overcoming the human conditionlnu.diva-portal.org/smash/get/diva2:1463367/fulltext01.pdf · 2020....

31
Overcoming the Human Condition An Arendtian analysis of the antipolitical tendencies in transhumanism Master Thesis Author: Alexander Hjelm Supervisor: Henrik Enroth Examiner: Mats Sjölin Term: Spring 2020 Subject: Political Science Level: Master Thesis, 30 hp Course code: 5SK30E

Upload: others

Post on 10-Feb-2021

3 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • Overcoming the Human Condition An Arendtian analysis of the antipolitical

    tendencies in transhumanism

    Master Thesis

    Author: Alexander Hjelm

    Supervisor: Henrik Enroth

    Examiner: Mats Sjölin

    Term: Spring 2020

    Subject: Political Science

    Level: Master Thesis, 30 hp

    Course code: 5SK30E

  • Abstract

    This article critically analyses transhumanism, an ideological movement that

    advocates the radical biomodification of the human body in order to overcome our

    deficiencies and progress towards our next phase in evolution. Following previous

    criticism against the depoliticization within transhumanism, the article will aim to

    highlight the difficulty within transhumanism to balance the respect for diversity

    against the imperative for human enhancement. This paper then turns to the political

    theory of Hannah Arendt as the theoretical lens to highlight the source of this tension

    as the ideology’s reductive view of politics. The paper concludes on the difficulties

    reconciling diversity with human enhancement, as well as raising awareness of the

    possibility of conscious action in concert related to the use of biomodification

    technologies advocated by transhumanists.

    Key words

    transhumanism, Arendt, depoliticization, action, diversity, political philosophy,

    human enhancement

  • Acknowledgments

    I would like to thank my supervisor Henrik Enroth for his continued support and

    guidance throughout the process of writing this thesis.

  • Table of contents

    Abstract 2

    Acknowledgments 3

    1 Introduction 1

    2 Transhumanism: enhancing the individual and remedying our deficiencies 3

    3 Critics against transhumanism 7

    3.1 The comparison with eugenics 8

    3.2 Dévédec: The anthropology of deficiency 9

    4 Beyond depoliticization 11

    5 Hannah Arendt’s The Human Condition 13

    6 Fabricating human beings for the future 15

    7 The freedom found in action 19

    8 Conclusions 23

    References 25

  • 1(27)

    1 Introduction

    “[The] future man, [with altered size, shape, and function], whom the

    scientists tell us they will produce in no more than a hundred years, seems to

    be possessed by a rebellion against human existence... which he wishes to

    exchange, as it were, for something he has made himself. There is no reason

    to doubt our abilities to accomplish such an exchange… The question is only

    whether we wish to use our new scientific and technical knowledge in this

    direction, and this question cannot be decided by scientific means; it is a

    political question of the first order” (Arendt in The Human Condition (1989),

    p. 2-3).

    This article addresses the ideological movement known as transhumanism, the

    proponents of which seek to improve “the human condition... by developing and

    making widely available technologies and to greatly enhance human intellectual,

    physical, and psychological capacities” as well as “to overcome fundamental human

    limitations” (Bostrom 2003, p. 4). It is a movement or “class of philosophies” that

    sees the current state of the human condition as one in several steps in the evolutionary

    trajectory, in which we would improve ourselves with technologies in order to no

    longer “suffer from disease, aging, and inevitable death”. The transhumanist

    movement does not entail or endorse particular technologies (More 2013, p. 3-4), but

    rather any which may improve the human condition. Such technologies include but is

    not limited to; biomodification of human beings to make them smaller to reduce their

    carbon imprint (Liao et al 2012); modifying human psychology to remedy it of its

    cognitive biases (Persson & Sandberg 2012); and uploading ourselves to digital

    platforms in order to overcome the limits of our biological bodies (Kurzweil 2005).

    Though the movement has generated a debate since its inception in the 80s and 90s,

    reservations about transhumanism have primarily concerned implementation of the

    technologies advocated by transhumanists, and what their implementation would

    mean for our concept of humanity (See Fukyama 2001; Agar 2010) or how unjust

    distribution of technologies would affect societies (See Brown 2001). More striking

    criticism appears in Dévédec’s (2018) writings in which it is argued that the

  • 2(27)

    movement - in addressing the deficiencies of human beings - exchanges the goal

    towards “social and political emancipation with the goal of technoscientific and

    biomedical adaptation” of the human to demands of the status quo or an inevitable

    future. In so doing, the movement constitutes a depoliticization of social issues and

    hence “marks a major rupture with the modern democratic project of autonomy” (p.

    488, 490, 501).

    This paper will expand on Dévédec’s critique and make a two-fold contribution; First,

    the article argues that the problem of depoliticization runs deeper than existing

    critique has suggested. Transhumanism not only removes social issues from political

    deliberation and decision-making; it rests on a reductive view of the political realm,

    a view that fails - both analytically and normatively - to identify what it means to

    speak and act politically. Second, to address these shortcomings, the article turns to

    the political thought of Hannah Arendt (1906-1975), primarily outlined in The Human

    Condition and Between Past and Future. Through the lens of Arendt’s political

    theory, the paper will argue that the question of the “future man” is indeed a political

    question, one that warrants questioning and debate as to its desirability. My ambition

    is not only to shed light on some of the troubling aspects of transhumanism in terms

    of its antipolitical tendencies, but also to raise consciousness in the choices we have

    in these matters, and in so doing, restore agency.

    The paper is structured as follows: First, it will map out several strands of the

    transhumanist movement in order to bring to light the commonalities between them

    for critical analysis. After a brief review of previous criticisms against the movement,

    the paper will then focus on Dévédec’s critique of the movement as depoliticizing. It

    will then look to Arendt’s political theory for a concept of politics to highlight the

    reductive view of politics in transhumanism as well as to resolve an internal tension

    within the movement between human enhancement and diversity.

