marion, jean-luc - on the foundation of the distinction between theology and philosophy

30
1 & 2 & 3 9 On the Foundation of the Distinction Between eology and Philosophy JEAN-LUC MARION UNIVERSITY OF PARIS-SORBONNE (PARIS IV), FRANCE UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO, U.S.A. e Conflict of the Faculties T he question of philosophy and of its being taught in the university always leads to the question of the freedom of inquiry. Like any other discipline, philosophy can unfold only under the condition of its freedom; and even more so than any other discipline, because it does not dispose, like the other disciplines, of an object determined by a method that would constitute it, but must each time build a road on which to march. It remains that philosophy is taught and developed only within the framework of institutions, particularly of universities. How can such an institution allow, tolerate, even guarantee such an unconditional freedom as the condition of everything? How can phi- losophy demand this without putting into question the institution to which it nevertheless belongs and without entering into conflict with other disciplines? is danger appears clearly when philosophy comes into contact—like two tectonic plates—with theology, which not only cannot not admit a normative authority (that of the revealed datum and, only then, that of the ecclesial Magisterium) but which can hardly avoid the temptation (or the duty) to impose its own norms and re- sults on other disciplines, and first of all on philosophy. What Kant called the conflict of the faculties (between theology, law, and medi- cine on the one hand and philosophy on the other) in fact goes back to the very foundation of the universities which immediately provoked a conflict between the faculty of theology and the faculty of arts and

Upload: jefferson-chua

Post on 31-Dec-2015

52 views

Category:

Documents


2 download

DESCRIPTION

This essay was originally a keynote lecture given at the Ateneo de Manila University in 2008. Here Marion talks about the distinction between theology and philosophy by looking at the historical constructions that allowed for the separation. In the end he proposes looking at the divide from the point of view of his own contribution to phenomenology: that of givenness.

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Marion, Jean-Luc - On the Foundation of the Distinction Between Theology and Philosophy

1 & 2 & 3 9

On the Foundation of the DistinctionBetween Theology and Philosophy

JEAN-LUC MARIONUNIVERSITY OF PARIS-SORBONNE (PARIS IV), FRANCE

UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO, U.S.A.

The Conflict of the Faculties

The question of philosophy and of its being taught in the university always leads to the question of the freedom of inquiry. Like any

other discipline, philosophy can unfold only under the condition of its freedom; and even more so than any other discipline, because it does not dispose, like the other disciplines, of an object determined by a method that would constitute it, but must each time build a road on which to march. It remains that philosophy is taught and developed only within the framework of institutions, particularly of universities. How can such an institution allow, tolerate, even guarantee such an unconditional freedom as the condition of everything? How can phi-losophy demand this without putting into question the institution to which it nevertheless belongs and without entering into conflict with other disciplines? This danger appears clearly when philosophy comes into contact—like two tectonic plates—with theology, which not only cannot not admit a normative authority (that of the revealed datum and, only then, that of the ecclesial Magisterium) but which can hardly avoid the temptation (or the duty) to impose its own norms and re-sults on other disciplines, and first of all on philosophy. What Kant called the conflict of the faculties (between theology, law, and medi-cine on the one hand and philosophy on the other) in fact goes back to the very foundation of the universities which immediately provoked a conflict between the faculty of theology and the faculty of arts and

Page 2: Marion, Jean-Luc - On the Foundation of the Distinction Between Theology and Philosophy

48 JEAN-LUC MARION

1 & 2 & 3 9

which cuts through the whole history of the university even to our day: one of the most decisive dividing lines among university systems in the world today passes between universities which have always had a faculty of theology and those which have suppressed it. Evidently, the conflict between faculties is noticeable above all in universities which have kept the two faculties alongside each other, and thus primarily in Catholic universities. Catholic universities paradoxically appear to be the privileged site of the conflict always possible between philosophy and theology.

The popular interpretation of this conflict amounts to an opposition of the faculty of philosophy, which would defend the rights of reason (or at least that of rationality), against the faculty of theology, which would defend the rights of faith and indeed of the Revelation. There is an additional variable in that the frontline could pass even within the faculty of theology: between the so called scientific disciplines (exege-sis, church history, etc…) and the speculative disciplines. Moreover, the frontline can pass within the speculative disciplines themselves: between the conservative positions and the progressive avant-garde, etc…. One can admit, following above all the authority of Kant, as a necessary evil, that “the conflict between the superior faculties [here, theology] and the inferior faculty [philosophy] will first of all be in-evitable, but, and secondly, that it will also be legal,” and even “that it cannot be stopped,” because “the faculty of philosophy can never lay down its arms in front of the danger that threatens truth, the protec-tion of which is entrusted to philosophy, because the superior faculties will never abdicate their claim to dominate.”1 Let us recognize that, more often than not and even in Catholic universities, once we discuss the “freedom of inquiry” before the authority of the Magisterium, we reason out like Kantians of the strict observance.

Our argument, however, will not be to take one side or the other in this conflict and not even to attempt, after so many others, a mediation. It will be to interrogate ourselves on the very terms of the relation between philosophy and theology: it could in fact be the

1Immanuel Kant, The Conflict of the Faculties (Der Streit der Fakultäten), trans. with an introduction by Mary J. Gregor (Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press, 1979), I.1.4, pp. 53 and 55. [Translator’s note: In this instance, we have translated from the French translation cited by the author. The source for the English translation cited here is provided for the benefit of the reader who wishes to consult the full text.]

Page 3: Marion, Jean-Luc - On the Foundation of the Distinction Between Theology and Philosophy

THE DISTINCTION BETWEEN PHILOSOPHY AND THEOLOGY 49

1 & 2 & 3 9

case that the lack of precision of these concepts, indeed the confusion in the definitions, not only forbids any clarification of obscurities, but constitutes in fact the heart of the problem, nobody knowing exactly what he is defending and against what. For the conflict of the faculties supposes that one identifies, to begin with, what one opposes in order to then clearly determine the difference between the disciplines. Now, this difference, most of the time and first of all, is found supposed-ly known and presupposed without ambiguity. We will show on the contrary that this is no longer evident today because the contemporary situation of philosophy—that of the “end of metaphysics” and the radi-cal possibilities that it opens up to thought2—renders problematic or even obsolete the criteria which up to now have been retained for rig-orously distinguishing philosophy and theology, and then eventually for describing the supposed conflict. It could be that, with the loss of these usual criteria of their differentiation, the conflict itself becomes obsolete and a totally different relationship is sketched between them.

Brief Historical Remarks

Before any conceptual discussion, it is appropriate to recall two his-torical facts that underlie the question that we have just introduced.

We must remember first of all that Christian thought, when it found itself charged with exposing, rendering credible, and therefore conceptualizing the Revelation of God in Jesus Christ, did not have recourse to the term theology. This term came from propositions concerning the divine proffered by poets and the first Greek think-ers, doubly mortgaged first of all by the indeterminate acceptance of the gods and of the divine, with which the designation of the one in-commensurable God of the biblical Revelation absolutely broke off; and then of the uncritical assumption of being able to say anything whatsoever about God, whereas the God of Revelation not only proves to be unsayable and unnameable as such, but paradoxically exercises for himself the function of the λόγος and, in speaking of himself, thus imposes a theo-logy before the least theo-logy.3 It is in this sense that

2Regarding this point, see our study on “The ‘End of Metaphysics’ as a Possibility,” trans. Daryl Lee, in Religion after Metaphysics, ed. Mark A. Wrathall (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2003), pp. 165-89.

3To the “theologia, quasi sermo de Deo – theology, as it were, talk about God,” (St.

Page 4: Marion, Jean-Luc - On the Foundation of the Distinction Between Theology and Philosophy

50 JEAN-LUC MARION

1 & 2 & 3 9

Dionysius will end up reintroducing the term when, in making use of affirmative and negative “theologies,” he refers to and repeats the names that God himself uses in his regard in the Scriptures (obviously in a manner different from any kind of Neoplatonism). We will have to wait until Abelard and even the constitution of theologia as a science by St. Thomas for the term to find itself definitively received by Christian usage. That for twelve centuries, and precisely during those centuries when it forged its most decisive concepts (concepts which underlie our discourse even today), Christian thought had almost ignored, that is to say did not really need, the term theologia, should at least surprise us and put us on guard against the assurance that the concept of “theol-ogy” is a matter of course. How can such a long absence of theologia in the history of “theology” not continue to determine its status today?

The reticence with regard to the term theologia, for example on the part of St. Augustine, indeed leads us, if we examine the reasons, to another surprise: that of the equivalence between theology and philoso-phy. When in fact he mentions the minimalist definition: “Theologiam pertinent, quo verbo græco significari intelligimus de divinitate ratio-nem, sive sermonem – Theology, a Greek term by which we understand to signify reasoning or discourse concerning divinity,”4 it is not yet a

Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiæ Ia, q.1, a.7, sed contra) one can contrast a more original sermo ab Deo whose “ad nos revelatio divina processit — divine revelation has come down to us.” (Summa theologiæ Ia, q.1, a.2, ad 2) [English translation: Summa Theologiæ, vol. 1, Christian Theology (Ia.1), ed. and trans. Thomas Gilby, O.P. (Cam-bridge, UK: Blackfriars, 1964). [Translator’s note: in all quotations from St. Thomas Aquinas, all emphases are those of the author.]

