information giving and enactment of consent in written consent forms and in participants’ talk...

28
EMPIRICAL STUDY/ANALYSIS Information Giving and Enactment of Consent in Written Consent Forms and in Participants’ Talk Recorded in a Hospital Setting Marilena Fatigante Franca Orletti Ó Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2013 Abstract The paper examines the attainment and adequacy of informed consent in an ethnographic–discursive study on gynecological visits involving doctors, patients, and nurses. Starting from a theoretical discussion on informed consent and the principles upon which it relies, the paper highlights the changes and the adjustments that these principle undergo in practice, from the planning of the research till later stages of the researcher’s fieldwork and data recording. Analyses first focus on the informed consent as a written artifact and show how the description of the study indexes the prospective participants’ identity, as well as, it works in favor of the researcher’s (or, other institutional representatives such as the managers of the Hospital) accountability. Then, the authors focus on instances of audio and video recorded doctor–patient–nurse interactions in which information is reformulated by the doctors, in such a way as to anticipate and/or respond to the nurses’ and patients’ concerns with regards the project (such as, the risk of exposure to the public). The analysis of these episodes carry ethical implications, in that they alert that patients, nurses, and doctors may be not equally knowledgeable about the project and that they can be conceded unequal opportunities to have their inter- pretations and identity performances acknowledged and inscribed on the tape. Keywords Informed consent Rhetoric Recording Institutional asymmetry Medical visits M. Fatigante (&) University ‘‘Sapienza’’ of Rome, Via dei Marsi 78, 00185 Rome, Italy e-mail: [email protected] F. Orletti Third University of Rome, Via Ostiense 236, 00146 Rome, Italy 123 Hum Stud DOI 10.1007/s10746-013-9303-z

Upload: franca

Post on 23-Dec-2016

212 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

EMPI RICAL STUDY /ANA LY SIS

Information Giving and Enactment of Consentin Written Consent Forms and in Participants’ TalkRecorded in a Hospital Setting

Marilena Fatigante • Franca Orletti

� Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2013

Abstract The paper examines the attainment and adequacy of informed consent in

an ethnographic–discursive study on gynecological visits involving doctors,

patients, and nurses. Starting from a theoretical discussion on informed consent and

the principles upon which it relies, the paper highlights the changes and the

adjustments that these principle undergo in practice, from the planning of the

research till later stages of the researcher’s fieldwork and data recording. Analyses

first focus on the informed consent as a written artifact and show how the

description of the study indexes the prospective participants’ identity, as well as, it

works in favor of the researcher’s (or, other institutional representatives such as the

managers of the Hospital) accountability. Then, the authors focus on instances of

audio and video recorded doctor–patient–nurse interactions in which information is

reformulated by the doctors, in such a way as to anticipate and/or respond to the

nurses’ and patients’ concerns with regards the project (such as, the risk of exposure

to the public). The analysis of these episodes carry ethical implications, in that they

alert that patients, nurses, and doctors may be not equally knowledgeable about the

project and that they can be conceded unequal opportunities to have their inter-

pretations and identity performances acknowledged and inscribed on the tape.

Keywords Informed consent � Rhetoric � Recording � Institutional

asymmetry � Medical visits

M. Fatigante (&)

University ‘‘Sapienza’’ of Rome, Via dei Marsi 78, 00185 Rome, Italy

e-mail: [email protected]

F. Orletti

Third University of Rome, Via Ostiense 236, 00146 Rome, Italy

123

Hum Stud

DOI 10.1007/s10746-013-9303-z

Informed Consent in Theory and Practice

The debate on informed consent is huge and crosses several fields such as law,

medicine, sociology, philosophy, and more (see Katz 1984; Faden and Beauchamp

1986; for annotated bibliographies Sugarman et al. 1999, and, from 1998 to 2004,

Wiles et al. 1999, accessible at http://www.sociology.soton.ac.uk/Proj/Informed_

Consent/Resources.htm). It is in healthcare, biomedical contexts that informed

consent has developed and received the highest degree of formalization. Immedi-

ately after World War II, the main concern was to protect human beings from the

risk of being recruited as subjects in harmful experiments such as those perpetrated

by Nazis in concentration camps (Hazelgrove 2002; Weindling 2004; quoted in

Murphy and Dingwall 2007). Since then, clinical trials and biomedical research was

subjected to a strict and strongly bureaucratized ethical monitoring (Nuremberg

Code 1948; Declaration of Helsinki 1974), prescribing that the researcher explains

to the participants, as clearly and exhaustively as possible, the aims and procedures

of the study, the absence of any risks or discomforts for them, the expected benefits,

the measures to protect participants’ confidentiality and archive data in secure ways.

These principles were maintained by other codes of behavioral research, such as

the American Psychological Association’s Ethical Principles of Psychologists and

Code of Conduct (see http://www.apa.org/ethics/code/index.aspx?item=3).

Adequate information delivered to the participants by written consent forms

should ensure the respect of the participants’ autonomy, which Faden and

Beauchamp (1986: 239) posit as the encompassing principle of ethics in research,

even considering the right to privacy as ‘‘reducible to or derivative’’ (1986: 9) from

the autonomy principle. Acknowledging someone as an autonomous agent, in fact,

enables that person to exert exclusive control over personal data and any other

information that can be disclosed or used by the researcher, a problem that charges

the individual himself with the opportunity to evaluate whether or not anonymity is

a desirable aim (Hopkins 1993).

Routinely, informed consent and related issues such as, the discussion of

confidentiality, is gained ‘‘at the outset of the relationship,’’ and ‘‘thereafter as new

circumstances may warrant’’ (Code of Ethics APA 1992). Such ‘‘anticipatory’’

regulatory regime (Murphy and Dingwall 2007), poses—particularly for ethno-

graphic and observational studies—serious problems with regards to the adjustment

of the procedure to the practice, i.e., the live context in which the research takes

place. Apprehending what the research is about, and understanding the degree to

which they can perceive their private realm be over-exposed to external gaze,

cannot be limited to a single moment in time prior to the ‘‘beginning’’ of the

research. Marzano (2007) emphasizes that ‘‘by subordinating the conduct of

research to formal assent by the participants studied or by prior approval by the

committees, the proponents of deontological positions attribute to participants an

ability to make rational comparison of the costs and benefits of their involvement in

the research that is very difficult to perform at the beginning of the research (…)’’

(2007: 428).

As a matter of fact, what the participants understand and agree to regarding their

involvement in the research may be not fully apparent to them, and often to the

M. Fatigante, F. Orletti

123

researcher as well, until particular incidents happen, which threaten the relationship

of trust and respect the two parties mutually established at the start of the research

(Ellis 2007; Etherington 2007).

