mahoney - objectivity, interpretation, and rights- a critique of dworkin

Upload: txtdc

Post on 14-Apr-2018

218 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 7/30/2019 Mahoney - Objectivity, Interpretation, And Rights- A Critique of Dworkin

    1/36

    JON MAHONEY

    OBJECTIVITY, INTERPRETATION, AND RIGHTS:A CRITIQUE OF DWORKIN

    (Accepted 10 October 2003)

    This paper addresses two significant features of Ronald Dworkins

    conception of law and justice. The first is Dworkins theory of

    constructive interpretation as first developed in his essay Hard

    Cases1 and more recently in his bookLaws Empire.2 The second

    is Dworkins long standing defense of a deontological conception

    of rights. This defense was first famously presented in TakingRights Seriously3 and Dworkin continues to defend this conception

    of rights in his more recent effort to elaborate a theory of justice

    based on equality.4 Dworkins theory of constructive interpreta-

    tion purports to both explain and justify legal practice. Dworkins

    theory of rights purports to show that individual rights impose

    deontological constraints on citizens, legislators, and judges.

    Much has been written on Dworkins position on rights and on his

    interpretive theory of law. There is little commentary, however, on

    the connection between these two central features of his conception

    of law and justice.5 This connection is important for two reasons.

    First, Dworkin rejects contractarian and Kantian approaches to law

    and justice. Basic political duties, including the duty to accept the

    coercive authority of law, do not stem from terms that rational

    agents can freely endorse under specified conditions such as the

    original position or a moral point of view. Political duties emerge,

    rather, from associative obligations.6 Associative obligations are

    rooted in a communitys treatment of its members rather than in an

    implicit agreement about principles of justice. In order to discern

    1 Dworkin (1977a).2 Dworkin (1986).

    3 Dworkin (1977b).4 Dworkin (2000).5 For a good overview of Dworkins work, see Guest (1991).6 Dworkin (1986, pp. 195216).

    Law and Philosophy 23: 187222, 2004.

    2004 Kluwer Academic Publishers. Printed in the Netherlands.

  • 7/30/2019 Mahoney - Objectivity, Interpretation, And Rights- A Critique of Dworkin

    2/36

    188 JON MAHONEY

    a citizens legal and political obligations to the state and to other

    citizens, Dworkin claims we need to examine her communitys

    treatment of her. In addition, we must also examine the political

    communitys understanding of basic legal and political principlesas this understanding provides the basis for interpretive claims

    about justice. Secondly, Dworkin claims that normative concepts,

    including rights, are interpretive concepts. Normative concepts are

    justified if they can survive a reflective exercise in constructive

    interpretation. Dworkins interpretive theory of normative concepts

    purports to show that norms are justified when the arguments for

    them fit and justify a social (e.g., law) practice. The appropriate

    characterization for the practical rationality that provides the reasons

    for or against a normative claim on this view is closer to the

    contextualist model familiar from the hermeneutical tradition than

    the Kantian conception favored by most defenders of deontolo-gical rights.7 At the same time, Dworkin claims to affirm a modest

    realism. There are truth-conditions for normative claims; claims

    to objectivity are not simply expressions of agents preferences;

    whether or not we are correct in asserting a claim about rights or

    justice is not up to us; and there are objectively right and wrong

    answers to normative questions.

    The purpose of this paper is to argue that Dworkins attempt to

    conjoin an interpretive theory of normative concepts with a deonto-

    logical conception of rights is problematic. I will not argue against

    Dworkins views concerning the internal relationship between lawand morality, a relationship that Dworkin has convincingly argued

    for in much of his work. Rather, I will argue that Dworkin has not

    shown that an interpretive theory of normative concepts can provide

    the right kind of justification for an important class of deontological

    rights. For example, universal moral rights that impose prohibitions

    on torture or that enjoin agents to tolerate others religious prac-

    tices are better supported by a conception of practical reason and

    moral argument that does not construe moral claims as interpretive

    claims in the sense characterized by the method of constructive

    interpretation.

    Part I provides a general overview of constructive interpreta-tion. Part II examines Dworkins critique of skepticism. Though

    7 For an overview, see Warnke (1993).

  • 7/30/2019 Mahoney - Objectivity, Interpretation, And Rights- A Critique of Dworkin

    3/36

    OBJECTIVITY AND INTERPRETATION 189

    Dworkin offers compelling reasons for rejecting common varieties

    of skepticism about law and morality, his alternative to skepticism is

    problematic. I argue that the moral justification for a deontological

    right is better understood to be a matter of reason and principle thana matter of interpretation. Since Dworkin claims that constructive

    interpretation is a matter of reason and principle, the aim of Part III

    is to show that Dworkins position fails to provide an adequate

    conception of moral justification. Finally, Part IV anticipates and

    responds to three objections that Dworkin might offer against my

    argument.

    One of my aims in this paper is to show that Dworkins concep-

    tion of justification is ambiguous.8 There are features of Dworkins

    view that pull in different directions. For example, there are good

    reasons for characterizing the method of constructive interpretation

    as one that sometimes supports judgments with global rather thanmerely local reach.9 If this is true, then objective standards of inter-

    pretation entitle judgments independently of the local practice or

    tradition from which they are made. One might argue that this aspect

    of Dworkins position establishes that his conception of justification

    is compatible with moral universalism. However, Dworkins method

    of constructive interpretation is presented as a model for how agents

    can justify interpretive claims about their own practices. This is why

    I believe Dworkins conception of justification is ambiguous. This

    conception is supposed to establish, on the one hand, that there are

    objective standards that determine the truth or falsity of interpretiveclaims. These standards include considerations of justice that are

    appealed to in order to evaluate claims that purport to have universal

    scope or global reach. At the same time, Dworkins characterization

    of what makes a claim an interpretive claim is that it be an interpre-

    tation of a practice and thus a claim within a practice by someone

    evaluating the practice. In what sense, then, are claims about justice

    or deontological rights with universal scope interpretive claims? If,

    as I will argue, claims with universal scope should be treated as justi-

    fied on grounds that any reasonable person should accept, there is no

    8 I thank a reviewer for this journal for helpful suggestions on how to developthis idea.

    9 See, for instance, Dworkins remarks on the peculiar sense in which justice

    is an interpretive concept in Dworkin (1986, pp. 424425).

  • 7/30/2019 Mahoney - Objectivity, Interpretation, And Rights- A Critique of Dworkin

    4/36

    190 JON MAHONEY

    reason to treat such claims as interpretive claims. This argument is

    developed further in Parts III and IV. I begin with an exposition of

    the idea of constructive interpretation and show how it is supposed

    apply to a type of reasoning that is common to many forms of social,moral, legal, and aesthetic criticism.

    I. CONSTRUCTIVE INTERPRETATION

    Dworkins theory of constructive interpretation is an attempt to

    establish that normative concepts are interpretive concepts that

    are justified by what he calls the interpretive attitude.10 Though

    primarily concerned with legal theory, Dworkin is explicit in

    claiming that his interpretive theory of normative concepts is a

    general theory for concepts central to the practices of art and literarycriticism, and morality, as well as law.11 Moral concepts, like their

    legal counterparts, are interpretive concepts that are justified when

    they are supported by a particular interpretation of a social prac-

    tice. A social practice (e.g., literary criticism, morality, and law)

    is a collective activity in which groups of people share norms and

    standards for criticism. Social practices are also identified by a

    mutual understanding regarding the aims and purposes of the prac-

    tice in question. An agent adopts the interpretive attitude when she

    deliberates about a norm from a point of view that considers both

    the purpose of the practice that contains the norm and the manner

    in which the norm contributes to a justification of the practice.Though Dworkin himself does not describe his position as such,

    when applied to morality, I take the interpretive attitude to be one

    way to model what has traditionally been called the moral point of

    view.

    The moral point of view has been characterized in a number of

    ways, of course, but anyone who defends a moral point of view is

    undertaking a defense of principles or procedures that people should

    use as a way to discern moral truth. In this sense, the interpretive

    attitude, like the moral point of view, provides grounds for justi-

    fying moral claims. In other words, agents are to adjudicate moraldisputes about concepts such as equality and rights by providing

    10 Dworkin (1986, pp. 4648).11 Ibid. See also Dworkin (1996).

  • 7/30/2019 Mahoney - Objectivity, Interpretation, And Rights- A Critique of Dworkin

    5/36

    OBJECTIVITY AND INTERPRETATION 191

    an interpretation of such concepts. There is, however, one crucial

    difference between the interpretive attitude and traditional versions

    of the moral point of view. The method of constructive interpretation

    is offered as an alternative to those versions of moral realism thatrequire a metaphysics of moral properties or other similarly contro-

    versial commitments. According to Dworkin, the objectivity of

    morality can be established without entering these controversies.12

    This is one reason why he claims, I am defending an interpretation

    of our own political culture, not an abstract and timeless political

    morality . . ..13

    When we reason about normative concepts, constructive inter-

    pretation and the interpretive attitude it supports provide guidelines

    for agents who want to reach an agreement about norms. This is

    why I claim the interpretive attitude is similar to the idea of a moral

    point of view. The interpretive attitude has four central features andeach contributes to how agents argue for normative claims. These

    features are: purpose, fit, justification, and integrity.

