kant and sade 01

Upload: chun-hsiung-chen

Post on 07-Apr-2018

226 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/3/2019 Kant and Sade 01

    1/10

    AH/HFrlazi

    B: Springhero

    Of all the couples in the history of modern thought (Freud and Lacan, Marx and Lenin...), Kant and Sade

    is perhaps the most problematic: the statement "Kant is Sade" is the "infinite judgement" of modern

    ethics, positing the sign of equation between the two radical opposites, i.e. asserting that the sublime

    disinterested ethical attitude is somehow identical to, or overlaps with, the unrestrained indulgence in

    pleasurable violence.

    A.

    infinite judgement

    B.

    , infinite judgement

    A lot-everything, perhaps-is at stake here: is there a line from Kantian formalist ethics to the cold-blooded

    Auschwitz killing machine? Are concentration camps and killing and genocides as a neutral business the

    inherent outcome of the enlightened insistence on the autonomy of Reason?

    A.

    B.

    as a neutral business

    Is there at least a legitimate lineage from Sade to Fascist torturing, as is implied by Pasolini's film version

    of Sal, which transposes it into the dark days of Mussolini's Sal republic?

  • 8/3/2019 Kant and Sade 01

    2/10

    A. Sal

    B. 120

    Sal

    This link between Sade and Kant was first developed by Adorno and Horkheimer ( A/H) in the

    ( deservedly ) famous Excursion II ( Juliette or Enlightenment and Morals) of the Dialectic of

    enlightenment : A?Hs fundamental thesis is that the work of Marquis de Sade displays the

    Reason which is not led by another agency , that is is to say, the bourgeois subject, liberated from

    a state of not yet being mature.

    A.

    B:

    Some fifteen years later, Lacan ( without knowing about A/Hs version ) also developed this link first in his

    Seminar on The Ethics of Psychoanalysis (1958-59), [1] and then in the crits "Kant with Sade" of 1963.

    [2]

    A. (1958-59) [1] 1963

    [2]

    B.

    (1958-59) [1] 1963

    [2]

    II

    How, then, does Lacan stand in regard to the A/ H version of Kant with Sade ( i.e. of Sade as the truth of

    Kantian ethics)? For Lacan also, Sade consequently deployed the inherent potential of the Kantian

    philosophical revolution, although Lacan gives to this a somewhat different twisthis point is that Sade

    honestly externalized the Voice of Conscience. ( which, in Kant, attests the subject s full ethical

    autonomy, i.e. is self-posited/ imposed by the subject ) in the Executioner who terrorizes/tortures the

    victimThe first association here is, of course: what's all the fuss about?

    A. Voice of Conscience

    B.

  • 8/3/2019 Kant and Sade 01

    3/10

    Voice of Conscience

    Today, in our postidealist Freudian era, doesn't everybody know what the point of the "with" is : the truth

    of Kant's ethical rigorism is the sadism of the Law, i.e. the Kantian Law is a superego agency that

    sadistically enjoys the subject's deadlock, his inability to meet its inexorable demands, like the proverbial

    teacher who tortures pupils with impossible tasks and secretly savors their failings?

    A.

    C.

    the sadism of the Law

    what the point of the "with" is "with" Kant with Sade

    Rigorism

    The moral teaching which holds that when there is a conflict of two

    opinions, one in favor of the law, the other in favor of liberty, the

    law must always be observed, even if the opinion in favor of liberty

    is the more probable or very probable one as compared with its

    opposite.

    Lacan's point, however, is the exact opposite of this first association: it is not Kant who was a closet

    sadist, it is Sade who is a closet Kantian. That is to say, what one should bear in mind is that the focus of

  • 8/3/2019 Kant and Sade 01

    4/10

    Lacan is always Kant, not Sade: what he is interested in are the ultimate consequences and disavowed

    premises of the Kantian ethical revolution.

    A.

    D.

    ;

    This first association it is not Kant who was a closet sadist, it is Sade

    who is a closet Kantian. this first association Closet to describe people who want to keep some fact about themselves secret

    02

    AH/HFrlazi

    B: Springhero

    In other words, Lacan does not try to make the usual "reductionist" point that every ethical act, as pureand disinterested as it may appear, is always grounded in some "pathological" motivation (the agent's

    own long-term interest, the admiration of his peers, up to the "negative" satisfaction provided by the

    suffering and extortion often demanded by ethical acts);

    A.

    B.

    the focus of Lacan's interest rather resides in the paradoxical reversal by means of which desire itself (i.e.

    acting upon one's desire, not compromising it) can no longer be grounded in any "pathological" interests

    or motivations and thus meets the criteria of the Kantian ethical act, so that "following one's desire"

    overlaps with "doing one's duty." Suffice it to recall Kant's own famous example from his Critique of

    Practical Reason:

  • 8/3/2019 Kant and Sade 01

    5/10

    E.

    F.

    the focus of Lacan's interest rather resides in the paradoxical reversal by means of

    which desire itself (i.e. acting upon one's desire by means of which which

    he paradoxical reversal A

    reductionist

    Suppose that someone says his lust is irresistible when the desired object and opportunity are

    present. Ask him whether he would not control his passions if, in front of the house where he has this

    opportunity, a gallows were erected on which he would be hanged immediately after gratifying hislust. We do not have to guess very long what his answer may be."3

    A.

    B.