  • 3(27)

    2 Transhumanism: enhancing the individual and remedying our deficiencies

    There are many strands within transhumanism (Hughes 2012), and it is beyond this

    paper to map out all the nuances that differentiate them. Here, transhumanism will be

    referred to as a movement that endorses the use of human engineering or

    biomodification as a means of achieving a political goal. This goal is either 1) taking

    charge of our evolution towards the next stage of evolution, either as an improved

    version of the homo sapiens or a post-human existence that bears little resemblance

    to homo sapiens as we know it in the name of progress or improving the human

    condition; or 2) taking charge of our evolution to avoid disaster by correcting our

    deficient biology, which causes the human species to be prone towards self-

    destruction. According to transhumanists, the human species has yet to attain its true

    potential which remains to be unlocked through “technological advancements and

    scientific understanding”. The prospects of such enhancement technology include:

    [Giving] us control over the biochemical processes in our bodies, enabling us

    to eliminate disease and unwanted aging. Technologies such as brain-

    computer interfaces and neuropharmacology could amplify human

    intelligence, increase emotional well-being, improve our capacity for steady

    commitment to life projects or a loved one, and even multiply the range and

    richness of possible emotions.

    In other words, the transhumanist movement concerns the use of enhancement

    technologies in order to further the capacities of the human being. Such technologies

    include but is not restricted to; germline manipulation, which would allow us to alter

    the genetic composition of an individual while also making such changes hereditary

    (See Stock 2013); “uploading” the consciousness and personality of a person to a new

    digital platform following the Singularity1 (Kurzweil 2005); and achieving a

    substrate-independent mind (a mind that is no longer reliant on a brain to perform its

    thinking process) (See Merle 2013; Koene 2013). As such, it includes a broad range

    1 The hypothesis predicting a point in time when there will be an intelligence explosion as a

    result of exponential technological growth (Kurzweil 2005).

  • 4(27)

    of authors and thinkers that endorse this movement towards the next step in evolution.

    However, this evolution would not be left to chance, but rather controlled and

    deliberate (See Harris 2007; Bostrom & Sandberg 2009) through a market structure

    in the form of an “enhancement market”. This has been envisioned by Miah (2013),

    who see these enhancements are merely an extension of cultural capital products that

    consumers may pick and choose between. “As such, it is sensible to presume that a

    transhuman future will be brought about within a commercial structure” (p. 300).

    Within this commercial structure, individuals would be free to exercise their

    “morphological freedom”, which Sandberg (2013) defines as “the right to modify

    oneself according to one’s desires.” (p. 56)

    While some transhumanists emphasize the potential for self-expression with human

    enhancement technologies, others highlight their potential in overcoming the

    limitations of human biology. Persson and Savulescu (2012) argue that due to the

    tangible risk that humans pose to future life on Earth, we are ill-equipped biologically

    to consider the moral repercussions of our actions. For as long as the human species

    have existed, “human beings have lived in comparatively small and close-knit

    communities... So their psychology and morality are likely to be better fit for these

    conditions” (p. 1). Our “psychological dispositions” - such as our bias towards the

    near future, our conception of responsibility as causally based, and egocentrically

    biased morality – are inappropriate for the scale of the complex, modern world in

    which we live today. Our potential to cause “ultimate harm” through our potential

    misuse of existing and future science, as well as cause irreversible damage to the

    environment, necessitate an intervention into our biology. As such, there is a need to

    adjust the “myopic” psychology of the human being to address our ineptitude when

    it comes to considering the repercussions of our actions (Persson & Savulescu 2012,

    p. 1-4, 12-30, 46-48). Moral bioenhancements, the authors argue, would prove an

    effective way to remedy this hazard (Ibid, p. 2):

    “[O]ur knowledge of human biology, in particular of genetics and

    neurobiology, is now beginning to supply us with means of directly affecting

    the biological and physiological bases of human motivation, e.g.by the use of

  • 5(27)

    pharmacological and genetic methods, like genetic selection and

    engineering.”

    Zoltan Istvan, a transhumanist candidate for the presidential election in the United

    States in 2016, raised similar concerns with our biology: “Humans are handicapped

    by our biology. We operate tens of thousands of years behind evolution with our

    inherited instincts, which means our behaviour is not suited to its current

    environment” (Istvan 2016).

    In similar spirit, Liao et al (2012) raise that human engineering bears potential as a

    solution to the issue of climate change. They argue that while other avenues to address

    the problem such as geoengineering are too risky and the technology needed is too

    distant, human engineering - “the biomedical modification of human to make them

    better at mitigating climate change” (p. 207) - represents an avenue that can remedy

    the issues with much less risk. The authors explore different biomedical modifications

    such as creating “pharmacological meat intolerance”, making “human beings

    smaller” to reduce their ecological footprint, or “cognitive enhancement” in order to

    lower birth rates. Given the insufficient means that we possess today to tackle climate

    change, the authors argue, “we believe that human engineering deserves to be

    considered and explored further in this debate” (Ibid, p. 207-2010, 218).

    Ultimately, transhumanists that highlight the societal benefit of human enhancement

    technologies trace all social issues to our deficient biology. Hughes (2004) argues that

    the pursuit of social equality is a pointless endeavour so long as there are biological

    differences between individuals. “Patriarchy,” he writes, “the most fundamental form

    of human domination, begins with the fact that men can beat women up, and that

    women are doubly vulnerable when pregnant”. Social inequality is a result of our

    biological differences, both between the sexes and between individuals, and will

    persist so long as these differences exist. Only technologies that can remedy the

    differences will provide everyone with “more real equal opportunities.” (p.195-197;

    my emphasis) In agreement, Persson and Savulescu claims the egalitarian doctrines

    promoted by the UN and liberal democracies merely act as a “facade” for the “deep-

    seated xenophobia of our nature”, which took their violent expressions in Rwanda

    and former Yugoslavia in the 90s (Persson & Savulescu 2012, p. 52, 97, 104-105).

  • 6(27)

    The genocides had their cause in our psychological dispositions, and hence ought to

    be remedied by biomedical means. Therefore, anyone true to their pursuit of political

    ideals ought to embrace these technologies, which the authors argue when discussing

    income disparities: “[W]elfare egalitarians have moral reason to wish it were possible

    to enhance – e.g. by means of genetic engineering – the abilities of individuals who

    are disadvantaged by nature... they have a reason to correct the effects of the natural

    lottery” (p. 45). Until this happens, political ideals will merely be empty platitudes

    that hide the true sources of human disparity, that is, the biological differences that

    separate individuals and genders alike.