    In Dworkins words, . . . constructive interpretation is a matter

    of imposing purpose on an object or practice in order to make of

    it the best possible example of the form or genre to which it is

    taken to belong.14 Suppose, for instance, that we want to under-

    stand courtesy.15 We begin by considering the aim or purpose of the

    social practice that inspires acts of courtesy. This is the appropriate

    context for considering the kinds of judgments and the reasons for

    them that people offer when they think reflectively about the natureof courtesy. Among other things, we need to consider the purpose

    that courtesy serves and for this we need to know the purpose of the

    social practice in which people use the concept. For Dworkin, we

    cannot fully understand courtesy without grasping how it serves the

    aim or purpose of a social practice.

    In every social practice it is likely that courtesy contributes to

    the purpose of that practice in multiple ways. This might include

    the following: preserving ascribed social roles, maintaining a social

    order, protecting a conception of respect, or keeping subordinates in

    12 Dworkin (1996).13 Dworkin (1986, p. 216).14 Ibid., p. 52.15 Ibid., pp. 4649.

  • 7/30/2019 Mahoney - Objectivity, Interpretation, And Rights- A Critique of Dworkin

    6/36

    192 JON MAHONEY

    their place. Moreover, there might very well be a dispute about how

    courtesy contributes to the purpose of a practice, or even a dispute

    about the purpose of the practice itself. What matters for Dworkin

    is that when we adopt the interpretive attitude we commit ourselvesto an interpretation of a normative concept that presupposes a claim

    about the purpose of a practice.

    Every interpretive claim must also satisfy the criterion of fit.

    Fit requires that an interpreter strive to make her practice intern-

    ally coherent. In a dispute about courtesy, we ask, for instance,

    does courtesy, expressed by such actions as men doffing their hats

    when entering church, fit other features of our social practice, or

    does this interpretation of the concept fail to fit the practice as a

    whole? Answers to interpretive questions about courtesy might

    support claims that deny that courtesy calls for doffing hats in

    church or even the claim that courtesy fails to fit our social practicealtogether in which case, courtesy must be rejected as a normative

    concept. Likewise, someone who claims that segregated education

    is constitutional has to show that segregated education does not

    violate other principles in our legal practice. Evaluating such claims

    requires an interpretive analysis that considers whether segregated

    education fits the idea of equality expressed in the 14th Amendment

    or other relevant features of our legal tradition. Fit constrains the

    range of permissible judgments about what kinds of principles a

    social practice can support; it does so by demanding that we bring

    our judgments about one principle or concept into harmony withother principles or concepts that are already embedded in the social

    practice.

    The criterion of fit does not stand alone, however, and no inter-

    pretive claim is justified simply because it fits the practice in

    question. For Dworkin, questions of justification dont reduce to

    questions of fit, though they are answerable to fit as one standard

    of interpretive judgments. Questions of justification always refer to

    a deeper issue concerning the justification of the practice as a whole.

    Questions of justification ask, in other words, whether one inter-

    pretation of a concept provides a better justification of our social

    practice than an alternative interpretation. If we want to understandhow legal argument is constrained by the principle equality, for

    instance, we ask whether a particular interpretation, such as the one

  • 7/30/2019 Mahoney - Objectivity, Interpretation, And Rights- A Critique of Dworkin

    7/36

    OBJECTIVITY AND INTERPRETATION 193

    offered in Brown provides a better justification for our legal practice

    as a whole than the interpretation offered in Plessy. This question,

    in turn, is answered in relation to a larger commitment, which is that

    the law as such should provide a justification for the use of politicalpower; we support our interpretation of equality by showing that it

    provides a good justification for when and how the state can enforce

    individual rights.

    In Hard Cases, which offers an early statement of the view that

    emerges more systematically in Laws Empire, Dworkin summar-

    izes the criterion of justification by claiming that one . . . must

    construct a scheme of abstract and concrete principles that provides

    a coherent justification for all common law precedents and, so far

    as these are to be justified on principle, constitutional and stat-

    utory provisions as well.16 The criterion of justification serves the

    role of a regulative ideal and thus is a very demanding criterionfor judgments about normative concepts. Dworkins well-known

    judge Hercules17 is supposed to capture the point of view of

    an ideal judge who is both committed to and capable of honoring

    the criterion of justification. Justification is therefore a counterfac-

    tual and regulative constraint on normative judgments. Moreover,

    this highly idealized conception of justification is one reason why

    Dworkin claims and is entitled to claim that constructive interpre-

    tation is a method of reasoning about norms that aspires to truth

    and objectivity. According to Dworkin, we justify our interpretive

    claims about norms in general by claiming that our interpretationyields a better justification of a social practice than can be provided

    by competing claims.

    One of the ways that Dworkin tries to preserve the objectivity

    of interpretive judgments is by demonstrating that there are right

    and wrong answers to interpretive questions. Disputants might be

    wrong about the claim that courtesy serves the interests of those

    who wish to maintain ascribed social roles, that courtesy norms

    conflict with the principle of equal respect, or that courtesy does

    not require returning email messages, etc. It is also possible that

    every member of a social practice fails to grasp courtesy. That we

    can be wrong about our own practices is an important claim because

    16 Dworkin (1977a, pp. 116117).17 Ibid. See also Dworkin (1985, 1986).

  • 7/30/2019 Mahoney - Objectivity, Interpretation, And Rights- A Critique of Dworkin

    8/36

    194 JON MAHONEY

    it helps explain how some features of a social practice persist even

    when they are incompatible with the central principles that underlie

    the practice. For instance, one way to explain the persistence of

    arguments in favor of segregated schools after the adoption of the14th Amendment is by demonstrating that members of the American

    legal and political community lacked an adequate understanding

    of their own practice. It is always possible that members of a

    community fail to adequately understand the interpretive concepts

    that shape their own practices. The method of constructive interpre-

    tation has explanatory value in part because it offers a perspicuous

    view of moral progress within a tradition.

    Failures in exercises of constructive interpretation can explain

    failures on the part of an entire community (or some subset of the

    community) to see inconsistencies in its treatment of some of its

    members. Likewise, successful exercises in constructive interpreta-tion help explain moral progress when it does occur. To illustrate

    this point, Dworkin offers a useful analogy from art and literary

    criticism. When a critic provides an interpretation of a work of

    literature, the criterion of justification requires that . . . an inter-

    pretation of a piece of literature attempts to show which way of

    reading (or speaking or directing or acting) the text reveals it as the

    best work of art.18 For example, someone who claims Eliots The

    Waste Land is a critical commentary on the demise of spirituality

    in modern culture is justified if his reading makes the poem better

    than alternative readings.In law as in literary and art criticism, a successful exercise in

    constructive interpretation will show the tradition or work in its

    best light. In this sense, constructive interpretation tries to inter-

    pret a concept or practice with a larger aim in mind. Someone

    who engages in such an exercise with respect to courtesy must,

    in addition to providing examples of courtesy and explaining prac-

    titioners understanding of the concept, attempt to show how her

    interpretation justifies courtesy norms. An exercise in constructive

    interpretation may therefore result in our discovering that doffing

    hats is a form of homage to antiquated values that embody the

    vestiges of anti-egalitarian roles that are incompatible with our prac-tices current conception of equality. The prevailing interpretation

    18 Dworkin (1985a, p. 149).

  • 7/30/2019 Mahoney - Objectivity, Interpretation, And Rights- A Critique of Dworkin

    9/36

    OBJECTIVITY AND INTERPRETATION 195

    of courtesy might support forms of behavior that we now regard as

    insulting or disrespectful. Dworkin argues that something analogous

    to this can account for how two incompatible judgments about

    equality can appear to have support from within the same prac-tice. The judgments that underlie Plessy and Brown for instance,

    were made within the same legal tradition by persons who believed,

    though in one case mistakenly, that their judgments were justified

    by an interpretation of common law practices as chartered by the

    U.S Constitution. The criterion of justification helps to show that

    Brown rather than Plessy better represents the concept of equality

    within the American legal tradition; Brown affirms, whereas Plessy

    conflicts with the political morality expressed by the American legal

    tradition.

