moti gitik and saharon shelah- cardinal preserving ideals

Upload: hutsdm

Post on 06-Apr-2018

219 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/3/2019 Moti Gitik and Saharon Shelah- Cardinal Preserving Ideals

    1/32

  • 8/3/2019 Moti Gitik and Saharon Shelah- Cardinal Preserving Ideals

    2/32

    310

    re

    vision:1996-05-05

    modified:1996-05-06

    We consider the notion of a -presaturated ideal which was basically introduced by

    Baumgartner and Taylor [B-T]. It is a weakening of presaturation. It turns out that this

    notion can be preserved under forcing like the Levy collapse. So in order to obtain such an

    ideal over a small cardinal it is enough to construct it over an inaccessible and then justto use the Levy collapse.

    The paper is organized as follows. In Section 1 the notions are introduced and various

    conditions on forcing notions for the preservation of-presaturation are presented. Models

    with N S cardinal preserving are constructed in Section 2. The reading of this section

    requires some knowledge of [G1,2,4].

    The results of the first section are due to the second author and second section to the

    first.

    Notation. N S denotes the nonstationary ideal over a regular cardinal > 0, NS

    denotes the N S restricted to cofinality , i.e. {X |X { < |cf = } N S}, D

    denotes a normal filter over a regular cardinal = (D) > 0, D+ = {A |A = mod

    D, i.e. A D}. D

    Q for a forcing notion Q, such that Q

    (D) is regular is the

    Q-name of the normal filter on (D) generated by D. By forcing with D+ we mean the

    forcing with D-positive sets ordered by inclusion.

    1. -Presaturation and Preservation Conditions

    The definitions and the facts 1.1-1.5 below are basically due to Baumgartner-Taylor

    [B-T].

    Definition 1.1. A normal filter (or ideal) D over is -presaturated if D+

    every

    set of ordinals of cardinality < can be covered by a set of V of cardinality

    .

    Let us formulate an equivalent definition which is much easier to use.

    Definition 1.2. A normal filter D on is -presaturated, if for every 0 < , and

    maximal antichains I = {Ai : i < i}, i.e.

    Ai D+, [i = j Ai A

    j D

    +], (A D+)(i < i)A Ai D

    +)

    (for < 0) for every B D+ there is A D+ such that A B and ( < 0)|{i . For < , < 0 let () be the least s.t. B if such exists and -1

    otherwise. Define f : by f() =

  • 8/3/2019 Moti Gitik and Saharon Shelah- Cardinal Preserving Ideals

    4/32

    310

    re

    vision:1996-05-05

    modified:1996-05-06

    Proof: (b) (c) since |D+| = +. The direction (c) (a), (b), (d), (e), (f) are trivial.

    If (b) holds, then, as in [B-T], also (a) holds. (a) implies (d), (e) and (f).

    We are now going to formulate various preservation conditions.

    Lemma 1.6. Suppose that < are regular cardinals, D a normal filter on = (D),

    Q a forcing notion Q

    regular and D

    Q denotes the normal filter on in VQ which

    D generates.

    If D is -presaturated (in V) then D

    Q is -presaturated in VQ provided that for someK

    ()1D,K,Q, K is a structure with universe |K|, partial order =K unitary function T =

    TK , and partial unitary functions pi = pKi such that

    (a) for t K, T(t) D+;

    (b) K|= t s implies T(s) T(t)mod D;

    (c) pi(t) is defined iff i T(t);

    (d) pi(t) Q and [K|= t s, i T(s) pi(t) pi(s)];

    (e) t

    =

    K

    t= {i T(t) : pi(t) G

    Q} is not forced to be mod D

    Q;

    (f) if q Q

    T

    (D

    Q)+

    for some q Q then there is s, s K, pi(s) q and

    Q

    s

    T

    mod D

    Q

    ;

    (g) if() < , for < () Y K is such that {T(t) : t Y} is a maximal antichain

    of D+ such that [t Y, s Y , > (C D)(i C T(t) T(s))pi(s)

    pi(t)], and T D+ then there is s, s K, T(s) T and there are y Y, |y|

    for < () such that [ < (), x Y\y T(x) T(s) = mod D] and

    < ()(x y)(C D)(i C T(x) T(s))[pi(x) pi(s)].

    Proof: Let () < , and I

    = {A

    i: i < i

    } (for < ()) be Q-names of maximal

    antichains of (DQ

    )+ (as in Definition 1.2) (i.e. Q

    I is a maximal antichain.

    We define by induction on < () Yh such that

    (i) Y K, {T(t) : t Y} a maximal antichain of D+;

    (ii) for every < , t Y, s Y for some C D i C T(s) T(t) pi(t) pi(s));

    (iii) h : Y ordinals, and

    t A

    h(t)for t Y.

    Using (g) pick s and y| < (). Then s

    will be as required in Definition 1.2.

    4

  • 8/3/2019 Moti Gitik and Saharon Shelah- Cardinal Preserving Ideals

    5/32

    310

    re

    vision:1996-05-05

    modified:1996-05-06

    Definition 1.7.

    1) Gm(D , , a) (where a ) is a game which lasts moves, in the ith move if i a

    player I, and if i a player II, choose a set Ai D+, Ai Aj mod D for j < i. If at

    some stage there is no legal move, player I wins, otherwise player II wins.2) If we omit a, it means a = {1 + 2i : 1 + 2i < }.

    3) Gm+(D , , a) is defined similarly, but for player II to win, Ai = has to hold as

    well.

    By Galvin-Jech-Magidor [G-J-M], the following holds.

