical objection arises from doubts about the theory of prudential

    valuethat is, the theory of personal well-being / happinessused by Jordans version of the

    Jamesian wager. The nearest Jordan comes to defining happiness occurs on page 90, where he

    writes:

    To get a grip on this complex issue [of happiness] let us adopt something like Benthams

    model of utility (duration plus intensity), stipulating that theistic belief provides more

    empirical benefit than not believing, even if no deity exists (a better this -world

    outcome), if, on average, believing theistically ranks higher than not believing theistically

    in at least one of two categories, reported satisfaction and mortality (life span), and is

    never lower in either of the two. Moreover, let us assume that happiness correlates with

    greater life satisfaction.

    While Jordan shies away from identifying happiness with feelings of life satisfaction (he says

    only that happiness correlates with these), he uses such feelings as a proxy for happiness in his

    defense of Jamesian wager: theists allegedly higher levels of life satisfaction, along with longer

    life spans, are the chief pragmatic reasons to become a theist.

    Jordans use of reported satisfaction as a key to happiness, however, is problematic. In

    saying this I have in mind more than just the suspicion that religious believers are more likely

    than non-believers to report feeling happy when in fact they are not (God loves me, so I should

    be happy; therefore, I am). Instead, I have in mind the deeper worry regarding the prudential

    worth of feelings of happiness that stem from false beliefs. In saying this I am not thereby

    declaring that theism is false; in fact, I am in no position to declare this since, as noted above, I

  • 8/6/2019 Pascal's Feather Bed (2009)

    10/29

    10

    have for purposes of this paper granted Jordans supposition that there is an evidential tie

    between the arguments for and against Gods existence. However, it is consistent with this

    supposition that theism may in fact be false, and we have seen Jordan himself recognizes in his

    key premise THIN (Theists = Happier in Naturalism, that is, are happier than non-theists in the

    case where God does not exist). Hence any full evaluation of the Jamesian wager must confront

    the important question: if theists beliefs are in fact false, do the feelings of happiness rooted in

    those beliefs lose any of their worth on account of this falsity?

    Some special terminology will enable a more precise statement of this question. I will

    henceforth refer to feelings of happiness that stem from false beliefs as fantastical happiness ,

    and to feelings of happiness that stem from true beliefs as realistic happiness. The key

    question, I submit, is whether a sophisticated value theory will discountthe prudential value of

    fantastical happiness, owing to its fantastical nature, and if so, to what extent.In other words, if

    we take two feelings of happiness quantitatively equal in terms of felt pleasure (as measured by

    the Benthamite dimensions of intensity, duration, etc.), where one feeling is fantastical in nature

    and the other realistic, is it the case that the latter contributes more to a persons well -being than

    the former, other things equal?

    I favor an answer of Yes, for there are powerful arguments against accounts of

    happiness that insist that only subjective feelings of satisfaction matter for happiness, regardless

    of whether they make any contact with reality . For instance, recall Robert Nozicks famous

    experiencemachine thought experiment, in which a machine exists that can produce for you a

    lifetime of illusory, happy experiences that you will forever mistake for reality. Should you step

    into such a machine? Nozick rightly judges you should not (Nozick 1974, pp. 42-45). Or

    consider Thomas Nagels example of a man who derives feelings of happiness from people

  • 8/6/2019 Pascal's Feather Bed (2009)

    11/29

    11

    whom he believes are friends, but who in fact ridicule him behind his back at every turn without

    him ever knowing (Nagel 1979, p. 4); are we really to judge that this treachery makes him no

    less well off at all, owing to his ignorance? These objections (the experience machine in

    particular) are well-known objections to wholly subjective accounts of happiness ; Jordans

    failure to address such objections is a serious shortcoming of his defense of the Jamesian wager.

    In response, Jordan may reply that unlike Nozick, who stipulates that the beliefs one

    acquires in an experience machine are false, the Jamesian wagerer by contrast does not know

    whether a belief in God is true or false. Thus, unlike those who would urge us to step into the

    experience machine, the Jamesian wagerer is notknowingly embracing falsehood. This is right,

    but it does let Jordan off the hook, for two reasons. First, the negative conclusion of the

    experience machine thought experiment surely does not depend entirely on the fact that those

    who enter the machine are knowingly embracing falsehood. For instance, it is easy to imagine a

    variation of the thought experiment in which a person is hooked up to the machine while asleep

    without her knowing it; as a result, she happily lives out the rest of her life in the machine with

    no way of ever recognizing she is in it. How should we regard such a persons feelings of

    happiness? Surely the same conclusion stands as in the original thought experiment: the feelings

    of happiness experienced in the machine are of less value on account of their being rooted in

    falsehood rather than reality, despite the fact that the individual is not to blame for having false

    beliefs. Thus, should the Jamesian wagerers theistic beliefs turn out to be false through no fault

    of his or her own, it stills seems that we should similarly judge the value of any felt happiness to

    be reduced on account of its stemming from falsehood.