  • 7(27)

    3 Critics against transhumanism

    The transhumanist thoughts such as those outlined above have generated criticism,

    most of which are derived from a discussion to what extent the transhumanist vision

    is likely to come to pass or how these technologies might affect our notion of what

    constitutes “humanity”. Hauskell (2016) has criticized the ambitions of

    transhumanism by framing them as myths, and that “the persuasiveness of

    transhumanist arguments for radical human enhancement crucially depends on their

    utopian content” (p. 9). Agar (2010) has similarly argued that the potential benefits

    outlined by transhumanists are too optimistic, and that we ought to instead take a

    cautionary approach to enhancements technologies to ensure that potential dystopian

    realities enabled by such technologies are not realized.

    Furthermore, Agar argues that in the transition from human to posthuman, we may

    lose valuable emotional experiences in which our humanity is rooted (2010, p. 15).

    Likewise, Sandel (2007) cautions the use of biomedical science such as genetic

    engineering, as it may lead to an “excess of mastery and domination that misses the

    sense of life as a gift” (p. 62). Meanwhile, Fukuyama (2001) raised the posthuman

    condition as problematic for human dignity, as this concept is dependent on what we

    consider to be human nature. Ultimately, there is some commonality between human

    beings that allows us to enshrine people deviating from social norms with as much

    rights as any other person, even if we will struggle to define what such a commonality

    would be in terms of a palpable essence (p. 107-174).

    Concerns with basis in notions such as human dignity has been dismissed by

    bioethicists and transhumanists as something irrational. Yuval Levin (2003) coined

    this as the “paradox of conservative bioethics”, in which private taboos in the form of

    “powerful moral intuitions” are brought into the public as arguments to regulate

    bioethical questions. Yet in so doing, these moral intuitions are unravelled and laid

    bare for public scrutiny, and hence become unsustainable (p. 55). Concurring with

    Levin, Hughes states “the bioconservatives cannot validate their taboos and ethical a

    prioris in the public square” (2010, p. 625). Hence, there is a scepticism among

    transhumanists towards moral intuitions that would inhibit progress attained through

    enhancement technologies, as seen in Pinker’s scepticism towards policies “based on

  • 8(27)

    nebulous but sweeping principles such as ‘dignity,’ ‘sacredness,’ or ‘social justice’.”

    (Pinker 2015)

    3.1 The comparison with eugenics

    While some may advocate caution towards the application of enhancement

    technologies based on such “sweeping principles”, other critics have made

    comparisons to transhumanism with the controversial eugenics movement (Koch

    2010; Newman 2010). The eugenics movement, originating in the United States in

    the late 1800s, advocated the cultivation of good genetic characteristics while

    discarding the inferior genetic characteristics. Like transhumanism, the eugenics

    movement sought to take conscious control of evolution for the purpose of the “self-

    direction of human evolution” (Koch 2010, p. 689-694).

    The eugenics movement influenced policies in Nazi Germany and the sterilization

    programmes in Scandinavia (Carlson 2001; Broberg & Roll-Hansen 2005), which has

    led some transhumanists to reject the comparison, saying that transhumanism does

    not share the “racist and classist assumptions on which [eugenics was] based”.

    However, other transhumanists tenuously accept the comparison (Hughes 2004, p.

    131-133), with some fully embracing it, such as Fuller & Lipinska: “[M]uch of what

    is nowadays proposed under the name of ‛transhumanism’ is simply ‛Eugenics 2.0’.”

    They claim that what was the error of previous policies employing eugenic thoughts

    was not the faulty science, but “the gradual loss of proportion in a policy that might

    have worked in a more circumscribed application” (2014, p. 92).

    Hence what differentiates transhumanism from the eugenics of the past concerns

    implementation; instead of state coercion, the “liberal eugenics” (See Agar 1998) of

    transhumanism relies on “self-applied” methods (Fuller & Lipinska 2014, p. 131).

    Additionally, transhumanism - because of its leanings towards the individualistic

    market driven human evolution, and the necessity of voluntary participation in that

    process - argues for a positive eugenics, the engendering of “good characteristics, as

    opposed to the negative eugenics, the neglect of “bad characteristics”, (Newton 2010,

    p. 31 for the distinction) that they argue define the “old eugenics”. Finally, the

  • 9(27)

    intended enhancements of the individual are not based in racial ideologies but instead

    for the betterment of the human species in general (See Bostrom 2003; Hughes 2004).

    Because the evolutionary enhancement will occur within a market-structure, it has

    been argued that the transhumanist vision of widespread usage of enhancement

    technologies is inevitable. Bailey (2014) compares bioconservatives and

    policymakers who wish to prohibit or restrict the usage of biomodification

    technologies (in his example, germline technologies) to those who tried to impede the

    industrial revolution. They write: “Policymakers sometimes mistakenly think they

    have a choice whether germline technologies will come into being. They do not.” (p.

    313). In a similar vein, Hughes (2004) calls the opponents of biomodification

    technologies “BioLuddites”, their namesake drawn from the anti-industrialization

    movement that sought to protect worker rights against the increasing automation of

    the industrial revolution. Either way, transhumanists argue, history has doomed the

    opposition to defeat, and should therefore consider Pinker’s (2015) imperative to

    simply “get out of the way”.

    3.2 Dévédec: The anthropology of deficiency

    While there are numerous critics of transhumanism in the form of dignity-advocates

    and authors concerned with the blurring lines between eugenics and transhumanism

    are plentiful, a more novel line of critique is raised by Dévédec (2018), who questions

    the movement’s self-proclaimed basis in the Enlightenment humanism and the notion

    of human perfectibility. He argues that the movement towards transforming human

    beings to better suit their environment and the demands of a fixed future is

    “fundamentally [a] political issue... that questions the values orienting collective

    action and establishing shared life.” Dévédec posits that rather than advocating human

    perfectibility in the sense of rejecting the status quo and using collective action for

    change, the transhumanist project results in a “depoliticization of social issues” by

    tracing social issues to a faulty human biology ill-equipped. Thus, instead of

    questioning whether these issues have a social, environmental, or political origin, the

    result is a “‘naturalization’ of social problems”, to which humans must be adapted (p.

    489, 497). Dévédec refers to this as the “anthropology of deficiency”, a “depreciative

    view of humans and the human body” which underpin the transhumanist movement.

  • 10(27)

    As a result of this view, there is a widespread scepticism about the desirability and

    need of political deliberation and decision-making not just among transhumanists of

    a libertarian leaning - and the associated centricity on individualism - but the

    transhumanist movement as a whole (Dévédec 2018, p. 496-497). Hence, while many

    transhumanist authors highlight the potential of the technologies as a means to

    enhance the individual for self-fulfilment (see Bostrom 2003), others explicitly

    emphasize the current existing deficiencies that mar the biology of the human being

    and the species as a whole.