    Proposition 1.8. D is precipitous if player I has no winning strategy in Gm+(D, ).

    Lemma 1.9.

    1) Suppose that < are regular cardinals, D a normal filter on = (D), Q a forcing

    notion Q

    regular, = (D).

    If player II wins the game Gm(D , , a) in V, then it wins in Gm(D , , a) in VQ

    provided that for some, , the following principle holds:

    ()2D,K,Q:

    K is a structure as in Lemma 1.6,

    (a) fort K, T(t) D+;

    (b) K|= t s implies T(s) T(t)mod D;

    (c) pi(t) is defined iff i T(t);

    (d) pi(t) Q and [K|= t s, i T(s) pi(t) pi(s)];

    (e) t

    = {i T(t) : pi(t) GQ

    } and pi(t) Q

    t

    (D

    Q)+

    for i T(t);

    (f) if, q Q

    T

    (D

    Q)+

    for some q Q then there is s, s K, pi(s) q and

    Q

    sT mod DQ

    ;

    (g) K is -complete, i.e. if ti : i < < is increasing and T(ti) D+ then there

    is t K, ti t;

    (h) Q is -complete and preserves stationarity of all A D+.

    2) The same holds with Player I having no winning strategy.

    5

  • 8/3/2019 Moti Gitik and Saharon Shelah- Cardinal Preserving Ideals

    6/32

    310

    re

    vision:1996-05-05

    modified:1996-05-06

    Proof:

    1) Let us provide a winning strategy for player II. Let G Q be generic over V without

    loss of generality the players choose Q-names for their moves. We will now describe

    the strategy of player II in V[G].Player II also chooses Ti, tj(j a, i < ), according to the moves. Player II preserves

    the following (for a fixed winning strategy F of player II in Gm(D , , a) in V).

    (*) the plays Ai

    : i < and Ti : i < so far satisfy

    (a) Ti : i < is a beginning of a play ofGm(D , , a) (in V) in which player II uses

    the strategy F;

    (b) for i a, Ai

    =ti

    , T(ti) = Ti, ti K;

    (c) for j < i < , tj ti;(d) V[G]|=A

    i[G] D+

    .

    Proposition 1.10. Suppose < are regular cardinals, < [

  • 8/3/2019 Moti Gitik and Saharon Shelah- Cardinal Preserving Ideals

    7/32

    310

    re

    vision:1996-05-05

    modified:1996-05-06

    If ()3D,K,Q holds then also the following statements are true:

    (1) If D is -presaturated in V, { : cf (in V)} D, then D

    Q is -presaturated in

    VQ.

    (2) If player II wins in Gm(,D,) in V ( ), Q -complete then he wins in Gm(,D,)in VQ provided that

    ()4D,K,Q :(a) p K pi

    Q

    p

    = mod D

    Q for i Tp

    (b) ()3D,K,Q

    (3) The same holds if we replace The player II wins by Player I does not have winning

    strategy or the game Gm(,D,) is replaced by Gm+(,D,).

    (4) In (2) we can replace()3D,K,Q by:

    D1 a normal filter over in V, K1 like K,

    player II wins also in Gm(,D,) and

    ()5D,K,D1,K1,Q :

    () ()4D1,K1,Q() ()4D,K,Q() for every p = pi : i Tp K there are

    q = q : S K1 p = pi : i T K

    T Tp pairwise disjoint[i T pi p

    i ], q

    p

    = mod D

    Q .

    Proof: Let us prove (1). The proof of (2) is similar. Let () < , I

    = {A

    i: i < i

    }

    ( < ()) be () Q-names of maximal antichains of D+ as mentioned in the definition

    of -presaturitivity (i.e. it is forced that they are like that).

    We define by induction on (), Y, j() and p( Y) such that

    (i) Y is a set of sequence of ordinals of length ;

    (ii) p K;

    (iii) < , Y implies | Y, p| p (i.e. T T|), [i T p|i p ];

    (iv) Y0 = {}, p = pi : i < , p

    i = Q (the minimal element);

    (v) for limit, Y = { : a sequence of ordinals g() = , (i < )|i Yi};

    (vi) {T : Y} is a maximal antichain;

    7

  • 8/3/2019 Moti Gitik and Saharon Shelah- Cardinal Preserving Ideals

    8/32

    310

    re

    vision:1996-05-05

    modified:1996-05-06

    (vii) for limit, Y, T =

  • 8/3/2019 Moti Gitik and Saharon Shelah- Cardinal Preserving Ideals

    9/32

    310

    re

    vision:1996-05-05

    modified:1996-05-06

    We define by induction on () Y and the function j|Y : Y ordinals and

    p(v Y) s.t.

    (i) Y a set;

    (ii) pv

    K let pv

    = pvi : i Tv, Tv D+;

    (iii) for every v Y and i Tv q0 pvi ;

    (iv) Tv : v Y} is a maximal antichain of D+;

    (v) for v Y, i Tv, pvi

    i A

    j(v);

    (vi) if Y, < , v Y, and Tv T D+ then for some Cv, D, (i

    Tv T Cv,) [pi p

    vi ];

    (vii) < Y Y = ;

    (viii) for < , v Y |{ Y : T Tv D+}| .

    If , v

  • 8/3/2019 Moti Gitik and Saharon Shelah- Cardinal Preserving Ideals

    10/32

    310

    re

    vision:1996-05-05

    modified:1996-05-06

    (v). Now / p (D

    +)Q so for some r Q r p (D

    +)Q. Hence for some r1,

    r r1 Q, and j the following holds:

    () 1 p A

    j D+.