    There is a second reason that feelings of happiness rooted in false belief are a problem for

    the Jamesian wager, even despite the supposition of an evidential tie for and against Gods

  • 8/6/2019 Pascal's Feather Bed (2009)

    12/29

    12

    existence. This isbecause by Jordans own admission, recall, the key test case for the Jamesian

    wager is the case of naturalismJordans word for the state of affairs in which no god of any

    sort exists. The case of naturalism is key, I earlier explained, because the two non-naturalistic

    cases considered in the decision matrixnamely, the case of a god who rewards religious belief

    and a god who rewards non-belieflead to exactly opposite outcomes in terms of salvation, and

    hence to a decision-theoretic tie. As a result, the case of naturalism is the crucial tie-breaking

    case. Hence the importance of Jordans own key premise THIN, noted earlier, which explicitly

    asserts that theistic belief has an outcome better than the other available alternatives if

    naturalism obtains (p. 28). This means that even though the Jamesian wagerer is not knowingly

    embracing falsehood, the Jamesian wagerer is doing this: in order to break the decision-theoretic

    tie regarding salvation he or she is looking to feelings of this-worldly happiness produced by

    religious belief and deeming them to be valuable, despite the fact that these feelings stem

    ultimately from beliefs that are acknowledged to be false on the hypothesis of naturalism. In

    other words, the Jamesian wagerers attitude can be summarized as follows: Given the

    evidential tie, I do not know whether my religious beliefs are true or false, but even if they are

    false, they have still contributed to my happiness in this world, and that is reason enough to keep

    such beliefs. Hence, the Jamesian wagerer, despite his or her official judgment that an

    evidential tie obtains regarding Gods existence, is all the same committed to asserting the

    positive value of feelings of happiness that are rooted in false belief.

    This fact is quite significant, for inasmuch as the Jamesian wager looks to fantastical

    happiness to tip the scales in favor of religious belief, it follows that a sizeable enough

    discountcall it the fantasy discountwill doom Jordans argument. After all, even if, prior

    to any fantasy discount, the size (and hence, the prima facie value) of religious believers

  • 8/6/2019 Pascal's Feather Bed (2009)

    13/29

    13

    fantastical happiness appears greater than the value of non-believers realistic happiness, it may

    be that in terms of prudential value, the non-believers happiness in fact outweighs the believers

    sort once a plausible discount owing to falsehood is assessed against the believers happiness. In

    such an event, the Next Best Thing rule would instruct the Jamesian wagerer to choose, not

    theistic belief, but non-beliefexactly the opposite of Jordans desired result!

    Moreover, this non-theistic result can follow even when the discounting function in

    question assumes a modest form. All that is required is that the fantasy discount lower the

    positive prudential value of the fantastical happiness by enough to wipe out the initial, prima

    facie advantage this happiness enjoyed in quantity. Hence, given that Jordans conclusion

    regarding the happiness advantage of theistic belief over non-belief is a modestone (With

    regard to happiness, then, there is sufficient evidence that believing theistically outranks not

    believing, at least slightly [p. 91; emphasis added]), it follows that the fantasy discount likewise

    need only be slight in order to push the Jamesian wager into an endorsement of non-belief.

    Does Falsity Matter Per Se?

    So far my case for a fantasy discount has rested on two thought experiments: a modified

    experience machine scenario (in which the machines resident is put there by others while

    asleep), and Nagels scenario in which false friends mock a person behind his back.

    Interestingly, both these cases are cases in which a person is harmed by others intentional

    doings. This leaves an opening for a possible response by Jordan, since the Jamesian wagerer,

    should his or her theistic beliefs turn out to be false, need not be the unwitting dupe of others

    nefarious shenanigans. Unlike the cases just mentioned, there is no guilty party responsible for

    the falsehood. This is relevant, for one might wonder whether in such cases the value discount

    applies in virtue of the person in question being a victim of others; that is, perhaps in such cases

  • 8/6/2019 Pascal's Feather Bed (2009)

    14/29

    14

    our disinclination to fully credit the individuals feelings of happiness lies in our recognition of

    the situations injustice, rather than in our knowledge of the falsity ofthe individuals beliefs.

    Accordingly, an important follow-up question is whether mere falsity of belief is by itself

    sufficient to trigger any discounting function. Unfortunately for the Jamesian wagerer, an

    example suggests to me that the answer to this is Yes, slightly. For instance, I can recall my

    elation on the day of the U.S. presidential elections in 2000 when shortly after the polls closed in

    the evening, the television networks called the election for Al Gore. Of course, these networks

    calls were soon thereafter retracted, beginning the long phase of political limbo that eventually

    resulted in George W. Bush obtaining the Presidency. Looking back now at my earlier elation, I

    do not think to myself, Oh well, at least I got some high value happy feelings out of my

    mistaken beliefs. Instead, the pleasures seem rather hollow, almost as if they were elements of

    a cruel hoax.