    The fourth feature of constructive interpretation, integrity, estab-

    lishes the overall coherence and plausibility of Dworkins inter-pretive theory of normative concepts. Dworkin regards integrity as

    the master component to constructive interpretation. Integrity brings

    together the other three features of constructive interpretation and

    shows that constructive interpretation provides a general method for

    providing a justification for interpretations of social practices. The

    following is a summary of Dworkins position:

    . . . convictions about fit contest with and constrain judgments of substance, and

    how convictions about fairness and justice and procedural due process contest

    with one another. The interpretive judgment must notice and take account of

    these several dimensions; if it does not, it is incompetent or in bad faith, ordinarypolitics in disguise. But it must also meld these dimensions into an overall

    opinion: about which interpretation, all things considered, makes the communitys

    legal record the best it can be from the point of view of political morality. 19

    Integrity is a distinct virtue that explains why we are opposed to

    things like checkerboard statutes, that is, laws that apply to com-

    munity members in arbitrary ways by selecting features of some

    members as the basis for special privileges or the denial of such

    privileges.20 In the present context, the most important feature of

    Dworkins concept of integrity concerns the role it plays in shaping

    a communitys moral identity.

    19 Dworkin (1986, pp. 410411).20 Ibid., p. 176.

  • 7/30/2019 Mahoney - Objectivity, Interpretation, And Rights- A Critique of Dworkin

    10/36

    196 JON MAHONEY

    Dworkin argues that the interpretive point of view acknowledges

    integrity as a virtue when the interpreter understands his community

    as a community of principle. In his words,

    Members of a society of principle accept that their political rights and duties are

    not exhausted by the particular decisions their political institutions have reached,

    but depend more generally, on the scheme of principles those decisions presup-

    pose and endorse. So each member accepts that others have rights and that he

    has duties flowing from that scheme, even though these have never been formally

    identified or declared.21

    In adopting the interpretive point of view, interpreters are committed

    to defending claims that promote the moral integrity of their

    community. For example, when an agent appeals to a right in order

    to defend or defeat a claim she addresses her interlocutors from the

    standpoint of someone who hopes to demonstrate that her interpreta-tion of a concept or principle preserves yet improves an established

    sense of moral community. This is what it means to understand

    oneself as a member of a community of principle. As a matter of

    principle, one must conform judgments about rights to judgments

    about the moral integrity of the community. In this respect, integrity

    brings together fit and justification. When applied to law, fit imposes

    a normative demand to preserve laws consistency, whereas justi-

    fication imposes a normative demand to preserve laws authority.

    Laws integrity requires both and thus enables the full expression of

    laws morality.

    i. Constructive Interpretation and Moral Concepts

    As Ive presented it thus far, the implication of constructive inter-

    pretation for moral concepts is significant. For example, an agent

    who argues that her rights, or the rights of others, are not prop-

    erly acknowledged is making a claim about obligations that her

    community should acknowledge. It is significant that, on Dworkins

    model, the addressees of an argument about rights are members

    of ones own community, rather than persons as such. This is one

    aspect of the interpretive attitude that differs from the moral point

    of view as it has been traditionally understood. Though there is acounterfactual component to normative claims about rights, such

    21 Ibid., p. 211.

  • 7/30/2019 Mahoney - Objectivity, Interpretation, And Rights- A Critique of Dworkin

    11/36

    OBJECTIVITY AND INTERPRETATION 197

    claims must always refer to an interpretation of some real, existing

    community. The interpretive point of view will not support claims

    that appeal for their justification to an imagined community, such as

    a Kingdom of Ends. Constructive interpretation is therefore incom-patible with moral realism as it is defended in the Kantian tradition.

    Since Kantians believe that a moral claim is true if it can be affirmed

    by all persons in a manner that upholds the fundamental moral

    concepts of equality and autonomy, moral truth for them is under-

    stood as a matter of what can be affirmed by the standpoint of

    practical reason.22 Not just any standpoint will suffice, of course.

    Rather, the truth of a moral claim is determined from the stand-

    point of practical reason that expresses what all rational agents can

    impartially affirm as true, where true means compatible with reasons

    for action that no reasonable person can reject.23 An exercise in

    constructive interpretation can at most establish that obligationsflow from a set of commitments to norms that already bind the

    community in question. Dworkin calls such obligations associative

    obligations because they derive from a communal association of

    individuals.24 The reach of constructive interpretation can at most

    appeal to a better version of ones existing practice by making crit-

    ical judgments about such a practice from the point of view of the

    better version.

    Dworkin is satisfied with this feature of his position, because

    he believes his model of constructive interpretation can support

    objective normative claims. A normative claim is objective if itclarifies the purpose of a practice, fits the practice better than

    competing claims, justifies the practice and preserves the integrity of

    the community defined by the practice. In the case of legal claims,

    disputants are accountable to interpretations of law. In the case of

    morality, disputants are accountable to interpretations of morality.

    The same goes for art, etiquette, or any other norm-governed social

    22 Korsgaard (1996).23 In this paper I stress a contractualist interpretation of Kantian ethics, one that

    stresses the idea ofreasonableness as this concept is understood and defended by

    Rawls (1971, 1996) and Scanlon (1998). On this view, a reasonable person is

    someone willing to seek fair terms for cooperation. In order for a principle toqualify as reasonable it must be one that can be affirmed by all in a manner that

    respects the dignity and autonomy of each.24 Dworkin (1986, pp. 195216).

  • 7/30/2019 Mahoney - Objectivity, Interpretation, And Rights- A Critique of Dworkin

    12/36

    198 JON MAHONEY

    activity; the best argument is one that supports the best interpretation

    within the domain-specific parameters of the genre or practice in

    question.25

    II. OBJECTIVITY AND TRUTH

    All varieties of moral realism require some account of how our judg-

    ments are answerable to truth. Moral realists are obliged, in other

    words, to tell us how somethings being the case rather than our

    moral belief is what justifies a moral claim.26 This is a very general

    way of construing the relation between truth and moral judgment in

    that it covers many different accounts of how truth is a constraint on

    the moral claims we make. For instance, a realist about moral prop-

    erties argues that the moral claims we make are answerable to someproperty that in some sense is there independently of our percep-

    tion.27 Aristotelians and virtue ethicists argue that agents with the

    right kind of character are able to recognize reasons based on facts

    about the proper function of human beings.28 Kantians, by contrast,

    claim that moral truth is determined by a moral point of view rooted

    in practical rationality and thus that truth in morality depends neither

    on a metaphysics of moral properties nor on a theory of human

    nature.29 Each of these views qualifies as a version of moral realism.

    In this section I consider the question, can Dworkins theory

    of constructive interpretation supply an adequate account of how

    truth is a constraint on the moral claims we make? Dworkin claims

    to be a moral realist,30 though not in any of the aforementioned

    senses. Dworkins recent essay Objectivity and Truth: Youd Better

    Believe It provides the clearest statement of his views on moral

    realism and thus I will be drawing mainly from this essay in

    what follows. After setting out Dworkins position, I argue that

    the modest realism advanced by Dworkin is in fact too modest to

    provide a foundation for moral rights.

    25 Dworkin (1996).26 Railton (1986, p. 172).

    27 Dancy (1993).28 Foot (2001, pp. 2223).29 Korsgaard (1996).30 Dworkin (1996, pp. 127128).

  • 7/30/2019 Mahoney - Objectivity, Interpretation, And Rights- A Critique of Dworkin

    13/36

    OBJECTIVITY AND INTERPRETATION 199

    i. Objectivity and Moral Skepticism

    In his discussion of moral realism, Dworkin considers two kinds of

    moral skepticism.31 The first, external or archimedean skepticism,

    denies that there is any subject matter that is properly speakingmoral and thus denies that when people make moral claims they

    are referring to moral facts or moral properties. External skeptics

    about morality reject the very idea that there is a domain of inquiry

    and argument that moral philosophers call the moral domain. They

    also deny that there are special standards for objectivity and truth

    that uniquely apply to morality. Internal skeptics, by contrast, claim

    to hold a moral position and thus regard their claims as moral

    claims. Unlike external skeptics, internal skeptics are willing to

    defend claims which they regard as moral claims and not just as

    claims about morality. However, although internal skeptics acceptthat there is a moral domain they offer reasons for rejecting the

    objectivity of moral claims. Dworkin insightfully argues that the real

    threat to those who want to defend the thesis that there is objectivity

    in moral argument comes from a version of internal skepticism

    he calls global internal skepticism.32 The global internal skeptic

    takes up the challenge of meeting the moral realist on her own terms

    by granting that moral claims seem to be susceptible to truth and

    falsity. Dworkins moral realism is best understood as an attempt

    to show the irrelevancy of external skepticism and as a response to

    global internal skepticism.