Furthermore, the displacement of the activity of consent—gaining at the outset of

the research course rules out the possibility to analyze how participants are

informed, how they manifest their understanding of the research instructions and

how they eventually express their agreement to participate.

Studies in Ethnomethodology and Conversation Analysis have analyzed routine

practices of gaining consent during recordings of telephone surveys (Maynard et al.

2010; Maynard and Schaeffer 2002), sociolinguistic observational studies (Mondada

2006), calls to services and organizations (Speer and Stokoe 2012), and face-to-face

interaction in a psychiatric setting (Speer and Stokoe 2012), all done while the

recording devices (as well as the data collection itself) were already ongoing. These

studies have explored how practices of gaining consent are handled in the

interaction in ways that may markedly differ from idealized protocols. Analyzing

the design of consent-gaining turns (typically formatted as announcements rather

than requests), Speer and Stokoe (2012) show how they ‘‘tilt research participants

towards assent’’ (2012: 15), something that holds true also for written forms of

requesting consent.

By opening the ‘‘methodological black box of informed consent’’ (Speer and

Stokoe 2012: 3) to overt investigation, these studies demonstrate the unavoidable

gaps between theoretical principles and actual practices of behaving ethically in

research.

Participants’ Concerns Arising in Audio and Video-Assisted Research

Studies that have analyzed participants’ orientation to the recording tools (Gordon

2012; Lomax and Casey 1998; Monahan and Fisher 2010; Speer 2002; Speer and

Hutchby 2003) have been revealing about both methodological and ethical aspects

embedded in giving consent to video- or audio-assisted research.

Aimed to contest the old prejudice about the non-naturalness of behaviors

produced when participants know they are being recorded (the observer’s paradox;

Labov 1972), these studies have turned the participants’ reactivity to the tape into an

analytical and hermeneutical resource for understanding what the participants treat

as morally relevant for them. Speer and Hutchby (2003) label as ‘‘tape-affected

speech’’ (2003: 321) sequences occasioned by the presence of the recording,

including episodes in which participants orient to the ‘‘inappropriateness of certain

kinds of talk’’ (2003: 325) and/or overtly express negative reactions (such as,

annoyance) to the recording technology. Rather than discarding these episodes, or

treating them as evidences of data contamination, these authors advocate the need

for analyzing them as ‘‘the situated ways in which research ethics and the morality

of recording are played out as participants’ concerns’’ (2003: 321).

Over the long-term audio recordings of American couples talking at home,

Gordon (2012) found how participants may comment about, through, or to the

Information Giving and Enactment of Consent

123

recorder, in both literal and non-literal ways. Similarly to Speer and Hutchby,

Gordon includes instances in which the recording is glossed as a burden or, within a

non-literal frame, as a spy-bug, a wire capable to exhibit sensitive aspects of

personal and family identity such as, political orientations.

If, on one hand, these instances may be heard to question the grounds upon which

the participants have expressed their consent at the beginning of the research, on the

other they show to be treated by participants themselves as interactional resources to

perform identity work, in Monahan and Fisher’s terms (2010), staged performances,

‘‘deeply revealing of how individuals perceive themselves and would like to be

perceived’’ (2010: 363). In this perspective, comments addressed to or about the

recorder, which make relevant its risky consequences for the morality of the

participants, are ways to inform the researcher about the participants’ reflexive

awareness of the research instruments; another tool by which informants exercise

their agency ‘‘to make sense of and influence researcher and research results’’

(Monahan and Fisher 2010: 362).

Participants though, may differ in their reactions to the tape or, as regards the

extent to which they can make their reactions evident and influential on the research

results.

Relevant to our topic, studies on the influence of videotaping in medical

consultations different, and sometimes inconsistent, results. Redman et al. (1989)

highlighted that doctors and patients markedly differ on a measure of perception

of behavioral efficacy when they were video recorded. Notably, the doctors

reported the feeling that their behaviour had been affected by the observation

more than patients did. Another study showed that in GP consultations, patients’

refusal to be video recorded was mainly accounted for reasons such as worrying

about being watched by others and embarrassment about the specific health

problem reported (Martin and Martin 1984). The same study also revealed how

patients were more willing to sign the consent form when they are ‘‘in the

territory of the doctor’’ rather than when the researcher handles the form to them.

Furthermore, patients who accept and sign the consent form, may still report

feeling uncomfortable by video recording afterwards (Coleman and Manku-Scott

1998; Coleman 2000).

These latter results hints to the fact that institutional hierarchy and power can

affect, and shape toward certain directions, what is otherwise expected as a

voluntary, autonomous choice of the individual (Katz 1984; Bain and MacKay

1995).

Grounding on the literature examined so far, the study discusses the process of

attainment of informed consent during an ethnographic research project carried out

in a gynecological unit of a public hospital in Italy, focusing on how aspects of the

consent were recalled and re-enacted during the recordings of the gynecological

consultations, involving patients, doctors, and nurses.

M. Fatigante, F. Orletti

123

The Study: Aim and Methodology

The study was carried out over the course of 1 year (2009–2010) in a Gynecology

Outpatient Department in an Italian public hospital. Data included the collection of

audio- and video-recorded gynecological visits with (mostly) pregnant patients.

For the aim of this paper, we examine two different kinds of data:

1. in the first section, we analyze written consent forms of the study, examining

how they were written and revised in consecutive versions;

2. in the second section, we analyze episodes from audio and video recorded

medical visits, in which the different participants (doctors, nurses, and patients)

make relevant issues associated with informed consent; this corpus includes

episodes in which participants refer to the loss of confidentiality that the audio

(or video) taping of their behavior can entail. As regards these episodes, we

particularly aim to examine what are the problems to which the participants

orient when they display attention to the research tasks and the recorder, and

how they deal with them.

As for the analysis of the letter accompanying the consent forms, we rely on the

theoretical and methodological framework of Discursive Psychology (Potter and

Wetherell 1987) and, particularly, on its recognition of the rhetorical ground of

descriptions (Billig 1987, 1991; Edwards 1994).

Transcripts of the video and audio recorded interactions in medical visits were

analyzed according to the principles of Conversation Analysis (Sacks et al. 1974;

Schegloff 2007), thus privileging in-depth analysis of the sequential structure (turn

by turn) of the event.