    Admittedly, this is a retrospective judgment of mine that is made in full awareness of the

    falsity of my past belief in Gores victory. This feature, Jordan might insist, makes such a case

    dissimilar to the Jamesian wager, in which (in this world, at least!) a theist never learns either

    way of the truth value of his or her belief in God. To make the cases more analogous, we might

    suppose counterfactually that the TV network calls of a Gore victory triggered in me an ecstasy

    that in turn caused a fatal brain aneurysm a few minutes later, so that I never learned of the

    electoral mix-up. Jordan could then point out that in such a case my relatives might really have

    said something like Well, at least he died with a smile on his face, which suggests that my

    feelings of happiness indeed had some value for me. This is so, but not relevant; the relevant

    question is whether these feelings possess as much value as they would have possessed had,

    contrary to fact, my belief in a Gore victory been true. I think the answer here is No, for in the

  • 8/6/2019 Pascal's Feather Bed (2009)

    15/29

    15

    actual case of the electoral mix-up there would presumably be a bittersweet element to my

    relatives claim that he died with a smilea bittersweet element that would not be present had

    Gore actually won and my feelings of happiness been realistic ones.

    These reflections suggest that the true or falsity of ones beliefs per se is relevant to the

    worth possessed by any feelings of happiness those beliefs occasion. And indeed, the relevance

    of beliefs truth valueper se to personal well-being is acknowledged by leading theorists of

    personal well-being. For example, although G. E. Moore and James Griffin do not explicitly call

    for a fantasy discount, theirbrief remarks about the positive value of personal experiences

    rooted in true belief are consistent with such a discount (Griffin 1986, p. 9; Moore 1993, pp. 244-

    47 [sections 118-119]). More explicitly, L. W. Sumner has written a book-length treatise

    defending a conception of well-being as authentic happiness; on this conception, happiness

    (which Sumner understands as satisfaction with ones life) maximally contributes to a persons

    well-being provided it meets both an information requirement and an autonomy requirement

    (Sumner 1996, p. 172).3

    Significant for our purposes is the fact that the information requirement

    identifies illusory happiness (i.e. happiness rooted in false belief) as inauthentic, and thus

    typically of less value to ones well-being. It is true that owing to a general stance of anti-

    paternalism, Sumner himself is reluctant to declare that each victim of fantastical happiness is

    rationally required to discount (retrospectively) the prudential value of that happiness; he wishes

    to let each individual determine the appropriate discount himself or herself (ibid., pp. 160-161).

    If Sumner is right, this variability complicates my objection to the Jamesian wager but does not

    3Regarding the autonomy requirement, Sumner argues that a persons judgments of life satisfaction, to be

    constitutive of well-being, should not be distorted by an adaptation to oppression, exploitation, indoctrination, or

    other autonomy-subverting mechanisms (Sumner 1996., pp. 167-171). Although this requirement is indeed

    relevant to the question of religious beliefs contribution to individual well-being (think for instance of religious

    indoctrination), it is not a topic I will pursue here.

  • 8/6/2019 Pascal's Feather Bed (2009)

    16/29

    16

    defeat it; it is sufficient for my purposes that individuals will typically choose at least a modest

    discount.

    Manufactured Happiness

    Indeed, there is a further problem, beyond merely failing to meet Sumners information

    requirement, with the sort of happiness valued by the Jamesian wagera problem that itself stems

    from a conception of authentic happiness much like Sumners. For consider that the happiness-

    producing religious beliefs recommended by the Jamesian wager are not just false (in the relevant

    case of naturalism); they are also willfully self-induced by the wagererand what is more,

    willfully self-induced in order to gain access to the feelings of happiness in question. We might

    say that the feelings in question are willfully manufacturedby agent himself. This artificiality

    surely puts them in tension with Sumners ideal of authenticity, and hence an approach such as his

    that defines well-being as authentic happiness should recommend discounting such feelings value.

    To see this point, consider a manletscall him Twenty-First Century Alwho

    possesses some evidence that he is related to, and just as much evidence that he is notrelated to,

    the first king of England, Alfred the Great. In other words, Twenty-First Century Al is in an

    evidential tie. However, finding the prospect of this illustrious heritage to be a source of personal

    esteem, inspiration, and satisfactionthat is, a source of feelings of happinessAl mentally

    assents to the proposition that he is a descendent of Alfred, and acts on the assumption it is true

    (say, by going on treks to historical sites associated with Alfred, immersing himself in Alfredian

    lore, filling his house with Alfredian memorabilia, seeking out others who believe themselves to be

    descendents of Alfred, and so on). Eventually, he comes to believe he is genuinely a descendent of

    Alfred. (This two-step process, of (1) assenting to a proposition and then (2) acting on the

  • 8/6/2019 Pascal's Feather Bed (2009)

    17/29

    17

    assumption it is true, is the belief-inducing technology that Jordan himself recommends by way

    of producing theistic belief in oneself over a span of time [p. 56].)