    Lacan's counterargument here is that we certainly do have to guess what his answer may be : what if we

    encounter a subject (as we do regularly in psychoanalysis), who can only fully enjoy a night of passion if

    some form of "gallows" is threatening him, i.e. if, by doing it, he is violating some prohibition? [3]

    A.

  • 8/3/2019 Kant and Sade 01

    6/10

    [3]

    C.

    [3]

    There was an Italian film from the 60's, Casanova 70, starring Virna Lisi and Marcello Mastroianni that

    hinged on this very point: the hero can only retain his sexual potency if doing "it" involves some kind of

    danger.

    A. 60 Virna LisiMarcello Mastroianni 70Casanova 70

    B.60 Virna LisiMarcello Mastroianni 70Casanova 70,

    ,

    At the film's end, when he is on the verge of marrying his beloved, he wants at least to violate the

    prohibition of premarital sex by sleeping with her the night before the wedding-however, his bride

    unknowingly spoils even this minimal pleasure by arranging with the priest for special permission for the

    two of them to sleep together the night before, so that the act is deprived of its transgressive sting. What

    can he do now?

    A.

    B. ,

    ,,

  • 8/3/2019 Kant and Sade 01

    7/10

    In the last shot of the film, we see him crawling on the narrow porch on the outside of the high-rise

    building, giving himself the difficult task of entering the girl's bedroom in the most dangerous way, in a

    desperate attempt to link sexual gratification to mortal danger

    A.

    B.

    So, Lacan's point is that if gratifying sexual passion involves the suspension of even the most elementary

    "egotistic" interests, if this gratification is clearly located "beyond the pleasure principle," then, in spite ofall appearances to the contrary, we are dealing with an ethical act, then his "passion" is stricto sensu

    ethical... [4]

    A.

    [4]

    B.

    [4]

    Lacan's further point is that this covert Sadean dimension of an "ethical (sexual) passion" is not read into

    Kant by our eccentric interpretation, but is inherent to the Kantian theoretical edifice. [5]

    A. Sadean

    ()

    B. Sadean

    ()

    this covert Sadean dimension of an "ethical (sexual) passion" ethical passion

    covert

  • 8/3/2019 Kant and Sade 01

    8/10

    inherent to

    the Kantian theoretical edifice

    If we put aside the body of "circumstantial evidence" for it (isn't Kant's infamous definition of

    marriage-"the contract between two adults of the opposite sex about the mutual use of each other's

    sexual organs"-thoroughly Sadean, since it reduces the Other, the subject's sexual partner, to a partial

    object, to his/her bodily organ which provides pleasure, ignoring him/her as the Whole of a human

    Person?), the crucial clue that allows us to discern the contours of "Sade in Kant" is the way Kant

    conceptualizes the relationship between sentiments (feelings) and the moral Law.

    A.

    /

    the Other/partial object/

    /

    B.

    /the Other/partial object

    //

    If we put aside the body of "circumstantial evidence" for it it ethicalsexualpassion

    "circumstantial evidence"

    .

    Although Kant insists on the absolute gap between pathological sentiments and the pure form of moral

    Law, there is one a priori sentiment that the subject necessarily experiences when confronted with the

    injunction of the moral Law, the pain of humiliation (because of man's hurt pride, due to the "radical Evil"

    of human nature);

    A.

  • 8/3/2019 Kant and Sade 01

    9/10

    B.

    there is one a priori sentiment that the subject necessarily experiences when confronted with the

    injunction of the moral Law, the pain of humiliation

    that the subject necessarily experiences a priori sentiment

    when the subject isconfronted with the injunction of the moral Law

    the pain of humiliationa priori sentiment the injunction of the moral Law,

    AB

    because of man's hurt pride, due to the "radical Evil" of human nature);

    because ofdue to and

    mans hurt pride mans hurt pride

    , the pain of humiliation

    the "radical Evil" of human nature);

    radical Evil

    In Religion within the Limits of Reason Alone, Kant discusses the

    concept of radical evil. The German word radikal derives from the Latin

    word rdx, which means root (Wurzel), origin (Ursprung), and

    source (Quelle) (Kluge 664). Therefore, when Kant explains the

    nature of radical evil, he also tries to enquire into the origin of moral evil

    (Religion 35). Kant observes that the source of evil . . . can lie only in a

    rule made by the will for the use of its freedom, that is, in a maxim (17).

    In Critique of Practical Reason, Kant makes a similar statement which

    echoes this observation. He writes that the concept of good and evil

    must not be determined before the moral law . . . but only . . . after it and

    by means of it (54). Therefore, in order to grasp the concept of evil, one

    has to understand the struggle in a pathologically affected human will,

    namely, the conflict of maxims with the practical laws cognized by

  • 8/3/2019 Kant and Sade 01

    10/10

    himself

    for Lacan, this Kantian privileging of pain as the only a priori sentiment is strictly correlative to Sade's

    notion of pain (torturing and humiliating the other, being tortured and humiliated by him) as the privileged

    way of access to sexual jouissance (Sade's argument, of course, is that pain is to be given priority overpleasure on account of its greater longevity-pleasures are passing, while pain can last almost

    indefinitely).

    A. /

    sexual jouissance

    B.

    /sexual jouissance

    C.

    the only a priori sentiment is

    only

    [email protected]

    http://springhero.wordpress.com

    mailto:[email protected]:[email protected]://springhero.wordpress.com/http://springhero.wordpress.com/http://springhero.wordpress.com/mailto:[email protected]