needleman, questions of the heart

Upload: jackspain

Post on 14-Apr-2018

219 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 7/30/2019 Needleman, Questions of the Heart

    1/6

    Jacob Needleman Questions of the Heart: Noetic Sciences Review, Summer 1993Inner Empiricism as a Way to a Science of Consciousne ss

    www.jacobneedleman.com

    A friend of mine told me recently that all his life he had been interested in the meaning of

    things and, naturally, that led him to a study of philosophy. What he found there, he said, was

    one of the greatest disappointments of his life. Instead of tackling the exciting questions, mostphilosophers seemed to be snared in the problems of dissecting language, and probing the

    nuances of grammar and semi-arbitrary logic. There was no vitality in this work; it was all dry

    academic, intellectual gamesmanship. He was looking for philosophers who, as he said,

    "really care about reality"; who would apply their philosophical training to help cut through

    the intellectual morass, clarify methodologies, and get back to the relationship between reality

    and experience. He very kindly described me as one of those philosophers who "really caresabout reality".

    As it happens, I believe there is a growing number of younger philosophers who are

    interested in getting to the heart of the matter--about what we mean by "reality" and the

    central role of experience. What draws them, and what originally drew me, to the whole areaof philosophy is a quest for meaning. I discovered that the mind by itself cannot complete the

    philosophic quest. As Kant decisively argued, the mind can ask questions the mind alone

    cannot answer. For me, this is where the juice of real philosophical investigation begins to

    flow. I believe it is precisely where intellect hits its limits that the important questions ofphilosophy start to come alive.

    Mainstream academic philosophy has for a long time tried to answer these fundamental

    questions with that part of the mind we call intellect. Frequently the difficulties encountered

    were so great, the logical tangles so confusing, that many philosophers decided such questions

    were meaningless, and some even began to ridicule anyone who dared ask "What is reality?"

    "What is the meaning of life?" "Is there life after death?" "What is the soul?" "Does Godexist?" Yet these are the questions of the heart. These are the questions that matter most to

    people--not whether the syntax and deep structures of our language can ever truly represent

    real knowledge. The meaningful questions, these " questions of the heart", rise up in human

    beings because of something intrinsic to our nature, an innate striving which Plato called

    Eros.

    One aspect of this is the striving to participate in a reality greater than ourselves. It is a

    yearning, a hunger, a force we may recognize as love. This drive is as much, if not more, a

    part of our nature as the sexual, physical and animal desires which psychoanalysis and

    mainstream psychiatry have identified as parts of our essential nature. Our drive for

    understanding, for participation in a higher reality, shapes our psyche as much as anythingelse.

    But what can the mind do with this deep participatory urge? Even at its most brilliant, the

    intellect alone can only ask questions that skim the surface of Eros; it cannot answer these

    questions. Yet such questions--the meaning of life, the nature of the soul--need to beanswered. If intellect is not up to the job, how can we penetrate these mysteries? The solution,I'm proposing, is that we can only extend the reach of intellect through experience. There is a

    certain type of experience that opens up the mind, expands our consciousness, and allows us

    to approach answers to many of these fundamental questions.

    In this sense, as a philosopher who cares about questions of the heart, I'm essentially a studentof consciousness. I'm talking about certain kinds of experiences that we have spontaneously as

    human beings, but which are all too uncommon and which are not valued or understood

  • 7/30/2019 Needleman, Questions of the Heart

    2/6

    Jacob Needleman Questions of the Heart: Noetic Sciences Review, Summer 1993Inner Empiricism as a Way to a Science of Consciousne ss

    www.jacobneedleman.com

    within our culture. But when they are approached from another angle, one sees that these

    experiences really point to an aspect of the mind, of the psyche, beyond reason and intellect.

    And they do more than that: They also point to the object of those experiences, that is, to afundamental reality. These experiences present us with an alternative or complementary way

    of knowing the world around us as well as the world inside us. The philosophical approach

    I'm talking about values these "questions of the heart" as invitations to experience, as well as

    to cogitations of the cerebral intellect.

    Appearances or Reality?This is an unconventional approach to philosophy in our culture. Yet it is one that can throw

    light on many of the great classic questions of philosophy. For example, "Is the world real, or

    only a construct of appearances?" Behind the appearances presented to us by our senses, is

    there a real world? And if so, how can we ever know it? These problems have been argued

    over for centuries, often brilliantly; and nobody has argued better or more cleverly aboutthese points than Immanuel Kant. There are many ways of looking at the issue; and what we

    find is a shifting mosaic of appearances depending on our point of view.