4St. Augustine, The City of God against the Pagans, ed. and trans. Robert W. Dyson (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1998), VIII.1.34, p. 312 [translator’s note: as with the first footnote, the translation has been modified], echoing a definition of “sapientia” by Cicero: “Sapientiam esse rerum divinarum et humanarum scientiam cognitionemque – Wisdom is the knowledge of things divine and human” in Tuscu-lan Disputations, with an English translation by John Edward King (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1996), IV.26.57, pp. 392-3 and: “Illa autem sapientia, quam principem dixi, rerum est divinarum et humanarum scientia, in qua continetur deorum et hominum communitas et societas inter ipsos – Again, that wisdom which I have given the foremost place is the knowledge of things human and divine, which is concerned also with the bonds of union between gods and men and the relations of man to man.” in De Officiis, with an English translation by Walter Miller (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1975), I.43.153, pp. 156-7 or ibid., II.2.5, pp. 172-3. The catalogue of reference has been drawn up by Goulven Madec, Saint Augustin et la philosophie. Notes critiques (Paris: Institut d’études augustiniennes, 1996), particularly chapter 2, which

Page 5: Marion, Jean-Luc - On the Foundation of the Distinction Between Theology and Philosophy

THE DISTINCTION BETWEEN PHILOSOPHY AND THEOLOGY 51

1 & 2 & 3 9

question here of what the moderns will name theologia in its double (even opposite) meanings: either the knowledge of Revelation or the other theologia rationalis, which, as one of the parts of the metaphysica specialis, is in turn framed by the metaphysica generalis (or ontologia).5 It is a question here of something much less than that. It only alludes to the usage in fact proposed by Varro: “Tria genera theologiæ dicit esse, id est rationis quæ de diis explicatur, eorumque unum mythicon appellari, alterum physicon, tertium civile… – He says that there are three classes of theology, that is to say of reason furnishing explana-tions concerning the gods: the one mythical, the other physical (and by this philosophers speaking of nature and the heavenly movements), and the third political,”6 in other words the theologia of the poets nar-rating stories about the gods, that of the philosophi considering the movements of the stars, and that of the priests celebrating the cult of the city.7 St. Augustine does not accept to be the “theologian” of any of the first two theologiæ, that of the poets (whose ridiculous and im-moral fables are a calumny of the divinity), and that of the city (purely political, for reflecting the ideological claims of the city). It therefore remains to consider only “theologia naturalis, quæ non huic tantum [sc. Varron], sed multis philosophis placuit – the natural theology that was suitable not only to Varro, but to a number of philosophers.”8 This privilege holds on to the fact that it is a question of this part of philoso-phy (physics, or more exactly cosmology) that defines what in nature, indeed in its regular heavenly movements, most closely approximates the divine immutability. And, therefore, since only philosophers reach this narrow but real rationality, Christian thought (what today we call theology) can only discuss with these philosophers and never with the other “theologies” (which are empty of all rationality) of the pagans:

we follow essentially.5See infra, note 13. 6St. Augustine, City of God VI.5.1, p. 246. [translation modified]7Varro, Antiquitates rerum divinarum libri I-II fragmenta, ed. Augusta Germana

Condemi (Bologna: Zanichelli, 1965), vol. 1, pp. 9, 10, 14, 16 and 17 (fragments 10, 14, 23, 28 and 29, respectively) reproducing City of God VIII.1, VII.6, VI.5 and VI.6. Even the formulation “[theologia] naturali, quæ philosophorum est – natural theology which belongs to the philosophers” (City of God VI.8.2, p. 256) refers to the discourse on di-vinity on the basis of nature, that is to say of cosmology such as Varro understands it, and evidently without anticipating in any way the metaphysica specialis.

8 St. Augustine, City of God VII.6, p. 276. [translation modified]

Page 6: Marion, Jean-Luc - On the Foundation of the Distinction Between Theology and Philosophy

52 JEAN-LUC MARION

1 & 2 & 3 9

“Non cum quibuslibet hominibus…; sed cum philosophis est habenda collatio. – The confrontation must not take place with just about any-body… but with philosophers.”9 Thus, in a strict sense, that is to say in the sense in which he himself understood it, St. Augustine does not, except in a very marginal way, work as a theologian: strictly speaking, he would rather admit doing the work of a philosopher, in the strict sense of an amator Dei. Thus concludes the discussion: “Verus phi-losophus est amator Dei. – The true philosopher is the one who loves God.”10 Obviously, this meaning of philosophy has nothing or very little in common with the contemporary use of the term. This never-theless remains a fact, and a fact which has persisted as long as the use of philosophia christiana could designate the monastic life, and, more generally, the properly Christian way of life (that is to say at least until Erasmus).11 Thus, not only does the term theologia not always define the exercise of thinking out the Revelation, but philosophia can be sub-stituted for it, by virtue of its obvious meaning of love of wisdom and, therefore, of the author and of the site of Wisdom. In this context, the conflict of the faculties is no longer a matter of course just as the very definitions of the opposing faculties are no longer a matter of course.

Reciprocally, the antagonism between theologia and philosophia implies that a rivalry can make them oppose each other, a rivalry im-plying in turn a common ground of confrontation. Historically, these conditions were not obtained before the intellectual climate of his

9Ibid., VIII.1, p. 312. [translation modified] This point has been strongly under-lined by Joseph Cardinal Ratzinger, “The Truth of Christianity?” in Truth and Toler-ance: Christian Belief and World Religions, trans. Henry Taylor (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 2004), pp. 165-72.

10 St. Augustine, VIII.1, p. 312. [translation modified] This remains in profound harmony with a more ancient position, that of St. Justin: “So, among the non-Hellen-ic peoples, those who are and those who seem to be wise all have the one common name—they are all named Christians.” in Writings of Saint Justin Martyr, trans. Thomas B. Falls (New York: Christian Heritage, Inc., 1948), Apology I.7, p. 40; and also ibid., XXVI.6, p. 63. See Daniel Bourgeois, La sagesse des anciens dans le mystère du verbe. Évangile et philosophie chez saint Justin, philosophe et martyr (Paris: Téqui, 1981).

11Étienne Gilson goes even all the way up to Calvin: “the ‘Christian philosophy’ of Calvin is a purely supernatural knowledge; in a word it is a theology.” in “Nature and Philosophy,” in Christianity and Philosophy, trans. Ralph MacDonald, C.S.B. (New York: Sheed and Ward Inc., 1939), p. 18. On this syntagma, see Gustave Bardy, “‘Phi-On this syntagma, see Gustave Bardy, “‘Phi-losophie’ et ‘philosophe’ dans le vocabulaire chrétien des premiers siècles,” Revue d’as-cétique et de mystique 25 (1949), pp. 97-108.

Page 7: Marion, Jean-Luc - On the Foundation of the Distinction Between Theology and Philosophy

THE DISTINCTION BETWEEN PHILOSOPHY AND THEOLOGY 53

1 & 2 & 3 9

time led St. Thomas Aquinas to make two genial but very particular decisions. First of all, that of articulating together under the title of metaphysica three sciences left unconnected by Aristotle: first of all the prima philosophia which “considers the first causes of things” (thus in the end God), then the metaphysica in a narrower sense “which con-siders ens (what is) and what follows from it,” and finally the scientia divina sive theologia which considers the separated substances (thus in the first place God).12 These three sciences will culminate, in a fixed form from Suarez to Kant (and beyond), in what will reign under the title of the system of metaphysics: the metaphysica treating (first of all as metaphysica generalis and then under the later title of ontologia) of ens in quantum ens (what is insofar as it is, being as being); the prima philosophia unfolding in a triple metaphysica specialis which includes (beside cosmologia rationalis and psychologia rationalis) what will then take the name of theologia rationalis.13 It is this discipline’s task to treat

12St. Thomas Aquinas, “Proœmium,” in In duodecim libros Metaphysicorum Aris-totelis Expositio. [English translation: “Prologue,” in Commentary on the Metaphysics of Aristotle, trans. John P. Rowan (Chicago: Henry Regnery Company, 1961), vol. 1, pp. 1-2.]

13On the contrary meanings of theology as metaphysica specialis in contrast with the theologia of Revelation, see our brief clarifications in “Théo-logique,” in André Jacob (ed.), Encyclopédie philosophique universelle, vol. 1, “L’Univers philosophique,” (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1989), pp. 17-25 and in Being Given: Toward a Phenomenology of Givenness (Stanford, CA.: Stanford University Press, 2002), pp. 71 ff., as well as Olivier Boulnois, Duns Scot: La rigueur de la charité (Paris: Éditions du Cerf, 1998), chapter 3. For a comprehensive history of the constitution of metaphys-chapter 3. For a comprehensive history of the constitution of metaphys-. For a comprehensive history of the constitution of metaphys-For a comprehensive history of the constitution of metaphys-ics in metaphysica generalis and metaphysica specialis (including theologia rationalis), see, in addition to On Descartes’s Metaphysical Prism: The Constitution and Limits of Onto-theo-logy in Cartesian Thought, trans. Jeffrey L. Kosky (Chicago and London: The University of Chicago Press, 1999), chapter 1, and “La science toujours recherchée et toujours manquante,” in La métaphysique. Son histoire, sa critique, ses enjeux, ed. Jean-Marc Narbonne and Luc Langlois (Paris: J. Vrin, 1999), pp. 13-36, the dossier of Jean-François Courtine, Suarez et le système de la métaphysique (Paris: Presses Uni-versitaires de France, 1990), on the basis of the works of Hans Reiner, “Die Enstehung und ursprüngliche Bedeutung des Namens ‘Metaphysik’,” Zeitschrift für philosophische Forschung 8 (1954), pp. 210-37 and Ernst Vollrath, “Die Gliederung der Metaphysik in eine Metaphysica generalis und eine Metaphysica specialis,” Zeitschrift für philoso-phische Forschung 16, no. 2 (April-June 1962), pp. 258-84, then in Die These der Meta-physik. Zur Gestalt der Metaphysik bei Aristoteles, Kant und Hegel (Wuppertal: Henn Verlag, 1969). — The Heideggerian background of this question has been treated in God Without Being: Hors-Texte, trans. Thomas A. Carlson, with a foreword by David Tracy (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1991), chapters 2 and 3.

