non-conceptual content and the soudn of music

Upload: kanebri

Post on 03-Jun-2018

220 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/12/2019 Non-Conceptual Content and the Soudn of Music

    1/26

    Non-conceptual Content and the Sound of Music

    MICHAEL LUNTLEY

    Abstract: I present an argument for the existence of nonconceptual representationalcontent. The argument is compatible with McDowells defence of conceptualismagainst those arguments for nonconceptual content that draw upon claims about thefine-grainedness of experience. I present a case for nonconceptual content thatconcentrates on the idea that experience can possess representational content thatcannot perform the function of conceptual content, namely figure in the subjectsreasons for belief and action. This sort of argument for nonconceptual content is bestachieved with examples from auditory perception, especially our perception of music.

    John McDowell has deployed a powerful strategy against the idea that the representa-

    tional content of personal level experience includes nonconceptual content.1 I call it

    the kidnapping strategy. The literature on nonconceptual content abounds with

    examples about the fine-grainedness of perceptual experience which, it is claimed,

    illustrate that experience represents properties that fall between the grip of the subjects

    conceptual repertoire.2 The kidnapping strategy shows how such representations can

    be rendered conceptual by treating them as examples of short-lived recognitional

    capacities for the fine-grained properties in question. In this paper I present an

    argument for nonconceptual content that is compatible with this strategy. The

    examples that I employ involve auditory perception, in particular, our experience of

    music. I shall briefly extend the argument to other sense modalities.

    1. Outline of the Case for Nonconceptual Content

    Suppose a subjects personal level experience represents something as F. Where therepresentation of F-ness is conceptual, the content of that part of the subjects

    experience at issue can be thought of as a component of the proposition expressed

    by the sentence,

    Earlier versions of this material were presented at CREA, Paris, University College, London, andthe University of Manchester. Thanks to all those present for hard questions and helpfulsuggestions. Thanks also to my colleagues Naomi Eilan, Christoph Hoerl, Peter Poellner andJohannes Roessler and to an anonymous referee for helpful comments on an earlier draft.

    Address for correspondence: Department of Philosophy, University of Warwick, Coventry,

    CV4 7AL, UK.Email: [email protected]

  • 8/12/2019 Non-Conceptual Content and the Soudn of Music

    2/26

    such-and-such is F.

    I disregard for present purposes the component that occupies subject position. If

    the content is conceptual it will be what we ordinarily call a concept. Bynonconceptual contents, I mean ways of representing properties that take

    predicate position in propositions which characterise a subjects experience and

    yet are not expressible with concepts the subject possesses. The challenge in

    making the case for nonconceptual content is to provide examples in which it

    makes sense to report on the subjects experience by saying that it represents:

    such-and-such is F

    and yet the subject has no capacity for grasping the proposition in terms of theircurrent conceptual repertoire. The fact that the point is put in terms of a proposi-

    tion that the subject cannot grasp should not be taken to entail that nonconceptual

    content is itself propositional in structure. Indeed, the phenomenology of non-

    conceptual content suggests quite the opposite.3 The idea then is that the proposi-

    tion in question characterises part of the content of the subjects experience, but

    they have no resources for expressing that proposition themselves. Put like that, it

    can both seem easy to accommodate the idea of nonconceptual content at the sub-

    personal level (in terms of propositions that express the information handled by

    sub-personal systems) and problematic to accommodate nonconceptual content at

    the personal level. Prima facie, the very idea of personal level nonconceptual

    content seems unintelligible, for how can a subjects personal level experience

    include the representation that such-and-such is Fand yet the subject not know

    this? The conceptualist will protest that if the content of the subjects personal level

    experience represents the way that the world is for them, how can the world be a

    certain way for them without their having a grip on it being that way for them?

    The protest points up a real difficulty.

    The notion of personal level experience is the notion of experience that is

    phenomenologically real; the content in which we are interested is the content

    of experience that characterises the subjects point of view on the world. Personallevel nonconceptual content is content that characterises the subjects point of view

    but is invisible to their concepts. If concepts are the means by which things and

    properties are brought into experience, then nonconceptual content must be

    invisible to the subjects point of view. So, how could nonconceptual content be

    3 Of course, it is not clear that this proposition is well-formed if it has a conceptual componentin subject position and a nonconceptual component in the predicate position. It is best to treat

    the propositions that express nonconceptual contents as nonconceptual through and through.For now, I simplify and concentrate on the predicate position. It is plausible to think that ifthe predicate component is nonconceptual the subject component must be also, for if the

    Non-conceptual Content 403

  • 8/12/2019 Non-Conceptual Content and the Soudn of Music

    3/26

    part of the subjects point of view? There appears to be an easy response to this

    protest. The response is to provide examples in which the subjects experience

    discriminates F-ness even though the subject lacks the concept of F-ness. For

    example, the subject discriminates a colour shade, e.g., magenta. The discrimin-ation is at the personal level (it hardly seems right to deny that the colour is, in

    some sense, there for them), and yet they do not possess the concept magenta. So

    the proposition expressed by:

    such-and-such is magenta

    characterises part of the content of the subjects experience but is invisible to the

    subject, for they have no resources for expressing it.4 It is this response that falls

    foul of McDowells kidnapping strategy. The fact that the subject cannot express aconceptual encounter with magenta using the word magenta does not show that

    their discrimination of the shade is nonconceptual. Their discrimination will be

    conceptual if we say that the proposition that characterises the content is that

    expressed by the sentence:

    such-and-such is that colour

    under appropriate circumstances of use where that colour expresses a short-lived

    recognitional capacity. This manoeuvre appears to be available to kidnap any

    putative example of nonconceptual content. The propositions that characterise

    the conceptual content of a subjects experience may only be expressible with

    context-sensitive linguistic items, but as long as the subject has some resources for

    expressing a conceptual discrimination ofF-ness, it hardly matters whether or not

    they have the resource that uses the normal word forF-ness. Lacking the canonical

    resources for expressing the concept of F-ness does not constitute lack of a

    conceptual discrimination ofF-ness.5

    In order to show that nonconceptual content has a role to play in characterising

    the subjects personal level take on the world, we require examples in which it is

    correct to say both that the proposition expressed by:

    such-and-such is F

    characterises part of the representational content of their experience and that the

    subject has no resources for expressing a conceptual discrimination ofF-ness. They

    must be conceptually blind with respect to F-ness. Most examples in the literature

    4

    It is only the component in predicate position that I am assuming is conceptually invisible, cfprevious footnote.

    5 The fact that the expression of the concept is context-sensitive will also determine the extent

    404 M. Luntley

  • 8/12/2019 Non-Conceptual Content and the Soudn of Music

    4/26

    on nonconceptual content do not prove this conceptual blindness; at best they

    illustrate lack of the canonical conceptual resources for discriminating F-ness.6

    The requirement of conceptual blindness with respect to F-ness in order to

    make the case for nonconceptual content reveals the potency of the kidnappingstrategy.7 There is a prima facie difficulty in showing both that a subjects personal

    level experience represents F-ness and that the subject is conceptually blind to

    F-ness. Nevertheless, the requirement of conceptual blindness with respect to

    F-ness shows why the conceptualist protest of three paragraphs back begs the

    question. The protest was:

    How can experience represent the world as being a certain way for a subject

    without the subject having some conceptual resources for expressing that way,

    for concepts are the ways in which things and properties are for us inexperience?