    What I want to emphasize is that once we begin to take seriously the potential capacity of thehuman mind for other kinds of experiences--for other states of consciousness--and develop the

    proper language and understanding, we discover that the whole question of appearanceversus reality itself shifts. Once we begin to realize that there is a selfhood that is more real,

    under what we usually call "my self ", we come to recognize that not only do we live in a

    world of appearances outside, we also live in an internal world of appearances.

    At this point, the whole issue gets really interesting. Now we see that in order to know theworld behind external appearances, we have to get behind the appearances of our inner

    world. The only way to gain real knowledge of the outer world is by penetrating the

    appearances of the inner world. Thus, if I want to know the numinous, the thing-in-itself, I

    need to activate that instrument in myself that is capable of perceiving it. This is the very

    "instrument" that Kant proved, so he believed, did not exist.

    Kant proclaimed that there is no instrument in the human psyche for perceiving things as

    they are in themselves; and he presented his argument with such logical and metaphysical

    brilliance that one must bow to his awesome mind. The Critique of Pure Reason, in which he

    developed this thesis within the framework of a detailed and comprehensive system, is so

    astonishing that few people dared say anything different, except in the most circuitous waypossible. Hegel tried, but that wasn't what survived of his work. Hardly anybody, particularly

    in the Anglo-American philosophical tradition, ever seriously challenged Kant's insistent

    proclamation, his proof, that we can ever know the Ding an sich--the thing-in-itself. Nobody

    would take on the awesome logic of Kant; and for more than a century his critique of

    empiricism reigned supreme, a monumental pinnacle of philosophical achievement-except itwas wrong.

    Kant's own instrument, his genius, was so brilliant it may have blinded him, at least in The

    Critique of Pure Reason, to the presence of that other instrument of investigation, his own

    inner experience. Certainly, the most highly developed capacity of reason and intellect could

    never, as Kant so brilliantly proved, burrow through the veils of appearances to the reality ofthe world-in-itself. But there is another way of knowing which Kant entirely omitted in The

    Critique.

  • 7/30/2019 Needleman, Questions of the Heart

    3/6

    Jacob Needleman Questions of the Heart: Noetic Sciences Review, Summer 1993Inner Empiricism as a Way to a Science of Consciousne ss

    www.jacobneedleman.com

    The force of Kant's philosophy continues to shape much of Western thinking and science

    today. Positivism and Scientism are just two of the more recent manifestations of the Kantianunderestimation of the cognitive capacities of the human psyche. Our culture is steeped in

    this paradigm. Freud, in his own way, perpetuated the Kantian myth of the mind.

    The Need for Rigorous Empirical Standards

    Because of the ubiquitousness of appearances in the outer world of objects, science has been

    driven to apply the most rigorous standards in a valiant effort to minimize the distortions of

    appearances. Science has developed a procedure, which I greatly respect, for asking questionsdesigned to eliminate the biases of wishful thinking and to avoid fooling ourselves about the

    nature of the external world. The critical question I want to explore in this article is to what

    extent can we legitimately apply those same rigorous scientific standards to investigation of

    experience-to get beyond the appearances that shroud the landscape of the inner world?

    I believe we can use scientific standards, and accompanying language, to guide our inner

    quest. Ultimately, it is a spiritual quest, and our understanding should be guided by the

    teachings and practice of the great spiritual traditions. We need to insure that our rigorous

    methodological standards do not squelch the very experiences we wish to investigate.

    For centuries, science has perfected the tools of external empiricism. This empiricism of thesenses has been directed toward the outer world--or what is in effect perceived as the "outer

    world"--organized by categories of logic and the conceptual powers of discursive intellect.

    From there, it leads us to theory and prediction, experimentation and generation of further

    observations. In the scientific enterprise, the experiential element--the knowledge and

    subjective perception--of the scientist is directed exclusively outward.

    In order to reach beyond the epistemological barrier so solidly put in place by Kant, to reach

    more deeply into the world of experience, we now need to develop what I call an "inner

    empiricism"--the empiricism of looking inward and experiencing the inner world. This is the

    world within the psyche, within the mind and the heart; it is the world of feelings, of directsensations. And this is the world that yields metaphysical truths. This is the world that Kantoverlooked. Prior to Kant, there were philosophers who recognized the importance of this

    other "instrument". Great metaphysicians, such as Plato or the ninth-century Christian

    philosopher Duns Scotus, or the great Islamic philosophers-almost all, I believe, based their

    metaphysical claims about reality on what they discovered from internal experience.

    Their state of meditation or contemplation, or whatever interior discipline they had, enabled

    them to see and experience things which they could say with absolute certainty were

    attributes of the universe, of reality itself. That is the application of inner empiricism. All great

    philosophy is based directly or indirectly on experience, just as much as modem science is.