Page 8: Marion, Jean-Luc - On the Foundation of the Distinction Between Theology and Philosophy

54 JEAN-LUC MARION

1 & 2 & 3 9

of God, whatever he may be, by means of pure reason, that is to say to eventually demonstrate his existence (by way of proofs) and to de-fine his essence (by defining his attributes). It is only in this frame-work that philosophy allows God to enter within its field, that is to say within the system of metaphysics. Without the erection of such a system, God, in particular the God of Revelation, would escape from philosophy—which does not signify that even with this system God as such becomes accessible to it. No one understood and emphasized this better than St. Thomas because he distinguishes as clearly as pos-sible the two meanings of theologia (“Sic ergo theologia sive scientia divina est duplex. – Thus, theology or divine science is twofold.”). On the one hand, the theology which philosophers developed (also called metaphysics) considers the divine things but uniquely as principles of their knowledge, and not as objects of this knowledge (“res divinæ non tamquam subjectum scientiæ, sed tamquam principia subjecti”). Rev-elation remains as the principle of their study without them being able, through pure reason, to reach it as the direct object of their study. On the other hand and by contrast, the divine things in themselves become a direct object of study only for the believing reason, which has access to it through faith in the Scriptures themselves as the direct object of understanding: “Alia vero [theologia], quæ ipsas res divinas considerat propter seipsas ut subjectum scientiæ, et hæc est theologia, quæ in sacra Sciptura traditur. – But of another sort is that theology which considers divine things on their own account as the very subject matter of its sci-ence. This is the theology taught in sacred Scriptures.”14 Thus must we distinguish and even oppose two theologies: the theologia philosophica indirectly connected to the revealed God (as the principle of its ob-ject), henceforth destined to be integrated as theologia rationalis in the system of metaphysics, against the theologia vero sacræ Scripturæ [true theology of sacred Scriptures], directly connected to the God of Rev-elation (as its object), henceforth maintaining its distance to the whole

14St. Thomas Aquinas, Expositio super librum Boethii De Trinitate q.5, a.4, resp. [English translation: The Trinity and The Unicity of the Intellect, trans. Sr. Rose Em-manuella Brennan, S.H.N. (St. Louis, MO: B. Herder Book Co., 1946), p. 164. Transla-tion modified.] See: “Theologia quæ ad sacram doctrinam pertinet differt secundum genus ab illa theologia quæ pars philosophiæ ponitur. – The theology of holy teaching differs in kind from that theology which is ranked as a part of philosophy.” (Summa theologiæ Ia, q.1, a.1, ad 2) [English translation: ibid., vol. 1]

Page 9: Marion, Jean-Luc - On the Foundation of the Distinction Between Theology and Philosophy

THE DISTINCTION BETWEEN PHILOSOPHY AND THEOLOGY 55

1 & 2 & 3 9

system of metaphysics. In this context, and in this context alone, can the two instances be distinguished from, be opposed to, and eventually confront one another. This was rapidly the case with the Protestant Reformation. This was not the case before the medieval restoration, first of all Thomist, of Christian thought (as non-theology) of the first centuries and of the Patristic period, which ignored the twofold nature of the two theologiæ that supposedly had the same interest at stake.

The question of the distinction between these two knowledges of God has a history. It is not eternal and is therefore not a matter of course.

Criteria for Distinguishing from the Point of View of Philosophy

We now reach the conceptual question: Which criteria are avail-able to us for distinguishing (thus eventually opposing) what are today named under the titles philosophy and theology? We will try to exam-ine them in assuming first of all the philosophical point of view, as it is only appropriate in a colloquium organized by a gathering of faculties of philosophy.

A first criterion results directly from the establishment of the sys-tem of metaphysics. Every science depends on the metaphysica gene-ralis, specifically ontologia, insofar as it treats of an object which, obvi-ously, must first of all be, of a being, of ens. This claim is also valid for each of the special metaphysics, hence first of all for the God of theo-logia rationalis; thus metaphysics examines God from the angle of his existence (and their proofs) and then his essence. But this is also valid for what the theologia sacræ Scripturæ [theology of sacred Scriptures] can claim to say of God in its own way. The events of the biblical nar-rative must be: they must be validated following the claims of the sci-ence of history, they must be attested in the texts following the rules of philology (the literal sense always being preeminent), etc…. The two theologies will therefore be subordinated to ontology, the difference being determined by the positivity, more or less accentuated, of the beings (des étants) concerned and, therefore, by the empirical charac-ter of ontic verifications. In fact, this differentiation by subordination, though stemming directly from the system of metaphysics, survives it and extends its effects in many ways. Without evoking the “positivity” of Revelation, following Schelling, one finds almost the same thing in

Page 10: Marion, Jean-Luc - On the Foundation of the Distinction Between Theology and Philosophy

56 JEAN-LUC MARION

1 & 2 & 3 9

Heidegger who, in 1928, still considered theology (non-philosophical as well as philosophical) as an “entirely ontic autonomous science” by virtue of its “positivity,” and, as such, as dependent on the analytic of Dasein, which, as fundamental ontology, assumes even more the pri-macy of ontologia.15 It can also be suggested that the whole enterprise of demythologization undertaken by Bultmann rests on the subordi-nation of theology, even and above all revealed theology, to a narrow determination of modern rationality (in fact as technique) established as an uncritical substitute for ontologia. Fundamentally, this hardly differs from the contemporary assumptions of Carnap, who assumed the logical critique of language as a quasi ontologia (curiously meant to undo what he imagined under the title of metaphysics). All these attempts, undertaken since then, to rectify theology in the name of the supposed authority of each of the now defunct “social sciences” (linguistics, psychoanalysis, sociology, literary theory, gender studies, etc…) are essentially limited to reproducing the same tactics, only with weaker and weaker substitutes and less and less critical substitutes of ontologia.

This criterion of distinction by subordination is exercised so of-ten and so much that one is not able to contest its power. It remains that this power rests on a serious and, therefore, fragile presupposition: the distinction between the ontological and ontical sciences obviously supposes an incontestable ontologia or at least a credible avatar of ens in quantum ens [being as being, what is insofar as it is]. Thenceforth, one can seriously doubt that a philosophy in a position to claim for itself the status of an ontology, of a universal science of being (l’étant), can be found today. Certainly, we do not lack claims for mastering or restoring ontology—in particular within the analytical and neo-Thomistic traditions—but without them being able to redefine being (l’étant) (supposing that one can surpass its irreducible undefinability in metaphysics from Duns Scotus to Hegel), without them also being

15Martin Heidegger, “Phenomenology and Theology,” trans. James G. Hart and John C. Maraldo, in Pathmarks, ed. William McNeill (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1998), pp. 50-4. A text which Heidegger refers very logically back to Being and Time, which includes theology among biology, sociology, etc… within the sciences of phenomena which phenomenology itself dominates and constitutes (ibid., p. 39). See Martin Heidegger, Being and Time: A Translation of Sein und Zeit, trans. Joan Stambaugh (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1996), §7, pp. 24-5.

Page 11: Marion, Jean-Luc - On the Foundation of the Distinction Between Theology and Philosophy

THE DISTINCTION BETWEEN PHILOSOPHY AND THEOLOGY 57

1 & 2 & 3 9

able to resolve the contradiction of its final equivalence with a cogi-tabile [what-can-be-thought], or even mastering the primacy of the concept in the conceptus entis. If Heidegger himself had to renounce his project of maintaining ontology even under the figure of a Funda-mentalontologie, if he ended up not only abandoning all use of the term metaphysica precisely in order “to think to be (l’être) without what is (l’étant), which signifies thinking to be (l’être) without consideration of all metaphysics,”16 if he had, in a sense, even turned his back on being (l’être) in favor of Ereignis in which “it disappears,”17 which phi-losopher today can still, while thinking what he said, make a claim for ontology in order to subordinate to it the theology of Revelation or even a philosophical theology, if there is still one? Otherwise pos-ited, an ontology (and therefore its primacy over any ontic science) has no meaning except in a metaphysical regime: what happens to it in a regime characterized by the “end of metaphysics”? If our thought finds itself henceforth in a non-metaphysical situation, can and must it make a claim for an ontological criterion in order to distinguish phi-losophy from a theology of Revelation?