    Is there not still something inferior about the value of the happiness that Twenty-First

    Century Al derives from his lifes pursuit, compared with other possible pursuits he might have

    embraced? Is he really as well-off with this life project as he would have been with some

    alternative project that generated feelings of happiness whose realistic nature is not in doubt? I

    do not think so. After all, while Als feelings of happiness are not as artificial as they would be

    had he knowingly self-induced a false belief, surely it is problematic that he is willing to stake a

    central project of his life on what by his own admission is just as likely as notto turn out to be a

    fantasy. This shows that he does not value staying in touch with reality as highly as he ought. To

    that extent, the manufactured feelings of happiness central to his life possesses an inauthentic

    natureeven an escapist taintand hence (I suggest), they must be discounted in their

    prudential value. To deny this is to come dangerously close to approving of making a drug of

    ones faculty of belief. We might say that even though Jordan explicitly turns his back on Marx

    (p. 94), he unwittingly, and ironically, comes close to endorsing religion as the opium of the

    people (Marx 1977, p. 64).

    Avoiding the Fantasy Discount: Religion as Medicine?

    Of course, it is not always wrong to take drugscertainly not when one is sick, for

    instance, and here the alleged health benefits of religious belief mentioned earlier are relevant. We

    might say that within a pragmatic argument that emphasizes health benefits, religion is still akin to

    a drug, but akin to a therapeutic drug rather than a recreational drug. Let us refer a form of the

    wager that emphasizes objective health benefits (such as a reduced rate of heart disease and the

    like), as opposed to higher levels of reported life satisfaction, as the medicalized Jamesian

  • 8/6/2019 Pascal's Feather Bed (2009)

    18/29

    18

    wager.4

    I believe this to be the strongest form of the Jamesian wager. After all, it is one thing to

    focus on feelings of happiness and endorse religion as the opium of the people; by contrast, it

    seems at least a bit less scandalous to endorse religion as, say, the Lipitor of the people! (Lipitor

    is common cholesterol-reducing drug; indeed, it is the worlds best-selling drug.5)

    The medicalized wagers focus on alleged health benefits of religion, then, may help to

    blunt the worries raised in the previous sub-sections regarding whether a discounting function is

    to be applied to fantastical happiness. For if a persons religious beliefs lead to better health, this

    may enable him or her to continue to experience sources of realistic happiness in other parts of

    his or her life (feelings of happiness that stem from intimate relationships, career success,

    worthwhile hobbies, etc.) longer than he or she otherwise would. I cannot see any justification

    for discounting the value ofthese further feelings of realistic happiness simply on account of

    their causal dependence, of an indirect kind, on false religious beliefs. The falsehood seems too

    distant in the causal chain, so to speak, to generate a discount.

    And yet despite the superiority of the medicalized wagersfocus on religions alleged

    health benefits, as compared with its alleged happiness benefits, even this version of the

    Jamesian wager will face at least two objections. First, one may object that the alleged health

    benefits of religion cannot in fact be cleanly separated from its alleged happiness benefits. For

    we must ask why, if in fact religious belief leads to health benefits, it has this effect. After all, if

    the health benefits are due simply to a healthy life style or to a supportive social network, then

    these benefits are available to non-believers too. Thus, if religious beliefs have a genuine health

    advantage that is inaccessible to non-believers, is it likely owing to the feelings of comfort and

    4For a discussion of religious believers rates of heart disease, see Koenig et al. 2001, pp. 231-249.

    5Peter Loftis, Pfizer Lipitor Patent Reissue Rejected, The Wall Street Journal (August 16, 2007), available at

    http://online.wsj.com/article/SB118730255664700229.html [accessed December 10, 2007].

  • 8/6/2019 Pascal's Feather Bed (2009)

    19/29

    19

    confidencethat is, the feelings of happinessthat such beliefs generate. But this simply returns

    us to the earlier claim, allegedly left behind by this improved version of the Jamesian Wager, that

    religious belief is valuable insofar as it produces feelings of happiness .

    Even waiving this worry, though, and supposing that (owing to a boost in health)

    religious belief does indeed increase a persons expected well-being all things considered, the

    medicalized Jamesian Wager still faces a second objection, one more powerful than the first

    objection just considered. For even if religious belief were to increase a persons expected well-

    being, it would be premature to conclude that this person has reason all-toldto inculcate

    religious belief in himself or herself. Such a conclusion would be premature, since we must first

    confront the question of the reason-giving force of first-person judgments of well-being.After

    all, reasons that stem from ones own well-being are not always reasons with overriding force.

    Most obviously, morality can demand that one accept sacrifices of personal well-being; I will

    address this issue in the next section of this essay. Additionally,perfectionistideals of human

    excellence can recommend sacrifices of well-being.6

    Climbing a mountain or pursuing an artistic

    vision or tending to a sick relative is not always good for ones health. And this leads straight

    into my second reservation regarding a Jamesian wager that focuses on the alleged health

    benefits of religious belief.