    According to Dworkin, traditional varieties of moral realism,such as realism about properties, unwittingly yield to external

    skepticism. Consider, briefly, the difference between beliefs about

    physical facts and moral beliefs. On some views both physical and

    moral properties are said to be that to which our judgments are

    answerable. And it surely does make sense to ask of ordinary beliefs

    about physical facts, what causes them? For moral beliefs, by

    contrast, appeals to properties to explain what causes us to have

    them and what justifies judgments about them seem fraught with

    difficulty. Dworkin argues that the external skepticism of people

    31 Earlier statements of Dworkins views on skepticism can be found in

    Dworkin (1985b, 1986).32 Dworkin (1996, p. 91).

  • 7/30/2019 Mahoney - Objectivity, Interpretation, And Rights- A Critique of Dworkin

    14/36

    200 JON MAHONEY

    like John Mackie33 gets its appeal by assuming the epistemology

    of beliefs about morality has to be the same as the epistemology

    of beliefs about physical properties or events. However, no one has

    provided an adequate account of how people acquire and justifymoral beliefs about properties in a manner analogous to the acquis-

    ition and justification of beliefs about physical properties. Moral

    skepticism therefore emerges as an appealing alternative to the

    quirky and unpalatable position required by moral realists who posit

    the existence of mind-independent moral properties. Mackies well-

    known argument from queerness is the most famous contemporary

    version of this argument.34 I believe that Dworkin concedes too

    much to Mackie and that he is mistaken in claiming there are no

    plausible versions of moral realism that rest on a theory of moral

    properties.35 But I will not argue this point here. On the other hand,

    Dworkin is right to claim that external skepticism about morality ismotivated by a recoil from what is regarded as an unpalatable theory

    of moral properties.

    Dworkin is also right to argue that external skepticism founders

    on an unjustified and uncharitable interpretation of the moral

    realists commitments. Furthermore, since external skepticism

    claims to be a neutral position, and thus one that stands outside of

    morality, it really isnt a moral position at all. This

    . . . helps explain why archimedians [external skeptics] always describe the wind-

    mills they make war on in bad metaphors they never cash, why they say that

    they do not believe that morality is part of the fabric of the universe or that itis out there, a phrase that appears hundreds of times in their texts, always in

    scare-quotes used like tongs holding something very disagreeable.36

    External skepticism, according to Dworkin, can be refuted by

    embracing a view about moral justification that does not appeal to

    moral properties. Rather, the moral realist requires only that there be

    moral claims that are open to refutation by other moral claims and

    that our convictions about the claims we make be treated as carrying

    a face-value commitment to truth. External skepticisms defeat lies

    33 Mackie (1977).

    34 Ibid., pp. 3842.35 Dworkin fails to consider, for example, the well-argued positions of Jonathan

    Dancy (1993) and John McDowell (1985).36 Dworkin (1996, p. 108).

  • 7/30/2019 Mahoney - Objectivity, Interpretation, And Rights- A Critique of Dworkin

    15/36

    OBJECTIVITY AND INTERPRETATION 201

    in its unwillingness to acknowledge that the only kind of skeptical

    claims about morality that count as skeptical claims against morality

    are themselves moral claims.

    Dworkin argues that internal skepticism is the real threat to objec-tivity in morality by appealing to the plausible idea that different

    domains of inquiry and argumentation have their own standards for

    adjudicating claims. For example, the only possible refutation of

    The Waste Land is a critique of modern culture is a competing

    literary interpretation of Eliots poem. Likewise, the only possible

    refutation of Persons are liable for emotional harm caused by their

    negligent actions is a competing interpretation of law. The same

    goes for morality. The only possible refutation of Slavery is unjust

    is a competing moral claim. Each of these claims can be justified by

    an exercise in constructive interpretation that appeals to the relevant

    standards for literary, legal, and moral judgment. Internal skepti-cism is troubling, if not in literary criticism then certainly in law

    and morality, because its defenders raise the possibility that our

    strongest convictions are false.37 A global internal skeptic about

    literature argues that there are no objective canons of interpreta-

    tion that constrain the judgments people make about novels, poems

    and other literary works. A global internal skeptic about law denies

    there are objective answers to legal questions. A global internal

    skeptic about morality denies that assertions such as Slavery is

    unjust amount to anything more than subjective opinions or at best,

    strongly held convictions.

    ii. Dworkins Modest Moral Realism

    Dworkins response to global internal skepticism is presented as a

    modest proposal for moral realism. Rather than claiming that our

    moral convictions latch on to timeless moral truths that are in some

    mysterious sense out there in the ether to be perceived by a special

    faculty of moral perception, our moral convictions should be under-

    stood as resting on convictions and arguments about substantive

    principles of morality.38 In morality as in law, conviction should

    be treated as belief supported by arguments that purport to estab-

    lish objective claims. There is no more to moral objectivity than

    37 Ibid., pp. 128129.38 For an earlier statements of this position, see Dworkin (1986, pp. 8081).

  • 7/30/2019 Mahoney - Objectivity, Interpretation, And Rights- A Critique of Dworkin

    16/36

    202 JON MAHONEY

    our convictions about what counts as the best argument. So the

    sense in which Slavery is unjust is true is best expressed by a

    consideration of how substantive moral principles, such as equality

    and human dignity, bear on the issue of how a community shouldtreat its members. Substantive principles define the parameters for

    moral argument, provide standards for practical reasoning, and thus

    support claims to objectivity. This form of moral realism is modest

    because it rests its case for objectivity on peoples ability to argue

    for their convictions rather than on their ability to grasp mind-

    independent moral truth. Here is a clear statement of Dworkins

    position:

    Of course I do not mean that our convictions are right just because we find them

    irresistible, or that our inability to think anything else is a reason or ground or

    argument supporting our judgment. On the contrary, these suggestions are formsof the skepticism I am opposing. I mean that any reason we think we have for

    abandoning a conviction is itself just another conviction, and that we can do no

    better for any claim, including the most sophisticated skeptical argument or thesis,

    than to see whether, after the best thought we find appropriate, we think it so.

    If you cant help believing something, steadily and wholeheartedly, youd better

    believe it. Not, as I just said, because the fact of your belief argues for its own

    truth, but because you cannot think any argument a decisive refutation of a belief

    it does not even dent. In the beginning, and in the end, is conviction. 39

    Our convictions about moral claims carry the force that they have

    because of the arguments that justify them.

    This position qualifies as a version of moral realism. It satisfiesthe requirements for a realist position stated at the beginning of

    this section. Our judgments are not merely opinions. Nor are they

    merely our convictions. Or at least they should not be so far as we

    claim to be offering reflective, reason-supported claims. Rather, as

    Dworkin argues in Objectivity and Truth we are entitled to affirm

    our convictions our good ones in any case because they support

    claims that we are justified in believing are true.

    There is much that is appealing in Dworkins account of

    objectivity and truth. His arguments against both external and global

    internal skepticism are compelling. Dworkins positive view about

    objectivity and truth, however, leaves open important questions.For instance, in claiming that the only refutation of a moral argu-

    39 Dworkin (1996, p. 118).

  • 7/30/2019 Mahoney - Objectivity, Interpretation, And Rights- A Critique of Dworkin

    17/36

    OBJECTIVITY AND INTERPRETATION 203

    ment is another moral argument Dworkin correctly suggests that

    the only authority we can appeal to for our moral convictions

    is the authority of morality itself. But where does this authority

    come from?40

    Since Dworkin rejects traditional forms of realism,the answer cannot be judgments that discern moral properties,

    virtues that enable moral character, or reasons that establish prin-

    ciples that no reasonable person can reject. On Dworkins view,

    the authority of the moral domain, rather, is a presupposition for

    moral argument, a presupposition that makes possible the social

    practice of presenting moral arguments for and against moral posi-

    tions. There is thus no reason to suppose that the account of

    objectivity defended in Objectivity and Truth is presented as an

    alternative to the account of objectivity defended in Laws Empire.