  • 11(27)

    4 Beyond depoliticization

    Dévédec’s critique is compelling, as it shows the degree to which the narrative of the

    deficiency of human beings side-lines the possibility of political action. Nevertheless,

    several objections will be raised here. First, while it may be true that the transhumanist

    movement represents a “rupture” rather than a continuation of Enlightenment

    thought, this may be explained because the Enlightenment tradition itself bore

    “contradictions and tensions” (Hughes 2010, p. 622). As a result, it would not be

    surprising that there are differing notions of human perfectibility which emphasize

    different aspects of progress, from social reforms to technical mastery over nature.

    Second, even if the transhumanist movement represents a reversal of the humanist

    tradition, it is questionable to what extent it would represent a challenge for liberal

    democracies today. While our understanding of democracy certainly owes itself to

    Enlightenment thought, it has also progressed since then, to such where the reversal

    is not enough to question the propositions of transhumanism.

    This paper contends that the criticism is simply not extensive enough: If we consider

    depoliticization as framing potential political issues as technical problems, “as

    transcendent imperatives that demand responses, without any attached specification

    as to who should respond to what and to whom” (Enroth 2014, p. 68), then the

    transhumanist solutions to climate change or preventing human extinction through

    biomodification certainly qualifies as such. Yet we will argue that what the

    transhumanists propose constitutes a step beyond just a “normative void”; rather than

    removing issues from the public realm, the imperative to address our deficient biology

    would mean to adjust the very basis of the political itself, namely the human beings

    themselves.

    I argue that the adaptation of human beings to new naturalized social situations creates

    a tension between safeguarding diversity and the drive towards enhancement. Some

    authors explicitly acknowledge this tension: Hughes (2004), pointing out that “innate

    biological traits... predict, even if they don’t determine... life success”, raises the

    example that “short men earn less than tall men” to point out how human engineering

    can be used to combat inequality. Nevertheless, he concludes that “[w]hen parents are

    able to choose the height of their children, more children will be tall, but we should

  • 12(27)

    also work on being less heightist.” (p. 195-197) Simultaneously, he is aware that “the

    ethical obligation... to enhance ourselves” should not be so “invasive that they inhibit

    diversity”, and that the lines between protecting diversity and encouraging

    enhancement “will be difficult to draw” (p. 256-257). Fuller & Lipinska recognize

    this difficulty as well (p. 135-136):

    “The burden on [transhumanists] will be to design welfare states that tolerate

    such a diversity of human conditions, whereby what some judge to be an

    enhancement to their capacities is taken by others to be a sign of disability.

    Failure in this task might result in a formally recognized sub-speciation:

    Apartheid 2.0.”

    What will be argued here is that this tension bears its source in the reductive and

    erroneous view of politics as just an instrument to deal with issues on a collective

    scale and safeguard the interests of individuals. While it may be that the methods

    advocated by transhumanist cannot be seen as problematic through the classic liberal

    lens of “autonomy, fairness, and individual rights” (Sandel 2008, p. 9), it nevertheless

    represents a misunderstanding of the full potential of politics in democratic societies,

    namely to engender diversity of identities.

    To resolve this tension and bring to light the normative dimension of the political

    realm that is neglected in transhumanism, we turn to the political theory of Hannah

    Arendt. Though political theories advocating democracy may argue its desirability

    based on the equal representation of the interests of its subjects (See Dahl 1989),

    Arendt takes care not to specify a purpose of/for politics in terms of substantive

    content; her emphasis is instead on action in concert, through which we can become

    individuals and experience autonomy. However, participation in the political realm

    can only occur as a result of the pluralism among human beings, which is currently

    in tension with the transhumanist imperatives of human evolution.

  • 13(27)

    5 Hannah Arendt’s The Human Condition

    Arendt sought to define the meaning of the political by drawing upon the ideas of

    Ancient Greece as the normative basis of what constitutes a genuine political life.

    This undertaking is what informs her political theory, which is primarily outlined in

    The Human Condition (1989). In it, Arendt outlines three activities that define the

    human condition (Arendt 1989, p. 7-9, 12-17, 48-49, 175-178):

    1) The first, labour, is related to the biological conditions which human beings

    (and animals alike) are subject to. It is defined by the repetitive actions that

    sustain the needs of the human body and “the maintenance of life”. To labour

    is to be “enslaved by necessity” and to respond to the human condition of

    “life itself” (Ibid, p. 7, 83-84).

    2) The second, work, is related to the fabrication and existence within an

    artificial environment that is distinct from the natural environment, including

    the “the [human] species’ ever recurring life cycle” (Ibid, p. 7). Unlike the

    natural world, the artificial world is durable and possesses some degree of

    permanence.

    3) The third activity, action, becomes possible through the human condition of

    plurality. Because we are distinct and unique human beings, we need both

    action and speech to communicate ourselves to other human beings. In so

    doing, we express our latent selves, and we become individuals through this

    disclosure.

    It is action which Arendt sees as the defining activity of humanity, as “neither beast

    nor a god is capable of it” (Arendt 1989, p. 22-23), as it requires and stands witness

    to the presence of other human beings. An animal may also labour, but they will only

    do so as an extension of their species. By contrast, human beings engage in action as

    individuals. These spontaneous actions made in concert with other autonomous

    agents take place in a political realm which Arendt likens to “webs” of relationships;

    the political realm is not a firm place, but spontaneous and continuous, like the action

    itself. Thus, we can never fully predict the consequences of an action. Yet it is

    precisely this spontaneity and unpredictability that makes the act liberating; it occurs

    against the expected, against the fatalistic belief in the automatic historical processes,

  • 14(27)

    such as the Singularity or our inevitable self-destruction through climate change.

    Action is faculty that allows us to free ourselves from such expected historical

    processes that would otherwise be the cause of our ruin (Ibid, p. 181-184, 188-192,

    232, 246-247; 1993, p. 168-171).

    Arendt arranges the triad in a hierarchy which she believes conveys the view of the

    ancient Greeks. Neither labour nor work were enough to be considered “authentically

    human [ways] of life” (Arendt 1989, p. 12-13). Nevertheless, each activity had their

    place. Labour is interrelated with life itself, while work provides a degree of durability

    to these deeds through the actual physical space for action in the form of the agora or

    the city itself and the laws that facilitate political action (Ibid, p. 8-9, 120, 188, 194-

    195, 207-208).