The Corpus

A total of 35 doctor–patient–nurse audiotaped interactions and 10 videotaped

interactions of gynecological visits were collected. The group of patients were either

expectant mothers or mothers who have just delivered their baby. Half of the

patients were native speakers of Italian, the rest were non-native speakers (coming

from different countries including Bangladesh, Morocco, Philippines, Peru,

Ecuador, India, Romania) talking fluently and understanding Italian in all cases

except three of them. Three different doctors (two men and one woman) participated

in the study. Medical visits lasted on average 180. Almost 25 % of the visits were

check up consultations conducted with the same patient. Informed consent was

collected before the beginning of the visit with only one exception, in which the

patient expressed her consent verbally prior to the visit and only signed the form

after that. When used, the video camera was oriented toward the desk, placed

sideways; given its position, it was able to capture the interaction as the doctor

interviewed the patient, in the front part of the room; the physical examination

(including weight measurement and body inspection) occurred instead in the back of

the room, separated by a curtain and invisible to the video camera.

Information Giving and Enactment of Consent

123

Prior to the collection of recordings of gynecological visits (which were only

allowed by the Director of the hospital few months later the admittance of the

researcher to conduct observations in the ward), the methodology included

fieldwork done by the researcher.

Analysis Section 1: The Crafting of the Consent Form

Some information on how the researcher (one of the author) had access to the

research site will provide a background to understand how the consent letter was

planned and its language formulated.

One of the doctors working in the hospital (kin-related to the researcher)

mediated access to the institution and brought the project to the attention of the

Head of Gynecology and Obstetrics. An appointment between the researcher and the

Head followed in July 2009. During this meeting, the overall objective of the study

was presented as follows: it was stated that we (researchers) wanted to examine

doctor–patient interactions as they would naturally develop during the gynecolog-

ical consultation in order to observe the communicative processes and find any

possible flaws, with particular regard to interaction with foreign patients. Due most

likely to the professional and personal trust between the Head and the doctor who

mediated the exchange, the proposal was immediately accepted and the Head

showed himself willing to help develop the project and facilitate communication

with the other institutional representatives (colleagues in the Ethical Committee of

the Hospital and the Administrative Manager), who were required to express formal

approval of the proposal.

As Pope (2005:1182) states, ‘‘ethical issues are magnified in medical settings, not

least the informed consent’’. As a matter of fact, a provisional draft of the informed

consent was the first document that the Department Head requested. A letter stating

the aims and procedures of the study and the request for authorization were then

prepared. We opted for an identical formulation of the consent form for both doctors

and patients, in that we chose to stress the ‘communication’ between them as the

focus of the research, not favoring either of the two sides. Informed consent forms

were translated into 9 languages, after considering the different ethnic and linguistic

backgrounds from which the patients participating in the study may plausibly

originate (according to reports by the Department Head and the other doctors):

English, French, Romanian, Tagalog, Chinese, Arabic, Spanish, Bangla, and Hindi.

Below is the informed consent form in its original format.

We numbered each paragraph in order to aid recall of the specific parts that were

later modified:

M. Fatigante, F. Orletti

123

Information Giving and Enactment of Consent

123

Although designed merely to inform the participants about the scope and

procedures of the study, it is immediately apparent that the letter does much more

than this. First of all, the letter frames the interlocutory context and indexes the

identities of the interlocutors: i.e., who is the author and who is the addressee. The

pronoun we, used at the very beginning (point 1), identifies the researchers as a

group, thus diffusing the responsibility of authorship and action over a plural

subject, of which the researcher present is thereby only a representative. This may

work as a rhetorical device that strengthens the likelihood that the addressee may

trust the interlocutor as a spokesperson (or partner) of a more authoritative subject.

Also, at point 3, there is a reference to the researchers’ knowledge and to previous

studies on the topics. Both these elements cast the researchers’ identity and

enterprise as a professional, scientific one, working again to enhance the reliability

of their proposal. As a matter of fact, science is commonly conceived as an

enterprise worthy of consideration and respect in its own right (Ziman 1978).

Furthermore, despite being addressed to doctors as well as to patients, the letter

displays the researchers’ efforts to take the patients’ perspective into particular

account and acknowledge the patients as the ultimate beneficiaries of the research

results. This is particularly evident in the wording of the last parts of paragraphs 3, 4,

and 10, marked in bold. Attention to the patients’ experience, their needs and

demands is explicitly stated and presented as both the reason motivating the study

(see the expressions ‘‘we know,’’ ‘‘we believe’’) and its ultimate, beneficial goal.

Beneficence for patients is also recalled in the reference to good treatment outcomes.

Overall, it seems that the first version of the informed consent letter was aimed at

gaining, in particular, patients’—more than doctors’—collaboration and support for

the project. This preference can be easily understood if one considers that

collaboration from health professionals was provided to the researcher quite

independently of the written consent: the researcher’s access was negotiated well

before, and the researcher had several other opportunities to inform the doctors and

obtain (or fail to obtain) their availability in participating in the study. Conversely, the

process of informing the patients was much more reliant on the written instructions in

M. Fatigante, F. Orletti

123

that the researcher would only meet them once, immediately prior to the visit, when

she asked for their authorization.

Whereas the first points of the letter appear to be inspired by the principle of

beneficence, points 6 and 7 seem to emphasize instead the autonomy principle, as

the participant is referred to as someone who authorizes and who is free to choose

whether or not to participate.

Notably, though, point 5 makes reference to the fact that the researchers themselves

have also asked for and obtained authorization from the official representatives of the

Hospital, the legitimate subject holding responsibility for the correct unfolding of the

institutional (i.e., clinical) activities of the ward. The sentence works in further

securing the researchers’ accountability (Garfinkel 1967; Heritage 1984; Buttny

1993), insofar as it declares that they have been formally entitled by the Hospital itself

to conduct their activity and, thus, they are not threatening agents.

The final section (point 8) contains a reference to the participants’ right to

privacy and to the researcher’s dutiful commitment to protect it. Interestingly,

whereas the epistemic responsibility for conducting the research has been attributed

to a collective subject, the legal responsibility for data protection is located onto one

single person, who is also the one who is materially visible to the participant. The

likelihood that someone self-nominates for a position of legal responsibility, even

accepting the risks connected to potential prosecutions if something goes wrong,

may be conceived as proportional to the likelihood that the person may be

considered responsible and trustworthy. The writing choices, then, help the

researcher to build a claim of reliability and trust, which may eventually affect the

participant’s likelihood of considering the option of authorizing the research.

Requests for permission to audio-record were prepared for doctors and patients as

follows:

Information Giving and Enactment of Consent

123

As regards the permission for using the data, the following was used:

M. Fatigante, F. Orletti

123

The language in the authorization forms provided above displays a particular

leaning towards the ethical concern of guaranteeing the participant enough

information for her to express free will in choosing whether or not to participate.