    For each i T choose if possible p

    i , pi p

    i Q p

    i

    i A

    j . Set Tb = {i : p

    i

    is defined}. It is necessarily in D+ (otherwise this contradicts ()). Applying (d) of

    ()6K,Q,D we get a final p contradicting Y maximal but {Tv : v Y} is not.

    For = 0, use (b) with our q0.

    Proposition 1.12. Let D, D1 are normal filters over a regular cardinal . Suppose that

    the following holds

    CD,D1 : for every T D+

    , F(T) = { < : T is stationary} D+1 .

    Let Q be a -closed forcing for a regular < . Then in VQ CD,D1 is not forced to fail

    provided that

    ()7D,K,D1,Q ()()6D,K,Q or ()

    3D,K,Q and

    (1) for p K

    { < :p

    is forced to be stationary} D+1

    or (2) for p K

    { < :p

    is not forced to be nonstationary} D+1

    and Q satisfies c.c .

    Proof: Suppose otherwise. Let

    S

    (D

    Q)+ and F(S

    ) (D

    Q

    1)+

    . Set T = {i is an inaccessibleQ = Col(, is an inaccessible, Q is the

    Levy collapse Col(, < ) and D, D1 are normal filters over . Then

    1) ()3D,K,Q holds if { < |cf } D and we let K = {pi|i T|T D+, pi Q};

    2) ()6

    D,K,Q holds if we let K = {pi|i T C|T D+

    , pi Q, C is as in Lemma 1.13};3) ()4D,K,Q holds if { < |cf } D and K is as in 2);

    4) ()7D,K,D1,Q holds if { < |cf < } D, { < | is an inaccessible } D1 and K

    is as in 2).

    Proof: 1), 2), 3) easy checking. 4). Suppose that in V CD,D1 holds. Let us show the

    condition (2) of ()7D,K,D1,Q. Let p = pi|i T K and C D1. We should find some

    C and q Q q p

    is stationary.

    Using CD,D1 find an inaccessible C such that C, T is stationary and for

    every i < pi Col(, < ). Now, as in Lemma 1.13, there is a stationary S T such

    that every pi (i S) forces in Col (, < ) that p

    is stationary. IfD concentrates on

    ordinals of cofinality < , then without loss of generality all elements ofT are of some fixed

    cofinality < . The forcing Col(, < ) is -closed, so it would preserve the stationarity of

    (p )Col(,

  • 8/3/2019 Moti Gitik and Saharon Shelah- Cardinal Preserving Ideals

    12/32

    310

    re

    vision:1996-05-05

    modified:1996-05-06

    Corollary 1.15. Let be an inaccessible, < be a regular cardinal and Q = Col(, 0 be ordinals and be a regular cardinal. Then

    (a) is an up-repeat point for F if for every A F(, ) there is , < < such that

    A F(, );

    (b) is a (, )-repeat point for F if (a1) cf = and (a2) for every A {F(, )|

    < + } there are unboundedly many s in such that A {F(, )| 2 + GCH or;

    (2) N S0+

    is -preserving for a regular > 2 + GCH or;

    (3) N S+ is 2-preserving for a regular > 2 + GCH or;

    (4) NSr+

    is 2-preserving for a regular > 2, < + GCH

    is the existence of an up-repeat point.

    14

  • 8/3/2019 Moti Gitik and Saharon Shelah- Cardinal Preserving Ideals

    15/32

    310

    re

    vision:1996-05-05

    modified:1996-05-06

    Proof: Use the model of [G4] with a presaturated N S over an inaccessible and the

    Levy collapse Col(,< ). By the results of Section1, N S will be -preserving in the

    generic extension.

    The rest of the section will be devoted to the construction of NS 1-preserving froman (, + + 1)-repeat point. The following theorem will then follow.

    Theorem 2.2.

    (1) the strength of N S0 is1-preserving + is an inaccessible is an (, + + 1)-repeat

    point;

    (2) the existence of an (, + + 1)-repeat point is sufficient for N S is 1-preserving +

    is an inaccessible +GCH;

    (3) the strength of N S0+ is 1-preserving +GCH for a regular > 2 is (, )-repeat

    point;

    (4) the existence of an (, + 1)-repeat point is sufficient for N S+ is 1-preserving

    +GCH, where is a regular cardinal.

    Suppose that U is a coherent sequence of ultrafilters with an (, + + 1)-repeat point

    at . Define the iteration P for in the closure of {|( = ) or ( < and is an

    inaccessible or = + 1 and is an inaccessible)}.

    On the limit stages use the limit of [G1]. For the benefit of the reader let us give a

    precise definition.

    Let A be a set consisting of s such that < and > 0() > 0. Denote by A the

    closure of the set { + 1 | A} A. For every A define by induction P to be the

    set of all elements p of the form p

    | g where

    (1) g is a subset of A.

    (2) g has an Easton support, i.e. for every inaccessible , > | dom g |;

    (3) for every dom g p = p

    | g P and p P

    p

    Q

    .

    Let p = p

    | g , q = q

    | f be elements of P. Then p q (p is stronger

    than q) if the following holds:

    (1) g f

    (2) for every f p P

    p

    q

    in the forcing Q

    15

  • 8/3/2019 Moti Gitik and Saharon Shelah- Cardinal Preserving Ideals

    16/32

    310

    re

    vision:1996-05-05

    modified:1996-05-06

    (3) there exists a finite subset b of f so that for every f\b, p p

    q

    in

    Q

    .

    If b = , then let p q.