    The problem for the nonconceptualist is that it seems to make sense to suppose that

    as soon as you notice something in experience it gets conceptualised. So the

    nonconceptualist has to challenge the assumption that concepts are the only way

    in which things and properties are for us in experience. What needs to be shown is

    the possibility of things you notice that you cannot conceptualisethings and

    properties made available in experience that you struggle to pick up. To pick them

    up in experience is to make the discrimination available for the rational organisa-

    tion of behaviour by the subject. The conceptualists protest is question begging for

    it ignores the possibility of there being elements of experience that discriminate

    things but which cannot be rationally deployed. Showing that this is possible

    requires a more radical departure from the conceptualist model than that which

    depends on examples about the fine-grainedness of experience, but it is not

    obvious that such a possibility can be ruled out a priori. It may turn out that no

    convincing examples can be given to illustrate the idea of a capacity to discriminate

    6 Crane (1992) explicitly put the case in terms of canonical versus non-canonical resources fordiscrimination. Bermudez and Peacocke sometimes express the idea of nonconceptual contentin a way that leaves it unclear with respect to which concepts fine-grainedness is characterised:(Bermudez, 1995 p. 335) the richness and grain of perceptual experience is not constrainedby the concepts a perceiver might or might not express; (Peacocke, 1992 p. 67) anexperience can have a finer-grained content that can be formulated using conceptspossessed by the experiencer. At other times both explicitly characterise fine-grainednesswith respect to descriptive concepts. Bermudez, 1994 p. 403 says that the idea ofnonconceptual content is particularly pertinent in the case of modalities for which veryfew people have a developed descriptive vocabulary. Peacocke (1992 p. 67) says that thecontent of visual perception when looking at rounded jagged mountains is far more

    specific than that description indicates. Kelly, 2001 argues that the fine-grainednessargument is too weak. See Heck, 2000 for a different argument in terms of the rolenonconceptual content plays in explaining our possession of conceptual content. See also

    Non-conceptual Content 405

  • 8/12/2019 Non-Conceptual Content and the Soudn of Music

    5/26

    F-ness which fails to satisfy the requirements on being a conceptual capacity, but it

    is an issue whether it has to be the case that no such examples can be given. By

    presenting the case for nonconceptual content in terms of a capacity to discriminate

    F-ness that fails on one of the marks of a conceptual capacity, the dialectic of thedebate swings round to put pressure on what is meant by saying of a capacity to

    discriminate F-ness that it is conceptual. It will not do simply to assume that

    capacities to discriminate are conceptual. So the issue is this: Under what condi-

    tions are we entitled to say that a subjects experience represents F-ness in giving

    them a capacity to discriminate F-ness and yet the subject is conceptually blind to

    F-ness?

    The idea behind the account of nonconceptual content that I want to promote

    can now be stated. I follow McDowell in taking concepts as filling out the space of

    the subjects reasons. The conceptual content of experience is content that canfigure in the subjects reasons for belief and action where the subjects reasons are

    identified with contents that figure in inferences.8 So I take the following as a mark

    of a conceptual capacity:

    If subject S has a conceptual capacity for discriminating F-ness (their experi-

    ence represents F-ness in some way), the representation of F-ness must be

    capable of contributing to the rational organisation of their behaviour by

    figuring in their inferential reasons for belief/action.

    This is not uncontentious. I am assuming that the only way a content can

    contribute to the rational organisation of behaviour is by being available for the

    subject to deploy in inference. This assumption would be denied by what we

    might call the Quick Argument for nonconceptual content. The quick argument

    says that nonconceptual content is content that figures in non-inferential reasons

    for action, e.g. the content deployed in imagistic reasoning. The best reason for

    endorsing such an argument is that it introduces a level of content possession of

    which can be used to explain full-blown conceptual content.9 The case is not

    proven or straightforward.10 For one thing, there is a danger that the quick

    argument reintroduces the given, the avoidance of which has been central toMcDowells defence of conceptualism. Campbell argues that reference to objects

    requires selective attention and that selective attention is the notion we need to

    describe the link between propositional and imagistic content.11 This seems right,

    8 It matters that it is the subjects reasons, not a third-party account of the subjects reasons forbelief/action, that is stake here, cf McDowell, 1994 p. 163ff for use of the distinctionbetween the subjects reasons for action and the theorists account of reasons for the

    subjects actions. Peacockes argument against McDowell seems to ignore this distinction,cf McDowell, 1998 and also Peacocke, 1998.

    9 Campbell, 1997; Heck, 2000; Eilan, 2001.

    406 M. Luntley

  • 8/12/2019 Non-Conceptual Content and the Soudn of Music

    6/26

    but runs the risk of leaving conceptual content detached from anchorage in objects

    and anchored only in the nonconceptual imagistic level of content. That would

    threaten the epistemological advantage of the conceptualist position that has the

    conceptual content of our reasons reaching right out to things.12

    If the case fornonconceptual content rests solely on the quick argument, the phenomenological

    point of nonconceptual content is left undeveloped. It also threatens the return of

    the given. The argument that I give turns on getting the phenomenological detail

    of auditory experience right. The position I defend is compatible with Campbells

    account of nonconceptual content, but the route I take shows why the concern

    about the given is unfounded. My concern is to show the phenomenological place

    of nonconceptual content, to show that it exists regardless of its potential role in

    explaining the existence of conceptual content.

    Given the above as the mark of conceptual content, the trick to showing thatnonconceptual content has a role to play in characterising personal level experience

    is to find ways of discriminating things in experience that cannot contribute to the

    subjects rational organisation of their behaviour. At the same time, such compon-

    ents must not drop through into the merely causal determinants of behaviour at

    the sub-personal level. The simple idea that I want to explore can then be summed

    up as follows:

    The capacity to discriminate F-ness as contributing to the content of the

    subjects experience is nonconceptual if and only if the capacity cannot

    contribute to the subjects rational organisation of their behaviour.

    As noted, much hangs on what it means for a capacity to discriminate F-ness to

    contribute to the subjects rational organisation of their behaviour. That is what

    makes such a capacity conceptual and its absence is what leaves it nonconceptual.

    The first task in clarifying the case for nonconceptual content is to put more

    substance to this key idea.

    2. The Mark of Conceptual Content

    Consider hierarchies of concepts such that concepts of level 1 fall under a sortal of

    level 2 which in turn falls under a sortal of level 3, etc. For example, let the

    concepts of red, green and magenta be level 1 concepts; colour a level 2 concept;

    the way things look a level 3 concept. Suppose subject S has an experience that

    represents magenta, they discriminate it. McDowells strategy is to say that even if

    they lack the appropriate level 1 expression for the concept, their experience can

    be kidnapped conceptually by:

    Non-conceptual Content 407

  • 8/12/2019 Non-Conceptual Content and the Soudn of Music

    7/26

    such-and-such is that colour.