    In fact, in his recent efforts to defend moral realism Dworkin

    develops further a line of thought he has been defending for severaldecades.41

    III. THE MORAL GROUNDS FOR DEONTOLOGICAL RIGHTS

    To construe a right as a deontological right is to treat that right as

    immune to cost-benefit analysis, calculations of social utility, or any

    other consequentialist consideration that could be used to argue in

    favor of a trade-off between collective goals and individual entitle-

    ments. Dworkins concept of a strong sense right nicely captures

    the idea of a deontological right.42 Prohibitions against torture,religious persecution, and imprisoning the innocent all qualify as

    examples of a deontological right. When considering the case of

    false imprisonment Dworkin argues for a deontological conception

    of rights or rights in the strong sense by claiming,

    40 I understand this to be a question about moral justification. Understood this

    way, the trap of external skepticism is avoided. Ones moral position might yield

    to external skepticism if one construes questions about moral justification as ques-

    tions that solicit an explanation for why morality has a claim on us that requires

    non-moral considerations in favor of morality.

    41 Dworkin (1985d) discusses the sense in which propositions such as Slaveryis unjust are true in a manner very similar to his recent account in Dworkin

    (1996).42 Dworkin (1977b).

  • 7/30/2019 Mahoney - Objectivity, Interpretation, And Rights- A Critique of Dworkin

    18/36

    204 JON MAHONEY

    . . . it makes no sense for our society to establish the right not to be convicted when

    known to be innocent as absolute, unless that society recognizes moral harm as a

    distinct kind of harm against which people must be specially protected. But the

    utilitarian calculus that the cost-efficient society uses to fix criminal procedures

    is a calculus that can make no place for moral harm. . .

    . For moral harm is

    an objective notion, and if someone is morally harmed . . . when he is punished

    though innocent, then this moralharm occurs even when no one knows or suspects

    it, and even when perhaps especially when very few people very much care. 43

    I favor this characterization of a deontological right for several

    reasons. First, it shows how those in favor of deontological rights

    believe that a right is a non-negotiable entitlement of an individual

    to be treated by others in a certain manner. Secondly, it illustrates

    that one important basis for such a right lies in a concept of moral

    injury or harm that is understood to be objectively wrong. The moral

    foundation for this conception of harm is the idea of the person as amoral equal. And thirdly, this characterization presents in a clear

    manner the sense in which someone in favor of a deontological

    conception of rights rejects consequentialism.

    I also favor a forth consideration that is commonly associ-

    ated with a deontological understand of rights, a consideration

    conspicuous by its absence in Dworkins account. For some deont-

    ological rights, the claims we make about them purport to have

    universal scope. Universality of scope is not a necessary feature

    of deontological rights as such, but it is a necessary feature of at

    least some deontological rights, for instance, the right to not be

    tortured or any other human right. Universality of scope is centralto many of the rights that defenders of deontological rights support.

    This is in fact so central a feature, that to eliminate it from ones

    conception of rights would be to retract the very reasons we have

    for our commitment to human rights.44 For instance, anyone who

    argues for a deontological conception of rights that includes basic

    moral entitlements to have ones person respected (e.g., freedom

    of religion, freedom from torture, freedom from politically motiv-

    ated imprisonment, etc.), is arguing for a conception of rights that

    treats the scope of such rights as inclusive of all persons. And

    one cannot have a justified reason for accepting this conceptionof rights unless the reason can satisfy a universalizability require-

    43 Dworkin (1985c, p. 81).44 For a good overview, see Habermas (2001).

  • 7/30/2019 Mahoney - Objectivity, Interpretation, And Rights- A Critique of Dworkin

    19/36

    OBJECTIVITY AND INTERPRETATION 205

    ment, that is, a requirement that shows the reason to be one that

    no one can reasonably reject. Moreover, some moral reasons that

    satisfy this criterion command universal assent. For instance, if a

    right not to be tortured cannot be reasonably rejected, it follows thatall reasonable persons should affirm such a right. On my view, a

    norm commands universal assent when the normative requirements

    of morality cannot be satisfied by withholding ones assent.

    Dworkin defends what is clearly recognizable as a Kantian

    conception of rights.45 Yet he offers a non-Kantian justification

    for such rights. There may be no in-principle objection to this

    strategy. However, since Dworkin does opt for what he regards

    as a modest realism about morality, one that rests on a theory of

    constructive interpretation, his claim to be able to show that deont-

    ological rights are objective merits close inspection. On my view,

    Dworkins modest moral realism fails to provide an adequate justi-fication for the class of deontological rights that have universal

    scope. These rights are best understood, not as interpretive concepts

    whose authority comes from a social practice of interpretation, but

    rather, as a kind of practical reason whose authority comes from

    a moral point of view that is constrained by principles that no

    reasonable person can reject.

    i. Interpretation all the way down?46

    Suppose that all normative claims, including claims about universal

    rights, are interpretive claims. Suppose also that a normative claimqualifies as an interpretive claim if it is advanced as a justification for

    a practice from within a practice. How might one advance a deont-

    ological theory of rights from this perspective? In Ronald Dworkin,

    Stephen Guest offers the following characterization of how Dworkin

    attempts to integrate an interpretive theory of normative concepts

    with a deontological conception of rights:

    [Rights] . . . are justified, first, by reference to communities which actually do have

    practices of making political decisions by reference to community goals. In that

    45 Dworkin himself notes the connection between his and Kants view in

    Dworkin (1977b, p. 198).46 The title for this his sub-heading is inspired by Dworkins claim, Inter-

    pretive claims are interpretive . . . and so depend on aesthetic or political theory

    all the way down (Dworkin 1985b, p. 168).

  • 7/30/2019 Mahoney - Objectivity, Interpretation, And Rights- A Critique of Dworkin

    20/36

    206 JON MAHONEY

    sense, they are contingent and historical. Second, they are justified in trumping

    such goals, not because they embody a fundamental right to be treated with

    equal concern and respect, but because history has proved that if communities are

    constrained in a fundamental way from pursuing certain kinds of goals, the right

    to equal concern and respect is more likely to be respected. Fundamental here

    refers to the nature of the constraint rather than the intrinsic quality of the right

    itself.47

    If we consider this conception of justification as one that extends

    to universal rights, this is a puzzling view for two related reasons.

    One is that this characterization of the justification for deontological

    rights is open to the charge of ethnocentrism. The current debates on

    universal rights include those who deny that Western moral ideals

    apply to their traditions or social practices. Some traditions and

    practices cannot be interpreted in a way that will support universal

    rights. Another is that this conception of justification seems unableto support claims to universality that purport to be binding on all

    persons. I consider each of these points in turn.

    Most who defend universal rights find appeals to culture, tradi-

    tion or community identity a weak response to the claim that rights

    apply to all persons.48 Consider, for example, someone who appeals

    to the interpretive attitude to support claims against universal human

    rights on the grounds that each of the criteria of constructive inter-

    pretation show that his tradition or social practice does not support

    such claims. There are, in fact, familiar arguments against moral

    universalism which appeal to considerations such as cultural iden-

    tity, tradition, language, and religion in order to support practices

    that are in clear violation of universal deontological rights. In

    general, such arguments are intended to show that what is claimed

    to be a universal human right in fact fails to be sensitive to local

    47 Guest (1991, p. 235). Guests passage does not consider Dworkins claim that

    a communitys exercise in constructive interpretation is constrained by justice and

    that justice is an interpretive concept that carries special weight. In this respect,

    I think Dworkin would rightly reject this as a complete characterization of his

    view. Since I believe both that Dworkins conception of justification is ambiguous

    and that Guests characterization emphasizes one feature of this ambiguity (i.e.,

    the problem of treating all interpretive claims as claims made within a practice)

    Guests interpretation merits consideration. In Part IV, I consider an alternativeinterpretation of Dworkins position, one that might be advanced as a response to

    the problems I raise here.48 Barry (2001).

  • 7/30/2019 Mahoney - Objectivity, Interpretation, And Rights- A Critique of Dworkin

    21/36

    OBJECTIVITY AND INTERPRETATION 207

    or group-specific conceptions of value. On some communitarian

    versions of this argument, claims are treated as justified if they can

    be defended from the point of view of a social practice.49 It is clear

    that Dworkins liberalism will not support a communitarian objec-tion to moral universalism. However, the method of constructive

    interpretation seems unable to provide the moral foundation for

    universal rights claims that defenders of such rights require in order

    to refute communitarian and other skeptical arguments.

    Secondly, an exercise in constructive interpretation does not seem

    capable of supporting the claim that some rights bind all persons.

    The convictions that are ratified by such an exercise are convictions

    that are too closely tied to a specific political and legal tradition to

    yield a universalist understanding of rights. It is undoubtedly the

    case that the best interpretation of some moral traditions supports

    the idea of universal rights. This by itself, however, cannot provide areason for agents to accept moral universalism about rights. If ones

    traditions and practices cannot be interpreted in a way that yields

    support for such rights, then there can be no interpretive grounds

    for accepting a universal rights claim. To establish that agents are

    bound to norms in this way requires a reason or principle that can

    be justified independently of an exercise in constructive interpreta-

    tion. The best argument for this position, in my view, is a familiar

    Kantian one; norms bind universally when they express principles

    that converge with what the free and rational assent of all agents

    can accept as legitimate.