    Suppose that is an inaccessible and P is defined. Define P+1. Let C(+) be theforcing for adding +-Cohen subsets to , i.e. {f VP |f is a partial function from +

    into , |f|VP

    < and for every < +{|(, ) dom f} is an ordinal}. P+1 will be

    P C(+) P(, O

    U()), where P(, OU()) is the forcing of [G1,2] with the slight change

    described below.

    The change is in the definition of U( , , t) the ultrafilter extending U(, ) for } p

    j(A

    ) .

    Note that the set D = {q|q||( j(A

    )} is E-dense and it belongs to N. So it appears in

    the list . Hence some p

    is in D.

    Let G be a generic subset of P C(+). Recall that by [G2] the sequence is commutative Rudin-Keisler increasing sequence of ultrafilters,

    for every .

    Now let j : V[G] M = V[G]/U(,, ). Then M = M[j(G)] for a model M

    of ZF C which is contained in M. We would like to have the exact description M.

    16

  • 8/3/2019 Moti Gitik and Saharon Shelah- Cardinal Preserving Ideals

    17/32

    310

    re

    vision:1996-05-05

    modified:1996-05-06

    The next definition is based on the Mitchel notion of complete iteration see [Mi 1,2,3].

    Definition 2.3. Suppose that N is a model of set theory, V a coherent sequence in N,

    is a cardinal. The complete iteration j : N M of V at will be the direct limit of

    j : N M , < for some ordinal , where , j, M are defined as follows. Set

    M0 = N, j0 = id, V0 = V, C0(, ) = for all and . If OV() = 0, then = 1.

    Suppose otherwise:

    Case 1. OV() is a limit ordinal.

    If j, M , V , C are defined then set

    j+1 : M M+1 = M/V( , ) ,

    where is the minimal ordinal so that

    (i) ;

    (ii) is less than the first > with OV() > 0;

    (iii) for some < OV () C(, ) is bounded in ;

    and is the minimal satisfying (iii) for .

    If there is not such an then set = , j = j , M = M , C = C . Define

    C+1|(, ) = C |( , ), +1 = j+1()

    C+1(+1, j+1()) =

    C(, ), if = C(, ) {}, if =

    Case 2. OV() = + 1.

    Define j , M, V and C as in Case 1, only in (ii) let be less than the image of

    under the embedding of N by V(, ).

    Theorem 2.4. Let j : V[G] M be

    (a) the ultrapower of V[G] by the ultrafilter U( ,, )

    or

    (b) the direct limit of the ultrapowers with the Rudin-Kiesler increasing sequence of the

    ultrafilters < U(, , )| < >.

    17

  • 8/3/2019 Moti Gitik and Saharon Shelah- Cardinal Preserving Ideals

    18/32

    310

    re

    vision:1996-05-05

    modified:1996-05-06

    Then M is a generic extension ofM, whereM is the complete iteration of U|(, +1)

    at , if (a) holds, and of U|(, ) at , if (b) holds.

    Main Lemma. Let M be as in the theorem and let i be the canonical embedding of V

    into M. Then there is G i(P C(+)) so that G V[G] and G is M[G] generic.

    Proof: Let us prove the lemma by induction on the pairs (, ) ordered lexicographically.

    Suppose that it holds for all (, ) < (, ). Let us prove the lemma for (, ).

    Case 1. = + 1.

    Let N be the ultrapower of V by U(, ) and j : V N the canonical embedding.

    We just simplify the previous notations, where N = N , j = j . Then M is the complete

    iteration of j( U)| + 1 at in N if is a limit ordinal, or for successor , the above

    iteration should be performed -times in order to obtain M. Let us concentrate on the

    first case; similar and slightly simpler arguments work for the second one.

    Denote by k : N M the above iteration. Then the following diagram is commutative

    Nj

    V k

    i

    M

    By the inductive assumption there exists G N[G] M-generic subset of Pk()

    C((k())+).

    If = 0 then k() = 0i(U)(k()) = 0 and C(k()+) is only the forcing used over

    k(). Suppose now that > 0. Then k() > 0 and the forcing over k() is C(k()+)

    followed by P(k(), k()). Let us define in N[G] a M[G]-generic subset ofP(k(), k()).

    Recall that a generic subset ofP(k(), k()) can be reconstructed from a generic sequence

    bk() to k(), where bk() is a combination of a cofinal in k() sequences so that b1k()({n})

    is a sequence appropriate for the ultrafilters i(U)(k(), ) with on the depth n. We refer

    to [G2] for detailed definitions.

    18

  • 8/3/2019 Moti Gitik and Saharon Shelah- Cardinal Preserving Ideals

    19/32

    310

    re

    vision:1996-05-05

    modified:1996-05-06

    Let us use the indiscernibles of the complete iteration C in order to define bk().

    Namely, only < C(k(), )| < k() > will be used.

    Set bk() = {< , n, > |n < , < k()+, < k(), for some < k() coded by

    < n, > in sense of [G2] C(k(), ))}.Let G

    be the subset of P(k(), k()) generated by bk(). Let us show that G

    is

    M[G]-generic subset. Let D M[G] be a dense open subset of P(k(), k()) and D

    its

    canonical name. Since M is the direct limit for some less than the length of the complete

    iteration, for some D

    M, D

    is the image of D

    . Let us work in M . Denote by G

    the appropriate part of G and by t a coherent sequence which generates bk()| . Let

    k : M M be the part of the complete iteration k on the step .

    Case 1.1. cfM(k()) < k(

    ).

    Then k() changes its cofinality to cfM (k(

    )) after the forcing with P(k(), k()).