But there is also another argument that can be opposed to this dis-tinction characterized by the contrast between the ontological and the ontical: it is not obvious that the theologia sive sacra Scriptura remains a purely and simply ontical science, under the pretext that it concerns only events of historical positivity. First of all because the phenom-enology of the event that contemporary thought has only begun to consider seriously—whereas metaphysics had obscured it under the cover of an ontology of the object—leads without a doubt beyond (or at least elsewhere and beside) what is (l’étant) considered in its con-cept. The event is indeed not limited to render an essence first of all conceived and then effectuated in existence, but accomplishes in ef-

16“To think Being without beings means: to think Being without regard to meta-physics.” in Martin Heidegger, On Time and Being, trans. with an introduction by Joan Stambaugh (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 2002), p. 24. [Translator’s note: In this and the following footnote, the author translates from the original German, which he provides in the footnote: “Sein ohne das Seiende denken, heißt: Sein ohne Rücksicht auf die Metaphysik denken.” As with the previous footnotes, we have trans-” As with the previous footnotes, we have trans-lated from the author’s own French translation and cite here a published English trans-lation for those who wish to consult the text in full.]

17“Being vanishes in Appropriation.” (ibid., p. 22) [“Sein verschwindet im Ereignis.”]

Page 12: Marion, Jean-Luc - On the Foundation of the Distinction Between Theology and Philosophy

58 JEAN-LUC MARION

1 & 2 & 3 9

fectivity what no essence has allowed to fore-see (pré-voir), such that the event imposes against the conceivable (metaphysical) possibility an inconceivable impossibility, at least before the arrival of what-is-to-come (l’avènement de l’advenant). It thus opens the site of new pos-sibilities inasmuch as and even while it remains inconceivable and thus metaphysically impossible. In fact, each event redefines what is pos-sible for what is in its being (les possibles de l’étant en son être), and, in this sense, exercises a more inaugural rather than ontical function, indeed a more inaugural rather than tangentially ontological function. It follows that the more a phenomenon is accomplished according to the mode of appearing of the event, the more it corrects and crit-icizes the metaphysical mode of being (être) in itself and for the beings (les étants) which it renders possible by its very effective impossibil-ity. Now the biblical Revelation deals precisely with these impossible events which nevertheless attest by their effectivity that “nothing is impossible to God (Gn. 18: 14 = Lk. 1: 37).” In particular, the events of the creation of the world and the resurrection of the flesh contra-dict at the same time possibility as non-contradictory conceivability for a finite mind (in the metaphysical sense) and the identity of what is (l’étant) to itself (according to the principle of non-contradiction), that is to say that these events contest ontology and its definition of what is (l’étant) as such. Even better, creation and resurrection consist precisely in not respecting the laws of ontologia, because they allow that which is not to be, thus that which is not to be identical to itself, and that an existence contradict an essence or that an essence contradict itself— because as a matter of fact and as a fact—each time God “calls those who are not (les non-étants) as if they were (des étants), καλοῦντος τὰ μὴ ὄντα ὡς ὄντα (Rom. 4: 17).”18 In this sense, the events par excel-lence accomplished by creation and resurrection take on an ontologi-cal status, or rather a meta-ontological one in that they contradict the laws of ontologia for themselves and for all other beings (étants) as well (creation and resurrection being brought to bear by definition on be-ing [l’étant] in its totality). Indeed, once the indifference of God to

18It could even be translated “calls non-beings as beings” (appelle les non-étants en tant qu’étants), echoing “being as being” (l’étant en tant qu’étant). See our read-See our read-ing concerning the theoretical bearing of this text in God Without Being: Hors-Texte, trans. Thomas A. Carlson, with a foreword by David Tracy (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1991), pp. 86-9, 93, and 127.

Page 13: Marion, Jean-Luc - On the Foundation of the Distinction Between Theology and Philosophy

THE DISTINCTION BETWEEN PHILOSOPHY AND THEOLOGY 59

1 & 2 & 3 9

the human (and therefore metaphysical) delimitation of the possible and the impossible is attested, therefore the indifference of God to the rules of ontologia, all that is (the world) finds itself reinterpreted on the basis of what gives it being or which allows it to be (donne d’être), even against the this-worldly determinations of the being of beings (l’être de l’étant), since it receives being (reçoit d’être) on the basis of an in-stance which surpasses all merely ontological determinations of what is (l’étant). Created or re-created, what is (l’étant) comes from, above all, the gift of God and no longer only from the laws which the thought of ontologia assigns to being (l’être). With this inversion of the relation between ontologia and the possible, the distinction between the theol-ogy of Revelation and the philosophy of metaphysics is inverted, and, henceforth the first determines the second.

In rendering invalid the ontological criteria of the distinction be-tween what we today call philosophy and theology, we have already put in question another criterion, that of the difference between the possible and the impossible (and thus between what can be experi-enced and what cannot be experienced). Whether it is a question of the distinction between the potentia ordinata [ordered power] and the potentia extraordinaria [extraordinary power] of God, between the “laws of order” and the “miracles,” or between sensible intuition and intellectual intuition, this division always supposes that one could de-termine a priori the limits of rationality. And this in turn supposes the finitude of this rationality established as a condition of possibility (and of impossibility). Through an exactly Copernican reversal, finitude, as a fact of reason, ends up determining (for Kant) the infinite (and not the other way around as for Descartes), such that it renders the infinite impossible for us, that is to say in principle absolutely. That finitude may define the limits of the possible and the impossible supposes that it would be qualified to fix the conditions of possibility of beings (des étants), in fact of beings (des étants) conceived as its objects—other-wise put, that finitude assumes a transcendental a priori function. If finitude does not have a transcendental status, no longer will it have the right to fix (of course a priori) the limits between the possible and the impossible. Therefore, this limit can differentiate what we today call philosophy and theology only by maintaining philosophy itself in a transcendental situation, that is to say in assuming a transcenden-tal ego and an equally transcendental idealism. This position can be

Page 14: Marion, Jean-Luc - On the Foundation of the Distinction Between Theology and Philosophy

60 JEAN-LUC MARION

1 & 2 & 3 9

held. Husserl at least held it just as Heidegger himself prolonged it in a way in Being and Time. But which other philosophy, including and above all among those that today most noisily refuse the theoretical legitimacy of theology, can and would still like to pay the price of a dis-tinction founded on the transcendental function of finite subjectivity? Not only does the distinction between the possible and the impossible find itself de jure refused by the theology of Revelation, according to the principle that “to God nothing is impossible,”19 but it could be that philosophy itself could in fact no longer guarantee the use of this dis-tinction, once no subjectivity can no longer assure the transcendental function.

The “end of metaphysics” is neither a slogan nor an optional hy-pothesis, for it in fact forbids us to support theses which were assured only by the arguments of metaphysics: without ontologia and the tran-scendental status of the ego, what we understand today by philosophy can no longer be distinguished from what philosophy understands to be theology, following the distinction between the ontological and the ontical, as well as the distinction between the possible and the impos-sible.

Criteria for Distinguishing from the Point of View of Theology

If, therefore, philosophy can no longer today formulate from its own point of view its difference with what it calls theology, it remains for us to ask theology itself if it can, from its own point of view, formu-late this difference.

Indeed it would seem that one could privilege the opposition per-fectly formulated by Duns Scotus, in the name of many other theolo-gians (medieval as well as modern ones): “In this question we are faced with the controversy between the philosophers and theologians. The philosophers insist on the perfection of nature and deny supernatural perfection. The theologians, on the other hand, recognize the defi-ciency of nature and the need of grace and supernatural perfection.”20

19See a more detailed argument in Jean-Luc Marion, “The Impossible for Man—God,” in Transcendence and Beyond: A Postmodern Inquiry, ed. John D. Caputo and Michael J. Scanlon (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2007), pp. 17-43.

20John Duns Scotus, “Prologue,” in Ordinatio, paragraph no. 5. [English transla-tion: “Duns Scotus on the Necessity of Revealed Knowledge (Prologue of the Ordinatio

Page 15: Marion, Jean-Luc - On the Foundation of the Distinction Between Theology and Philosophy

THE DISTINCTION BETWEEN PHILOSOPHY AND THEOLOGY 61

1 & 2 & 3 9

Against the letter of meta-physics (understood as transphysica), but according to its concept, philosophy, constituted as a system of meta-physics, would therefore treat of every being (l’ étant) inasmuch as it admits of a nature, leaving to theology the consideration, if there would be one, of what does not have a nature or which surpasses it. This distinction can seem relatively clear if one confines oneself to the problem which, for the most part, has given rise to it: the opposition between the natural beatitude of man (that of the wise man through contemplation exemplified in Book X of the Nicomachean Ethics) and beatitude by divinization or the vision of God, obviously beyond the natural powers of man. This nevertheless soon becomes problematic once we explicitate the principle that underlies it: that nature does nothing in vain, that nothing can desire what it cannot reach through its own strength. This thesis (of an Aristotelian origin) is perhaps val-id for the things of the world, at least for those for which a quiddita-tive definition remains conceivable or possible following a restrictive καθ᾽ αὑτό; but it becomes problematic for the things (beings [étants], or more radically creatures) whose quidditative definition remains in-conceivable because it does not remain radically by itself nor in itself. But such is the case par excellence for man who, created in the image of God, bears his image and likeness up to and including the incom-prehensibility proper to God. Man, in order to remain himself, must remain undefinable, because he carries in himself, for his essence, the image of the undefinable God.21 The impossibility and illegitimacy of defining human nature allows, in the case of his desire for beatitude or desire to see God, for a natural desire of a supernatural good; it even demands this as a consequence of the paradox that man’s nature is to surpass his own nature by virtue of the substitution in him of the least essence with the image of God that renders this essence useless and that replaces it. St. Thomas Aquinas has perfectly formulated this par-adox: “Nobilioris conditionis est natura quæ potest consequi perfectum bonum, licet indigeat exteriori auxilio ad hoc consequendum, quam na-tura quæ non potest consequi perfectum bonum, sed consequitur quod-

of John Duns Scotus),” trans. Allan Wolter, O.F.M., Franciscan Studies 11, nos. 3-4 (1951), pp. 231-72.]