    50

    In contrast to constructive interpretation,this justification for rights connects both the idea that a strong sense

    right is deontological with the claim that this conception of rights is

    based on a view about practical reason and the idea of persons as free

    and equal. Moreover, unlike the account of moral conviction that

    Dworkin offers in Objectivity and Truth Kantian realism provides

    an account of how our convictions are sensitive to reasons all can

    share. In this respect, I believe that Dworkins rejection of a Kantian

    foundation for rights is a mistake; his method of constructive inter-

    49 For a defense of this strategy, see Walzer (1987). For an incisive criticism,

    see Barry (2001).50 Scanlons (1998) contractualist model of justification represents a positive

    step towards developing a deontological conception of norms that does not have

    a problem connecting universal scope with universal obligation.

  • 7/30/2019 Mahoney - Objectivity, Interpretation, And Rights- A Critique of Dworkin

    22/36

    208 JON MAHONEY

    pretation and the conception of objectivity it supports do not offer

    the kind of justification for rights that shows how universal rights,

    deontologically understood, inform our moral convictions.

    Consider, for instance, the claims to universality we make onbehalf of such rights each time we see them violated. Torture,

    slavery, religious persecution and other unjust practices solicit from

    us judgments of moral condemnation. These are all easy cases, of

    course, but the adequacy of a moral theory can be tested by looking

    at the explanation it provides for why and on what basis we make

    such judgments. One such account is offered by Joshua Cohen in

    his paper The Arc of the Moral Universe.51 Cohen offers an illu-

    minating discussion of moral realism, moral explanation, and moral

    ideals such as human dignity, ideals that command universal assent.

    He connects these themes from metaethics to a moral and histor-

    ical analysis of slavery. Cohens account of how moral judgmentsbear on social practices differs significantly from Dworkins in that

    the truth of a moral claim is taken to be independent of any inter-

    pretive exercise. Though Cohen is less modest in his realism than

    is Dworkin, his characterization of human dignity provides a more

    suitable foundation for deontological rights with universal scope.

    On Cohens view,

    . . . the central feature of dignity . . . is its social aspect that it involves a desire

    for public recognition of ones worth. Though a person can sustain a sense of self-

    worth in the face of repeated insults, still, public recognition is related to dignity in

    two ways: first, persons with a sense of their own worth regard such recognition asan appropriate acknowledgement of that worth; and, second, recognition provides

    psychological support for that sense, making it easier to sustain. In particular,

    having a sense of dignity, we want others to recognize that we have aspirations and

    to acknowledge the worth of those aims and aspirations, by inter alia, providing

    conditions (opportunities and resources) that enable us to pursue them.52

    There are features of Dworkins defense of deontological rights

    that align with this account.53 However, on Cohens account, moral

    claims that are incompatible with human dignity are false because

    compatibility with dignity is a truth condition for moral claims.

    51 Cohen (1998).52 Ibid., p.115.53 The moral significance of human dignity is central to Dworkins argument

    for strong sense rights in Dworkin (1977b).

  • 7/30/2019 Mahoney - Objectivity, Interpretation, And Rights- A Critique of Dworkin

    23/36

    OBJECTIVITY AND INTERPRETATION 209

    Dworkins interpretive theory and overly modest realism, however,

    preclude this kind of defense of the moral foundations for funda-

    mental universal rights. On Dworkins account, rights that appeal

    to human dignity are justified through an exercise in constructiveinterpretation, and justification is a matter of interpretation all the

    way down. On my view, rights are a matter of affirming what all

    reasonable people must accept, namely, terms for social interaction

    that affirm the equality and dignity of all persons. This is not simply

    a more direct way of affirming a universalist understanding of rights.

    It is a better way.

    The last sentence of the passage from Guest (quoted on pp. 19

    20) offers additional support this objection. The sentence reads

    Fundamental here refers to the nature of the constraint rather

    than the intrinsic quality of the right. This shows that if construed

    as an interpretive claim, a right is fundamental because of the role itplays in a political or legal practice. The phrase intrinsic quality

    of the right is unclear, but Guests interpretation of Dworkins

    position does show how one might treat moral rights claims as inter-

    pretive claims. Presented in this light, its hard to see how one could

    generalize an interpretive claim and justify its universal scope as

    an interpretive claim. If a moral claim has to be construed as an

    interpretive claim as a condition for its being judged, then it would

    seem impossible to justify universal claims.

    There is straightforward way to avoid the problems that come

    with treating all moral claims as interpretive claims. The followingconception of moral justification is sufficient: if a right with

    universal scope is justified then its grounds must be such that a

    reasonable person could affirm the right. This conception of moral

    justification rightly treats questions about what makes a moral

    reason a good one as questions about what a reasonable person can

    affirm rather than what can be affirmed from the point of view of a

    particular moral tradition. There is more than one way to construe

    what is meant by claiming that a norm is justified independently of

    a practice. This might mean the norm is taken to be independent of

    practical reason altogether and thus something like a Platonic form.

    By contrast, a norm may be said to be justified independently ofa social practice in the sense that it is supported by a moral point

    of view or a standpoint of practical reason that confers validity on

  • 7/30/2019 Mahoney - Objectivity, Interpretation, And Rights- A Critique of Dworkin

    24/36

    210 JON MAHONEY

    norms that bind all rational agents. This is the position that I prefer;

    a right is justified by the moral reason one can provide for it; moral

    reasons are justified by principles that all reasonable persons can

    accept.Dworkin denies that rights can be justified in either of these two

    ways, because he denies that rights are norms that can be justified

    without reference to a tradition or practice. This is implicit in what

    he calls the rights thesis, a thesis about the nature of legal and

    political rights. Political rights are creatures of both history and

    morality: what an individual is entitled to have, in civil society,

    depends on both the practice and the justice of its political institu-

    tions.54 This of course is a statement about legal or political rights

    and thus it would be unfair to treat it as a statement of Dworkins

    view about moral rights. However, since the connection between

    constructive interpretation and morality has already been noted, thispassage is relevant to the current discussion. It shows how normative

    concepts are on Dworkins view justified by a practice of interpre-

    tation, a practice that makes the truth of interpretive claims, rather

    than truth, the basis for a moral judgment. On a Kantian view, strong

    sense rights are justified not as interpretive claims, but rather, as

    moral claims that appeal to reasons whose justification lies in a

    conception of practical reason and the moral point of view such

    reasons support.

    My position is that in order to support claims about deontological

    rights that have universal scope one must accept that the justificationfor such rights rests on a moral point of view that expresses a stand-

    point of practical reason that includes the idea of persons as free and

    equal. This is not to say that someone who defends a deontological

    yet non-universal conception of rights holds an incoherent position.

    Rather, I am arguing that if we claim that some rights are universal,

    then we cannot provide adequate support for such claims from the

    interpretive point of view.

    Interpretive claims can justify treating legal rights as deontolo-

    gical, yet an interpretive model of justification is not compatible

    with a conception of moral argument that tries to show that our

    judgments about universal rights establish both that such rightsare deontological and that such rights are universal. It would be a

    54 Dworkin (1977a, p. 87).

  • 7/30/2019 Mahoney - Objectivity, Interpretation, And Rights- A Critique of Dworkin

    25/36

    OBJECTIVITY AND INTERPRETATION 211

    mistake to claim that when an agent defends such a right, the only

    sense in which she ought to take the right to be fundamental is that

    it expresses her political communitys conception of its own moral

    integrity. Some legal rights do, of course, fit this conception, butit would be an odd claim indeed to say that an agent who asserts,

    people should not be tortured is offering an interpretive claim

    about her legal or moral tradition. If a social critic claims that a

    political community is unjust because it violates peoples rights, is

    this a claim about how members of that community fail to respect

    their own traditions? The fact that it might be hardly establishes

    that it must be. The method of constructive interpretation, however,

    suggests that claims about rights are only claims about how one

    type norm imposes constraints on people and institutions from the

    standpoint of a tradition. This seems clearly wrong in the case of

    those norms we call moral rights, for such norms are reasons foraction which bind agents independently of their social practices.