    For every T so that < t, T > P(k(), k()), there exists i < cfM (k()) and

    T so that < t, T > is a condition stronger than < t ,T > and < t, T > forces some

    < t, T > D with t on the level i is in the generic set. In order to find such T just

    use the k()-completeness of the ultrafilters involved in the forcing P(k(), k(

    )) and

    the Prikry property. Now for every t T which is appropriate for i or some j i there

    exists T such that < t, T > D . The same property remains true for k(T) for every

    < length of the iteration k. Pick to be large enough in order to contain

    elements of bk() appropriate for i. Let t be a coherent sequence generating bk()| . It

    is possible to pick such t in k(T). But then for some T < t, T k(T

    ) > k (D).

    The image of < t, T k(T) > under the rest of the iteration will be in G

    .

    Case 1.2. cfM (k()) = k(

    ).

    Then k() changes its cofinality to .

    For every T so that < t, T > P(k(), k()) there exist n < and T so that

    < t, T > is a condition stronger than < t, T > and < t, T > forces some < t, T > D ,

    with t containing the first n elements of the canonical -sequence to k(), is in the generic

    set.

    Pick in order to first reach n elements of the canonical -sequence to k().

    19

  • 8/3/2019 Moti Gitik and Saharon Shelah- Cardinal Preserving Ideals

    20/32

  • 8/3/2019 Moti Gitik and Saharon Shelah- Cardinal Preserving Ideals

    21/32

    310

    re

    vision:1996-05-05

    modified:1996-05-06

    Let us check that G is M[G ]-generic subset of C(+). Suppose that D M[G ] is

    a dense open subset of C(+). Let D

    be a canonical P-name of D. By the assumption

    on there are indiscernibles < 1 < < n < such that the support of D

    is a

    subset of {, 1 , . . . , n}. Since the forcing C(+

    ) is -closed D can be replaced by itdense open subset with support alone. Let us assume that D

    is already such a subset.

    Then D

    = k(D

    ) for dense open D

    N subset of C(()+). By the choice of the master

    condition sequence for some < +

    p | p(

    )|C(()+) D

    .

    But this implies

    k(p)()|C(+

    ) D .

    So G D = .

    Suppose now that 0k(U)() > 0. We need to define G

    a M[G G]-generic subset of

    P(, 0k(U)()). In this case is a limit of indiscernibles, i.e. C(, ) is unbounded in for

    every < 0k(U)()). So we are in the situation considered above. The only difference is that

    some ps may contain information about the generic sequence b to . In order to preserve

    k(p)| + 1 in the generic set, we need to start b according to k(p)(). Notice, that

    further elements of the master condition sequence do not increase the coherent sequence

    given by p.

    Case B. is a limit ordinal.

    Set G = {p P| for every < p| G}. Let us show that G is M-generic

    subset of P. Consider two cases.

    Case B.1. There are unboundedly many in indiscernibles for ordinals .

    Since = k(), is a limit of indiscernibles for . Then is measurable in M and thedirect limit is used on the stage . Let < i|i < > be a cofinal sequence of indiscernibles.

    Let D M be a dense open subset of P. Then { < |D H() is a dense open

    subset of

    is almost contained

    in every club of M so there is i0 s.t. D P0 is dense. But then G0 D = . Hence

    G D = .

    21

  • 8/3/2019 Moti Gitik and Saharon Shelah- Cardinal Preserving Ideals

    22/32

    310

    re

    vision:1996-05-05

    modified:1996-05-06

    Case B.2. There are only boundedly many in indiscernibles for ordinals .

    Then, since = k(), there is no indiscernibles for ordinals below . So there

    are unboundedly many in ordinals which are in the range ofk.

    Let D be a dense open subset of P in M. Define D = {p P| for some k(p0)|

    G for every < . So

    k(p0)| G.

    So G is an M-generic subset of P. It completes Case B and hence also Case 1 of

    the lemma.

    22

  • 8/3/2019 Moti Gitik and Saharon Shelah- Cardinal Preserving Ideals

    23/32

    310

    re

    vision:1996-05-05

    modified:1996-05-06

    Case 2. is a limit ordinal.

    Use the inductive assumption and the definitions of the generic sets of Case 1. Define

    a generic subset of Pk() as in Case B.1.

    of the lemma.

    Let G V[G] be the M-generic subset of Pi() C(i()+) defined in the Main

    Lemma. Then G P C(+) = G and for every < + i(p) G. Define the

    elementary embedding i : V[G] M[G] by i(a

    [G]) = (i(a

    ))[G]. Then i|V = i,

    i(G) and, if U = {A | i(A)} then U = U(,, ). So the following diagram is

    commutative

    M[G]i

    V[G]

    M = V[G]/U

    where ([f]U) = i(f)().

    It remains to show that = id. Notice, that it is enough to prove that every indis-

    cernible in C is of the form i(f)() for some f V[G]. Examining the construction of

    G, it is not hard to see that every indiscernible is an element of the generic sequence b

    for some k

    (N).

    So indiscernibles are interpretations of forcing terms with parameters in k

    (N). But

    such elements can easily be represented by functions on in V[G]. Let C and

    = (t())[G] for = k(), where t is a term. Let = [f]U(,) for some f : ,

    f V. Define a function g V[G] on as follows: g() = t(f())[G]. Then i(g)() =

    t(t(f)())[G] = (t())[G] = .

    Let us now turn to the construction of 1-preserving ideal. Suppose that is an

    (, + + 1)-repeat point for U in V. Let < + + be an ordinal. Denote by M

    the complete iteration ofj (U)|((j (), (j

    (

    + +)) in N . Let i, k be the canonical

    23

  • 8/3/2019 Moti Gitik and Saharon Shelah- Cardinal Preserving Ideals

    24/32

    310

    re

    vision:1996-05-05

    modified:1996-05-06

    elementary embeddings making the diagram

    Njk

    V

    ki

    M

    commutative.