    Only the focus of experience is different. Metaphysical philosophers have handed on to us thefruits of their experience of the internal world, not of the external world which is the domainof science. As anyone who has ventured into this interior domain knows, it is a vast realm,

    rich in the possibilities of experience which mystics and great teachers of all spiritual

    traditions, at all times, have told us about.

    In the Western philosophical tradition the possibility of inner empiricism has been mostlyforgotten. David Hume was able to shake the world (particularly the young Kant) with a

    smattering of self-observation. He reported that when he looked into himself he did not see

  • 7/30/2019 Needleman, Questions of the Heart

    4/6

    Jacob Needleman Questions of the Heart: Noetic Sciences Review, Summer 1993Inner Empiricism as a Way to a Science of Consciousne ss

    www.jacobneedleman.com

    causal connections, nor a "self " persisting through time. Such pronouncements flew in the

    face of both common sense and the science of the time. Admirers of Hume reacted to his

    unorthodox method and conclusions by exclaiming "What an honest, extraordinary man. Helooks into himself and tells it like it is. He doesn't see what everybody thinks should be there

    and has the courage to say so. " But nobody asked "How did he look? What precisely was his

    method of inner observation? How long did he sit focused on his inner universe?" To

    Western minds, accustomed only to flights of intellect and the incessant dance of thoughts,

    Hume's quiet self-observation might have seemed remarkable. But a vipassana yoga teacher

    or a zen master might have advised: "David, you've only taken a few first steps. Stay with theprocess for another two, three, four or five years and you'll see a lot more. And even then,

    there's a lot you won't see."

    Hume, in other words, was completely unaware that he was stepping onto the very bottom

    rung of a giant ladder of self-observation, familiar in many cultures as the practice ofmeditation. What is remarkable, however, is that although Hume just dipped his toe into the

    water, that one touch created waves that revolutionized major streams of Western

    philosophy, from Kant onwards-without any development of a methodology for

    self-investigation.

    Modem academic philosophers practice inner empiricism even more primitively than Hume.They assume--as our culture assumes--that people have a natural capacity to look at

    themselves. All you need to do is stop and analyze or observe your thinking. But, as any

    serious practitioner of meditation knows, deep self-insight is not something that comes

    naturally to the mind. It needs to be cultivated over time and with careful guidance.

    In Western culture, this faculty of self-observation is often completely overlooked, even

    denied. For instance, I had a colleague who professed an academically respectable stance that

    there are no such things as mental images. He was willing to argue and defend this

    philosophical position because he wasn't even aware how to put it to a test. At a party one

    evening, after a few drinks, I suggested he assist me in a card trick. I said "Take a card. Now,without looking at it, guess what it is and don't tell me." He took a card and an instant laterexclaimed "My God, I just had a mental image!" That one moment of internal observation

    completely refuted his whole philosophy. He had never bothered to look into his own mind;

    he hadn't known how to. A little wine freed him of his customary prejudice about what was

    supposed to happen in his mind. The image just appeared and he saw it.

    I mention that episode to underline the importance of the need for training in inner

    empiricism. When, after sustained guidance from an experienced teacher, you look deeply

    into yourself you see not only something about who you are; you see, also, something about

    the nature of reality, about the universe. Furthermore, what you see can be expressed in

    conceptual, abstract language, with precise logic and systematization. And that, in myopinion, is the true methodology of philosophy. It yields knowledge just as valid as any gainedfrom the application of scientific empiricism. The only difference is that conventional science

    yields communicable information about the external world. In both cases, however, the

    investigators developed the capability to conduct careful observations and to report their

    findings in precise language as a result of years of dedicated training, guided by masters in

    their field.

  • 7/30/2019 Needleman, Questions of the Heart

    5/6

    Jacob Needleman Questions of the Heart: Noetic Sciences Review, Summer 1993Inner Empiricism as a Way to a Science of Consciousne ss

    www.jacobneedleman.com

    Moving Deeper: Observing the Observer

    There is one other aspect of the philosophical methodology I'm outlining here that needs to

    be addressed. Inner empiricism can lead to experience and knowledge of a very beautiful,compelling and often extraordinary interior world. This knowledge can also yield rich insights

    into the nature of the outer world. But beyond that, a persistent application of inner

    empiricism leads to another, deeper, aspect of self-knowledge. The "instrument" with which

    the investigator sees is itself conditioned, and changes in the process of observation. In the act

    of observation, the observer is changed.