    Return to the case of Twenty-First Century Al, and suppose that peoples beliefs in an

    illustrious heritage were statistically linked to gains in health (owing to a comforting boost in

    self-esteem, say). Would that genuinely give Al adequate reason, all-things-considered, to induce

    6 It is common to distinguish individual perfection (i.e. human excellence) from individual well-being. See for

    instance Kant 1996, pp. 517-520 (pp. 385-388, vol. 6, in the Prussian Academy Edition pagination); Sumner 1996,

    p. 19; and Hurka 1993, p. 17. (But see Toner 2006 for a critique of this distinction. Needless to say, the less

    distinction there is between human excellence and human well-being, the more problems there are for the Jamesian

    wager.)

  • 8/6/2019 Pascal's Feather Bed (2009)

    20/29

    20

    in himself the belief that he is related to Alfred the Great? Even if it turns out that we ought not

    to discount the genuine contribution to Als well -being made by any increase in health that stems

    from his genealogical beliefs, we can surely wonder whether his life now displays less human

    excellence inasmuch as he deliberately has placed at the center of his life beliefs that by his own

    lights lack even a preponderance of evidence in their favor, and hence are just as likely to be

    false as they are to be true. We ought to worry that if indeed he has purchased a greater quantity

    of life, then it has come at an unacceptable cost in quality. Surely the same worry ought to apply

    to the religious believer. If so, then a complete argument for the Jamesian wager would either

    have to rebut this perfectionist objection or argue that the gain in expected well-being occasioned

    by religious belief (if indeed there is such a gain) ought to trump the loss of excellence that

    concomitantly occurs.

    A Possible Response

    I will end this section by exploring a possible response Jordan can make to my objection

    based on worries regarding fantastical happiness. This response points once again to the

    supposition of an evidential tie between the evidence for and against Gods existence, and argues

    that given this parity, the same issues of fantastical happiness that I allege afflict the theist will

    also afflict the atheist. For like the theist, the atheists belief that there is no God is just as likely

    to be false as it is true; therefore, any happiness that stems from the atheists belief that there is

    no God runs the same risk of being subjected to a fantasy discount. Hence, my objection tells as

    much against atheism as it does against theism.7

    This is correct: on the supposition of an evidential tie, my objection does entail that one

    should not seek to derive ones happiness from atheism-related beliefs and activities. This

    7 Jeff Jordan, personal communication (July 2009).

  • 8/6/2019 Pascal's Feather Bed (2009)

    21/29

    21

    observation, however, fails to rescue the Jamesian wager from my objection, for two reasons.

    First, my objection yields a negative conclusion, namely, that Jordans pragmatic case for theistic

    belief fails. It does not aim to establish the positive conclusion that one has pragmatic reason to

    inculcate atheistic belief in oneself. Indeed, given the supposition of an evidential tie for and

    against Gods existence, the rational response is surely not atheism, but rather agnosticism.

    Second, in any case most atheists do notlocate their happiness in their atheistic beliefssay, by

    participating in atheistic practices that play the role in their lives that theistic practices (for

    instance, worship) play in the lives of theists. Instead, atheists typically find their happiness

    elsewhere, in human relationships, career pursuits, community service, political activism,

    interesting hobbies, and the like. In short, to warn against trying to find happiness through theism,

    as I am doing, is not ipso facto to recommend that one try to find happiness through atheism.

    Objection 2: Religions Social Harms

    Avoiding Harm: The Non-Dogmatic Matrix

    My second main objection to the Jamesian wager calls into question whether the Next

    Best Thing rulethe proposed principle of rational choice at the heart of Jordans Jamesian

    wagerleads to an endorsement of religious belief even assuming a subjective theory of well-

    being and no fantasy discount (that is, even assuming my first main objection is wrong-headed).

    For Jordan rather blithely dismisses the possibility that religious belief might lead to greater

    societal harms than non-belief, by claiming that social science has not proven religious belief to

    be a net harm to society (pp. 94-95). Though Jordan does not himself canvas potential social

    harms of religious belief, a reasonable list of possibilities would include religious war and

    terrorism, religious bigotry, misogyny, homophobia, apathy about this-worldly suffering, anti-

    intellectualism, support for authoritarian politicians, prudish judgmentalism, rigid orthodoxy in

  • 8/6/2019 Pascal's Feather Bed (2009)

    22/29

    22

    place of human individuality, and an excessive zeal for moral condemnation and retributive

    punishment.

    Of course, it is trueand importantthat there are forms of compassionate religious

    belief that oppose all these harms. Moreover, I agree with Jordan that social science has certainly

    not proven that, owing to such harms, religious belief on the whole generates less societal well-

    being than non-belief. All the same, the potential social harms of religion deserve more attention

    than Jordan gives them. At the very least, in a case of decision under uncertainty (such as the

    Jamesian wager), potential societal harms like these ought to be included in any decision matrix

    as possible outcomes of widespread religious belief. There is surely no rule of rational choice

    that tells us simply to leave out of our decision matrix, in a choice under uncertainty, all those

    possible outcomes for which one lacks rigorous statistical evidence. But, of course, including

    these bad outcomes as possibilities would mean that the Next Best Thing rule no long applies