21On the incomprehensibility of man, defined by the very absence of definition, see our essay “Mihi magna quæstio factus sum: The Privilege of Unknowing,” The Jour-nal of Religion 85 (January 2005), pp. 1-24.

Page 16: Marion, Jean-Luc - On the Foundation of the Distinction Between Theology and Philosophy

62 JEAN-LUC MARION

1 & 2 & 3 9

dam bonum imperfectum, licet ad consecutionem ejus non indigeat ex-teriori auxilio. – A nature which can attain the perfect good, although it needs outside help, is of a higher condition than a nature which can attain without such recourse only a lesser good.”22 The distinction be-tween nature and the supernatural has at least one exception: that of the nature (immediately supernatural) of man himself. The decision of Cajetan concerning the supernatural (and no longer natural) character of the desire for God (henceforth reduced to a so called “obediential power”) will later on define the terms of the debate de auxiliis, a quar-rel with neither issue nor legitimacy because it maintains, without in-terrogating it, a distinction which is perhaps valid for each thing, but precisely not for the first thing which theology (which at this moment bears its name well) must take into consideration. Moreover, even if this distinction has governed theology for a long time, from the Refor-mation and the seventeenth century, Scholasticism or dogmatics was no longer but one of the three theologies in opposition to positive the-ology and to mystical (or spiritual) theology. And it seems clear today that the renewal of Christian theology (in particular of Catholic theol-ogy) owes its essential results to these two latter theologies, the first one (positive theology) remaining creative only through a return—cease-lessly renewed and threatened outside the various neo-Thomisms—to St. Thomas who, in retrospect, appears to be in the direct line of the Fathers, particularly of St. Augustine.

Theology cannot remain what it must be, a comprehension of the world as creation and of man as image of God on the basis of the Rev-elation of God in Jesus Christ, except by developing a discourse where nature is precisely never found to be separated from the supernatural, because the gift of grace precedes everything: being (l’être), essences,

22St. Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiæ IaIIæ, q.5, a.5, ad 2. [English transla-tion: Summa Theologiæ, vol. 16, Purpose and Happiness (IaIIæ. 1-5), ed. Thomas Gilby, O.P. (Cambridge, UK: Blackfriars, 1969)] On this doctrine see the works of Henri de Lubac, S.J., The Mystery of the Supernatural, trans. Rosemary Sheed, introduction by David L. Schindler (New York: The Crossroad Publishing Company, 1998) and Au-gustinianism and Modern Theology, trans. Lancelot Sheppard, introduction by Louis Dupré (New York: The Crossroad Publishing Company, 2000). On the intrinsic link of this doctrine with metaphysics beginning from Suarez and Descartes, see our study “What is the Ego Capable of? Divinization and Domination: Capable / Capax,” in Car-tesian Questions: Method and Metaphysics, foreword by Daniel Garber (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1999), pp. 67-95.

Page 17: Marion, Jean-Luc - On the Foundation of the Distinction Between Theology and Philosophy

THE DISTINCTION BETWEEN PHILOSOPHY AND THEOLOGY 63

1 & 2 & 3 9

nature, freedom, etc…, all of which precisely constitute immediately the gifts of grace, before being defined by themselves as autonomous natures in the pure state of nature [in puris naturalibus]. In the theol-ogy of Revelation, nature [natura] is revealed as always already na-tured [naturata] and never “pure,” and natured by a naturing nature [natura naturans] which is itself originarily super-natural.23 Not only can theology not be opposed to philosophy as the knowledge of the supernatural confronting the knowledge of nature and of the natural (because what we today call philosophy and theology can no longer define, neither one nor the other, a precise concept of nature, thus, by opposition, of the supernatural) but this dichotomy would take away from theology itself all its seriousness and its specificity.

A remark imposes itself here. As a matter of fact, contemporary philosophy is not only characterized by its critique of the different meanings of the supernatural (rejected under the title of the “world be-hind” [Hinterwelt] since Nietzsche) but also and coherently by its aban-donment of the concept of nature—abandonment or rather powerless-ness to define it since, henceforth, the ontico-ontological foundation of metaphysica generalis has also (and first of all) been wrecked to the advantage of the entirely imprecise univocity of objectivity. Strangely, only a handful of theologians maintain, with no further arguments, the concept of nature, sometimes only to allow for the survival of the supernatural. This powerlessness as such is no serious damage be-cause it is precisely not the role of theology to define or re-define an intrinsically philosophical concept. But this excusable powerlessness dissimulates the tasks proper to the theology of Revelation, tasks that philosophy as such can never and will never be able to accomplish.

The Shared Indeterminacy

Let us summarize the provisional negative result that we have ar-rived at in these analyses. Firstly, the distinction between theology and philosophy has nothing original about it, but arises from a late histori-

23It must not be forgotten that Spinoza takes up the formulations natura naturans/natura naturata (Ethics, I, proposition 29) of St. Thomas Aquinas (in Summa the-ologiæ IaIIæ, q.85, a.6, resp., among others), who himself follows John Scotus Erigena. [English translation: Summa Theologiæ, vol. 26, Original Sin (IaIIæ. 81-85), ed. T. C. O’Brien, O.P. (Cambridge, UK: Blackfriars, 1965)]

Page 18: Marion, Jean-Luc - On the Foundation of the Distinction Between Theology and Philosophy

64 JEAN-LUC MARION

1 & 2 & 3 9

cal conjuncture, without any necessity in principle as confirmed, on the one hand, by their marginal role (if not their absence) in the first twelve centuries of Christian thought and, on the other hand, by the difficult complexity of mutually putting them in place from the thir-teenth century onwards. Secondly, philosophy cannot be conceptually distinguished from what is now named theology except by assuming the fundamental decisions of the system of metaphysics (ontologia as metaphysica generalis, theologia as simply one of the metaphysicæ spe-ciales, determination of the possible and the impossible on the basis of the finitude of the ego henceforth understood to be transcendental). Thirdly, the clearest attempt of modern theology to delimit its own territory while admitting the metaphysical turn of philosophy, indeed the distinction between nature and the supernatural (from Cajetan to transcendental Thomism), dangerously compromises the naturally su-pernatural character of the nature of man, exactly as metaphysics mis-understood in principle the originally created, that is to say, the origi-nally given character of what it restrictively called ontologia. Fourthly, what is today called philosophy can no longer (and, as a matter of fact, no longer claims to) assume the decisions of metaphysics and thus can no longer conceptually justify its right to exclude from the field of ra-tionality what it calls theology. Reciprocally, what is today named the-ology no longer in fact invokes the distinction between nature and the supernatural in order to define its specificity with regard to philoso-phy, but precisely proceeds following other criteria that are in fact em-pirical and historical, and that are minimally connected (if at all) to the contemporary state of philosophy. From all this follows a provisional result: the debates concerning the relationship of the disciplines of the-ology and philosophy, and therefore, consequently, the conflict of their respective faculties, and finally on the equilibrium (or the contradic-tion) between what is commonly called the freedom of inquiry, etc… and what is commonly called the fidelity to the deposit of the faith, to the Magisterium, in other words concerning all these silent tensions that, for more than two centuries, have not ceased to compromise the work of the indivisible Christian thought in all its disciplines—these debates no longer have any conceptual justification. They certainly still trouble contemporary research, but on the basis of an opposition which has disappeared, for want of combatants who are really armed, since the period when the “end of metaphysics” began. It is now only a

Page 19: Marion, Jean-Luc - On the Foundation of the Distinction Between Theology and Philosophy

THE DISTINCTION BETWEEN PHILOSOPHY AND THEOLOGY 65

1 & 2 & 3 9

question of the dark light of already extinguished stars.We find a remarkable indicator of this common indecisive inde-

terminacy in the renunciation by what is today called theology and philosophy of their claims to the status of sciences. Philosophy, im-mediately confronted with the paradigmatic scientificity of mathemat-ics (Plato) has not ceased, in spite of strong reservations (Aristotle, the new Academy, Thomas Aquinas, etc…), building a system with the sciences within metaphysica, and then equaling them and sur-passing their certitude (Descartes), or even defining itself directly as a Wissenschaft (Hegel), a Wissenschaftlehre (Fichte, Bolzano), until a banal Erkenntnistheorie (of the various neo-Kantian philosophies), and finally a “rigorous science” (Philosophie als strenge Wissenschaft, Husserl). The obsessional prestige of the paradigm of science has gone so far that Carnap and the Vienna Circle could only conceive of the so called overcoming of metaphysics by a recourse to a “science,” be it only approximative of the analysis of language (“Überwindung der Metaphysik durch logische Analyse der Sprache”). But the conditions to justify this scientificity always end up, consciously or implicitly, re-quiring nothing less than a transcendental posture, thus by recogniz-ing an a priori which is itself essentially finite. No figure of contempo-rary philosophy today can still assume this transcendental posture, at least in the sense that metaphysics had never hesitated to make a claim for it.