    Although Arendt found the normative basis for her theory in the ideas of the ancient

    Greeks, she did not wish for a return to the polis (Arendt 1993, p. 156-157): The

    purpose of their analytical triad was rather to show that, while labour and work had

    their place in determining the human condition, what was problematic was the

    “generalization” of their standards for a world occupied by human beings – the

    political realm. Her contention was rather with the notion that the logics of labour or

    work had replaced action as the dominating activity of the public realm (Arendt 1989,

    p. 156-157). Labour, Arendt argued, had come to dominate the public realm in the

    way in which the modern consumer’s society, emulating the logics of biological

    metabolism, had assumed a self-perpetuating cycle of production and consumption in

    which the modern human being cannot enjoy freedom, which for Arendt is itself

    tantamount to spontaneous action (Ibid, p. 96-101, 126-135).

    Work, on the other hand, was useful in explaining the way in which the language of

    means and ends had come to define the idea of politics in the modern age (Arendt

    1989, p. 153-159, 220-230); a matter on which we will elaborate upon in the following

    section.

  • 15(27)

    6 Fabricating human beings for the future

    Work is the activity that concerns the “work of our hands”, and it is the realm of the

    craftsmen. It is distinct from the activity of action in that the activity of work is guided

    by a model that is reified through the process of fabrication. Because this process

    serves towards the creation of a designated end, the activity is defined by a logic of

    instrumentality. All of nature becomes potential material for reification, and the

    material, in turn, is defined by its potential to attain a desired end (Arendt 1989, p.

    136, 139-144, 153-159). Arendt contended that the logic of work has been

    “generalized” outside of its boundaries to such an extent that it characterizes a great

    deal of the “modern age” (Ibid, p. 305):

    “[His] instrumentalization of the world, his confidence in tools and in the

    productivity of the maker of artificial objects; his trust in the all-

    comprehensive range of the means-end category, his conviction that every

    issue can be solved and every human motivation reduced to the principle of

    utility; his sovereignty, which regards everything given as material and thinks

    of the whole of nature as of ‛an immensive fabric from which we can cut out

    whatever we want to resew it however we like...’”

    In particular, Arendt argued that the ancient philosophers were a decisive influence

    on modern thinking on politics as a process of fabrication. The ancient philosophers

    turned to the fabrication process as an inspiration for the shaping of the realm of

    human affairs for its reliability, as it would mitigate the unpredictability of action in

    the political realm. Plato was particularly influential: Mirroring the platonic idea of

    an abstract “good” which existed as an eternal idea outside of reality, he believed that

    the political realm could only be good to the extent it realized the abstract image that

    informed its shaping. To accomplish this, Plato split action into two components:

    knowing and doing - and subsequently, thought and action were separated from one

    another in a manner mimicking ruler and the ruled. Plato’s ideal vision of public

    affairs mirrored the household, with a ruler who knows what to do and the ruled who

    carry out the actions to realize the knowledge of the ruler; the “Philosopher King”.

    Hence, forming the public domain according to a predetermined design or shape

    understood only by the Philosopher King - similar to how the idea of a table informs

  • 16(27)

    the craftsman - would lend some degree of predictability to the tumultuous political

    realm. This perception would come to define modern political theory, Arendt writes,

    in which utopian designs of the public realm would inform the “foundation of a new

    body of politic”; the instrumentality of work – the language of means and ends –

    defines political thought, “rather than the... understanding of action itself” (Arendt

    1989, p. 188-190, 192-195, 220-230).

    Transhumanists share these views of the political realm - the resentment of its

    unpredictability and the desire to replace it with the logic of fabrication - yet they

    differ in one regard: Arendt writes that the ancient philosophers’ scepticism towards

    the political “rests on a suspicion of action rather than on a contempt for men” (Arendt

    1989, p. 222). Transhumanists, however, base this suspicion on the deficiency of our

    biology. Just as Plato’s “attempt to replace acting with making” in order to critique

    democracy “will turn into an argument as against the essentials of politics” (Ibid, p.

    220), so too does the transhumanist imperative to remedy our deficiencies turn into

    an argument against the basis of the political itself.

    As a result, there is a scepticism towards democracy in general within this narrative

    due to our deficient biology making us fall short of our potential as active, informed

    citizens. The solutions to the looming issues such as climate change, Persson and

    Savulescu (2012) argue, will not find a solution in democracy, “unless the will to act

    morally grows stronger in the public” (p. 104). Furthermore, the authors remain

    concerned over the pluralism that characterizes liberal societies, the argument being

    that it could have a destabilizing effect that raises the likelihood of “ultimate harm”;

    the self-destruction of human civilization as a whole. This plurality, along with the

    sizes of liberal democracies, also result in these countries experiencing a greater

    likelihood of minority discrimination (Ibid, p. 93-95).

    The transhumanist imperatives are informed by a vision of the future which is

    inevitable in one way or another. The transhumanist dream of evolution through an

    individual self-enhancement market will come to pass regardless of our moral

    quandaries simply as a result of market forces. In the more pessimistic strand, our

    species faces certain extinction due to our inherent deficiencies of our biology that

    make us incapable of reckoning the consequences of our actions. Because of the

  • 17(27)

    unreliability of political action and the fickle motivations of individuals, the potential

    for human engineering are especially worth exploring, if not necessary. For instance,

    the consumerist pattern of capitalist societies is linked to many environmental issues.

    At the same time, any attempt to restrict the affluent consumerist lifestyle that citizens

    in first world countries enjoy would likely fail, as such efforts would receive little in

    the way of popular support (Persson & Savulescu 2012, p. 76-81). Liao et al (2012)

    likewise argue that behavioural solutions to environmental problems would likely not

    suffice as “many people lack motivation to alter their behaviour in the required ways”.

    When discussing the necessity to reduce our red-meat eating in order to reduce our

    collective carbon imprint, the authors argue that “[w]hile reducing the consumption

    of red meat can be achieved through social, cultural means, people often lack the

    motivation or willpower to give up eating red meat even if they wish they could.” (p.

    207-208)

    Other technological solutions to mitigate these existential risks on a larger scale can

    be found in the writings of Bostrom (2006) and Yudkowsky (2004). Bostrom

    describes this solution to internal dangers as the singleton, which he defines as “a

    world order in which there is a single decision-making agency at the highest level”,

    which would possess several powers (p. 48):

    ...(1) [T]he ability to prevent any threats (internal or external) to its own

    existence and supremacy, and (2) the ability to exert effective control over

    major features of its domain (including taxation and territorial allocation).