Information Giving and Enactment of Consent

123

The register of the authorization form is more ‘formal’ and neutral than the

summary of the project stated in the informative letter (Annex 1/a), and references

to specific laws and paragraph numbers are included. The neutral register makes

effective the attempt to avoid or reject ‘‘the rhetoric adornment’’ (Billig 1987: 4) of

communication and to forestall the risk that the recipient may lose his independence

in making a choice.

A special effort was made in order to make sure that the reader had fully

understood the information stated in the briefing. Terms such as ‘‘examine,’’

‘‘read,’’ and ‘‘understand’’ are mentioned in series, scaffolding the participant’s

attention and making sure that he only comes to a decision (as to whether or not to

participate) with full knowledge of what such consent implies.

The Ethical Committee of the Hospital gathered on October 19th 2009. Revisions

of the informed consent were requested: the Ethical Committee asked us to better

specify the research aims and describe the data collection procedures in more detail

in the informative letter (paragraphs 3 and 5); they also required that specific

reference to the Ethical Code on Personal Data Protection and a guarantee of secure

data storage be included (see paragraphs 7 and 9).

We report below the second version of the informative letter, sent after the

revision. Substantial changes to the previous version are marked in bold.

M. Fatigante, F. Orletti

123

Information Giving and Enactment of Consent

123

As can be observed, in the revised version the references to the personal,

ideological commitment of the researchers (‘‘we know’’ and ‘‘we believe’’ in

paragraph 3 of the first version of the letter) have been erased, in favor of a clear

statement of the aims and objectives of the research (‘‘the aim of the study’’; the

‘‘overall purpose of the study’’; paragraphs 3 and 4 of the revised letter). Also,

procedures of data collection were described in more detail (par. 5).

In the second version of the form, the researchers also add more specificity about

the kind of analysis they will conduct on the data. They wrote: ‘‘The conversations,

collected as such, will be transcribed and analyzed with exclusive attention to their

linguistic and discursive features’’ (point 5 of the revised letter).

This is quite a critical point: what does it mean to conduct an analysis of

linguistic and discursive features exclusively? How is it possible to overlook the

content of what is said, once every single word produced by the participants has

been recorded and transcribed? The perspective followed by the researchers (trained

in Conversation Analysis) alerts them to consider the form and sequential structure

of the talk as more informative—and relevant for the analytic aims of the stated

approach—than any content analysis of the talk. Still, to look at the form cannot

M. Fatigante, F. Orletti

123

prevent them from hearing what people say. This is a dilemma that cannot be

avoided and cannot be erased by the quite vague—elliptic—expression at point 5.

Besides this specification, more details were provided with regards to the

legislation to which the researchers adhere (parr. 7 and 9).

The researchers responded in this way to the concern voiced by members of the

Ethical Committee and the Administrative Manager about the threat of procedures

that risked over-exposing the privacy of patients. Because the study involved

audio and video recordings, and given that data related to health status are among

the most sensitive data that may be collected from individuals, the institutional

representatives were particularly concerned with ensuring protective measures

against the risk of participants being identified, namely, anonymization. The

choice of a technical, procedural lexicon works here to strengthen vis a vis the

addressee the identity of the researcher as a knowledgeable, responsible, and

trustful agent.

The analysis of the written forms of consent shows, then, how giving information

is never a straightforward, neutral activity. The changes that the written letter and

authorization forms underwent during negotiations between the researchers and the

managing directors of the Hospital reveal the researchers’ attempts to strengthen

their accountability as professional members, acting ethically towards their

interlocutors, either the institutional representatives of the Hospital, and the patients

as prospected participants.

Descriptions of the study aims and procedures are inevitably constructed as

rhetorical discourses, allowing the researchers to perform identity work and pursue

particular social, interpersonal aims: while emphasizing the expected beneficial

outcomes of the study, the researchers attempt to enhance affiliation with the

interlocutors and make them part of a shared enterprise that would be equally

profitable for the participants and for themselves; while referring to legal articles on

privacy, the researchers attempt to secure themselves as trustful interlocutors, aware

of the judicial value of their assertions and commitment they make with the

participants.

Both strategies work to build and maintain a relationship of overall solidarity and

trust between the researchers and the participants, which may favor the opportunity

that these latter, at least, consider authorizing the study as an option.

Analysis Section 2: Informed Consent in Action

As Faden and Beauchamp (1986) stress, ‘‘[s]ubstantial understanding demands

apprehension of all the material and important descriptions—not all the possible

descriptions…’’ (1986: 304). By ‘‘material’’ the authors indicate that information

which is considered relevant according to a subjective criterion of the participant,

that is, according to the set of norms, preferences, and values which constitute the

moral framework of that particular individual.

A series of episodes selected from the audio and video recorded interactions

show how the participants express their concerns about their talk being recorded.

Information Giving and Enactment of Consent

123

These episodes show that not all material descriptions were provided in the

informed consent by the researcher.

In the following excerpt from an audio recorded interaction, the patient, the

doctor, and the nurse have engaged in a sequence of ‘‘small talk’’ (Coupland 2000)

regarding the advantages and disadvantages of delivering the baby at the end of the

current year or at the beginning of the next (the patient’s pregnancy’s full term falls

exactly on December 31st). The nurse, in particular, had voiced her opinion that to

deliver at the end of the year would be a definitive misfortune in that the newborn

would be doomed to be attributed 1 year more when in fact he is only a few days or

even a few hours older than people who are attributed 1 year less. That comment

had solicited the doctor’s amused reaction. At this point, the nurse expresses her

wish that the researcher would ‘‘cancel’’ parts of the data.

The nurse’s comment opening the exchange is an example of what Speer and

Hutchby (2003) call as ‘‘tape-affected speech’’. These authors looked at the precise

ways in which participants react to being recorded and consider them as instances of

‘‘situated morality,’’ defined as the set of ethical preoccupations (such as, concerns

related to rules of proper demeanor in public) which cannot be formulated in

principle but, rather, emerge as participants’ concerns are made relevant in talk.

Coming immediately after the sequence of small talk in which she has engaged,

the nurse’s formulation marks the recorder as a risky tool in revealing awkward

performances—in that they depart from an expected professional demeanor—to a

wider audience. Her turn reveals her orientation regarding the extent to which the

anonymity of their data and talk will be preserved.

M. Fatigante, F. Orletti

123

Underlying the nurse’s comment, though, is not only a concern regarding her

public image as a sensitive issue. There is also her interpretation that only certain

data are good and useful for the research purposes; mundane assessments, personal

opinions, and, generally, talk that is not professionally relevant seems to be

considered negative and trivial, such that it needs to be removed from the ‘‘official’’

data that will constitute the object of the research.

The doctor responds to the nurse’s comment with extended laughter (line 2);

treating it as a laughable, she soothes the seriousness of her claim. Further, she

contrasts the nurse’s interpretation, maintaining that the sequence that the nurse is

referring to is still part of communication and in this sense it needs not be discarded.