Now it happens that what we today call theology did not impose itself as theologia of Revelation except through a certain resistance and mimetism—at the same time towards philosophia and what was to be-come its theologia rationalis—in claiming for itself, too, the title of sci-ence (obviously rigorous), thus accomplishing what a great historian has qualified as “the most sensational episode of the entry of Aristotle in Christendom.”24 This claim did not take for its paradigm the cer-titude and the evidence of mathematics but, being regulated by the decisions of Aristotle, took for its paradigm the model of logical for-mality and the hierarchization of the sciences. To the recurring ques-tion “How can we establish the scientific character of the Christian

24On this once so crucial question, we are following Marie-Dominique Chenu, O.P., La théologie comme science au XIIIe siècle, 3rd ed., rev. and enl. (Paris: J. Vrin, 1969), p. 13. It can evidently be understood in two opposing senses.

Page 20: Marion, Jean-Luc - On the Foundation of the Distinction Between Theology and Philosophy

66 JEAN-LUC MARION

1 & 2 & 3 9

faith whose materials (Revelation, Scriptures in the tradition, etc…) are not immediately given in the experience of the world but indirect-ly through faith?,” St. Thomas proposes to answer by the subalterna-tion of the sciences or, more exactly, by a “quasi-subalternation”25: in the same way that mathematics establishes its truths as principles for physics (geometry for perspective or astronomy, arithmetic for mu-sic, etc…), likewise, because the habitus fidei is almost [quasi] like a habitus of principles, theologia draws its principles from faith (which receives the Revelation, Scriptures in the tradition, etc…) by a quasi-subalternation and therefore formally fulfills the criteria of scientifici-ty.26 The development of contemporary theology, in the renewal of Thomistic studies and the reappropriation of the Fathers, as well as in the various dialectical, kerygmatic, aesthetic, dramatic theologies (and even the theological theology in the sense of the last part of the triptych of Hans Urs von Balthasar) unfolds entirely—at least one can reasonably argue so—on the basis of surpassing the ambition of sub-jecting the Christian thought of the Revelation to the paradigm of a science, whatever this paradigm may be, whatever this science may be. And this for an essential reason: contemporary rationality, dominated by the “end of metaphysics,” no longer has a univocal concept of science at its disposal, even and above all in the most fundamental scientific disciplines. The crisis of foundation, which characterizes the progress of physics in quantum physics, has even been made possible by the

25Ibid., pp. 82-3.26“habitus fidei, qui est quasi habitus principiorum” (Scriptum super libros Senten-

tiarum Magistri Petri Lombardi Episcopi Parisiensis I, Prologus, q.1, a.3, sol.2, ad 3); or “ipsa, quæ fide tenemus, sint nobis quasi principia in hac scientia. – those truths that we hold in the first place by faith are for us, as it were, first principles in this science.” (Expositio super librum Boethii De Trinitate I, q.2, a.2, resp.) [English translation: ibid., p. 53] See: “Et hoc modo sacra doctrina est scientia, quia procedit ex principiis notis lumine superioris scientiæ, quæ scilicet est scientia Dei et beatorum. – In this second manner is Christian theology a science, for it flows from founts recognized in the light of a higher science, namely God’s very own which he shares with the blessed.” (Summa theologiæ Ia, q.1, a.2, resp.) [English translation: ibid., vol. 1] — Let us emphasize that, in principle, it is not a matter of a strict subalternation between two sciences, because the science of God and the saints does not itself constitute a science in the Aristotelian sense; it is only a question of the givenness (or availability) of principles which are themselves non-scientific; it is therefore, at best, a question of a quasi-subalternation. Marie-Dominique Chenu, O.P. underlines this very honestly, despite his uncritical en-thusiasm.

Page 21: Marion, Jean-Luc - On the Foundation of the Distinction Between Theology and Philosophy

THE DISTINCTION BETWEEN PHILOSOPHY AND THEOLOGY 67

1 & 2 & 3 9

renunciation of any unification of knowledge on the basis of univo-cal principles which are compatible among themselves. It is appropri-ate that what we call theology today accepts this state of affairs and, consequently, definitively gives up seeking, in the latest philosophical fashion or the latest fashion in the “social sciences,” an ultimate and illusory paradigm (supposedly scientific) to which it must conform at any price (even at the price of losing the least access to the Revelation).

And yet the attempt of St. Thomas Aquinas to confer a scientific status to theology offers the more attentive reader an indication that could perhaps break through this aporia. Indeed the principles that the habitus fidei can assign to the sacra doctrina as scientific theol-ogy comes to it from the (quasi) scientia superior which comes from and is dispensed by God and the saints (“quæ scilicet est scientia Dei et beatorum”).27 It is here a question of principles, if you wish, but of principles given in the knowledge of experience, given in a non-imme-diate empirical way (which is not universally available, which is not an a priori but an enigmatic a posteriori), and yet effectively given. The event—for it is indeed an event—of the Revelation, in giving this abso-lutely unforeseeable experience, which in a sense is absolutely impos-sible according to the criteria of metaphysical scientificity (because it is without horizon, without transcendental ego, without repetition, with-out predictability, without a quidditative definition, therefore without being an object), paradoxically opens a space of new knowledge, a field of phenomena which would have otherwise remained invisible. And thus it gives the possibility (metaphysically impossible) of a compre-hension, that is to say it offers an extension of the field of rationality. As always, the extension of the field of the struggle liberates theory, even theological theory. The only question for a theology aware of its origin and thus of its originality will then be to understand how the new given of Revelation can unfold in a rationality that corresponds to it. And this extension of the given also constitutes—for every philoso-phy that wants to overcome, one day if it can ever do so, the “end of metaphysics”—the most serious challenge, but also the only one which can save it. And in this way we can have a glimpse of how “only a god could still save us.”

27St. Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiæ Ia, q.1, a.2, resp. [English translation: ibid., vol. 1]

Page 22: Marion, Jean-Luc - On the Foundation of the Distinction Between Theology and Philosophy

68 JEAN-LUC MARION

1 & 2 & 3 9

To Know in order to Love, to Love in order to Know

The criterion, which remains between what we today call philoso-phy and theology, does not depend or, more exactly, no longer depends on the delimitations imposed by metaphysics on the field of the con-ceivable (and thus of what can be experienced); it depends instead on a separation that, at God’s initiative, Revelation introduces there: the distinction concerns the revealed and the non-revealed, the kerygma received and the wisdom (or knowledge) constructed: “The λόγος of God is alive, effective, and more cutting (τομώτερος) than a two-edged sword; it penetrates until the very division of the soul and the spirit, between the joints and the marrow, discerning the intentions and the thoughts of the heart (κριτικὸς ἐνθυμήσεων καὶ ἐννοιῶν καρδίας) (Heb. 4: 12).” Literally the Word, thus reason, introduces a division, estab-lishing a critical criterion for distinguishing among the thoughts and conceptions of men those which come from God. Inevitably, one can raise an objection to this criterion literally fallen from heaven: it al-ready supposes the fact of Revelation (otherwise said, it implies that the tradition transmitted by the biblical texts is trustworthy). Thus it has meaning only for believers, supposing that the difficulty is resolved even before examining it—theology is distinguished from philosophy if one immediately admits the fact that a given, specific to the theol-ogy of Revelation, can be found. But it is precisely a question of what this criterion implies: it depends on each thinker to decide on what he admits as being given to him, thus, of deciding for himself in the face of the critical word (λόγος κριτικὸς), in deciding whether he adds a given to the field of the conceivable and of what can be experienced or not. Theology begins when thought considers the revealed given as a phenomenal given, in principle equal to all other givens, in deciding to satisfy the particular epistemological procedures that it nevertheless claims for its reception.

These conditions can be formulated in various ways but they al-ways come back to the same reversal on the basis of the interpreta-tion of Isaiah 7: 9 (according to the Vetus latina) that St. Augustine never stopped meditating on: “Nisi credideritis non intelligetis – Un-less you believe, you will not understand.” To understand the revealed given as an equally rationalizable given (thus in order to integrate it to

Page 23: Marion, Jean-Luc - On the Foundation of the Distinction Between Theology and Philosophy

THE DISTINCTION BETWEEN PHILOSOPHY AND THEOLOGY 69

1 & 2 & 3 9

a univocal and universal rationality), it is necessary (contrary to the procedures common to the other fields of knowledge) to begin by be-lieving—accepting, validating, assuming—it as given. In a sense the quasi-subalternation of theologia to the scientia beatorum [science of the blessed] is inscribed, in St. Thomas, in this line of thought. More-over, this is also the case among certain of his predecessors when they reverse the conjunction between reason and belief: “On the side of Ar-istotle, the argument is that reason, knowing one doubtful thing, pro-duces belief, but from the side of Christ, the argument is that it is belief that produces reason.”28 It was Pascal who fully clarified the originary radicality of this reversal in retrieving a formula of St. Augustine (“Non intratur in veritatem nisi per charitatem. – One does not enter into the truth except through charity.”)29 and in commenting on this perfectly: “Hence when speaking of things human, we say that we should know them before loving them—a saying which has become proverbial. Yet

28“Propter hoc bene dictum est a quodam, quoniam apud Aristotelem argumentum est ratio rei dubie faciens fidem; apud Christum autem argumentum est fides faciens rationem.” (Guillaume d’Auxerre, Summa aurea. Prologus, ed. Philippe Pigouchet, fol. 2 ra), cited by Marie-Dominique Chenu, O.P. (ibid., p. 35), who identifies Simon de Tournai as the originator of this formula: “Doctrina Aristotelis est de his de quibus ratio facit fidem, sed Christi doctrina de his quorum fides facit rationem.” in Expositio in Sym-bolum Quicumque, ms. Paris, Nat. lat. 14886, fol. 73a. See also Gilbert de la Porrée, In librum (Boethii) de prædicatione trium personarum, PL 64, pp. 1303-4: “In cæteris fac-ultatibus… non ratio fidem, sed fides prævenit rationem. In his enim non cognoscentes credimus, sed credentes cognoscimus.”