    Bostrom provides several suggestions as to what form the singleton could take, such

    as an undetectable machine intelligence that enforces a certain conduct; a world

    government, democratic or otherwise; or the evolution of humans into a single

    cohesive entity, such as a “transcending upload”. Because of the existential risks such

    as those described above, Bostrom believes it is more likely than not that such a

    singleton would come to pass, especially paired with the likely advancements

    surrounding security technologies such as surveillance and mind control that could

    enable the realization of the singleton (2006, p. 48-50, 53). Yudkovsky (2004),

    advocating for a form of a singleton that would take the shape of a “friendly AI”,

    conceptualizes a Coherent Extrapolated Volition, which is the extrapolated will of

  • 18(27)

    individuals which shares cohesion with most other individuals (p. 3-11). Since this

    “friendly AI” operates on and extrapolates our own desires and wishes, disagreeing

    with it would be “dangerous and harmful” for us; we would be acting against our own

    interests (p. 33). After all, who could oppose a ruling entity that only wishes to see

    our own interests safeguarded and fulfilled? Let the ruler rule, while the ruled concern

    themselves with other things.

    Yet, such a retort is rooted in an insufficient view of politics as merely the safeguard

    of the sovereignty of the individual and the protection of our freedom to pursue our

    interests (See Mill in Hughes 2004, p. 11). Hence, transhumanists do not infuse

    democratic arrangements with any intrinsic value on their own; instead, they were

    only a necessity as a result of our limited biology (Hughes 2010, p. 628-630). Because

    we will have the technological capacities to intervene directly in the make-up of the

    human being, we will not only have better, more reliable ways of tackling issues

    which require immediate measures, but we will also have unlocked a new means of

    self-realization. With our biological selves subject to the fabrication process, we

    become means for the realization of the “idea” of the transhuman.

    The application of the logic of work to politics is not a novel notion in of itself: After

    all, Arendt had noted this in the totalitarian regimes pursuing utopian designs (Arendt

    1989, 228-229). Likewise, Enroth (2014) has observed how issues, through the

    discourse of governance, came to be addressed as technical rather than political

    matters. Yet while these observations concerned the shaping of the public space or

    the framing of issues that have potential to be political, what the transhumanists

    propose goes beyond depoliticization: Rather than removing issues from the public

    realm, the technologies advocated by the writers of this movement to address our

    deficient biology would mean to adjust (and reduce) the very basis of the political

    itself, that is, the distinctiveness of human beings that inform the plurality which

    allows for action to take place (Arendt 1989, p. 175-176).

    Yet even if Arendt’s political theory may provide explanatory power as to why there

    is tension between the transhumanist desire for enhancement and diversity, why

    should we accept Arendt’s view of politics to begin with? To elaborate upon this, we

    must turn our focus to the essence of her theory: Freedom.

  • 19(27)

    7 The freedom found in action

    Arendt means to accomplish two things in particular with her political theory: First,

    she means to separate our view of the political from the philosophical traditions of

    political theory, which, as we have observed, meant to control the unpredictability of

    the political by deferring to a stable and peaceful abstract “idea” (See also Buckler

    2011, p. 3). Second, her theory means to criticize the dehumanizing consumption

    society in which the political has been reduced to become solely about security of the

    individual’s interests and ensuring that individuals could be left to their own devices

    with as little intervention from the state as possible. Because “the maintenance of life”

    has come to dominate the political, the political has become overshadowed by the

    administration of the “the gigantic and still increasing sphere of social and economic

    life” (Arendt 1993 p. 149-151, 155). In such a consumption society, there was no

    longer any way for human beings to become equal as individuals in the political

    realm; all activities became connotated with the survival of society at large, with

    human beings merely being reduced to specimens of the human species (Arendt 1989,

    p. 320-321). Arendt’s theory is a claim to take back agency in a world where the

    possibility of expressing oneself through action has been reduced.

    For that reason, no matter how we may be liberated from necessity, this would not be

    sufficient for someone to be free (Arendt 1989, p. 70-71). In an interesting passage,

    Arendt argues that (Arendt 1993, p. 160; my emphasis):

    The necessity which prevents me from doing what I know and will may arise

    from the world, or from my own body, or from an insufficiency of talents,

    gifts, and qualities which are bestowed upon man by birth... all these factors,

    the psychological ones not excluded, condition the person from the outside

    as far as the I-will and the I-know, that is, the ego itself, are concerned; the

    power that meets these circumstances, that liberates... willing and knowing

    from their bondage to necessity is the I-can. Only where the I-will and the I-

    can coincide does freedom exist.

    An initial reading of this passage might suggest that Arendt equates freedom with

    liberation from its opposite, necessity. Yet what defines action is its character as the

  • 20(27)

    “actualization of the human condition of natality”. It is the manifestation of a

    beginning that has appeared out of seemingly nowhere, a “miracle” that occurred

    “against the overwhelming odds of statistical laws and their probability”. This miracle

    is that which will “[save] the world, the realm of human affairs from its normal,

    ‛natural’ ruin” (Arendt 1989, p. 178, 247). Habermas, in reading Arendt’s emphasis

    on natality, highlights that it bears an importance because it is a beginning that is not

    at our disposal. Natality is a “bridge that connects the natural world with the

    awareness of the adult subject”. The birth brings “the indeterminate hope” that

    “[shatters] the power of the past over the future” (p. 62-63). Given the spontaneous

    and unpredictable nature of action, and the relationship between necessity and the

    “normal, ‘natural’ ruin” (Arendt 1989, p. 247), this warrants a reading of Arendt’s

    notion of freedom as action taking place in spite of necessity. Action is the unexpected

    expression of both an individual’s agency and their identity in rebellion of routine

    structures that constrain us.

    In stark differentiation to the fabrication logic of work, action can never be planned,

    and its outcomes never controlled reliably. Because of its freedom from the temporal

    processes that initially may seem inevitable, it allows us to take back agency in places

    where we might deem it impossible to change the existing circumstances. We find

    therefore a mutually reinforcing relationship between politics and freedom in its

    associated activity of action; without the presence of our peers, we could not

    distinguish ourselves through action. Without this political realm, we would not be

    able to experience freedom by acting in the present. This makes political life

    something desirable in and of itself; it not only allows us to meet the circumstances

    that condition our existence, but it also allows us to define ourselves beyond them. In

    the political realm, we can publicly express our identities.