    (since it would no longer be the case that the various possible this-worldly outcomes of religious

    belief are all superior to the various possible this-worldly outcomes of non-belief). The Jamesian

    wager would be deprived of its key support.8

    As best I can tell, Jordans only explicit response to this is a brieftu quoque argument:

    Atheism was the official creed of the Soviet Union and still is of China. Do we tote the many

    millions murdered in those regimes to atheism, or to communism, or to both? (p. 95). This is a

    puzzling response. Even if atheism did cause these harms, all that follows is that we need to

    include such harms in the relevant decision matrix as potential negative effects of atheism. It

    8I have here assumed that possible social benefits and harms are relevant to the question of whether, a ll things

    considered, one ought to inculcate theistic belief in oneself. This is to assume that the Jamesian wager is more than

    merely a prudential wager. Jordan himself would agree; his thesis is thatall things considered, one has reason to

    inculcate religious belief in oneself, and he defends the notion of all things considered rationality which

    adjudicates conflicts between epistemic, prudential, and moral reasonsagainst charges that the notion is incoherent

    (pp. 61-63).

  • 8/6/2019 Pascal's Feather Bed (2009)

    23/29

    23

    does notfollow that there is no need to include in the matrix any potential negative effects of

    religion. So what does Jordan have in mind with this reply? The idea seems to be that if religion

    has social harms, well, the same can be said of atheism, so that for all we know there is at least a

    decision-theoretic tie in this regard, if not an outright victory for theism. This tie is then to be

    broken by reference to personal health and happiness benefits, where Jordan thinks theism is

    clearly superior to atheism.

    This is hardly sufficient, however. To begin with, even at the personal level religion can

    cause harm: excessive feelings of guilt, a disabling fear of hell, rigid orthodoxy of thought,

    sexual repression, a puritanical aversion to pleasure, acceptance of subordinate gender roles,

    anxiety at the unknown, and so on. Moreover, even at the level of socialharms, Jordans tu

    quoque argument is lacking. Consider again the case of atheistic communism. With its quasi-

    religious faith in the historical inevitability of communism, as well as its unrealistic account of

    human nature, communist ideology was hardly an exemplar of the sort of critical thinking

    recommended by modern atheistic philosophers. In practice, moreover, the ideology of

    communist regimes became a totalizing dogma that discouraged critical thinking. Thus it is a

    mistake to lay the harms perpetrated by such regimes at the feet of atheists generally.

    Of course, there is an analogue of this reply in the case of religion. In response to any

    invocation of the possible social harms (as well as possible personal harms), Jordan can, and

    should, reply (1) that it is only particular types of religious belief that lead to the social and

    personal harms in question, namely, the dogmatic and exclusionary types of religious belief; and

    (2) that this sort of irrational belief is forbidden by the Jamesian wagers respect for rationality

    (as shown by its insistence on the need for an evidential tie before approving of pragmatic

    belief). Thus, if the non-theist wishes to distance herself from the abuses of Stalin, Pol Pot, etc.,

  • 8/6/2019 Pascal's Feather Bed (2009)

    24/29

    24

    by labeling her option in the decision matrix as non-dogmatic non-theism, then Jordan can

    respond by labeling his favored option as non-dogmatic theism. Let us refer to a matrix with

    options labeled in this way as theNon-Dogmatic Matrix. In essence, Jordan can claim that the

    Non-Dogmatic Matrix avoids the issue of the social and personal harms of religion, thereby

    rebutting the objection of this section. With these social harms out of the way, he can then claim

    that the Next Best rule favors non-dogmatic theism on account of its pragmatic benefits.

    An appeal to the Non-Dogmatic Matrix has some merit. In any case, moreover, it is a

    good thing if the Jamesian wager explicitly endorses only a non-dogmatic sort of religious belief,

    thus ensuring that the wager cannot be hijacked by religious fundamentalists. That said, this

    response is not without its costs. For at least two reasons, making use of the Non-Dogmatic

    Matrix ends up significantly weakening the Jamesian wagers force. Briefly, the first reason

    alleges that even non-dogmatic religious belief aids and abets dogmatic religious belief; the

    second reason alleges that a shift to non-dogmatic religious belief may sacrifice some of the

    health benefits of religious belief that Jordan touts. I will discuss each of these reasons in turn.

    A First Problem with the Non-Dogmatic Matrix: Legitimizing Non-Evidential Belief

    The first reason arises from the fact, we might say, that Jordan recommends believing

    beyond the evidence (my phrase; by it I mean that he recommends believing in a proposition

    that does not enjoy a preponderance of evidence in its favor). It is true that Jordan does not

    recommend believing againstthe evidence (as he would if he recommended belief in God

    even when the preponderance of evidence leans against this); indeed, he counsels against such

    belief (see pp. 47-53). However, the worry still arises that Jordans weakening of the link

    between evidence and belief will have the problematic effect of aiding and abetting dogmatic

    religious belief. After all, encouraging belief on the basis of faiththat is, belief beyond the

  • 8/6/2019 Pascal's Feather Bed (2009)

    25/29

    25

    evidencecan have the effect, whether intended or not, of discouraging critical rational thought

    in others. (These others may not bother to distinguish believing beyond the evidence, of which

    Jordan approves, from believing against the evidence, of which Jordan disapproves.) This in

    turn, can help to create a faith-friendly cultural milieu in which it is easier for uncritical dogmas

    to flourish and gain adherents.