    McDowell, 1994, 1998, is clear that the conceptual content represented by the

    phrase that colour is the content of a short-lived recognitional capacity; it is not acontent in which the level 2 concept colour figures as a componentcall that a

    compound demonstrative concept. For the moment I ignore the distinction

    between recognitional and compound demonstrative concepts, although I shall

    later discharge this.13

    Suppose that the concept deployed in the kidnapping strategy is a compound

    demonstrative concept. The case for nonconceptual content will be illustrated if

    we can produce examples of subjects who are novices with the sortal required to

    deploy the kidnapping strategy. In the case of colour examples we would need a

    subject who had no grasp of the sortal concept colour and yet had the ability todiscriminate, say, magenta, so that we would say that their experience represented

    such-and-such as being magenta. Their lack of grasp of the sortalcolourwould then

    make the kidnapping strategy unavailable, for it requires that the content of their

    experience is the content expressed by:

    such-and-such is that colour

    but, by hypothesis, the concept that colour is not available to them.14 In the visual

    case it is hard to see how such an example could be available. In part, this is due to

    the sophistication of our visual concepts and the central role they play in determin-

    ing action. In auditory perception this structure is easier to satisfy. Testing the

    phenomenology of music perception against such a theoretical structure is, how-

    ever, only of value if I discharge the assumption that the distinction between

    recognitional and compound demonstrative concepts does not matter. Discharging

    this assumption turns on a key mark of conceptual content in McDowells theory.

    The mark of conceptual content for McDowell is that concepts fill out the

    space of reasons. This means that concepts are content components that have the

    potential to figure in the subjects rational organisation of their behaviour (beliefs

    and actions). For a representation of F-ness to be conceptual it must have thepotential to figure in Ss reasons for behaviour. On the assumption that contents

    that figure in reasons do so in virtue of figuring in inferences, then in order to have

    this potential, the representation of F-ness must have a capacity to recur in

    combination with other contents in inferences. By such means the representation

    13 Concepts formed from sortals and demonstratives are property-dependent concepts in thesame way that demonstrative ways of thinking about objects are object-dependent. Propertydependent concepts are ways of thinking about properties that depend on the subject

    keeping the property in perceptual experience. Cf Luntley, 2002 for further discussion ofexamples.

    14 Lack of the sortal concept colouris not the same as lack of use of the word colour. A subject

    408 M. Luntley

  • 8/12/2019 Non-Conceptual Content and the Soudn of Music

    8/26

    ofF-ness satisfies the Generality Constraint on content.15 So, if the representation

    ofF-ness is to fall within the subjects space of reasons, it must be possible for it to

    be entertained and recur in contents other than that in which it is given in

    experience thus underpinning the rational connectivity of the contents availableto the subject. In short, suppose S has an experience that includes the content

    expressed by:

    such-and-such is F.

    If the representation ofF-ness is conceptual it must have the capacity to recur in

    other propositions, e.g.,

    All Fs are G

    making it rational for S to conclude that:

    such-and-such is G.

    The subject might not exploit the connections rationality provides, what matters is

    that the representation has the capacity to be combined with other representations

    to underwrite the rational linkages of belief and of belief and action. That the

    representation has the capacity to be so deployed must, of course, be understood in

    terms of the subjects conceptual repertoire at the time of the experience, it cannot

    be a capacity for rational deployment that depended on an increase in Ss cognitive

    abilities. In conclusion, if the representation of F-ness is conceptual it must have

    the combinatorial capacity typical of propositional components without S needing

    to acquire any further information or concepts. This is what it means for the

    representation to be available to Ss reasons. The test I propose for this is to say that

    if the representation is available to Ss reasons, there must be an argument con-

    cerning Ss beliefs, that exploits the representation, the validity of which is trans-

    parent to S. The requirement of transparency is to ensure that the validity of the

    argument does not require further information or cognitive enhancement.16

    For example, suppose S attends to a magenta coloured item and they have only a

    very limited stock of colour names and a poor descriptive vocabulary for colours.

    We say that the appropriate part of the representational content of their experience

    is characterised by the proposition expressed by:

    such-and-such is that colour.

    15

    Evans, 1982 was clear that nonconceptual content failed the generality constraint p. 104 n.22,but then his notion of nonconceptual content was not a personal-level notion of content.Peacocke (1992), Bermudez (1995), Heck (2000) also acknowledge that nonconceptual

    Non-conceptual Content 409

  • 8/12/2019 Non-Conceptual Content and the Soudn of Music

    9/26

    If it is correct to see this proposition composed of conceptual components, then,

    regardless of whether it is a compound demonstrative content or the content of a

    short-lived recognitional capacity, the that colour must be capable of figuring in

    other propositions inferentially connected in a way that is transparent to S. Forexample, if S possesses the concepts of brightness and attractiveness, then, without

    increase in Ss cognitive abilities, the validity of:

    That colour is bright.

    Bright colours are attractive.

    That colour is attractive.

    will be transparent to S. In other words, the validity of the inference does not require

    an identity premiss linking the first occurrence of that colour and its occurrence in

    the conclusion. The inference exploits the subjects capacity to hold that contentsteady in thought and re-employ it in different whole thoughts. This is mastery of a

    concept and the transparent validity of the inference exploits Ss mastery. The that

    colour must then be a conceptual content. A further argument against restricting

    reasons to inferential reasons is given by Hurley (2001) who thinks that practical

    reasoning that exploits a subjects perceptions can employ reasons to act that lack the

    hallmark context-freedom of conceptual inferential reasons. I think Hurley overstates

    this context-freedom; see also Brewer, 2001 and Noe, 2002.

    For any account that takes seriously the demonstratively expressed conceptual

    contents exploited in McDowells kidnapping strategy it will have to be the case

    that the rational deployment of such contents is context-bound. Context bound

    contents will only be available for context-bound inferences. This is something

    made clear by the requirement of transparency above. The transparency of an

    inference turns on the subject being able to trade on the identity of sense of the

    relevant component and that is something that, in turn, is context-sensitive. To

    suggest that the concept of practical reason automatically requires a notion of

    nonconceptual content because practical reasons do not enjoy the context-freedom

    of reasons fully expressed linguistically is to ignore the very idea of context-bound

    concepts that is central to the conceptualists account of experience. It is also to

    assume an overly abstract model of concepts and to work with too crude a conceptof the practical.17 I think there is little value in pursuing the issue who is right

    about whether practical reasoning shows the existence of nonconceptual contents

    and reasons without first getting a lot more detail in the examples that show that

    the conceptualist position is incomplete. I propose then to continue to assume that

    believing/acting for a reason requires possession of a content that is available to

    inference. This might strengthen the conceptualist position, but it ends up allowing

    a more discriminative range of options with regard to conceptual practical reasons

    and, crucially, the existence of nonconceptual content.

    17 See Noe, 2002 p. 187 for a criticism of Hurleys overly reflective model of conceptual

    410 M. Luntley

  • 8/12/2019 Non-Conceptual Content and the Soudn of Music

    10/26

    The account of what it is for a representation to have the capacity to figure in

    the subjects rational organisation of their behaviour places a constraint on the

    operation of the kidnapping strategy. There is a danger of being too liberal with the

    kidnapping strategy and thinking that a putative nonconceptual content can bekidnapped just in case the subject is prone to respond with:

    I f that colour

    where f is an attitude verb such as, like, want, dislike. The existence of that

    response alone is insufficient to kidnap the content. For the kidnap to work the

    representation must be available to figure in an argument that is transparent to the

    subject. I shall proceed as if the kidnapping strategy employs compound demonstra-

    tive concepts. The strategy will then be twofold. First, I shall show that there can berepresentational contents of experience that cannot be kidnapped by such means

    because the subject lacks grasp of the appropriate sortal concept. Second, I shall

    develop the examples in sufficient detail to show that there is nothing to the idea that

    a concept based on a short-lived recognitional capacity might suffice for kidnapping

    the representation instead. I start with the compound demonstrative concept.