    The performative emphasis of politics of Arendt’s political theory has been criticized

    as hollow in content and as an activity that merely serves a vain, secular quest for

    immortality, in which “Arendt’s citizens begin to resemble posturing little boys

    clamoring for attention and wanting to be reassured that they are brave, valuable, even

    real.” (Pitkin 1981, p. 338) I suggest that this is intentional because Arendt is careful

    not to assign any substantive content as to what politics should entail or what it should

  • 21(27)

    promote precisely because such an effort would be caught within the language of

    means and ends of which she is so staunchly critical. Her emphasis is instead on the

    sustained engagement itself, which we maintain through thoughtful action.

    Nevertheless, Arendt’s political theory is of the normative kind, in which engaging in

    political activity, regardless of what it “produces”, bears intrinsic value. Given the

    antipolitical in its various expressions - the thoughtless, mass conformism of modern

    consumer’s society or the totalitarian regimes in which lives are merely means to an

    end - we can extrapolate that actions in the political are conscious actions in which

    individuals engage that promote the possibility of further action. This would exclude

    efforts that infringe upon other members’ ability to disclose themselves in the political

    realm, or actions which actively bear a homogenizing effect of human experiences,

    and in turn, human subjectivities (Arendt 1989, p. 38-46, 57-58, 229).

    It stands to clarify that Arendt did not imply that the conditions which informed the

    activities of her conceptual triad were fixed: On the contrary, she wrote that they never

    regulate our activities “absolutely” and could be overcome to the point where their

    associated activities “would no longer make sense” (Arendt 1989, p. 9-11). Therefore,

    it is possible that the condition of plurality could be diminished to such an extent that

    it would be difficult to speak of action as a general activity, as would be the case if

    human beings came to be “endlessly reproducible repetitions of the same model”

    (Ibid, p. 8).

    Bearing the Arendtian theoretical lens, we must view the transhumanist quest for

    freedom from the labours of our biological being with great scepticism for two

    reasons: First, not only must we contend that the path to freedom lies not in the

    transhumanist desire to free ourselves of the biological, as this would only engender

    passivity and reduce our existence to a “lifeless life”; it would be liberation from

    necessity at the cost of plurality, and at the cost of the prospect of experiencing

    freedom through action.

    Second, the discourse of evolutionary enhancement or the need to remedy our

    deficient biology is incompatible with Arendt’s emphasis on individuals experiencing

    freedom from temporal processes through action as a result of their quality of

  • 22(27)

    uniqueness, “in such a way that nobody is ever the same as anyone else who ever

    lived, lives, or will live.” (Arendt 1989, p. 8). Instead, an evolutionary discourse, in

    order to make us compatible for comparisons in a timeline, assumes a deterministic

    outlook in which we are merely the sum of the capacities bestowed upon us by our

    biology; we are only members of the species of humankind.

    Hence, the pursuit towards enhancement or the transition to a new, better species is

    misguided on the basis that we do not enjoy freedom by defining ourselves as human

    beings or posthumans, but as unique beings. It may be that we may frame

    posthumanity as an improvement in an evolutionary timeline when compared to

    humanity as we know it today, but this cannot apply to human beings acting as

    individuals in the present; as such, they defy comparison in relation to any progress.

  • 23(27)

    8 Conclusions

    With the lens of Arendt’s political theory, we must view the transhumanist agenda to

    enhance or adapt the human being with great scepticism for several reasons: First, it

    is a misguided effort, as transhumanism confuses freedom with liberation from

    necessity. Second, because it addresses enhancement or compatibility of our biology

    with the current order of things, it bears a deterministic outlook in which we cannot

    transcend our biology, to which our flaws and our merits are owed. Third, the

    discourse of progress necessitates that the capacities are viewed in light of a timeline,

    which is incompatible with the uniqueness inherent in the human condition. Finally,

    the adjustment of human beings towards a designated end is antithetical to human

    plurality; as such, transhumanism does not merely constitute depoliticization; it is

    antipolitical.

    As the introductory paragraph by Arendt suggests, the transhumanist agenda of

    human enhancement is not a “neutral” technical matter, but a political question that

    warrants questioning. Transhumanism is not only problematic in its instrumentality

    and scepticism towards the agency of humans and the affected societies at large to

    address the problems, it is also locked to a view of our future as already determined

    by processes that appear outside of our control. Such a view engenders passivity and

    only helps perpetuate a feeling of helplessness before the inevitable future that will

    happen regardless of our own desires, and to which we must be adapted to if we are

    to cope with it.

    Yet this belief is also illusory: Though plurality may be reduced and our capacity for

    action may be restrained in various ways, that capacity is never fully diminished. We

    always have the potential to determine our own fate and take charge of the

    development of our society through collective, conscious actions. Arendt’s theory

    reminds us that there is no future that is fixed, and that through action, we may free

    ourselves from the predetermined fates predicted by the historical and natural

    processes. We must therefore reject the inevitability of the transhumanist vision; we

    will always possess the power to determine our future.

  • 24(27)

    As discussed above, previous criticisms against transhumanism have primarily

    centred on how the new biological conditions will affect what we consider humanity

    (Fukuyama 2001; Agar 2010) or how transhumanism obscures “social determinants

    in social issues” such as the current climate crisis (Dévédec 2018, p. 497). Yet the

    latter critique is itself based in the means-oriented, reductive view of the political as

    a social dimension of problem-solving. I have argued here that the greater loss is

    instead the loss of the freedom we experience through the expression of ourselves in

    the political realm.

    The disclosure of our identity through action entails a non-negotiability with the

    demands of the external society. In the political realm, we are equals, each with our

    own autonomy. This gives us the ability to question: Whose future am I unfit for?

    Towards what end must I be enhanced? In the political realm, we cannot be reduced

    to mere means, nor can we accept any dystopian future that awaits us should we not

    adapt. As human beings, we must ourselves take part in the discussion and ask

    ourselves whether the transhumanist vision is something desirable or not.

    The debate surrounding transhumanism will continue, but this paper will hopefully

    have contributed to the realization that the premises of transhumanism, such as the

    inevitability of technological progress and usage of enhancement technologies to the

    necessity of adopting them, are up for question. In other words, we must remember

    to “think about what we are doing” (Arendt 1989, p. 5).