    As in the Main Lemma find in V[G] a P(, )-name of a M-generic subset G

    of

    Pi

    () C(i

    (

    +

    ))/P+1 so that each k

    (p

    ) G

    for <

    +

    , where < p

    | < +

    > is themaster condition sequence for U(,, ). Let G

    be obtained from G

    by removing all the

    information on the generic subset of C(i(+)) except i

    (G C(+)).

    We shall define a presaturated filter U(, ) on in V[G] extending U(, ) so that

    (i) all generic ultrapowers of U(, ) are generic extensions of M;

    (ii) every set U(,, ) is U(, )-positive.

    Property (i) will insure that the forcing for shooting clubs over i() will be -closed

    forcing. Property (ii) is needed for the iteration of forcings for shooting clubs over in

    V[G].

    Denote G P by G and G C(+) by G. Let G() denote the -th function of G

    for < +. Let j be the embedding of V[G] into the ultrapower of V[G] by U(,, ).

    Let < | < + > be the list of all the indiscernibles for i() of the complete iteration

    used to define M. For every < + extend G

    to G

    by adding to G

    conditions

    < + + 1, , > for every < +, i.e. the + + 1 generic function moves to .

    Define a filter U(, ) on in V[G] as follows:

    A belongs to U(, ) iff for some r G some r

    s.t. r

    G

    , for every

    p

    C

    (j (+))(0) s.t. in N [j

    (G)] p j(G(0)), and for some r

    s.t. r

    G

    (p

    )

    in M

    r 1P(,) p

    r

    Pi()+1

    i(A

    )

    24

  • 8/3/2019 Moti Gitik and Saharon Shelah- Cardinal Preserving Ideals

    25/32

    310

    re

    vision:1996-05-05

    modified:1996-05-06

    where (p) < + is the minimal s.t. p| j(G(0)), for the (p) member of some fixed

    enumeration of j ().

    Claim 1. U(,, ) U(, ).

    Proof: Let A U(,, ), then for some < + some r, < , T > P(, ), in N

    r {< , T >} p

    j (A

    ) .

    Let us split p

    into three parts p1

    =p

    | Pj , p2

    =p

    C(j (+))(0) and p

    3

    = the rest of

    p

    . Then, using k, in M

    r {< , T >} k

    (p) i

    (A) .

    Extend p2

    to some p

    2

    , still remaining in the master condition sequence, in order to make

    its domain above all the indices of the generic sequences listed in p3

    . Extend p2 to some

    p

    2 C(j (

    +))(0) which is incompatible with a member of the master condition sequence.

    Then, using k, in M

    r {< , T >} k(p1

    ) k(p

    2

    ) k(p3

    ) i(A

    ) .

    By the definition of U(, ), it implies that A is a U(, )-positive set.

    So every member of U(,, ) is U(, )-positive. The fact that U(,, ) is an

    ultrafilter completes the proof of the claim.

    Claim 2. U(, ) is normal precipitous cardinal preserving filter and its generic ultra-

    power is a generic extension ofM.

    Proof: Let U = U(, )V[G, G(0)]. The arguments of Theorem 1 show that a generic

    ultrapower by U is isomorphic to a generic extension of the complete iteration of N with

    j (U)|j () above . Actually the forcing with U is isomorphic to P(, ) followed by

    C(j (+))(0) (in the sense of this iteration) over V[G, G(0)]. Clearly, the generic function

    form j (+) into j (

    +) produced by this forcing is incompatible with j(G(0)) which

    belongs to V[G, G(0)].

    25

  • 8/3/2019 Moti Gitik and Saharon Shelah- Cardinal Preserving Ideals

    26/32

    310

    re

    vision:1996-05-05

    modified:1996-05-06

    Now the forcing with U(, ) over V[G] does the following: First it picks p

    C

    (j (+))(0) incompatible with j(G(0)) and then G(p

    ) is added. G(p

    ) insures that a

    generic ultrapower is a generic extension ofM. So the forcing with U(, ) is isomorphic

    to P(, ) followed by a portion of C(i(+)), which is -closed.

    Force over V[G] with the forcing Q which is the Backward-Easton iteration of the

    forcings adding +-Cohen subsets to every regular < with 0U() > 0. Fix a generic

    subset H of Q. All the filters U(, ) extend in the obvious fashion in V[G, H]. Let us

    use the same notations for the extended filters.

    Set F = {U(, )| + +}. Then F is a -preserving filter in V[G, H]

    and forcing with it is isomorphic to P(, ) (for some , + +) followed

    by -closed forcing. Let us shoot clubs through elements of F, then through the sets of

    generic points and so on, as was done in [G 3,4]. Denote this forcing by B. Let R be its

    generic subset over V[G, H]. We shall show that N S is 1-preserving ideal in V[G,H,R].

    The forcing with N S consists of two parts:

    (a) embedding of B into P(, );

    (b) (-closed forcing) (i(B)/i(R)).

    By the choice of i(), the forcing i(B) is a shooting club through sets containing a

    club (the club of indiscernibles for i()). So it is -closed forcing and part (b) does not

    cause any problem.

    Let us examine part (a) and show that this forcing preserves 1. Recall that B is the

    direct limit of < B| < + > where each B is of cardinality and for a limit , B =

    the direct limit of B( < ), if cf = and B = the inverse limit of B(

    < )

    otherwise. The forcing of (a) is

    P = { V[G, H]| for some < +

    is an embedding of B into P(, )} .