    The formulation of the first part of my strategy camouflages an important and

    interesting range of cases that pose difficulties for the nonconceptualist. These are

    cases in which the subjects possession of the sortal concept is expressed with higher

    order sortals. Recall the hierarchy of concepts mentioned above. Suppose the

    concepts exploited in visual perception arrange in the following hierarchy:

    Level 1 concepts: magenta, green, circular, dodecahedron . . .

    Level 2 concepts: colour, shape, brightness . . .

    Level 3 concepts: how things look, . . .

    Level 2 concepts are the sortals for level 1 concepts, and level 3 is sortal for level 2.

    I use F for level 1 concepts; G for level 2 concepts and H for level 3 concepts.

    The obvious way of exploiting the kidnapping requirement is to say that a

    representation of F-ness is kidnapped just in case the subject finds transparent anargument employing thatG. But that leaves out of the picture the possibility that

    the subjects mastery of G is, in turn expressed contextually and manifest in their

    finding transparent arguments employing thatH. Of course, for use of thatH, to

    manifest grasp of the concept of colour, let alone colour concepts, we will demand

    that behaviour manifests a discriminative ability to distinguish between ways things

    look, and behaviour here will have to include taking the validity of the appropriate

    inferences as transparent. In principle, however, the expression of the sortal that the

    subject exploits in order for the representation to be kidnapped need not belong at

    the next level up from the target concept. Allowing that the appropriate sortalcould belong at higher levels introduces the possibility that a large segment of

    ld i i i l i if d i l

    Non-conceptual Content 411

  • 8/12/2019 Non-Conceptual Content and the Soudn of Music

    11/26

    complex nestings of thatH. The possibility of constructing such an account of

    concept possession for significant segments of our conceptual explains the power

    latent in the kidnapping manoeuvre.18 Acknowledging this power means that we

    have to read the kidnapping strategy in a way that places no a priori restriction onthe linguistic level from which the sortal is taken. What matters is that from

    whatever level the sortal is taken, its use manifests a combinatorial potential

    appropriate for the target concept. Being competent with a concept, or being

    a novice, is not a matter of vocabulary.

    In the light of the above clarification of the way the kidnapping strategy works we can

    now formulate a confirmation condition for the existence of nonconceptual content:19

    Confirmation condition: A representation ofF-ness will be nonconceptual if

    (a) the subject can discriminateF-ness, (b) the subject is a novice with respectto the sortal concepts required for generating demonstrative kidnapping

    concepts, (c) the subject fails to treat transparently the validity of inferences

    that exploit a conceptual representation ofF-ness.

    Satisfaction of clause (c) discharges my assumption that it does not matter that

    I ignore the distinction between compound demonstrative and short-lived recogni-

    tional concepts.

    3. The Sound of Music

    In order to construct examples to illustrate the existence of nonconceptual content

    I borrow some terminology from DeBelliss treatment of these issues.20 DeBellis has

    argued that an important part of the content our musical experience is nonconcep-

    tual. I agree with his conclusion, but not with his argument. DeBellis distinguishes

    18 The idea of practical concept mastery is frequently overlooked. I return to it in the nextsection. Bermudez (1997) employs a simple dichotomy between practical engagedunreflective representations and reflective theoretical representations. Bermudez representsCampbell (1994) as offering just such a simple contrast, as if a practical engaged grasp ofcausation in actionhasto be unreflective and thereby not a conceptual one. In fact, it seem tome that Campbell says no such thing. For sure, his notion of causal indexical representation isconcerned with an immersed grasp of causation in action that is unreflective, e.g. seeCampbell, 1997a, p. 634. This does not, however, mean that there cannot also be apractical form of representation which is reflective and hence conceptual without requiringthe apparatus of theoretical representations. Indeed, Campbell (1997b) allows that option, seecomment at p. 658 contrasting the theoretical linguists explanations of language structurewith the grammarians practical familiarity with structure. From now on, I use practical topick out an immersed engaged conceptual representation. The concept of practice that I amusing is, for present purposes, a concept of something that is in principle open to reflection.

    19

    This is a strong condition the meeting of which confirms the existence of nonconceptualcontent. I do not rule out cases in which the subject is competent with the appropriate sortalconcept, but in such cases everything turns on the empirical matter of the sophistication of

    412 M. Luntley

  • 8/12/2019 Non-Conceptual Content and the Soudn of Music

    12/26

    between weakly nonconceptual content and strongly nonconceptual content. The

    former is open to the kidnapping strategy, for it captures elements of musical

    experience for which the subject lacks music-theoretic concepts and that leaves

    such elements open to kidnap by other concepts.21

    DeBelliss notion of stronglynonconceptual content captures the content of a hearing that is not the exercise of

    any concept.22 This is a notion of content for which the subject is conceptually

    blind. The problem with DeBelliss case for strongly nonconceptual content is that

    the argument draws upon empirical research into listening abilities which are plaus-

    ibly seen as involving discriminations operating at the sub-personal level.23 Such

    examples do not address the phenomenological issue that I want to get into focus.

    Where DeBellis considers personal level characterisations of experiences, most of the

    time he contrasts listening informed by music-theoretic concepts and listening not so

    informed.

    24

    Apart from the fact that lack of deployment of music-theoretic conceptsdoes not amount to a lack of concepts, this dichotomy leaves too much lumped

    together on the second category. No case for nonconceptual content can be made

    unless we can rule out the sort of contextualised practical conceptual listening that is

    characteristic of many musical idioms, especially those with a strong folk tradition.

    For example, jazz and blues musicians often have a comprehensive and

    deeply comprehending perception of music without that perception being

    informed by music theory. They have a sense of immersion in a musical land-

    scape of melodies, harmonies and rhythms that they navigate in a manner not

    unlike our navigation of the spatial environment.25 This is a form of practical

    knowledge and practical belief that lies between the novice listener and the

    musical theorist.26 Indeed, to say that this form of musical knowledge lies

    between the poles that, most of the time, DeBellis, considers is already to

    beg important questions. For many purposes, it is the hands-on, ears-alert

    understanding of where you are in a melody or harmonic progression that

    matters, not the theoretical grasp.

    The key concept that I want to take from DeBellis is that of an expectation.27

    Expectations are components of experience that have satisfaction conditions. In

    21 See the discussion of Budd at pp. 268. See p. 28 for DeBelliss acknowledgement of thekidnapping strategy.

    22 DeBellis, p. 57.23 See the discussion of pitch representation at pp. 613.24 It is, for example, the topic of Chapter 5 although, by that point of the book, his interest is

    not in the topic of nonconceptual content as such, but in understanding the differencesbetween novice and theoretically informed listeners.