    IV. OBJECTIONS AND REPLIES

    There are a number of possible objections to my criticisms of

    Dworkin. I consider and respond to three. The first is that Dworkins

    conception of moral justification is more nuanced than Ive made

    it out to be and that there are features of his theory of justice

    that illustrate how for Dworkin questions of justification do notreduce to questions of interpretation. The second is that Kantian

    realism is vulnerable to skepticism. Thirdly, one could argue that

    the global authority of justice can be established by an interpre-

    tation of a particular legal and political practice and thus that the

    method of constructive interpretation is compatible with the idea of

    deontological rights with universal scope.55

    i. Dworkins Alternative

    Perhaps some norms are expressive of fundamental and universal

    conditions for human flourishing. An equality of resources56

    55 I thank a reviewer of this journal for helpful suggestions on how to char-

    acterize this point.56 Dworkin (2000a, pp. 65119).

  • 7/30/2019 Mahoney - Objectivity, Interpretation, And Rights- A Critique of Dworkin

    26/36

    212 JON MAHONEY

    argument might develop this idea as follows. First, the distribu-

    tion of social resources has a significant impact on persons life

    chances. Secondly, the distribution of economic and social resources

    is patterned by public policy choices rather than the market alone.Thirdly, a liberal democracy is founded upon an ideal of equality.

    Therefore, any pattern of distribution that results in someones

    disadvantage through no fault of her own is unjust. This is an

    example of an argument from Dworkins egalitarian liberalism that

    could be defended independently of the method of constructive

    interpretation. The general framework for distributive justice estab-

    lished by the moral ideal of equality is not necessarily dependent

    on an exercise in constructive interpretation. By analogy, one might

    defend a system of fundamental moral rights on the grounds that

    such rights are required by the conception of equality that is the

    foundation for liberal justice. Such a view could advance a numberof deontological rights with universal scope and all such rights could

    be justified on egalitarian liberal grounds.

    Dworkin offers some relevant commentary on this point when

    he claims that some normative concepts, justice, for instance, differ

    from those such as courtesy or negligence in that they are more

    complex and thus, . . . less useful as an analogy to law.57 This idea

    is spelled out in some detail in a lengthy footnote in Laws Empire.

    The most important difference between justice and courtesy, in this context, lies

    in the latent global reach of the former. People in my imaginary community use

    courtesy to report their interpretations of a practice they understand as localto them. They know that the best interpretation of their own practice would not

    necessarily be the best of the comparable practice of any other community. But

    if we take justice to be an interpretive concept, we must treat different peoples

    conceptions of justice, while inevitably developed as interpretations of practices

    in which they themselves participate, as claiming a more global or transcendental

    authority, that they can serve as the basis for criticizing other peoples practices

    of justice even, or especially, when these are radically different. The leeways

    of interpretation are accordingly much more relaxed: a theory of justice is not

    required to provide a good fit with the political or social practices of any particular

    community, but only with the most abstract and elemental convictions of each

    interpreter.58

    Isnt this a clear refutation of my argument that Dworkins under-

    standing of the moral justification for deontological rights cannot

    57 Dworkin (1986, p. 424).58 Ibid., pp. 424425.

  • 7/30/2019 Mahoney - Objectivity, Interpretation, And Rights- A Critique of Dworkin

    27/36

    OBJECTIVITY AND INTERPRETATION 213

    support norms with universal scope? On the surface, it would seem

    so. My objection claimed that Dworkins method of constructive

    interpretation and his modest moral realism fails to offer an adequate

    moral justification for universal rights. However, if justice is aspecial case among interpretive concepts because it can support

    claims with universal scope, then in principle, Dworkin should be

    able to derive universal rights from justice.

    Dworkin does claim that justice is an interpretive concept59

    yet adds an important qualification, namely, that some interpretive

    concepts purport to have global reach. Perhaps when people make

    claims about universal rights, their claims ought to be treated as

    having this characteristic. Since claims about justice can be under-

    stood to have a global reach, the claims people make on behalf of

    such concepts can be understood to be applicable across social prac-

    tices and traditions. What justifies the global reach of such concepts?Consider two possible characterizations of interpretive moral claims

    that purport to establish a universal right. One is that an agent is

    entitled to affirm a right with global reach because this is the best

    interpretation of her practice. Another is that she is entitled to affirm

    a right with global reach because this is the best interpretation of

    justice. If Dworkin opts for the first option, then he can consistently

    treat claims about justice as interpretive claims because such claims

    are about an identifiable practice. This option, however, entails that

    a local practice can provide a justification for norms that are binding

    beyond the practice. I explore some problems with this positionshortly.

    The second option would place enormous stress on the coherence

    of calling both legal and universal moral claims interpretive claims.

    For example, if the restrictions of fit do not preclude affirming a

    principle as just, the sense in which claims about justice are inter-

    pretive is rather unclear. This option does, however, have the virtue

    of showing how Dworkin might develop a conception of moral

    justification that can provide straightforward support for universal

    rights. Justice might be taken to be a special normative concept

    that by itself can justify claims with universal scope. Considered

    in conjunction with Dworkins view that judgments qualify as trueonly if our reflective convictions support them and the suggestion

    that we can relax the leeways of interpretations when it comes

    59 Dworkin (1986, p. 424).

  • 7/30/2019 Mahoney - Objectivity, Interpretation, And Rights- A Critique of Dworkin

    28/36

    214 JON MAHONEY

    to justice, this proposal would warrant a special priority for justi-

    fication in disputes about norms with universal scope. One could

    develop the thought that claims about justice appeal for their justi-

    fication to the most abstract and elemental convictions of eachinterpreter by claiming every interpretive exercise that concerns

    justice is subordinated to demands of practical reason that enjoin

    agents to accept reasons all can share. However, for this strategy

    to succeed, Dworkin would have to characterize the constraints on

    our reflective convictions in terms of reasons that potentially bind

    all reasonable persons. And if he accepts this, then the moral rather

    than interpretive point of view will be advanced as the source of

    justification for moral norms with universal scope in which case

    his conception of moral justification would be similar to the one

    preferred by Kantian realists.

    Since I have argued that constructive interpretation cannotprovide the proper foundation for universal rights, my objection

    could be met by a conception of justification for deontological rights

    with universal scope that advances a moral point of view. To accept

    this, however, is to jettison the idea that treating a moral claim as

    an interpretive claim tells us anything about the conditions for its

    justification. Later in the passage just cited, Dworkin does claim that

    justice is a constraint on interpretive claims. This implies that there

    is a peculiar sense in which the concept of justice is not an inter-

    pretive concept; perhaps interpretations of justice are answerable to

    moral truisms about human nature. Although it seems in tensionwith central features of his work on legal and political philosophy,

    and contrary to his modest moral realism, Dworkin does claim

    that:

    Interpretations of justice cannot themselves appeal to justice, and this helps

    explain the philosophical complexity and ambition of many theories of justice.

    For once justice is ruled out as a point of fundamental and pervasive political

    practice, it is natural to turn for a justification to initially non-political ideas, like

    human nature or the theory of the self, rather than to other political ideas that

    seem no more important or fundamental than justice itself.60

    Dworkin puts this idea to use in a comment about how justice is

    a constraint on associative obligations.61 He also claims that inter-

    60 Ibid., p. 425.61 Ibid., p. 202.

  • 7/30/2019 Mahoney - Objectivity, Interpretation, And Rights- A Critique of Dworkin

    29/36

    OBJECTIVITY AND INTERPRETATION 215

    pretation is in part a matter of justice62 thereby suggesting there are

    moral constraints on constructive interpretation that are not simply

    competing interpretive claims.

    I am very sympathetic to this aspect of Dworkins position. Itis compatible with a conception of moral justification that treats

    reasons whose moral authority does not depend on a local practice as

    the grounds for judgments about moral claims with universal scope.

    But how, exactly, are we to understand the concept of justice if it

    is treated both as an interpretive concept defended by exercises in

    constructive interpretation and also as a concept whose content is

    answerable to facts about the self or human nature? Granted that

    I have not misconstrued Dworkins position, it is not clear how to

    characterize the conception of justification that his comments about

    the status of fundamental moral concepts like justice suggest. These

    considerations do, however, suggest that Dworkins position on theissue of whether some claims about normative concepts can be

    defeated by other claims that are not properly speaking interpretive

    claims (e.g., claims about human nature) should be characterized

    with some caution. I have been arguing for a Kantian foundation

    for deontological rights. Dworkin would apparently prefer to rely

    on a theory of human nature, an approach better suited for his non-

    contractarian view of justice. Each approach could be advanced as

    providing the moral foundations for universal rights.