    For 1, 2 P let 1 2 if 1| dom 2 = 2.

    Claim. N S is an 1-preserving ideal in V[G,H,R].

    Proof: Suppose otherwise. Then for some + + some condition in the

    forcing P(, ) (the forcing isomorphic to the adding of+-Cohen subsets of+) P over

    26

  • 8/3/2019 Moti Gitik and Saharon Shelah- Cardinal Preserving Ideals

    27/32

    310

    re

    vision:1996-05-05

    modified:1996-05-06

    V[G, H] forces 1 to collapse. Let us assume that the empty condition already forces this.

    Consider the case when P(,)cf = . The remaining cases are simpler.

    Let S be a V[G, H]-generic subset of P(, ) (+-Cohen subsets of +). Denote

    V[G,H,S] by V. Let f be a P-name in V of a function from to V

    1 . Pick an elementarysubmodel N of < H(),,B, P, , f

    >, for big enough, satisfying the following three

    conditions:

    (1) |N| = ;

    (2) N HV();

    (3) N + = for some s.t. cfV[G,H] = .

    Then B N = B. Also B is a direct limit of < B | < >. Pick in V[G, H]

    a cofinal sequence < | < > to and in V a cofinal sequence < n|n < > to .

    Consider the subsets of , s.t. B+1/B is the forcing for shooting club

    into A

    . Assume for simplicity that all As are in V. Let A = 0. Denote n0 by 0. Let

    C0 be the generic club through A0 defined by 0 and S. As in Lemma 3.6 [G4], it is

    possible to find an element of the generic sequence to , (0) A n0 such that C is a

    V[G|(0), H|(0)]-generic club through A . Choosing (0) more carefully, it is possible

    to also satisfy the following A (0) =

  • 8/3/2019 Moti Gitik and Saharon Shelah- Cardinal Preserving Ideals

    28/32

    310

    re

    vision:1996-05-05

    modified:1996-05-06

    = + for a regular > 1. It is possible to use the model constructed above, collapse

    to + and apply the results of Section 1. But an (, + + 1)-repeat point was used

    in the construction of the model. It turns out that an (, + 1)-repeat point suffices

    for N S+ and an (, )-repeat point for N S+ |{ < +

    |cf < }. On the other hand,precipitousness of N S0

    +implies an (, )-repeat point, by [G4].

    Let us preserve the notations used above. Assume that < is a regular cardinal and

    some < 0U() is an (, + 1)-repeat point. Let G be a generic subset of P C(+).

    Over V[G] instead of the forcing Q, in the previous construction, use Col(, ) the Levy

    collapse of all the cardinals , < < on . Let H be a generic subset of Col(, ).

    Denote by H() the generic function from on where (, ).

    Now the forcing for shooting clubs should come. In order to prevent collapsing

    cardinals by this forcing, j() was made a limit of + indiscernibles for the measures

    {U(, )| < + +}. But now we have only measures. So the best we can do

    is to make j() a limit of indiscernibles and then its cofinality in V will be < . It

    looks slightly paradoxical since usually cf j() = +, but it is possible by [G5]. In order

    to explain the idea of [G5] which will be used here let us give an example of a precipitous

    ideal I on 1 so that:

    () I+

    cfV(j(1)) = .

    Example. Suppose that is a measurable cardinal. Let U be a normal measure on

    and j : V N = V/U the canonical embedding. Let P be the Backward-Easton

    iteration of the forcings C(+) for all regular < . Let G H be a generic subset ofV.

    Collapse to 1 by the Levy collapse. Let R be V[G H]-generic subset of Col(1, ).

    Denote V[G H R] by V1. We shall define a precipitous ideal satisfying () in V1.

    Let j0 = j, N0 = N, 0 = , U0 = U. Set N1 = Nj0()0 /j0(U), 1 = j0(), U1 = j0(U)

    and let j1 : N0 N1 be the canonical embedding. Continue the definition for all n < .

    Set j, N to be the direct limit of < jn, Nn|n < >. Then j() =

    n

  • 8/3/2019 Moti Gitik and Saharon Shelah- Cardinal Preserving Ideals

    29/32

    310

    re

    vision:1996-05-05

    modified:1996-05-06

    Define a filter U in V[G H R] as follows:

    A U iff for some r G H R for some n < in N

    r pn j(A

    )

    where pn is the name of condition in the forcing C(j(+)) defined as follows:

    let h

    be the name of the generic function from onto (+)V in Col(, j())/G H R.

    Set pn = {< j(h

    (0)), , 1 >, < j(h(1

    )), , 2 >, . . . , < j(h

    (n)), , n+1 >}. The

    meaning of the above is that the value on of j(h(m))-th function from j() to j()

    is forced to be m+1.

    It is not difficult to see now that U is a normal precipitous ideal on 1 and a generic

    ultrapower with it is isomorphic to a V[GH R]-generic extension of N[G, H, R].

    Also for a generic embedding j, j|V = j. Hence j() = which is of cofinality in

    V.

    As in [J-M-Mi-P], it is possible to extend U to the closed unbounded filter with the

    same property. Using the Namba forcing, it is possible to construct a precipitous ideal

    satisfying () on 2. Starting from a measurable which is a limit of measurable, it is

    possible to build such an ideal over an inaccessible or even measurable. Since then it is

    possible to change the cofinality of the ordinal of cofinality + to in N and that is what

    was needed to catch all ns in the above construction. We do not know if one measurable

    is sufficient for a precipitous ideal satisfying () over > 2.