    25 See Sudnow (1993) for explorations of the phenomenology of jazz piano that are full of thesesorts of remarks.

    26 This sort of practical competence is precisely the sort of concept mastery that comes into

    view once we acknowledge the idea that concept possession can be generated from complexnestings of what are, from the music-theoretic point of view, rather crude sortals. See section2 above, especially footnote 18.

    Non-conceptual Content 413

  • 8/12/2019 Non-Conceptual Content and the Soudn of Music

    13/26

    listening to music our experience gives us expectations about melodic, harmonic

    and rhythmic progression. We can think of these expectations in terms of sets of

    subjective probabilities that capture the way we expect a piece of music to

    develop. These expectations can be satisfied or not; it is this that makes themrepresentational. To take a simple harmonic example, on hearing a 7th chord,

    most listeners will have a strong expectation of the related tonic; hearing a D7

    chord creates a strong expectation that a G major chord is due. The experience of

    the D7 chord has a content that represents a sort of tension, it has a pullingness-

    to-a-resolution quality about the experience of the chord. It is this quality that

    captures the expectation. Subsequently, on hearing the tonic chord, most listen-

    ers have a sense of completion, the music is at rest and there is no further

    expectation about what comes next. I shall characterise the content of these

    respective experiences as:

    (1) It sounds V7

    and,

    (2) It sounds I.

    I use V7 to represent the dominant 7th chord and I to represent the tonic. (1)

    and (2) are the theoreticians ways of cataloguing the expectational content of

    experience; they are not ways of characterising the content by the subject. I shall

    just say that, for the subject, they have expectations. The expectational content of

    (1) is that it assigns a high probability to:

    (3) It will sound I,

    an expectation that is satisfied when the experience represented by (2) occurs.

    Expectations can be treated in terms of probabilities assigned to propositions, but

    only from the theoreticians point of view. From the point of view of the

    phenomenology of the subject there is no such propositional content. The issueis whether such experiences can be rationally inert. I shall assume that expectations

    are rationally inert; the test is to provide an example that illustrates this. The

    examples involve a novice listener.

    By a novice I mean someone who lacks both music-theoretic knowledge and

    the practical competence of a musical performer and, analogously, they lack a

    practical competence at listening. The practical competence of a performer might

    depend on music-theoretic knowledge or it might depend on a demonstratively

    articulated musical knowledge. By the same token, although this is more difficult

    and rarer than practical competence at performance, there can be a practicallistening competence that consists in a demonstratively articulated knowledge of

    i d b i h i k l d S hi i d f hi

    414 M. Luntley

  • 8/12/2019 Non-Conceptual Content and the Soudn of Music

    14/26

    out a harmonic or melodic progression and recognise it, where the recognition

    consists in your ability to place yourself within it without necessarily being able to

    articulate in music-theoretic terms where you are. This is a complicated achieve-

    ment. A simpler illustration of practical listening would be the case of a guitarist who,on hearing a tune, can recognise the chord progression and find it immediately on

    the guitar neck. Guitarists can survive with only a rudimentary grasp of theory. It is

    common to recognise a progression with, as it were, your fingers without stopping

    to think theoretically about which key you are in or which chords you are playing.28

    Exploiting such recognitional capacities gives the listener with practical competence

    a rich systematicity to their musical experience.

    In contrast, the novice has no systematicity to their musical listening. It is

    doubtful that anyone is a novice with respect to all aspects of musical hearing,

    but most of us are novices with respect to some. That is all that is required for whatfollows. We need cases in which the novice has an experience that represents some

    musical featureF. The experience representsFbecause it produces the expectation

    appropriate forF-ness, but the discrimination has no generality to it.

    Consider in more detail our experience of tonality. Much music in the western

    tradition gives us an experience of being in a key. The music has a harmonic

    structure to do with our sense of tension and rest within it. The harmonic structure

    of simple tunes is normally representable with three chords based on the first,

    fourth and fifth notes of the scale: the tonic, sub-dominant and dominant or

    dominant 7th. We represent these as I, IV and V or V7. The use of V7 instead

    of V gives a stronger sense of tonal centre, for the sound of a dominant 7th chord

    has such a powerful pull towards the tonic that it is almost impossible to hear a

    dominant 7th chord without a sense of tonality centred on the respective tonic. I

    suggest that the sense of tonality produced by hearing the dominant 7th is, for the

    novice, a nonconceptual representational content. This sense of tonality means that

    if the subject hears the tonic chord, the music will sound at rest. The case I am

    suggesting involves no more than the isolated hearing of a 7th chord and the way

    that such a hearing produces a sense of tonality. This is representational because it

    has correctness conditions and, furthermore, they are correctness conditions to

    which the subject has some access, for, if they hear the tonic chord the subject willbe disposed to say That sounds right. And, similarly, should some other chord be

    28 Like the piano, the guitar offers not only the opportunity for playing more than one note at atime, but it has all its notes spatially arranged under the hands. Competence with chordshapes exploits a spatial sense of where the chords lie and what shape they have. A similarpoint applies to scales. The difference between, say, a Major, Minor, or blues pentatonic scalein so far as it is grasped by anything other than how they sound is often grasped in terms ofdifferent spatial patterns across the neck. Such practical competence requires an extensiverange of recognitional capacities, but it does not require mastery of music-theoretic concepts.

    Both the case of the jazz musician and the guitarist are best conceived as subjects who exploitrecognitional capacities for the relevant musical properties, recognitional capacities that getexpressed demonstratively. I am still ignoring the distinction between recognitional-based

    Non-conceptual Content 415

  • 8/12/2019 Non-Conceptual Content and the Soudn of Music

    15/26

    played, they will affirm, That sounds wrong. Let me make this suggestion more

    precise.

    I shall say that the novice has an experience, on hearing the chord of D7, that

    I shall represent as,

    (4) That sounds V7.

    That is to say, there is a way that the music sounds that indicates that hearing G

    major will be experienced as the music moving to a position of rest. The experi-

    ence of tonality need not be the same as expecting that a G major chord will come

    next. The expectation about what comes next can be a different expectation,

    although in the limited case I am currently considering, the two thingsa sense

    of tonality and the sense of what is due nextinvariably have the same content. Inmore complex contexts the content of the experience can be more sophisticated.29

    I use (4) to represent, from the theoreticians point of view, the representational

    content of the novices experience. What I am assuming as uncontroversial is the

    claim that the novice has a sense of tension in the music that amounts to the

    expectation that the harmonic progression to the tonic is called for.30 Their

    experience assigns a high probability to,

    (5) That will sound I.

    The issue concerns the nature of the representational content of the expectation. If

    it is correct to say that the novice has a sense of tension or pull in the music, then it

    is legitimate to say that their experience discriminates the V7-ness of the music.

    Hence, it is legitimate to employ (4) to represent the representational content of

    their experience.

    Can the content of (4) be kidnapped? To be kidnapped, the representation of

    V7-ness must be capable of figuring in Ss space of reasons. It is not enough to

    kidnap this merely to suggest that S hears,

    (6) That soundsthat way,

    where that way is either the expression of a recognitional capacity or a demon-

    strative concept. Simply claiming a recognitional capacity is too quick.