29St. Augustine, Contra Faustum XXXII.18, PL 42, p. 507. One must not omit (as Heidegger does, Being and Time, §29, pp. 131 and 403-4) the conclusion: “Probamus etiam ipsum [sc. Spiritum sanctum] inducere in omnem veritatem: quia non intratur in veritatem nisi per charitatem; charitas autem Dei, diffusa est, ait Apostolus, in cordibus nostris per Spiritum sanctum qui datus est nobis (Rom. v, 5). – We also prove that he [the Holy Spirit] leads us into all truth because one does not enter into truth except through love. But the love of God has been poured out in our hearts, the apostle says, by the Holy Spirit, who has been given to us (Rom. 5: 5).” [English translation: Answer to Faustus, a Manichean (Contra Faustum Manichæum), trans. with an introduction and notes by Roland Teske, S.J. (New York: New City Press, 2007), p. 420.] The epistemo-logical reversal consists well in recognizing the revealed given as a given on the basis of what the Holy Spirit gives to be loved (ce que le Saint Esprit donne d’ aimer); one can therefore not make it a part of an analytic of Dasein supposedly “methodologically atheistic”—otherwise, it would be necessary to acknowledge that this analytic destroys ontologia only with the tools of Revelation itself, without the most powerful conceiv-able deconstruction of the system of metaphysics (as proven negatively by the recent attempts of Jean-Luc Nancy and, to a lesser degree, Jacques Derrida).

Page 24: Marion, Jean-Luc - On the Foundation of the Distinction Between Theology and Philosophy

70 JEAN-LUC MARION

1 & 2 & 3 9

the saints, on the contrary, when speaking of things divine, say that we should love them in order to know them, and that we enter into truth only through love. Of this they have made one of their most useful maxims.”30 Pascal even makes of this a universal epistemological rule: “Truth is so obscured nowadays and lies so well established that unless we love the truth we shall never recognize it.”31 And thus, to claim to know God such as he reveals himself without loving him amounts to not knowing his truth and not even seeing it: “What a long way it is be-tween knowing God and loving him!”32 Reciprocally, if love dominates among the three theological virtues (1 Cor. 13: 13), and if truth is not discovered here at the last instance except through love, then we can obviously sustain the paradox that “the greatest of the Christian vir-tues… is the love of truth.”33 These formulations, which are systemati-cally related, correspond directly to those of St. Augustine: “Volo eam [sc. veritatem] facere in corde meo coram te in confessione. – I want to do the truth in my heart before your face in a confession (Confessiones X.1.1.14.140).”33 bis This same epistemological role of love towards truth can also be described negatively, following the thread of hatred which resists the repercussion, all the more accusatory, of truth: “… for it [self-love] conceives a deadly hatred for the truth which rebukes it and convinces it of its faults. It would like to do away with this truth, and not being able to destroy it as such, it destroys it, as best it can, in the consciousness of itself and others; that is, it takes every care to hide its faults both from itself and others, and cannot bear to have them pointed

30See Blaise Pascal, “The Art of Persuasion,” in Great Shorter Works of Pascal, trans. with an introduction by Emile Cailliet and John C. Blankenagel (Westport: Green-wood Press, 1974), p. 203. We have commented on this thesis in On Descartes’s Meta-physical Prism: The Constitution and Limits of Onto-theo-logy in Cartesian Thought, trans. Jeffrey L. Kosky (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1999), §25, pp. 333-45. – Heidegger, who cites this sentence “ibidem,” refers this erroneously to the Pensées, a confusion owing to the imprecise usage of the Léon Brunschvicg edition of Pensées et Opuscules (Paris: Hachette, 1912), p. 169 (see footnote 4 of Being and Time, §1, pp. 2 and 399).

31Blaise Pascal, Pensées, trans. with an introduction by Alban J. Krailsheimer, rev. ed. (London: Penguin Books, 1995), §739, p. 229.

32Ibid., §377, p. 110.33Idem, “Fragment d’une XIXe Provinciale,” in Œuvres complètes, ed. Louis Lafuma

(Paris: Éditions du Seuil, 1963), p. 469. 33 bisSt. Augustine, Confessions, trans. with an introduction and notes by Henry

Chadwick (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991), p. 179. [translation modified]

Page 25: Marion, Jean-Luc - On the Foundation of the Distinction Between Theology and Philosophy

THE DISTINCTION BETWEEN PHILOSOPHY AND THEOLOGY 71

1 & 2 & 3 9

out or noticed.… For is it not true that we hate the truth and those who tell it to us, and we like them to be deceived to our advantage…? … [T]elling the truth is useful to the hearer but harmful to those who tell it, because they incur such odium.”34 Evidently, this is a literal com-mentary of Confessions X.23.34 which successively treats of the veritas redarguens [the truth which challenges], the nolunt convinci quod falsi sint [they do not wish to be persuaded that they are mistaken], the oderunt eam [they hate the truth], and the initial citation of veritas parit odium [truth engenders hatred].34 bis Otherwise put, for Pascal as for Augustine, “truth apart from charity is not God, but his image and an idol that we must not love or worship. Still less must we worship its opposite, which is falsehood.”35

The field of what can henceforth be legitimately named theology is therefore defined thus: Revelation offers a given comparable to every other given of every other science. But the procedures of access to this given call for a different epistemology: here the given has noth-ing immediate about it because it is necessary to believe it in order to receive it and to eventually reach a partial and always provisional comprehension of it. In fact, to believe here means much more than

34Blaise Pascal, “Self-love,” in Pensées, §978, pp. 324-6. [Translator’s note: empha-ses by the author] See together with: “There is a lot of difference between not being for Christ and saying so, and not being for Christ and pretending to be. The former can perform miracles, but not the latter, for it is clear in the case of the former that they are against the truth but not in that of the others, and so the miracles are clearer.” (ibid., §843, p. 265)

34 bis St. Augustine, Confessions, pp. 199-200.35Blaise Pascal, Pensées, §926, p. 295. – At the same time, the text containing “Con-

tradictions have always been left to blind the wicked, for anything offensive to truth and charity is wrong. That is the true principle.” (ibid., §962, p. 316) is almost a literal commentary of a series of Augustinian sentences: “Initium operum bonorum, confessio est operum malorum. Facis veritatem, et venis ad lucem. Quid est, Facis veritatem?… Venis autem ad lucem ut manifestentur opera tua, quia in Deo sunt facta; quia et hoc ipsum quod tibi displicuit peccatum tuum, non tibi displiceret, nisi Deus tibi luceret, et ejus veritas tibi ostenderet.” (In Joannis evangelium XII.13, PL 35, p. 1491) – The begin-ning of good works is the confession of evil works. You do the truth and you come to the light. What does it mean, you do truth?… But you come to the light that your works may be made manifest, because they have been done in God, because also this very thing which displeases you, your sin, would not displease you unless God were shedding his light upon you and his truth showing it to you.” [English translation: Tractates on the Gospel of John 11-27, trans. John W. Rettig (Washington, DC: The Catholic University of America Press, 1988, pp. 41-2]

Page 26: Marion, Jean-Luc - On the Foundation of the Distinction Between Theology and Philosophy

72 JEAN-LUC MARION

1 & 2 & 3 9

to hold as true (assumption, opinion, conviction, doxa, the first kind of knowledge, etc…); to believe demands loving because the revealed given is not only worthy that we love it because it results from a gra-cious gift (a grace), but above all because it concerns in the last instance and from the very beginning the revelation of love itself. Love plays a role of epistemological mediation; it is a required condition of access to the revealed given. And it plays this role because, more radically, it exhausts and identifies that itself which Revelation gives: love in action (en acte, in actu). Such a theology, in the proper sense, is directly op-posed to the thesis, for example, of Fichte: “For me the relation of the divinity to ourselves as ethical beings is what is immediately given.”36 Indeed, with perfect coherence, Fichte guarantees this immediacy of the given in postulating a strict transcendental attitude: “To summa-rize: my philosophy of religion cannot be judged, discussed, or con-solidated except from a transcendental point of view.”37 And he con-cludes very logically that as long as “theology” is not summarized in a “doctrine of religion, the doctrine of the relations of God to finite beings (êtres finis), but, as must be the case, claims to remain a doctrine of the essence of God in and for himself,” then, “clearly and directly: this theology must be abolished as an illusion surpassing all finite faculty of comprehension.”38 Theology, in the sense which we have tried to make more precise, results from a given, but from a given the experience of which contradicts the system of metaphysics in that it transgresses the limits between the possible and the impossible, the ontological and the ontical, the natural and the supernatural, limits which result from the transcendental attitude and which accomplish it. This contradic-tion becomes the fundamental condition of all serious thought about the Revelation and the conditions of mediate access to its given. To face this contradiction constitutes the duty and even the identity of

36Johann Gottlieb Fichte, “Appel au public contre l’accusation d’athéisme II,” in Querelle de l’athéisme: Suivie de divers textes sur la religion, trans. Jean-Christophe Goddard (Paris: J. Vrin, 1993), p. 55; Fichtes Werke, vol. 5, Zur Religionsphilosophie, ed. Immanuel Hermann Fichte (Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1971), p. 214. For example, because the same antagonisms can easily be found in Kant and Hegel, not to mention their successors.