The negotiation between the doctor and the nurse ends quite rapidly: the doctor puts

the argument to a close (alright, line 4), normalizing the episode as something that

can be expected (after all) and pursuing the nurse’s agreement by means of the tag

question at the end of the turn (Heritage and Raymond 2005). We do not have

access to possible multimodal displays of the nurse’s agreement or disagreement,

but we know that she does not continue, accepting the doctor’s turn as a termination

of the topic. The patient too, orients to the closing of the activity by initiating the

greeting exchange, and thanking the doctor for the visit. In the way in which the

doctor cuts short the nurse’s concerns, and the nurse does not insist, this episode

makes relevant the institutional distribution of entitlement to action among the

participants in the medical visit. As a matter of fact, the nurse’s wish cannot be

satisfied, insofar as the participants consented to the video recordings of the ‘‘visit’’.

The doctor’s response defends the procedure, and aids the researcher’s interest of

saving as much data as possible and avoiding data deletion, which the nurse’s wish,

inscribed on the tape, would entail.

This can be discussed as evidence that the doctor, in the absence of the

researcher, acts as her ally, employing rhetorical strategies to face the other

participants’ concerns.

In the next excerpt, the doctor anticipates and neutralizes the concern that may

(potentially) arise from a patient, about being subject to the researcher’s external

scrutiny. The researcher has momentarily left the room1 in order to recruit patients

who were expected to arrive later in the morning, and inform them about the

research.

1 Once the data collection started, it was decided that the researcher would stay in the room while the

consultation was recorded. This condition was negotiated between the researcher and the doctors, as these

latter expressed their preference for having the researcher physically identifiable by and accessible to the

patients.

Information Giving and Enactment of Consent

123

a

a meaning, the researcher

The excerpt originates from a case in which the participants

interpreted differently some of the information given by the researcher: the

researcher had mentioned to her informants (both doctors and patients)

M. Fatigante, F. Orletti

123

the possibility that she could recruit the same patients across consecutive

visits.2

The doctor (not shown in the transcript) interpreted these as part of the research

protocol and delivered this information as such to the patient in the room. The

sequence opening between lines 1–5 casts the researcher as someone who

apparently did not understand or fully acknowledge what the participants told

her. The doctor’s turn ‘‘the lady has given the consent but’’ (line 1) makes clear that,

in the doctor’s understanding, the formal authorization is only a partial

accomplishment, in that further events will prevent the researcher’s aims (as

interpreted by the doctor) from being properly fulfilled. The patient aligns to this

version, as she underlines that she had informed and warned the researcher about the

fact that she was about to deliver, so she would have not been available a second

time to contribute to the research project as a pregnant patient. Note that the

patient’s choice of the word warned to refer to what she told the researcher implies a

certain degree of complaint from her part, toward the researcher’s inability to

understand or inattention.

Soon after this sequence, the doctor, unsolicited, adds in a formulation of the

nature of the study (line 6). Several adverbs she uses (by the way, actually) display

her attempt to reassure the patient about the non-harmfulness of the recordings (and

the research overall), and normalize the effects of the study on the patient’s

experience.

As a matter of fact, she had solicited the patient’s complaint that the researcher

had not attended to what she told her. Now, she orients instead toward a

minimization of the implications of this failure, emphasizing that the interest of the

study is only restricted to the limited, and local sphere of the communication they

have (lines 6–8).

The use of the extreme case formulation (Pomerantz 1986; Edwards 2000) at line

7 (‘‘it has nothing to do’’) is also interesting. It appears quite similar to that

employed in the informed consent discussed earlier, when the form referred that the

analysis would be conducted ‘‘with exclusive attention to linguistic and discursive

features’’ (paragraph 5 of the revised letter). In rephrasing the study details, then, the

doctor seems to use the same argumentative move, aimed at reducing the

threatening quality of the research as a self-exposing and possibly exploitative

activity.

The way in which the doctor frames the researcher’s analysis is also interesting.

She labels it in terms of a ‘‘communicational analysis’’. The adjective communi-

cational is quite rare in ordinary language and there is a lack of consensus as to

whether it can be considered a correct Italian word at all. When used, it is associated

with a specialized register, such as certain theoretical and practical approaches to

communication in sociology or psychology, or bureaucratic and administrative

language (Fortis 2005). Viewed as such, the doctor’s choice of communicational

2 According to the hypothesis of the researcher (not mentioned to the patients), which guided the design

of the study, collecting data over an extended period of time from the same patients would provide the

possibility to compare and analyze possible changes and developments in the patient’s communicative

and health literacy skills, as the pregnancy unfolded and the chances to discuss pregnancy-related matters

with the doctors improved.

Information Giving and Enactment of Consent

123

instead of the more common communicative would place the researcher’s interest at

such a high, ‘‘technologized’’ level of specialization that the chances that her actions

may overlap or impinge effectively on the patient’s experience would be

diminished. This is further stressed at line 7, as the doctor asserts that what the

analysis will target ‘‘has nothing to do with what we do’’. In this way, she rules out

the hypothesis that the researcher is interested in the effective medical practice the

doctor and the patient are engaged. By displacing the interest of the researcher onto

the level of ‘‘communication’’ only, the doctor addresses—and attempts to

prevent—the patient’s potential concern of having her health and her body exposed

to an external gaze; this would imply an harm to her right to confidentiality.

The patient, similarly to the nurse in excerpt 1, ratifies the doctor’s interpretation,

without pursuing the argument further. By repeating twice that she was informed by

the researcher herself, she concurs to repair the breach in the researcher’s

accountability and trustfulness that the event recounted has generated.

To sum up, we have seen in both excerpts how participants recall, during the

audio or video recorded visits, the conditions they have stipulated in the informed

consent.

When made relevant, it was the doctor who reasserted the aims and procedures

implied in the research instructions, anticipating and reassuring the other

participants about the benignity of the research.

The management of research-related tasks and activities (for which the

researcher, and not the doctors, should be held accountable) among participants,

then, indexes the asymmetrical, institutional distribution of roles and authority

between doctors, the nurses and the patients in the medical visit.