    29 For example, hearing a D7 after a D major chord might produce an expectation that a Gmajor will follow, but this does not necessarily mean that the tonality is centred on the key ofG. It is common, on hearing D7 following D to have a sense of tonality centred on D. In partthis is due to the D major chord setting the tonal centre, it is also because the harmonic

    transition in the move from D to D7 is a common move in a twelve bar blues to introducethe sub-dominant at bar 5. In such a case, the tonal centre stays on D, and the G major chordis the sub-dominant.

    416 M. Luntley

  • 8/12/2019 Non-Conceptual Content and the Soudn of Music

    16/26

    An expectation is, even if nonconceptual, a capacity to represent a property that

    can be redeployed. It is a repeatable component of experiences over time. The

    repeatability of the capacity to represent a property is not enough to make it

    conceptual. What makes a recognitional capacity conceptual is its potential tocontribute to Ss rational organisation of their behaviour. In order for that way

    to be a conceptual representation there must be some argument the validity of

    which is transparent to S without S acquiring further information or cognitive

    enhancement. The basic idea for nonconceptual content is very simple.

    Nonconceptual representations are ways in which we respond to the world that

    we are not able to rationally organise. They are representations that provide us

    with a response to X, but not a rational response; they are not responses that can

    figure in the rational organisation of behaviour.31 So the novice responds to V7,

    they discriminate it, but their discrimination does not and can not rationally bearupon their behaviour. This is not to say that the nonconceptual representation

    introduces an element of the given in experience. The nonconceptual representa-

    tion provide a means of orientating directly to the environment, but it is an

    orientation that produces no rational pattern to behaviour. If such an orientation

    is to be kidnapped, we need a lot more detail to see whether a kidnap works.

    First, suppose the expectation is to be kidnapped by a concept figuring in subject

    position. This requires that there should a transparent argument of the form,

    That way sound is F

    Fs are G

    That way sound is G.

    For the novice, by definition, there is a shortage of candidates for the concepts Fand

    G. In order for the representation to be kidnapped, there has to be the space in the

    subjects conceptual repertoire in which the representation can exercise the combi-

    natorial potential that makes it conceptual, rather than nonconceptual. Of course,

    there could be a conceptual content available to the novice, e.g., if the music does

    not resolve as they expect, they hear the sound as not nice. But what we need is a

    conceptual content with respect to V7-ness, not nice does not capture the expecta-tion hears V7. Indeed, with respect to non-satisfaction of the expectation produced

    on hearing a dominant 7th, not nice is a sophisticated concept, it presupposes that

    the subject possess some means for detecting the dominant 7th but it does not

    provide access to, its sense does not determine, the property of being a dominant 7th.

    31 By rational organisation of behaviour I mean an organisation in which the content isavailable to the subject in inference. Anyone who thinks that spatial reasoning deploysnonconceptual contents simply because the contents are deployed in imagination rather

    than pure thought is in danger of assuming too intellectualist a model of inference. Asnoted above, demonstrative inference has to be understood in less than a fully articulatedlinguistic structure. I prefer to load the dice in favour of the conceptualist and still find space

    Non-conceptual Content 417

  • 8/12/2019 Non-Conceptual Content and the Soudn of Music

    17/26

    The novice lacks the appropriate space in which the representation can, as it

    were, be exercised. In general, a subjects inarticulacy with respect to a feature does

    not entail lack of a conceptual orientation. It does, however, make it harder to see

    what possession of a conceptual orientation can consist in. In visual perceptionthere is normally a large number of potential sortal concepts available that can be

    exploited in the kidnapping strategy. Even if the subject lacks the appropriate

    sortal, the range of concepts that can be applied to visual perception by normal

    subjects means that appeal to short-lived recognitional capacities to kidnap putative

    nonconceptual representations is in line with the richness of the conceptual

    resources of the normal subjectthe content of the recognitional capacity is

    secured by the surrounding conceptual structure of the subjects repertoire. In

    auditory perception there is a much smaller standard stock of concepts available for

    organising auditory perception. In auditory perception, our relative inarticulacyshows up a conceptual naivety of an order that simply would not be warranted

    when considering examples from visual perception.

    It is a condition on applying a recognitional capacity, or demonstrative concept,

    to kidnap a putative nonconceptual representation that there be an argument the

    validity of which is transparent to the subject. No argument with the representa-

    tion in subject position appears to be available. There is a sense in which the

    subject recognises the V7-ness of the music: they discriminate it; it sounds familiar;

    it makes other musical events sound right and others sound out of place. None of

    this, however, shows that there is a conceptual representation of V7-ness, for in

    order for that be in place, the subject would have to find transparent the validity of

    an argument that turned on the concept of V7-ness. But for the novice, there is no

    such argument. The novice lacks the sortals for constructing a compound demon-

    strative concept and therefore lacks the conceptual space in which a recognitional

    capacity could exercise its conceptual muscle. Consider now the possibility that the

    representation could be kidnapped in predicate position.

    Could our subject not think something like this,

    (7) x sounds that1 way

    things that sound that1 way sound that2 wayx will sound that2 way

    where that1way is the concept that kidnaps the representation of V7? Clearly, the

    subject might think something like (7). The issues is whether we can show that

    their that1way has the right sense to pick out V7. (7) is easy to say, but difficult to

    mean with the appropriate sense. I have three arguments against such a kidnap.

    First, for the kidnap to work we need to be sure that the that1way has the correct

    reference. Our subject might speak of things sounding that way, but the issue is

    whether they have a sense that picks out the V7 character that I am claimingthe novice can hear. For sure the novice can hear the unfinished quality of the

    i i i h i ll i l b h d h h h i h

    418 M. Luntley

  • 8/12/2019 Non-Conceptual Content and the Soudn of Music

    18/26

    in which a piece of music can sound harmonically incompletein the right

    harmonic context the minor seventh of the second note of the scale (IIm7) can

    have a strong pull towards the tonic. By hypothesis, the novice can hear the

    incompleteness of the music, but they cannot conceptually discriminate betweenthese different kinds of incompleteness. They need have no sense that a D7 chord

    is similar in this respect to a C7 as opposed to an Am7. Why then do they hear the

    harmonic incompleteness of the music? The subject has a conceptual content of

    incompleteness, but this is a content that does not pick out the V7 quality of the

    music. There are many ways of sounding harmonically incomplete. So incom-

    plete does not represent V7. Given the vague character of incomplete, why then

    do they employ this concept? On my account, the answer is that they hear the

    music as incomplete because they have a representation of the V7 in virtue of the

    expectation of the tonic that that representation captures, they have a nonconcep-tual representation of V7. Without this, it becomes a puzzle why they hear the

    incomplete nature of the music. So, if that1way is something like incomplete it

    will not do the job; its sense is too crude to pick out the feature to which novices

    are able to respond. At the same time, without the nonconceptual representation of

    V7, we are left with a puzzle about why they say the music is incomplete. The

    answer, on my account, is that they are troubled by the music, but they can be

    troubled in different ways. They hear different kinds of troublings even though

    they cannot conceptually discriminate between them.32

    Second, could the that1 way be a recognitional concept? Could our subject

    simply have a recognitional capacity for picking out V7s? This is not, given the

    argument against kidnapping in the subject position, a viable strategy. For the that1way to be a recognitional capacity for picking out V7, there would need to be

    sufficient conceptual surround to ensure that it was a sense with the right reference.