    By contrast with non-dogmatic theism, non-dogmatic non-theism, by refusing to believe

    in God absent a preponderance of evidence, if anything strengthens rather than weakens the link

    between belief and evidence. Thus unlike non-dogmatic theism, non-dogmatic non-theism does

    not run the risk of unintentionally bestowing cultural legitimacy on faith-based dogmatic belief.

    Hence this potential social harm must be included in the Non-Dogmatic Matrix as a possible

    effect of theism rather than non-theism. But in virtue of running a risk that its rival option does

    not run, it is no longer the case that theism always yields a better outcome in this world than non-

    theism. Hence the Next Best Thing rule no longer applies, and thus can no longer be used to

    single out theism as the favored alternative within the Non-Dogmatic Matrix.

    Perhaps Jordan might at this point reply with an analogy: A society such as our own , in

    which social drinking of alcohol is culturally legitimate, will probably produce more alcoholics

    than a society whose dominant cultural norms disapprove of any use of alcohol. However, we do

    not typically blame moderate social drinkers for creating a cultural milieu in which alcoholism

    can flourish. Likewise, within the Non-Dogmatic Matrix we should not list as a possible outcome

    of moderate theism the social harm of creating a cultural milieu in which dogmatism can

    flourish. It is unfair to blame non-dogmatic theism for the irresponsible behavior of dogmatic

    theists, just as it would be unfair to blame moderate social drinkers for the irresponsible behavior

    of alcohol abusers.

  • 8/6/2019 Pascal's Feather Bed (2009)

    26/29

    26

    This analogy is interesting, but two shortcomings render it less than fully persuasive.

    First, consider that if hardcore gin aficionados, say, had armies that they sent to war against

    hardcore vodka aficionados, or hardcore beer lovers flew planes into the skyscrapers of hardcore

    wine lovers, or hardcore scotch drinkers fielded authoritarian political candidates, and so on, then

    we might really have to rethink our moral approval of moderate social drinking. Secondly, to

    make use of this analogy by way of defending the Non-Dogmatic Matrix is to import

    considerations of responsibility into the Non-Dogmatic Matrix; it is to moralize the matrix and

    thereby depart significantly from the consequentialist framework that decision theory employs.

    That may be the correct thing to do, but it simply shows how much more work remains to be

    done before the Jamesian wager is persuasive.

    A Second Problem with the Non-Dogmatic Matrix: Less dogma, less comfort?

    I have a second reason for doubting the strategy of appealing to the Non-Dogmatic

    Matrix to avoid the issue of the potential social harms of religion. It is this: even if this strategy

    is right that it is chiefly dogmatism that produces the social harms of religious belief, by the same

    token it may be that it is dogmatism, alas, that produces many of the health and happiness

    benefits of religious belief. Suppose, for instance, that these health and happiness benefits stem

    mainly from the comfort and confident hope that religious belief provides. If so, it may in turn be

    the case that the more immune to doubt ones faith is, the more comfort and confident hope one

    derives from it, and thus the more pronounced are its health and happiness effects. Of course, if

    dogmatic religious belief leads to the types of personal harms mentioned earlier (a disabling fear

    of hell, Puritanism, etc.), then these harms may offset the health benefits of comfort and

    confident hope; the empirical issues are undoubtedly complicated. The social scientific studies

  • 8/6/2019 Pascal's Feather Bed (2009)

    27/29

    27

    relied on by Jordan (e.g. Koenig, et al., 2001), however, do not attempt to distinguish between

    dogmatic and non-dogmatic belief.

    By contrast, some careful social scientific research does try to distinguish these forms of

    belief; it finds greater health benefits associated with religious certainty as opposed to more

    open-ended types of religious belief. Important research conducted by C. D. Batson, P. A.

    Schoenrade, and W. L. Ventis, for instance, distinguishes a quest dimension of religious belief

    and an intrinsic end dimension, a distinction that approximates the non-dogmatic / dogmatic

    distinction employed above. These researchers conclude that

    [t]he intrinsic end dimension ispositively associated with reports of (1) greater absence

    of illness, (2) more appropriate social behavior, (3) greater freedom from worry (but not

    guilt), (4) greater personal competence and control, and (5) greater unification and

    organization, but not with (6) greater self-acceptance or (7) greater open-mindedness and

    flexibility. The quest dimension is positively associated with (1) greater open-

    mindedness and flexibility and, possibly, with (2) greater personal competence and

    control and (3) greater self-acceptance, but not with (4) greater absence of illness or (5)

    greater freedom from worry (Batson et al. 1993, pp. 290-91; emphasis added).