The episodes analyzed so far raise a double concern for the researcher: first, one

may question to what extent the participants have been made aware about the kind

of use (e.g., analysis, dissemination) that the researcher will make of the data. The

nurse’s comment in excerpt 1 reveals that she had imagined that only work-related

talk would be taken as object of analysis whereas, as scholars in the analysis of

doctor–patient interactions (among others) know, small talk or other ‘‘non-

instrumental’’ sequences of actions regularly provide the basis for relevant

analytical claims (see, among others, Maynard and Hudak 2008). In the consent

letter, the restriction of the research’s interest to ‘‘doctor-patient’’ communication

and the emphasis devoted to the efficacy of the communication may have

legitimately obscured the likelihood that any instance of talk, also including the

nurse or other participants who have delivered their consent, would be observed and

analyzed. Secondly, the excerpts show evidence that in both cases the doctor, in the

absence of the researcher, acts as her ally, reassuring about the non-harmfulness of

the recordings (and the research overall), strengthening then the likelihood that the

participants would not express resistance to—or simply doubts about—the use of

data, and eventually repairing (excerpt 2) to momentary breaches in the researcher’s

accountability.

Given that the doctor’s behavior has an influential character on the other

participants’ responses (Martin and Martin 1984), this raises a doubt with regard to

the likelihood that all participants in the medical visit can be given equal

opportunities to consent to research in full autonomy and with no external influence.

M. Fatigante, F. Orletti

123

Another set of episodes, regarding the participants’ orientation to the recording

device, shows how doctors entitle themselves to engage with the researchers and the

research apparel in a different, more authoritative way, as compared to nurses, and

patients.

Staged Performance in the Hearing Space of the Tape

We found a few number of episodes, in different visits, in which participants overtly

gloss the presence of the recorder. Consistently, it is the nurse, rather than the

doctor, who makes this concern explicit.

We show only one of these instances.

The episode starts as the pregnant patient reports a ‘‘bad experience’’ that she had

with a certain doctor working in the hospital, whose name is ‘‘Marini’’ (fictional

name). Specifically, the referred doctor gave her a wrong diagnosis and made her

feel very anxious, so much that she could not sleep, for several days. The patient is

Ecuadorian and she mispronounces the doctor’s name converting the original name

‘‘Marini’’ into ‘‘Marines’’ (accordingly to the Latin habit for which many names

terminate with an ‘‘s’’). This error is repeatedly recalled in the interaction in favor of

the possibility that the participants can tease the absent party, i.e., the doctor whose

name has been transformed.

Information Giving and Enactment of Consent

123

Recycling the patient’s mistake as a ‘‘prior laughable’’ (Glenn 2003:82), the

doctor hooks the opportunity for launching a joke: he ironically suggests to modify

the name of another colleague, in the same fashion in which the Ecuadorian patient

had modified the name of doctor Marini (line 3). At this point, a scene is constituted,

in which the doctor, the nurse, and the young trainee present in the consultation

room talk behind someone’s back. Parody and tease are ‘‘improper’’ and tactless

moves with regards to the tacit assumption and ethical expectations that members of

the same professional community behave fairly towards co-members. The nurse’s

comment, at line 12, ‘‘we’re recorded’’ provides evidence that she interprets the

current exchange as vulnerable to the public scrutiny, alerting the co-participants

about the threat that the recorder could make upon the confidential nature of the

gossiping exchange. The trainee also refers to the recorder (line 13), probably

M. Fatigante, F. Orletti

123

commenting on how it is presently conditioning the context, in which he is only

temporarily present.

In the turns that follow (lines 15, 18), the doctor makes the implications of the

threat explicit: the recorder is qualified as a spying device (Gordon 2012) able to

publicly reveal opinions that would be otherwise concealed to the external audience.

Contrary to the previous turns, the doctor’s move is uttered at a normal volume of

voice; in this way, it appears to be overtly heard by the recorder (and, thus, by the

researcher who will later transcribe the tapes). Whereas the nurse commented about

the recorder, the doctor, comments to the recorder (Gordon 2012), making explicit

the risky consequences that the recording of their behavior can have for their

professional identity and career (‘‘he will report me’’). In so doing, he not only

displays (as the nurse did) a reflexive awareness of the research device, but he also

entitles himself to stage an identity performance—at the thresholds between the

literal and non literal meanings—in which he plays as someone who might

potentially be prosecuted for misbehavior in the professional context. In so doing,

he also implicitly addresses the issue of whether or not the researcher can fully

respect what he stated in the informed consent, i.e., protection of participants’

confidentiality. As a matter of fact, in cases such this one, the only measure to

protect participants from being recognized would be never playing the data (voices

could be identified) or even deleting them. Our choice, as analysts, was to keep this

extract, given that the participants neither chose to stop the recorder, nor asked us to

do. Still, the option (methodologically valid) favoring the analytical treatment of

such instances, is done at the cost of behaving ‘‘indifferently’’ with regards to what

the participants mark, in the hearing space of the recorder, as strictly confidential

and morally sensitive.

Looking at the three excerpts altogether, we are able to better understand how

issues related to informed consent on one hand, and concerns about recordings on

the other (mutually dependant in this study) are dealt with as participants’ matter,

and how they solicit particular actions by the different parties involved in these

triadic (doctor–patient–nurse) institutional encounters.

The excerpts showed how participants, in the institutional setting of a medical

visit, may have differential access to information and experience different degree of

understanding of the aims, procedures, interests, and identity of the researcher.

Ethnographers working in settings such as hospitals or hospices, claim in fact that to

ensure all participants an equal knowledge about the research project is impossible

(Marzano 2007), and that a ‘‘hierarchy of consent’’ (de Laine 2000) needs instead to

be anticipated.

All excerpts make clear how participants orient to the recordings as something

that may impinge over either the integrity of their professional demeanor (excerpts 1

and 3) or the meaning of the institutional transactions between the doctor and the

patient, which powerfully involve in this case the inspection of the body.

Excerpt 2 and 3 in particular, show that nurses oriented to the recording device as

a threatening device. Having examined a larger set of instances in which

participants address the recording instruments, we have observed that comments

directly addressed to the recorder or the researcher about the arrangement and the

effects of the recording instruments are explicitly formulated by nurses only and, in

Information Giving and Enactment of Consent

123

few cases, keyed as ironic comments by doctors. Patients may join comments by

professionals but they do not initiate them (see excerpt 1). Once in the consultation

room, the patients seem to act in conformity to their institutional role, adhering to

the tacit script prescribed by the observational research frame: ‘‘act spontaneously,

as if you were not being recorded’’. In this fashion, they do ‘‘being patients’’. How

this relates to autonomy in expressing consent, and implications for building consent

with the participants is what we address in the conclusions.

Conclusions

We have presented in the introductory section how respect for the autonomy and

self-determination of participants relies on granting them full information on the

process in which they will participate.

However, we have seen in the practical delivery and enactment of informed

consent that information given to participants can be far less neutral, exhaustive,

and relevant to them.

Rhetorical Pitfalls of Information-Giving

In the analysis of the written consent, we have seen how information about research

aims and procedures always conveys the researchers’ preferences and assumptions.