    But that surround is, for the novice, absent. My suggestion is that the novice

    responds each time to V7 chords in a similar way without realising that there is a

    sense in which their response is similar, beyond the fact that the music sounds

    incomplete. That is not enough to fix a V7. Suppose a subject has only ever heard

    V7 incompleteness, that still does not make their sense of incomplete a sense that

    picks out the V7-ness to which they are responding, for if they then come to hear aIIm7 kind of incomplete that too will sound incomplete, where incomplete is a

    conceptual content.

    Third, suppose our novice comes to recognise conceptually the transition from

    dominant 7th to tonic. Suppose that can figure in exercises of judgement as one of

    those kinds of completions. Perhaps they even come to recognise subtly different

    kinds of completions, e.g. the completion from the minor 7th on the second note of

    32

    The explanation of the conceptual content incomplete in virtue of the nonconceptualrepresentation of V7 fits Campbells model of attention as the link between conceptual andnonconceptual content, but offers no reason to think that expectations reintroduce the given.

    Non-conceptual Content 419

  • 8/12/2019 Non-Conceptual Content and the Soudn of Music

    19/26

    the scale to tonic. Now, unless they can pick out dominant 7th chords, their ability

    to recognise the move from dominant 7th to tonic would be a mystery. But there is

    no reason to suppose that because they can conceptually pick out the relevant type of

    completion, they can also conceptually pick out the 7th chord. Therefore, we canconsider the case of someone who conceptually discriminates the type of completion

    but cannot conceptually discriminate the 7th. Their conceptual ability is then

    unexplained. On my account, it is explained in virtue of their nonconceptual

    representations of the dominant 7th and tonics, a discrimination finer than the

    conceptual discriminations in virtue of which they rationalise their behaviour.

    What if the novice listener hears a piece of atonal music, or something in which

    they can detect no tonal centre? Suppose they have an experience characterised by

    (4), but the music does not resolve in the way they expect and it concludes on an

    unrelated chord. Suppose our novice then says,

    (8) I dont like that.

    Would this not show that the representation of the V7-ness figured in the rational

    organisation of their behaviour?33 I think not. The idea behind the kidnapping

    strategy using (8) must be this: The that in (8) is a conceptual representation for

    the dischordant way in which the music sounded when the expectation established

    by (4) was thwarted. If the representation for the dischordant way the music

    sounded is conceptual and fit to kidnap the that way in (4), it would have to

    pick out the way such that the inference in which it transparently figured were

    sufficient to manifest a representation of V7. But, as I have argued, there are no

    such inferences. There are, of course, inferences available to the subject whose

    validity is transparent. For example,

    That awful sound is F

    Fs are G

    That awful sound is G

    What is at issue is not just whether a concept is at play for the novice, but whetherthere is a concept that represents V7-ness. The kidnapping strategy is a powerful

    strategy because whenever a subject lacks the normal way for representing a prop-

    erty, they can normally be presumed to possess another sense for the same reference.

    They lack the music theoretic concept for a dominant 7th, but they might have a

    practical recognitional concept for it. Such a concept must still, of course, have the

    appropriate referencethe property in question. In the case of the novice, the lack

    of conceptual surround means that whatever inferences are transparent for them,

    these are insufficient to provide a focus for a sense that determines the right

    reference. The inferences that the novice deploys show, at best, that their that is

    420 M. Luntley

  • 8/12/2019 Non-Conceptual Content and the Soudn of Music

    20/26

  • 8/12/2019 Non-Conceptual Content and the Soudn of Music

    21/26

    sensitivities to expectations, combining them in sophisticated ways. And this can be

    just as true of visual experiences as of auditory ones. Bell provides a compelling

    account of the experience when a painting previously seen as stubbornly prob-

    lematic begins to acquire a point.34

    Bell is keen to insist that when the painting beginsto have a point this does not depend on the subject providing an interpretation.

    The change in experience is not conceptual. I think this is right and I think the

    apparatus that I have been deploying in the auditory case makes sense of such cases.

    As you look at an abstract painting that initially fails to generate any response, one

    of things that happens is that you set up a framework of expectations about line,

    tone and colour. Perhaps you begin to allow your expectations with respect to

    such things to tune in to patterns that are not to be found in representational art?35

    The point can be very simple. Consider, for example, such apparently simple art

    works as Matisses Blue Nude I & II. The art lies not in tearing out pieces ofcoloured paper to represent the human form, but in producing something in which

    the balance between elements is just so satisfyingly right. And that, I suggest, is, in

    part, a matter of meeting visual expectations.

    Here is a more complex example that reveals something common in our experi-

    ence of popular music. Consider the chord sequence A, Em7, D as experienced by a

    novice. A common way of hearing this sequence is as a movement from dominant to

    tonic via the minor seventh of the second note of the scale; that is the harmonic

    sequence V, IIm7, I.36 The novice non-conceptually hears the harmonic progression

    V, IIm7, I. The novice need have no conceptual mastery of the harmonic relation-

    ships involved here, either music-theoretic or practical. To say the novice non-

    conceptually hears the progression V, IIm7, I, is to do no more than note the

    character of their expectations. The sequence feels complete, it has come to rest.

    Consider now the difference if the same chord sequence is played in a different

    voicing of the chords.37 This is still the sequence A, Em7, D but it is a voicing that,

    for many people, is recognisable as the opening sequence of the James Taylor song,

    Fire and Rain. What is significant about this voicing of the chord progression is

    that it produces an expectation that is absent from the first version of the progres-

    sion. In the new version, the expectation is that the tonal centre rests on A, not D.

    This means that the expectations can be represented by saying that the novice non-conceptually hears I, Vm7, IV. Each of the chords has a different harmonic value.

    34 Bell, 1987 pp. 2367.35 Like tuning your ear into modern jazz.36 If these chords are played in root position on a guitar they are typically heard with the

    harmonic values indicated.37 On the guitar the difference is achieved by playing the A chord not in the standard root

    position, but with the top three strings played in the normal F major shape moved five fretsup, the Em7 played with the same shape two frets lower and the D played in root position.The different voicings of the A chord are then: (listing the string values from the 5th string

    422 M. Luntley

  • 8/12/2019 Non-Conceptual Content and the Soudn of Music

    22/26

    The listener is left with a sense of a different tonal centre manifested in the

    expectation that they will get chord I againanother A chord.38

    The change in expectation illustrates something that is, I suspect, very common

    in our experience of popular music. Our experience and recognition of popularsongs is extraordinarily sensitive, for much popular music is built around subtle

    variants of cliched musical devices. We learn to associate very particular voicings of

    chord progressions and other features of orchestration and accompaniment with

    this music. There is a level at which our experience discriminates precisely that

    song, that chord voicing, rather than at a level at which the song has elements in

    common with others. We frequently have no concept of the respects in which the

    song is similar to others. It is important to recall that the expectations at play here

    are not to be thought of as perceptual cues that prompt recognition where a

    perceptual cue is something that operates below the level of conscious awareness.The cues are elements of phenomenology. The novice hears the progression in

    ways that produce different expectations. In the first case, musical experience has a

    phenomenological sense of completeness. This is absent in the second version that

    requires a further A chord and probably, beyond that, an E followed by Gmaj7 to

    complete the opening sequence to the song. It is musical experience at the personal

    level that is acutely sensitive to changes of chord voicings. It takes an experience of

    just the right version of the chord progression to set up the expectation that is

    characteristic of an experience of the song. It does not matter whether the novice

    recognises the tune. All that matters is that the experience changes with the change

    in chord voicing. And even if it were claimed that the change were recognition

    driven, as a result of a recognition of the gestalt whole of the song, it is still the case

    that there is an element to the experience in the second case, an expectation, that is

    there to be met or un-met. The element in question is not the recognition of the

    song. That is conceptuala that song conceptual content. The element in

    question is the representation of the key, the expectation that picks out the

    chord that brings the harmonies to rest.