  • 25(27)

    References

    Agar N (2010) Humanity’s End. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Arendt H (1993) Between past and future. London: Penguin Books.

    Arendt H (1989) The Human Condition. Chicago, Illinois: University of Chicago

    Press.

    Bailey R (2013) For Enhancing People. In: More M and Vita-More N (eds) The

    Transhumanist Reader. Aufl., Somerset: Wiley-Blackwell, pp. 327-316.

    Bostrom N (2003) The Transhumanist FAQ: version 2.1. World Transhumanist

    Association. Available at: http://www.nickbostrom.com/views/transhumanist.pdf

    (Last accessed 17 August 2020).

    Bostrom N (2006) What is a Singleton? Linguistic and Philosophical Investigations.

    5(2): 48-54.

    Bostrom N and Sandberg A (2009) The Wisdom of Nature: An Evolutionary

    Heuristic for Human Enhancement. In: Savulescu J and Bostrom N (eds) Human

    Enhancement. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Broberg G and Roll-Hansen N (2005) Eugenics and the Welfare State. East Lansing:

    Michigan State University Press.

    Buckler S (2011) Hannah Arendt and Political Theory. Edinburgh: Edinburgh

    University Press.

    Carlson, E.A (2001) The Unfit: A History of a Bad Idea. Cold Spring Harbor, New

    York: Cold Spring Harbor Laboratory Press.

    Dahl R.A (1989) Democracy and its Critics. New Haven: Yale Univ. Press.

    Dévédec N.L (2018) Unfit for the future? The depoliticization of human perfectibility,

    from the Enlightenment to transhumanism. European Journal of Social Theory.

    21(4): 488–507.

    Enroth H (2014) Governance: The art of governing after governmentality. European

    Journal of Social Theory. 17(1): 60–76.

  • 26(27)

    Fukuyama F (2002) Our Posthuman Future. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux.

    Fuller S and Lipińska V (2014) The Proactionary Imperative: A Foundation for

    Transhumanism. Houndmills, Basingstoke, Hampshire: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Harris J (2007) Enhancing Evolution: The Ethical Case for Making People Better.

    Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Habermas J (2003) The Future of the Human Race. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Hauskeller M (2016) Mythologies of Transhumanism. Basingstoke: Palgrave

    Macmillan.

    Hughes J (2004) Citizen Cyborg: Why Democratic Societies Must Respond to the

    Redesigned Human of the Future. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.

    Hughes J (2010) Contradictions from the Enlightenment roots of transhumanism. The

    Journal of Medicine and Philosophy. 35(6): 622–40.

    Hughes J (2012) The Politics of Transhumanism and the Techno-Millennial

    Imagination, 1626–2030. Zygon. 47(4): 757–776.

    Istvan Z (2016) Transhumanism and our outdated biology. Huffington Post. Available

    at: (Last accessed 17 August 2020).

    Koch T (2010) Enhancing who? Enhancing what? Ethics, bioethics, and

    transhumanism. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy. 35(6): 685–699.

    Koene R (2013) Uploading to Substrate-Independent Minds. In: More M and Vita-

    More N (eds) The Transhumanist Reader. Aufl., Somerset: Wiley-Blackwell, pp.

    146-156.

    Kurzweil R (2005) The Singularity is Near. New York: Viking.

    Levin Y (2003) The Paradox of Conservative Bioethics. New Atlantis. 1: 53-

    65.

    Liao M, Sandberg A and Roache R (2012) Human Engineering and Climate Change.

    Ethics, Policy & Environment. 15(2): 206–21.

    https://www.huffingtonpost.com/zoltan-istvan/transhumanism-and-our-out_b_9749138.htmlhttps://www.huffingtonpost.com/zoltan-istvan/transhumanism-and-our-out_b_9749138.html

  • 27(27)

    Merkle R (2013) Uploading. In: More M and Vita-More N (eds) The Transhumanist

    Reader. Aufl., Somerset: Wiley-Blackwell, pp. 157-164.

    Miah A (2013) Justifying Human Enhancement: The Accumulation of Biocultural

    Capital. In: More M and Vita-More N (eds) The Transhumanist Reader. Aufl.,

    Somerset: Wiley-Blackwell, pp. 290-301.

    More M (2013) The philosophy of transhumanism. In: More M and Vita-More N

    (eds) The Transhumanist Reader. Aufl., Somerset: Wiley-Blackwell, pp. 3-17.

    Newman S.A (2010) The Transhumanism Bubble. Capitalism Nature Socialism.

    21(2): 29–42.

    Persson I and Savulescu J (2014) Unfit for the Future: The Need for Moral

    Enhancement. Oxford. Oxford University Press.

    Pinker S (2015) The Moral Imperative for Bioethics. The Boston Globe. 1 August.

    Available at: (Last accessed

    18 August 2020).

    Pitkin H.F (1998) The Attack of the Blob: Hannah Arendt's Concept of the Social.

    Chicago, Ill.: The University of Chicago Press.

    Sandberg A (2013) Morphological Freedom – Why We Just Don’t Want it, but Need

    It. In: More M and Vita-More N (eds) The Transhumanist Reader. Aufl., Somerset:

    Wiley-Blackwell, pp. 56-64.

    Sandel M (2007) The Case Against Perfection: Ethics in the Age of Genetic

    Engineering. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Stock G (2013) The Battle for the Future. In: More M and Vita-More N (eds) The

    Transhumanist Reader. Aufl., Somerset: Wiley-Blackwell, pp. 302-316.

    Yudkowsky E (2004) Coherent extrapolated volition. San Francisco, CA: Singularity

    Institute for Artificial Intelligence.

    https://www.bostonglobe.com/opinion/2015/07/31/the-moral-imperative-for-bioethics/JmEkoyzlTAu9oQV76JrK9N/story.htmlhttps://www.bostonglobe.com/opinion/2015/07/31/the-moral-imperative-for-bioethics/JmEkoyzlTAu9oQV76JrK9N/story.html

    AbstractAcknowledgments1 Introduction2 Transhumanism: enhancing the individual and remedying our deficiencies3 Critics against transhumanism3.1 The comparison with eugenics3.2 Dévédec: The anthropology of deficiency

    4 Beyond depoliticization5 Hannah Arendt’s The Human Condition6 Fabricating human beings for the future7 The freedom found in action8 ConclusionsReferences