37Idem, “Rappels, Réponses, Questions,” §19, in Querelle de l’athéisme, p. 149; Werke, p. 351.

38Idem, “Lettre privée,” in Querelle de l’athéisme, p. 181; Werke, pp. 386 ff.

Page 27: Marion, Jean-Luc - On the Foundation of the Distinction Between Theology and Philosophy

THE DISTINCTION BETWEEN PHILOSOPHY AND THEOLOGY 73

1 & 2 & 3 9

theology as a knowledge of God in the twofold meaning of a knowl-edge about God and a knowledge starting from (à partir de) God.

Recapitulation and suggestions

From these quick remarks, we can at least draw the sketch of some conclusions which are also valid as the anticipated description of a new relation yet to come between a theology on the basis of Revelation and a philosophy at the “end of metaphysics.”

Firstly, between these two knowledges, the unbridgeable gap be-tween the modes of givenness (revealed from elsewhere for one, expe-rienced by oneself for the other) and the gap between their modes of experience (immediate or mediated by faith and the love of truth) nev-er put in question the formal identity of their relation to a given: like all knowledge, one and the other are concerned with the comprehension of a given. Moreover, the gap between the procedures of access to their respective givens and between the corresponding protocols of their ex-perience cannot be measured except against the background of this formal univocity of the givens which come into play. If it is absolutely necessary to take notice of a difference, we can say that theology ad-mits of a given which is broader (precisely because revealed, mediated, and coming from a radical elsewhere) than that of philosophy and, obviously, than those of the regional positive sciences. But this gap yet again manifests even better the fact that they exercise the same ratio-nality as the comprehension of a given. It is enough to recognize that, if we consider it strictly from the philosophical point of view, without satisfying its epistemological requirement (believing in order to un-derstand, loving in order to know), and thus without the mediation that opens up its given, the theology of Revelation remains and must remain a discourse of the as if : in the best of cases, a philosopher will admit that everything takes place as if the theological discourse ratio-nally understood a given, but a mediate given, thus, obviously, without access to its own presupposition of the immediacy of the given in gen-eral: the unavailability of the revealed (mediate) given does not prevent the recognition of the rationality of its comprehension. The theologian can never ask for more, but the philosopher should never settle for less. On this condition, there will never be a competition between these two knowledges (their givens differ as radically as the manner of acceding

Page 28: Marion, Jean-Luc - On the Foundation of the Distinction Between Theology and Philosophy

74 JEAN-LUC MARION

1 & 2 & 3 9

to them) nor an epistemological contradiction (for the rationality of the procedures remains univocal).39 In this context, it then becomes absurd to imagine that, between philosophy at the “end of metaphys-ics” and the theology of Revelation, the contrast can be confined to having more or less freedom of inquiry or freedom of thought.

Secondly, this gap and this supplementary mediation nevertheless place theology in a dominant position in relation to the other knowl-edges, and particularly philosophy. Indeed, theology, as theology of Revelation, has always had to resist the metaphysical constitution of philosophy; that it often easily or uneasily arrived at this in the course of history only confirms that it always tried to remain itself without devaluing itself in a compromised or counterfeit philosophy. By voca-tion, the theology of Revelation must settle outside metaphysics. It therefore precedes philosophy, which today struggles to admit the “end of metaphysics,” and, sometimes, to even see the question. But the-ology precedes philosophy on its own path, on the road of its own expansion as non-metaphysical philosophy. It does not impose any constraint on philosophy, but offers it the possibility of being deliv-ered from the mortgage that still weighs heavily upon it because of the onto-theological constitution of metaphysics. In this way, theol-ogy becomes the rational bad conscience of philosophy because it can (and must) immediately consider a given (which is nevertheless medi-ate)—it is true that it is a given which is highly exceptional—among all the other new givens that philosophy at the “end of metaphysics” must consider and struggles so much to integrate. For the question of the fullness to be recognized in the given—otherwise said, the question of the extension of the fields of givenness and the modes of givenness—is also posed to philosophy: that it does not have to integrate the mediate given of Revelation does not exempt it from considering the admission of givens that surpass the limits fixed by the system of metaphysics and by the transcendental attitude that accomplished it. Thus must it integrate non-objectifiable phenomena and non-beings (non-étants):

39It is necessary to emphasize that philosophy never does and can never do theol-ogy (above all when it does philosophy of religion): what philosophers denounce as a theological turn remains an unfounded fear because it is a matter of a pious wish, of an illusory claim. Philosophy does not have the means for such a turn and much more is required of it, since it does not have access to the given (mediated by faith) of Revelation.

Page 29: Marion, Jean-Luc - On the Foundation of the Distinction Between Theology and Philosophy

THE DISTINCTION BETWEEN PHILOSOPHY AND THEOLOGY 75

1 & 2 & 3 9

the phenomena of the flesh, of the other human being (l’autrui), of the idol, of the event, but also of the call, of boredom, of the lover, of the unsayable language (langage dénégatif ),40 etc…, in short, all that we have called saturated phenomena. Until where can and must this expansion extend? As far as it is concerned with this question, the theology of Revelation cannot, by origin and definition, but already respond to it: it must expand the given until the given of Revelation mediated by faith. But philosophy, situated at the “end of metaphys-ics,” has hardly begun to heed this demand today. Philosophy must admit—what it already practices in reality without always being able to admit it clearly—that its abandonment in fact of the transcendental attitude opens to it the a priori limitless field of a radical empiricism, which is freed from the required interrogation concerning what one is allowed to experience and what one has no right to experience. As an adept of a radical (because transcendent) empiricism, theology also has the function of being the empirical bad conscience for philoso-phy. And in this sense, it happens that, by excess and inadvertently, it precedes philosophy in the openness to and the construction of philo-sophical questions.

There is therefore a rationality of theology and it is the same as, although more complex and more powerful than, that of philosophy, and, to an even lesser degree, the same as that of the positive sciences: the comprehension of a given.41 The fact of ignoring this extension of

40We are thinking here of the retrieval of what is mistakenly called “negative theology” by contemporary philosophy within the phenomenological movement [for Derrida and his discussion of our retrieval of the Dionysian doctrine to deconstruct deconstruction, see “In the Name: How to avoid speaking of ‘Negative Theology’,” reprinted in In Excess: Studies of Saturated Phenomena, trans. Robyn Horner and Vincent Berraud (New York: Fordham University Press, 2002), pp. 128-62 and “On the Gift: A Discussion between Jacques Derrida and Jean-Luc Marion, moderated by Richard Kearney,” in God, the Gift and Postmodernism, ed. John D. Caputo and Michael J. Scanlon (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1999), pp. 54-78] as well as the analytic tradition, where the later Wittgenstein appears as the patient and resolute transgression of the prohibition which concludes the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus: whereof one cannot speak, thereof one must precisely not be silent, for to be silent already implies saying it (déjà de [se] le dire) in one way or another, indeed of saying it in a third voice.

41We are all familiar with the famous definition formulated by Étienne Gilson: “Christian philosophy is a philosophy which, though formally distinguishing the two orders, considers Christian Revelation to be an indispensable guide to truth.”

Page 30: Marion, Jean-Luc - On the Foundation of the Distinction Between Theology and Philosophy

76 JEAN-LUC MARION

1 & 2 & 3 9

the given and, consequently, the possibility of an extension of rational-ity neither confers any rigor on those who ignore it and nor puts into question those who attempt to practice it.42 We can discuss if philoso-phy has ever played the role of a servant of theology (ancilla theologiæ), but it does not seem absurd to suggest that theology plays the role of the guardian of philosophy in order that philosophy may remain at the peak of its destiny.

Translated by Eduardo José E. Calasanz and John Carlo P. Uy

in “Theology and Philosophy,” in Christianity and Philosophy, p. 101. See The Spirit of Mediæval Philosophy: Gifford Lectures 1931-1932, trans. A. H. C. Downes (New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons, 1949), p. 37 and our discussion on “Christian Philoso-phy – Hermeneutic or Heuristic?” in The Visible and the Revealed, trans. Christina M. Gschwandtner and others (New York: Fordham University Press, 2008), pp. 66-79 whose conclusions we essentially maintain. However, we would correct it thus: Chris-tian theology precisely does not distinguish its rationality from that of philosophy (for reason is one and universal), but, through a mediation (that of faith), it accedes to a given more extensive than that of philosophy; in playing its proper role, Christian the-ology obliges philosophy to be liberated from the transcendental limits of the system of metaphysics.

42A remark of Étienne Gilson is worth noting: “To be sure, there are and will, per-haps, always be philosophers without faith or law, but what they lack cannot confer any formal exactitude on what they possess. Philosophy is not more a philosophy when it is pagan than when it is Christian; it is then only an obscured philosophy. Philosophy is not less a philosophy when it is Christian than when it is pagan, nor is it more so; but it is better.” (ibid., p. 87).