    In short, it may well be that in rejecting dogmatism and thereby avoiding the potential social

    harms of religious belief one also sacrifices many significant potential health benefits. Absent

    strong evidence of significant pragmatic benefits, however, the Jamesian wager surely fails, for

    the inculcation process that the wager recommends (assenting to a proposition and using it as a

    premise in ones practical deliberation) is doubtless long, not always easy, and (as I earlier

    noted) is arguably at odds with important perfectionist values. It would surely be irrational to

    shoulder such a task for very modest and uncertain expected gains.

    Comment [CD3]: Explain the meaning of this

  • 8/6/2019 Pascal's Feather Bed (2009)

    28/29

    28

    Conclusion

    I believe these two objectionsthat happiness rooted in false beliefs is worth less than

    happiness rooted in reality, and that the potential social harms of religious belief cannot be

    ignoredreveal Jordans defense of the Jamesian wager to be seriously incomplete at best. If the

    Jamesian wager is indeed a featherbed for falling Pascalians, it has some significant lumps still in

    need of smoothing out. Let me be clear, however: I have concluded only that Jordans argument in

    favor of the moral and rational permissibility of religious belief fails in its current form. This, of

    course, is distinct from positively concluding that religious belief is always both morally and

    prudentially impermissible, all things considered. I do not claim to have shown this, and I doubt

    whether it is even true. I suspect such permissions will depend, in a much more nuanced way than

    the Jamesian wager envisions, on a host of contextual features that vary from individual to

    individual. I leave the task of exploring such contextual features to another day; let me here simply

    adduce two points, one positive and one negative, by way of suggesting what I have in mind. The

    positive point is this: if inculcating religious faith represents the best chance of bringing a person

    back from the brink of suicide, say, or from a life-ruining addiction, then I would agree that such

    an individual has sufficient reason all-told to adopt a religious faith, at least until the dangers have

    significantly abated. The negative point asks about the source of the suffering that leads

    individuals to seek consolation in religion. Does this suffering stem from injustices prevailing in

    the individuals society, so that religion is, in another ofMarxs famous phrases, the sigh of the

    oppressed creature (Marx 1977, p. 64)? If so, then even if consoling religious belief should turn

    out to be pragmatically justified as a coping mechanism, it is surely only a second-best response;

    the best response is for citizens collectively to remove the injustices that are the source of such

    suffering.

  • 8/6/2019 Pascal's Feather Bed (2009)

    29/29

    29

    In essence, then, this essay is a plea for complexity: the questions of whether one has

    prudential reason to inculcate religious belief in oneself, and how those reasons combine with

    other reasons one has (moral and epistemic), are complicated questions. The Jamesian wager is

    too simple an answer.

    REFERENCES

    Batson, C. D., P. A. Schoenrade, and W. L. Ventis 1993:Religion and the Individual: A Social-

    Psychological Perspective. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Griffin, James 1986: Well-Being: Its Meaning, Measurement, and Moral Importance. Oxford:

    Clarendon Press.

    Haidt, Jonathan 2007: Moral Psychology and the Misunderstanding of Religion .

    http://www.edge.org/3rd_culture/haidt07/haidt07_index.html [accessed July 2009].Hurka, Thomas 1993: Perfectionism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Ingleheart, Ronald and Pippa Norris 2004. Sacred and Secular: Religion and Politics Worldwide.

    Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    James, William 1956 [1896]: The Will to Believe, in his The Will to Believe and Other Essays.

    New York: Dover Publications, pp. 1-31.

    Jordan, Jeff 2006:Pascals Wager: Pragmatic Arguments and Belief in God. Oxford: OxfordUniversity press.

    Kant, Immanuel 1999 [1797]: The Metaphysics of Morals, pp. 353-604 in Mary J. Gregor, ed.

    and trans., Practical Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Koenig, Harold, Michael McCullough and David Larson 2001: Handbook of Religion and

    Health. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Mackie, J. L. 1982: The Miracle of Theism. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Marx, Karl 1977 [1844]: Toward a Critique of Hegels Philosophy of Right: Introduction, in

    David McLellan (ed.), Karl Marx: Selected Writings. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Martin, Michael 1983: Pascals Wager as an Argument for Not Believing in God.Religious

    Studies 19, pp. 57-64.

    -------------- 1993: The Case Against Christianity. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.

    Moore, G. E. 1993 [1903]: Principia Ethica, rev. ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Nagel, Thomas 1979: Death in hisMortal Questions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Nozick, Robert 1974:Anarchy, State, and Utopia. Malden, MA: Basic Books.

    Sloan, Richard P. 2006:Blind Faith: The Unholy Alliance of Religion and Medicine . New York:

    St. Martins Press.

    Sumner, L. W. 1996: Welfare, Happiness, and Ethics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Toner, Christopher 2006: Aristotelian Well-Being: A Response to L. W. Sumners Critique.

    Utilitas 18, pp. 218-231.

    Wilson, David Sloan 2002:Darwins Cathedral: Evolution, Religion, and the Nature of Society .

    Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.