Insofar as they display the researcher’s commitment toward certain ‘‘desired

outcomes,’’ descriptions are rhetoric artifacts, pursuing not only understanding but

also agreement and affiliation with the speaker.

What appears as a limit here could, if properly acknowledged, be included as an

integral and legitimate part of the informative letter, insofar as a clear distinction

could be made between information about the project (and particularly, about the

kind of participation required by that project) and disclosure of the researchers’

scientific and moral positioning.

In the context of informed consent in medical treatment and research, the

disclosure of the professional’s own perspective, opinions, and recommendations

proves reasonable and less ethically debatable, if it serves the task of preserving the

patient’s health. Faden and Beauchamp favor the hypothesis that the researcher

supplies information about these topics also in order to avoid charging ‘‘the patients/

subjects as the solely responsible for processing and evaluating the information

provided’’ (1986: 308).

The ‘‘beneficial’’ outcome for participants in behavioral research is less obvious

and certainly not essential to the individual’s physical wellbeing. For this reason, the

decision about whether or not to participate needs to rely ‘‘solely’’ on the

participant’s judgment. Still, the opportunity for the researcher to disclose his own

position, including elements of the theoretical and methodological approach s/he

uses—for instance, in our specific case, in analyzing conversations—could

encourage the participant to have her/his own independent opinion about the

nature and validity of the study, and better consider whether to contribute or not.

M. Fatigante, F. Orletti

123

Rhetoric in itself does not deterministically orient the interlocutor’s judgment

but, rather, opens up a context for debate and argumentation (Billig 1987; Edwards

1994).

Recording Tools and Participants’ Concerns

The analysis of ‘‘tape-affected’’ sequences of speech (Speer and Hutchby 2003)

helped to understand what the participants orient to as matters of concern when they

exhibit their bodies and talk in front of a video camera, or in the presence of a

recording device.

As a matter of fact, the use of recording tools alerts participants about the risk

that anonymity, although promised in the written form of consent, cannot be totally

guaranteed, a possibility of which the researchers are also highly aware (Corti et al.

2000). Conversation Analysis has transformed the ethical question of whether or not

the researcher is allowed to use data that are marked as sensitive and private by the

participants, into a methodological claim and advantage, in that they can help better

understand the participants’ perspective and respect ‘‘the situated ways in which

research ethics and the morality of recording are played out as participants’

concerns’’ (Speer and Hutchby 2003:321).

Recording tools, inasmuch as they amplify—for the analysts—the possibility to

observe and deepen the understanding of the formal structure of interaction, also

enhance participants’ possibility to gain reflexive awareness of what they are doing.

Following this line, we add that the instances in which some of the participants

voiced their concerns that their behavior could be publicly observed or evaluated

can also be interpreted as the ‘‘share’’ of ‘‘instructions’’ that the participants

themselves communicate to the researcher.

By formulating their own views on the recording practices, participants display

themselves as fully entitled partners in the research process, not merely ‘‘subjects’’

being observed, but agents capable to frame events according to certain

interpretations, and thus, to intervene on the ‘‘inscriptions’’ (Latour and Woolgar

1986) that their social performances leave on the tape.

Interpreting reflexive instances of the sort we have analyzed in light of

participants’ agency (as other authors did) may constitute, we suggest, another way

to respect the principle of autonomy. In this regard, we must also consider that in no

instance these episodes have led the participants to revise their consent. Interpreting

their concerns as suggestions for the researcher to erase the data, or treat them

differently from the rest of the talk, would actually disable, without consulting with

them, the agreement that participants have formally stipulated in the signature of the

consent.

Information and Democracy of Participation in the Institutional Setting

To open up an interlocutory context in which the research plan and its antecedents

can be openly disclosed by the researcher, rather than embedded and disguised as

self-evident information in the consent letter, may also allow for information—and

Information Giving and Enactment of Consent

123

understanding—to be better negotiated, even with participants whom the researcher

meets for one time only, as in the case of patients in the present study.

We have observed how doctors, nurses, and patients were themselves able to

manage and embody part of the information delivered by the researcher. Still, these

participants exhibited unequal opportunities to voice their concerns and doubts or

interpretations with regard to the aims and procedure of the study. This was related

to the study design: the doctors, particularly, had the chance to meet the researcher

beginning with the preliminary access stage, when she was allowed to carry out

paper and pencil observations in the unit, and they also had prolonged opportunities

to have access to her and her research artifacts. They entitled themselves to

‘‘master’’ the research setting more than the nurses did, and, by declining or

neutralizing the nurses’ concerns in a playful way, more than they allowed the

nurses to do. The doctors were also able to transform the recording tools into

amplifiers of their staged performances, thus exerting an active influence on the data

and results.

As regards the patients, they only entered the scene as the recording was switched

on, and they remain mostly ‘‘voiceless’’ in the staged performances that we have

analyzed. Correspondingly, the researcher gained more knowledge about the

doctors and the professional organization of their practices than she had of patients’

experience, which, nonetheless, figured in the informed consent as a primary

concern of the researchers and a motivating force of their research activity.

Dedicating more efforts to allow participating patients and nurses as well, the

opportunity to discuss informed consent, understand the researcher’s commitment

independently from the doctor’s commitment, voice their concerns and interpre-

tations, and revise—if they feel the need—their authorization even soon after the

visit would be a proper way to respect these (apparently less noticeable)

participants’ autonomy in full awareness of what they consented to.

References

Bain, J. E., & MacKay, N. S. D. (1995). Patient assessment of trainee general practitioners. Medical

Education, 29, 91–96.

Billig, M. (1987). Arguing and thinking: A rhetorical approach to social psychology. Cambridge:

Cambridge University Press.

Billig, M. (1991). Ideology and opinions: Studies in rhetorical psychology. London: Sage Publications.

Buttny, R. (1993). Social accountability. London: Sage.

Coleman, T. (2000). Using video-recorded consultations for research in primary care: Advantages and

limitations. Family Practice, 17(5), 422–427.

Coleman, T., & Manku- Scott, T. (1998). Comparison of video-recorded consultations with those in

which patients’ consent is withheld. British Journal of General Practice, 48(427), 971–974.

Corti, L., Day, A., Backhouse, G. (2000). Confidentiality and informed consent: Issues for consideration

in the preservation of and provision of access to qualitative data archives. Forum Qualitative

Sozialforschung/Forum: Qualitative Social Research (http://www.qualitative-research.net/fqs-texte/

3-00/3-00cortietal-e.htm).

Coupland, J. (2000). Introduction: Sociolinguistic perspectives on small talk. In J. Coupland (Ed.), Small

talk (pp. 1–25). Edinburgh Gate, UK: Pearson Education.