    I concede that some features of Dworkins position could be

    developed in favor of a more robust form of moral realism than themodest realism that I have attributed to him.63 It is unclear whether

    an approach to justice and rights that relies on a theory of human

    nature can be reconciled with the account of objectivity Dworkin

    defends in Objectivity and Truth without raising the specter of

    external skepticism, but this hardly counts as an objection. At the

    same time, Dworkins own comments on the relationship between

    justice and interpretation are ambiguous and thus its implications

    will vary depending on where the emphasis is placed. One point

    62 Ibid., p. 203.63 Dworkin (2000b, pp. 221222) considers in passing a conception of moral

    objectivity that could be used as the basis for a theory of moral rights thatare grounded in more substantive commitments than those that are argued for

    in most of Dworkins work. This position, however, though alluded to is not

    systematically developed.

  • 7/30/2019 Mahoney - Objectivity, Interpretation, And Rights- A Critique of Dworkin

    30/36

    216 JON MAHONEY

    that merits special emphasis is that as long as Dworkins position

    is construed as an interpretive model of justification, one that treats

    the grounds or justification for moral claims as invariably a kind

    of interpretive claim, there will be good reasons to worry about itsability to provide a justification for universal human rights.

    ii. Kantian Realism and Skepticism

    Dworkins modest realism is in part motivated by the claim that

    traditional forms of realism fail. Though he does not discuss Kantian

    realism in Objectivity and Truth his objections to traditional forms

    of moral realism could have been aimed at Kantian realism. Ive

    already noted that I believe Dworkin overstates the case against

    traditional moral realism. Here I offer a brief argument for why

    the Kantian justification for deontological rights defended in thispaper yields to neither of the versions of skepticism considered by

    Dworkin.

    Kantians, as Korsgaard puts it, defend the view that . . . a reason

    derives its normative force for an agent from a perspective provided

    her by her identification with a principle of choice.64 Some reasons,

    call them deontological reasons, carry with them a special, over-

    riding normative force and are such that their authority commands

    the assent of all reasonable persons. Korsgaard calls this procedural

    moral realism in contrast to substantive moral realism.65 Proced-

    ural moral realism claims that moral claims are true or false and

    that we can determine whether they are by applying a procedural

    test. This is the only kind of realism that a Kantian has to embrace.

    Kantian realism affirms the view that a moral claim is true if it

    can be justified by a reason that can be shared by all reasonable

    persons. Though there are a number of similarly formulated versions

    of this test, the Categorical Imperative, Rawlss method of reflective

    equilibrium, and the point of view adopted by persons willing to

    64 Korsgaard (1996, p. 246). Kosrgaards reasons for rejecting substantive

    moral realism are similar to Dworkins reasons for rejecting traditional moral

    realism (see Korsgaard (1996, pp. 3440)). In contrast to Dworkin, she defends

    the Kantian idea that reasons and moral principle are sufficient to establish thetruth of a moral claim. No exercise in constructive interpretation is required to

    test a moral claim.65 Ibid., p. 35.

  • 7/30/2019 Mahoney - Objectivity, Interpretation, And Rights- A Critique of Dworkin

    31/36

    OBJECTIVITY AND INTERPRETATION 217

    affirm as moral only those reasons that all reasonable persons can

    accept, one basic idea is common to each version of procedural

    moral realism: procedural moral realists affirm the idea that a justi-

    fied moral reason is one that can be jointly affirmed by all in amanner respectful of the autonomy and dignity of each.

    Substantive moral realism, by contrast, affirms the existence of

    intrinsically normative entities such as Platonic forms or moral

    properties. Though procedural moral realism is defended as a less-

    controversial alternative to substantive moral realism, and thus,

    like Dworkins modest realism is motivated in part by the aim of

    responding to skepticism, procedural moral realism is still a more

    robust kind of realism than the version Dworkin prefers. Compared

    to procedural moral realism, Dworkins method of constructive

    interpretation and the modest realism defended in Objectivity and

    Truth is even more modest; too modest, in fact.This Kantian view of universal rights claims that someone who

    argues for a right is providing a reason, a reason that enjoins,

    forbids, or permits an action depending on the right. These features

    enjoining, forbidding, permitting of arguments about universal

    rights suggests that sometimes the demands of reason exceed what

    an interpretation of a tradition can support. In other words, claims

    about universal rights presuppose a moral point of view that is

    answerable to a conception of truth that amounts to more than

    reflective convictions informed by an exercise in constructive inter-

    pretation. Moral claims with universal scope are justified becauseof the reasons which support them; and these reasons are justified, if

    they are, independently of interpretive questions. Therefore, in order

    to establish that appeals to such rights are legitimate when we argue

    about traditions or practices, rights should be understood as norms

    that can be affirmed from the standpoint of practical reason rather

    than the interpretive point of view.

    Moreover, Kantian realism is immune to moral skepticism. It

    avoids external skepticism by advancing a conception of moral

    argument and justification that treats moral claims as claims within

    morality. Like Dworkins view, it stresses the idea that only a moral

    argument defeats a moral argument. It avoids internal skepticism byaffirming a theory of practical reason that treats reasons for action

    as considerations for action open to public and rational examination

  • 7/30/2019 Mahoney - Objectivity, Interpretation, And Rights- A Critique of Dworkin

    32/36

    218 JON MAHONEY

    by agents who want to find moral principles compatible with moral

    equality and human dignity. However, Kantian realism offers a more

    explicit conception of moral justification, a conception that emphas-

    izes moral reasons, the principles that support them, and the capacityfor practical reason that gives reasons priority over convictions. This

    conception of moral justification can, whereas Dworkins cannot,

    show how a norm with universal scope is justified when the reasons

    for it are reasons that command universal assent.

    iii. Justification and Universalism

    I have been arguing that the attempt to reconcile the global authority

    of claims about justice with constructive interpretation reveals an

    unresolved tension in Dworkins philosophy. A third possible objec-

    tion to my argument tries to resolve this tension in a way that Ihave not yet considered. It argues that an exercise in constructive

    interpretation, though an interpretation of a local practice, might

    nevertheless provide a justification for moral norms with universal

    scope. On this view, one would try to argue that an interpretation

    of one social practice could yield a justification for norms whose

    application is global. This strategy has at least two related problems,

    one practical, the other conceptual.

    On my view, moral universalism requires a conception of justi-

    fication that appeals to reasons that transcend social practices.

    Universal rights, for instance, presuppose for their justification,

    reasons that all reasonable persons can share. Consider one practical

    implication of a position that denies this. Someone who denies that

    some moral reasons can be shared by all reasonable persons, while

    at the same time affirming norms with global scope, holds a position

    that licenses the use of political and legal power without rational

    justification. On such a view, the enforcement of a universal right,

    for example, can be regarded as justified even though there is in-

    principle no rational justification for the use of power by those legal

    and political institutions that enforce the right.

    There is no reason to deny that a normative concept with

    universal scope can originate in a local practice. However, thereis good reason to reject the inference from the fact that a norm

    with universal scope can be affirmed on the basis of an interpre-

    tation of a local practice to the claim that the norm is justified

  • 7/30/2019 Mahoney - Objectivity, Interpretation, And Rights- A Critique of Dworkin

    33/36

    OBJECTIVITY AND INTERPRETATION 219

    because it is affirmed by an interpretation of such a practice. This

    is a conceptual point about the nature of justification. The criteria

    that an agent appeals to in order to justify a norm with universal

    scope cannot be criteria of justification because they are standardsaccepted within her social practices. There are of course local stand-

    ards for justifying norms that lack universal scope, standards for

    evaluating claims about etiquette for instance, but agents who appeal

    to these standards do not purport to establish norms with universal

    scope.66

    One might try to argue from an interpretive point of view that

    some rights have universal scope because such rights are justified

    by the best interpretation of a specific political tradition. However,

    persons who do not participate in such a tradition can reason-

    ably reject a justification whose professed basis is the practice in

    question. So if the grounds or justification for a norm is one thatreasonable persons can reject, the scope of such a norm cannot be

    universal. All of this assumes, of course, the difference between a

    de facto or assumed justification and a justification that satisfies

    the normative requirements for moral justification. The denial of

    this distinction, however, comes at a serious cost. Without it, one

    is no longer entitled to profess a moral position. Ones entitlement

    to claim of a normative concept that it has global reach cannot be

    based on an interpretation of a particular social practice. Rather, one

    is entitled to affirm a norm with global reach only if the reason for

    it is one that all reasonable people can accept.

    V. CONCLUSION

    The following is intended to be a straightforward, though admittedly

    compressed, argument for the position defended in this paper. First,

    66 I am convinced that Dworkin does not make this conceptual mistake. His

    comments about justice in the passage cited above (p. 26) show that he believes

    claims about justice . . . can serve as the basis for criticizing other peoples prac-

    tices of justice . . . (Dwor