    It is the musical sophisticate who will notice the similarities between one

    popular song and another, where the sophisticated listener has either a music-

    theoretic or practical grasp of musical structure. But that is conceptual. Our noviceenjoys a song, their expectations are played with, whether or not they recognise it.

    If they do recognise the song, the recognition need involve no exercise of a general

    capacity to detect similarities in structures of expectations.

    The general idea in these examples is of expectations as components of experience

    such that their satisfaction conditions discriminate particular musical events and

    properties and yet have no rational bearing on the satisfaction conditions of other

    expectations. Having an expectation is having a representational content without, as

    38 There are a number of explanations for this change in expectations. One explanation is thatthe second voicing of the chords produces a descending sequence of notes which emphasises

    Non-conceptual Content 423

  • 8/12/2019 Non-Conceptual Content and the Soudn of Music

    23/26

    it were, knowing what to do with it. The subject of experience with non-conceptual

    content cannot deploy this content in rational action. This explains why it is easier to

    construct examples that are impervious to the kidnapping manoeuvre in the auditory

    case rather than in the visual. Visual perception has a more dominant role for us inaction control. It is much harder to sideline visual perception from our action than it

    is to sideline auditory perception. It is not, however, impossible.

    Suppose you walk into a familiar room in which the furniture has been subtly

    re-arranged, perhaps a chair is moved slightly closer to the window. It is possible to

    have an experience of things being not quite right, not quite as expected, but not

    be able to say in what respect this is so. A related example is that of the person who

    revisits the botanic gardens last seen as a child. They are puzzled. Everything looks

    wrong, they find the place troubling. Their expectations are being continually

    thwarted. They may, or may not, eventually cotton-on that the difference is thatthey have grown up and an environment that had consistently prompted expect-

    ations of being dwarfed has lost this relative hold over them.

    Once the key point of the idea of nonconceptual content is grasped, the search is

    not for fine-grained representations, it is for representations which the subject

    cannot, in terms of their current conceptual abilities, employ in the rational

    organisation of behaviour. This is not a level of content below the conceptual or

    a level of content in terms of which the application of conceptual content is in

    general to be explained. That, of course, is McDowells concernit would

    reintroduce the notion of the given. The troubling is not the given. It is, rather,

    direct openness to the world that we cannot at present handle rationally.

    The account of nonconceptual content proposed offers resources for tackling a

    number of basic issues. One issue is the relation between the content of experience

    appropriately ascribed to non concept possessing creatures and that enjoyed by

    subjects with conceptual understanding. The obvious suggestion is that animals

    without concepts have an experience the content of which troubles themthey

    have nonconceptual representations. They have expectations about what will happen

    next, but they do not have the resources to organise their troublings in a rational

    manner. We do. To acquire concepts is to overcome your troubles. The speculative

    hypothesis is that the difference here turns on having a will, coming to conceptualiseexperience in the development of human cognition is not unconnected with the

    development of agency.39 The vehicle for achieving this is, as Campbell suggests,

    attention. Possession of concepts requires possession of will and, for developed

    human adult experience, you have to look hard, and in normally unexamined

    corners, to find those areas of experience where we find it hard to exercise will.

    Dept of Philosophy

    University of Warwick

    424 M. Luntley

  • 8/12/2019 Non-Conceptual Content and the Soudn of Music

    24/26

    References

    Bell, D. 1987: The art of judgement. Mind, XCVI, 22144.

    Bermudez, J.L. 1994: Peacockes argument against the autonomy of nonconceptualcontent. Mind & Language, 40218

    Bermudez, J.L. 1995: Nonconceptual content: From personal experience to sub-personal computational states.Mind & Language, 33369

    Bermudez, J.L. 1997: Practical understanding vs. reflective understanding. Philosophyand Phenomenological Research, LVII, 63541

    Brewer, B. 1999: Perception and Reason. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Brewer, B. 2001: Replies to comments.Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LXIII,44964.

    Budd, M. 1985: Understanding music. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, supplementaryvolume, 59, 23348.

    Campbell, J. 1988: Is sense transparent? Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 88, 27392

    Campbell, J. 1994: Past, Space, Self. Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press.

    Campbell, J. 1997a:Precis of Past, Space and Self. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research,LVII, 6334.

    Campbell, J. 1997b: Replies. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LVII, 65570.

    Campbell, J. 1997c: Sense, reference and selective attention.Proceedings of the AristotelianSociety, supplementary volume, 71, 5574.

    Crane, T. 1992: The nonconceptual content of experience. In T. Crane (ed.), TheContents of Experience. Cambridge University Press, 13657

    DeBellis, M. 1995: Music and Conceptualisation. Cambridge: Cambridge UniversityPress.

    Eilan, N. 2001: Consciousness, acquaintance and demonstrative thought.Philosophy andPhenomenological Research, LXIII, 4329

    Evans, G. 1982: The Varieties of Reference. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Heck, R. 2000: Nonconceptual content and the Space of Reasons. The PhilosophicalReview, 109, 483523.

    Hurley, S. 1998: Consciousness in Action. Harvard University Press.Hurley, S. 2001: Overintellectualizing the mind. Philosophy and Phenomenological

    Research, LXIII, 42331.

    Kelly, S. 2001: The non-conceptual content of perceptual experience: situation depend-ence and fineness of grain. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LXII, 60115.

    Luntley, M. 1999: Contemporary Philosophy of Thought. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Luntley, M. 2002: Agency and our tacit sense of things. In L Hahn (ed.), Library of

    Living Philosophers: Marjorie Grene. La Salle, Illinois: Open Court.

    McDowell, J. 1994: Mind and World. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.

    McDowell, J. 1998: Replies. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LVIII, 403431.McDowell, J. 2001: Comment on Richard Schantz. The Given regained. Philosophy

    Non-conceptual Content 425

  • 8/12/2019 Non-Conceptual Content and the Soudn of Music

    25/26

    Meyer, L. 1956: Emotion and Meaning in Music. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Noe, A. 2002: Is perspectival self-consciousness non-conceptual? The PhilosophicalQuarterly, 52, 18594.

    Peacocke, C. 1992: A Study of Concepts. Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press.Peacocke, C. 1998: Nonconceptual content defended. Philosophy and Phenomenological

    Research, LVIII, 3818.

    Russell, J. 1996: Agency: Its Role in Mental Development. Hove: Erlbaum (UK) Taylorand Francis Ltd.

    Schantz, R. 2001: The Given regained. Reflections on the sensuous content ofexperience. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LXII, 16780.

    Sudnow, D. 1993: The Way of the Hands. Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press.

    426 M. Luntley

  • 8/12/2019 Non-Conceptual Content and the Soudn of Music

    26/26