M. Fatigante, F. Orletti

123

de Laine, M. (2000). Fieldwork, participation and practice: Ethics and dilemmas in qualitative research.

Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.

Edwards, D. (1994). Script formulations: An analysis of event descriptions in conversation. Journal of

Language and Social Psychology, 13(3), 211–247.

Edwards, D. (2000). Extreme case formulations: Softeners, investment and doing non-literal. Research on

Language and Social Interaction, 33, 347–373.

Ellis, C. (2007). Telling secrets, revealing lives: Relational ethics in research with intimate others.

Qualitative Inquiry, 13(3), 3–29.

Etherington, K. (2007). Ethical research in reflexive relationships. Qualitative Inquiry, 13(5), 599–616.

Faden, R., & Beauchamp, T. (1986). A history and theory of informed consent. New York: Oxford

University Press.

Fortis, D. (2005). Il linguaggio amministrativo italiano. (The Italian administrative language) Revista de

Llengua i Dret, 43, 47–116.

Garfinkel, H. (1967). Studies in ethnomethodology. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.

Glenn, P. J. (2003). Laughter in interaction. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

Gordon, C. (2012). Beyond the observer’s paradox: The audio-recorder as a resource for the display of

identity. Qualitative Research, 13(3), 299–317.

Hazelgrove, J. (2002). The old faith and the new science: The Nuremberg Code and human

experimentation ethics in Britain 1946–1973. Social History of Medicine, 15, 109–135.

Heritage, J. (1984). Garfinkel and ethnomethodology. UK: Polity Book.

Heritage, J., & Raymond, G. (2005). The terms of agreement: Indexing epistemic authority and

subordination in assessment sequences. Social Psychology Quarterly, 68(1), 15–38.

Hopkins, M. (1993). Is anonymity possible? Writing about refugees in the United States. In C. B. Brettell

(Ed.), When they read what we write: The politics of ethnography (pp. 121–129). Westport, CT:

Bergin and Garvey.

Katz, J. (1984). The silent world of doctors and patients. New York: Free Press.

Labov, W. (1972). Some principles of linguistic methodology. Language in Society, 1(1), 97–120.

Latour, B., & Woolgar, S. (1986). Laboratory life: The construction of scientific facts. Princeton, NJ:

Princeton University Press.

Lomax, H., Casey, N. (1998). Recording social life: reflexivity and video methodology. Sociological

Research Online, 3(2). (accessed at http://www.socresonline.org.uk/socresonline/3/2/1.html on 13

Aug 2013).

Martin, E., & Martin, P. M. L. (1984). The reactions of patients to a video camera in the consulting room.

Journal of Royal College of General Practice, 34(268), 607–610.

Marzano, M. (2007). Informed consent, deception, and research freedom in qualitative research.

Qualitative Inquiry, 13, 417–436. doi:10.1177/1077800406297665.

Maynard, D. W., Freese, J., & Schaeffer, N. C. (2010). Calling for participation: Requests, blocking

moves, and rational (inter)action in survey introductions. American Sociological Review, 75,

791–814.

Maynard, D., & Hudak, P. L. (2008). Small talk, high stakes: Interactional disattentiveness in the context

of prosocial doctor–patient interaction. Language in Society, 37, 661–688. doi:10.

10170S0047404508080986.

Maynard, D. W., & Schaeffer, N. C. (2002). Opening and closing the gate: The work of optimism in

recruiting survey respondents. In D. W. Maynard, H. Houtkoop-Steenstra, N. C. Schaeffer & J. van

der Zouwen (Eds.), Standardization and tacit knowledge. Interaction and practice in the survey

interview (179–205). New York: John Wiley.

Monahan, T., & Fisher, J. A. (2010). Benefits of ‘observer effects’: Lessons from the field. Qualitative

Research, 10(3), 357–376.

Mondada, L. (2006). La demande d’autorisation comme moment structurant pour l’enregistrement et

l’analyse des pratiques bilingues [The requests for authorization as a configuringmoment for the

recording and analysis of bilingualpractices]. Travaux neuchatelois de linguistique, 43, 129–155.

Murphy, E., & Dingwall, R. (2007). Informed consent, anticipatory regulation and ethnographic practice.

Social Science and Medicine, 65(11), 2223–2234.

Pomerantz, A. M. (1986). Extreme case formulations: A new way of legitimating claims. Human Studies,

9, 219–230.

Pope, C. (2005). Conducting ethnography in medical settings. Medical Education, 39, 1180–1187. doi:10.

1111/j.1365-2929.2005.02330.x.

Information Giving and Enactment of Consent

123

Potter, J., & Wetherell, M. (1987). Discourse and social psychology: Beyond attitudes and behaviour.

London: Sage.

Redman, S., Dickinson, J. A., Cockburn, J., Hennrikus, D., & Sanson-fisher, R. W. (1989). The

assessment of reactivity in direct observation studies of doctor–patient interactions. Psychology and

Health, 3, 17–28.

Sacks, H., Schegloff, E. A., & Jefferson, G. (1974). A symplest systematics for the organization of turn

taking for conversation. Language, 50(4), 696–735. doi:10.2307/412243.

Schegloff, E. A. (2007). Sequence organization in interaction: A primer in conversation analysis (Vol. 1).

Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Speer, S. A. (2002). ‘Natural’ and ‘contrived’ data: A sustainable distinction? Discourse Studies, 4(4),

11–525.

Speer, S. A., & Hutchby, I. (2003). From ethics to analytics: Aspects of participants orientations to the

presence and relevance of recording devices. Sociology, 37(2), 315–337. doi:10.1177/

0038038503037002006.

Speer, S. A., & Stokoe, E. (2012). Ethics in action: Consent-gaining interactions and implications for

research practice. British Journal of Social Psychology,. doi:10.1111/bjso.12009.

Sugarman, J., McCrory, D. C., Powell, D., Krasny, A., Adams, B., Ball, E., et al. (1999). Empirical

research on informed consent: An annotated bibliography. Hastings Center Reports, 29(1), 1–42.

Weindling, P. (2004). Nazi medicine and the Nuremberg trials: From medical war crimes to informed

consent. London: Palgrave.

Wiles, R., Heath, S., Crow, G., Charles, V. (1999) Informed Consent in Social Research: A Literature

Review. National Centre for Research Methods, School of Social Sciences, University of

Southampton. NCRM Methods Paper Series 001 (accessed at http://eprints.ncrm.ac.uk/85/1/

MethodsReviewPaperNCRM-001.pdf, on August 13, 2013).

Ziman, J. M. (1978). Reliable knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

M. Fatigante, F. Orletti

123