    When the "see-er" recognizes that he or she is being changed by the very process of seeing

    inward, the possibilities of inner empiricism shift to another level and a whole new area of

    investigation opens up. There comes a time, as one persists in the practice of meditation,

    when even the extraordinary and captivating phenomena of the interior landscape begin to

    lose their fascination. Instead, attention is drawn to the more encompassing and morepowerful mystery of that which is doing the seeing. The question of "who" or "what" is seeing

    becomes more--much more--interesting and important than the content of what is being seen.

    At this stage, the science of inner empiricism leads the investigator to the threshold of what

    may be a spiritual journey.

    Experience now moves beyond the capabilities of expression in scientific, or any other,language. It moves beyond the acquisition of knowledge distinct from the knower; it moves

    beyond theory or explanation, but becomes deeply meaningful as a profound transformation

    begins to take place at the core of one's being. In Hindu tradition, this is spoken of as the

    recognition of "purusha", which we may loosely translate as self-spirit, or the god within. A

    whole new level of inner development and inner struggle begins, perhaps leading to a deeperinner awakening; the meditator knows that the universe is permeated by a great

    consciousness, purusha, Buddha nature, Logos, God. I'm not aware that there are any limits

    to this process. The struggles and development can lead to extraordinary heights of Self

    awareness.

    It is entirely inappropriate in an article such as this for me to attempt to say more aboutwhere this process might lead. My intention has been to draw attention to inner empiricism

    as a critical methodology for any true philosophy, and to intimate its limitless possibilities.

    Specifically, I wanted to suggest that even the initial stages of the process can lead to

    experience and knowledge of deeper realities. The question of who the see-er is is best left to

    the committed spiritual (inner-scientific) aspirant to discover for him- or herself. However, Ido want to emphasize that if you are motivated to explore the possibilities of inner

    empiricism, there comes a point where you realize that you can't access more fundamental

    levels until that which is seeing itself begins to be transformed. At that point, you realize that

    what is fundamental is not what you are seeing, but the see-er itself in all its forms. "Tat tvam

    asi, " the Hindu masters said: "Thou art That."

    Inner Empiricism at the University?

    Should universities and colleges of higher education establish courses in inner empiricism?

    The short answer is probably not. Meditation is not the sort of practice that would benefit

    from official encouragement or sanction. When colleges begin establishing Chairs and

    professorships in meditation, that would be the time to get concerned. Inner empiricismwould not flourish within the strictures of academic bureaucracy. Pressure to get good grades

  • 7/30/2019 Needleman, Questions of the Heart

    6/6

    Jacob Needleman Questions of the Heart: Noetic Sciences Review, Summer 1993Inner Empiricism as a Way to a Science of Consciousne ss

    www.jacobneedleman.com

    in meditation would thoroughly disrupt and negate the practice. It doesn't need to be part of

    academic policy, it just needs to be permitted.

    A university course in philosophy could point the way to such a path, but it could never be

    the path. The university can help open students' minds to the existence of the spiritual option,

    but from there it is up to individuals to find their own way and what works for them. A

    healthy culture would have special places for spiritual seekers to pursue their inner quest.

    (Our society already allows for this. There are, however, many cultures where Gurdjieff

    groups or vipassana meditation, for example, would not be permitted.)

    What is missing from our educational system is not so much courses in meditation or inner

    empiricism but classes in how to think for ourselves and how to balance our whole lives. A

    university course designed to teach students how to think things through from fundamental

    principles--combining the psychology of perception with meaningful philosophy--could beadded to the curriculum. There are signs that this is beginning to happen in academia--in

    philosophy, in comparative religion, in divinity studies, in anthropology, and in the

    humanities. It is possible, for example, to reframe perhaps as much as 90 percent of the

    world's great literature--from Homer to Shakespeare--as expressions of the spiritual quest forself knowledge. The emphasis on inner experience may even be already happening in the

    sciences. But wherever it occurs, it evolves through individuals, not through institutionalizedmass movements.

    Ultimately, though, individual seekers will not make it on their own without guidance and the

    support of peers. For that reason, it is important for serious and committed seekers to come

    together, not in the sense of an academic school, but as a spiritual school. The whole point ofsuch a school would be to assist the development of the autonomous observer. Top of the

    agenda for any spiritual school would be disciplines aimed at developing the observer's

    instrument for perceiving the reality beyond inner appearances.

    Jacob Needleman is professor of philosophy at San Francisco State University. Educated inphilosophy at Harvard, Yale and the University of Freiburg, he has also served as Research

    Associate at the Rockefeller Institute for Medical Research. His books include The New

    Religions, A Sense of the Cosmos, The Heart of Philosophy, and his latest, Money and the

    Meaning of Life, published by Doubleday in 1991.

    Noetic Sciences Review, Summer 1993, pp. 4-9. Guest editor Christian de Quincey is a

    California-based writer specializing in science and consciousness.