    Note also that by Proposition 1.5 ifI is -preserving, then cfVj() . In particular,

    if I is presaturated then cfVj() = +.

    Let us now return to the construction ofN S+ 1-preserving. Let < + be

    an ordinal. Define M as in the construction of N S 1-preserving for an inaccessible .

    Now cfVi() will be . We shall define, in V[G, H], U(, ) extending U(, ) satisfying

    conditions (i) and (ii) from page 23. To do so simply combine the definition there with the

    definition of the example. We leave the details to the reader. The rest of the construction

    does not differ from an inaccessible cardinal case.

    The above results give equiconsistency for NS| (singular) or something close to

    equiconsistency for N S, but for > 2. For = 2, we do not know if the assump-

    29

  • 8/3/2019 Moti Gitik and Saharon Shelah- Cardinal Preserving Ideals

    30/32

    310

    re

    vision:1996-05-05

    modified:1996-05-06

    tion of the existence of an (, 1 +1)-repeat point (or of an (, 1)-repeat point for N S02

    )

    can be weakened. By [G3], a measurable is sufficient for the precipitousness of N S02 and

    a measurable of order 2 for N S2 . Let us show that 1-preservingness requires stronger

    assumptions.

    Lemma 2.5. Suppose that > 1 is a regular cardinal, 2 = +, 20 = 1. I is a normal

    1-preserving ideal over so that { < |cf = } I. Then 0() 2 in the core

    model.

    Proof: Without loss of generality, assume that 0() = ++. Denote by K( F) the

    core model with the maximal sequence F. We refer to Mitchell papers [Mi 1,2] for the

    definitions and properties of K( F) that we are going to use.

    The set A = { < | is regular in K( F) and of cofinality in V} is I-positive.

    If the set A = { A| is not measurable in K( F)} is bounded in , then 0() 2.

    Suppose otherwise. Let j : V M be a generic elementary embedding so that the set

    { < |cf = } belongs to a generic ultrafilter GI. Then j(A) is unbounded in j().

    Pick the mimimal j(A) .

    Claim. cfK(F)() = (+)K(

    F).

    Proof: Suppose otherwise. Then, since is regular in K( F) and j|K( F) is an iterated

    ultrapower of K( F) by F, is a limit indiscernible of this iteration. By Proposition 1.5.

    M V[GI] M. Since is not a measurable in K(j( F)), it implies that cfK(F) > .

    But then, using M V[GI] M and the arguments of [Mi 2] and [G4], we obtain some

    with 0F() (1)K

    ( F). of the claim.

    By [Mi 2], (+)K(F) = (+)V. But in V[GI], cf = and hence cf(

    +)V = which

    contradicts Proposition 1.5.

    Lemma 2.6. Suppose that > 1 is a regular cardinal, 2 = +, 20 = 1 and I is a

    normal 1-preserving ideal. If there exists an -club C so that every C is regular in

    K( F), then 0F() 1 in K( F).

    The proof is similar to Lemma 2.5; just consider the 1-th member of j(C) .

    30

  • 8/3/2019 Moti Gitik and Saharon Shelah- Cardinal Preserving Ideals

    31/32

    310

    re

    vision:1996-05-05

    modified:1996-05-06

    Theorem 2.7. Assume GCH, if N S02 is 1-preserving then 0F() 1 in K( F).

    The proof follows from Lemma 2.6.

    References

    [A] U. Avraham, Isomorphism of Aronszajn trees, Ph.D. Thesis, Jerusalem, 1979.

    [B] J. Baumgartner, Independence results in set theory, Notices Am. Math. Soc.

    25 (1978), A 248-249.

    [B-T] J. Baumgartner and A. Taylor, Ideals in generic extensions. II, Trans. of Am.

    Math. Soc. 271 ( 1982), 587-609.

    [G-J-M] F. Galvin, T. Jech and M. Magidor, An ideal game, J. of Symbolic Logic 43

    (1978), 284-292.

    [G1] M. Gitik, Changing cofinalities and the nonstationary ideal, Israel J. of Math.

    56 (1986), 280-314.

    [G2] M. Gitik, SC H from 0() = ++, Ann. of Pure 43 (1989), 209-234.

    [G3] M. Gitik, The nonstationary ideal on 2, Israel J. of Math. 48 (1984), 257-288.

    [G4] M. Gitik, Some results on the nonstationary ideal, Israel Journal of Math.

    [G5] M. Gitik, On generic elementary embeddings, J. Sym. Logic 54(3) (1989),

    700-707.

    [H-S] L. Harrington and S. Shelah, Equiconsistency results in set theory, Notre

    Dame J. of Formal Logic 26(2) (1985), 178-188.

    [J-M-Mi-P] T. Jech, M. Magidor, W. Mitchell and K. Prikry, Precipitous ideals, J. Sym.

    Logic 45 (1980), 1-8.

    [Mi 1] W. Mitchell, The core model for sequences of measures I, Math. Proc. Camb.

    Phil Soc. 95 (1984), 229-260.

    [Mi 2] W. Mitchell, The core model for sequence of measures II, to appear.

    31

  • 8/3/2019 Moti Gitik and Saharon Shelah- Cardinal Preserving Ideals

    32/32

    re

    vision:1996-05-05

    modified:1996-05-06

    [Mi 3] W. Mitchell, Indiscernibles, skies and ideals, Contemp. Math. 31 (1984),

    161-182.

    [S1] S. Shelah, Proper forcing, Springer-Verlag Lecture Notes in Math, 940 (1982).

    [S2] S. Shelah, Some notes on iterated forcing with 20 > 2, Notre Dame J. of

    Formal Logic.

    32