history of psychology 2007 lecture 6 professor gerald c. cupchik office: s634 email:...

59
History of Psychology 2007 Lecture 6 Professor Gerald C. Cupchik Office: S634 Email: [email protected] Office Hours: Wednesdays 1-2 pm Thursdays 12-1 pm T.A: Michelle Hilscher Office: S150 Email: [email protected] Office Hours: Thursdays 11-12; 3-4 pm Course Website: www.utsc.utoronto.ca/~cupchik

Upload: edwina-west

Post on 27-Dec-2015

214 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

History of Psychology 2007

Lecture 6

Professor Gerald C. Cupchik

Office: S634

Email: [email protected]

Office Hours: Wednesdays 1-2 pm

Thursdays 12-1 pm

T.A: Michelle Hilscher

Office: S150

Email: [email protected]

Office Hours: Thursdays 11-12; 3-4 pm

Course Website: www.utsc.utoronto.ca/~cupchik

RECALL:

* Rationalism goes back to Plato and particularly to Aristotle’s doctrine of the rational “soul” as something above the nutritive and sensory functions of the individual.

Rationalists believe in a special mental substance with its own inherent properties and which cannot be reduced to matter.

* Christian theologians kept the idea alive during the Middle Ages. However, they emphasized destiny rather than nature and its attributes.

* Descartes also described a thinking substance, res cogitans, which was distinct from physical matter. I am speaking of a non-material rational principle that reveals itself in the facts of experience.

* The Empiricists had asserted that Aristotle’s five senses were the sole source of knowledge.

RECALL:

* Opposed to this are mental faculties or functions or activities which can be classified and which imply pre-existing mental capacities.

* They are revealed in experience but not created by experience. A faculty psychology does not deny the importance of observation. Rather, we must have a complete inventory of psychological functions.

THE SCOTTISH SCHOOL

A strong reaction to the position of the Empiricists came from professors in the Scottish Universities who were reflecting the feelings of their church.

They were concerned about the denial of the external world and the emphasis on contents of the mind. This conflicted with the conception of the soul as unitary. They developed a faculty psychology.

Thomas Reid (1710-1796)

- He argued for the distinction between perception and sensation.

- How do we experience a rose?

- Sensation may be in the mind but perception is of the

object outside in the world.

- We add the conception of it and the belief in its existence.

- This was a partial answer.

Further, Reid argued against the idea that the mind knows only its contents.

He listed 24 active powers of the mind such as self-preservation, hunger, desire for power, self-esteem, gratitude, pity.

He included 6 intellectual powers such as perception, judgment and memory.

The lists of regions of the mind names by the phrenologist Gall comes from Reid.

Thomas Brown (1778-1820)

- He made his major contribution in 1826: The recognition of a muscle sense which could add to the other senses in the interpretation and recognition of objects.

- Charles Bell had already recognized the presence of sensory and motor nerves in the muscles.

- Brown argued that the felt resistance of muscular exertion gives us the belief in external objects!

Reid’s rose provides at first a smell as pure sensation. But when we find that it requires muscular effort to move it, then the sensed rose gains perceptual unity.

This is an Associationistic solution.

And of course it anticipates Piaget’s sensorimotor basis for the emergence of objects in the world as well as Freud’s notion of double touch whereby the child squeezes his/her own arm… it both feels and is felt at the same time.

Sir William Hamilton (1788-1856)

- He contributed to a faculty psychology by believing in an active mind that controlled mental states and directed action.

- The faculty of perception deals with the direct entrance of knowledge.

- The faculty of preservation retains ideas.

Redintegration - One part of an experience tends to recall the whole. This suggests the activity of the mind.

GERMAN RATIONALISM

The English psychologists set out from the ideas of the contents of the mind and explained the unity of consciousness by the natural affinities between these contents which are at various times described as associated, chemically united or physiologically assimilated. So they emphasized going from the plurality to the unity. John Locke gave the impression that the outer sense was separate from the power of reflection.

German rationalists set the unity first and left to others the task of showing how this unity occurred.

They also emphasized the spontaneity of the mind or soul. The work of the mind was something more than a mere arranging, sorting, and associating of the given; it was essentially productive, creative, and freely active.

Gottfried Leibniz (1646-1716)

Born in Leipzig during the 30 Years War which ended in 1648. Germany was at its lowest ebb of prosperity and culture. This was an age of reviving aspirations.

He was the first philosophical mind to appear in modern Germany and was the founder of German psychology. He was cosmopolitan in life, character and thought and lived his last years in Paris which was the focus of Europe.

His ideas fit with the post-war theme of inner welfare and mysticism.

Three points in his doctrine are important to psychology:

1. Theory of mind-body relations.

2. Introduction of the term apperception.

3. His insistence against Locke that one must have general ideas in the mind in advance of experience.

Mind-Body Relations:

Underlying these points is his picture of the universe which is composed of independent entities that may be represented as thinking atoms. Each entity is both a material and thinking being and these aspects don’t interact (dualism).

Every existing thing from the smallest particle to God is a monad. Each monad is defined in terms of its degree of consciousness or potency. It is a centre of force, a living reality, a pure energy known and interpreted through our own self-consciousness.

The material monads have only vague ideas and the range of clearness passes through animals and humans to attain perfect clearness in God. This was based on a Law of Continuity in the study of quantity and relates to the idea of a continuous uninterrupted scale of being (i.e., degrees of mind).

What is the relationship of this to the mind-body problem? The body was made up of a vast number of monads each of which had unclear notions only. The mind was made up of clearer ideas or monads. The body could be controlled by the mind on the assumption that a great idea might dominate a vaguer one.

Mind-Body Relations:

Leibniz was little concerned for the body in general and makes no provisions for the body to influence the mind. This notion of psychophysical parallelism was later adopted by Wundt. Body and mental processes go on side by side but don’t influence each other.

Apperception:

This term developed from grading the ideas in the monads according to their clearness. Just as different monads exhibit different degrees of clearness in ideas, so, in the individual human consciousness, ideas vary in distinctness. According to the Law of Continuity a perception rises by degrees to the stage of actual realization.

The very faint: petites perceptions (minutes perceptions)The very clear: Apperceptions

Apperceptions are always fully self conscious in addition to being clearly conscious. The degree of clearness is a sign of truth. Like Descartes, he asserts that what is fully clear is true, while the vague ideas may be false or uncertain. Clearness carries with it a greater strength of action.

The existence of unconscious ideas and the relation between clearness and activity both continue as elements of the notion of apperception until Wundt.

This also relates in a meaningful way to the psychodynamic notion of potent unconscious ideas.

There is a clear contrast between the German and French notion of clarity and the English notion of vividness.

Arguments Against Locke’s Sensationalism

The idea that all knowledge comes through the senses was incompatible with Leibniz’s theory.

He prepared a work refuting paragraph by paragraph Locke’s Essay Concerning Human Understanding. But he withheld publication because Locke had just died and he did not want to increase the bitterness of the English toward him which was great because they erroneously believed that he had plagiarized Newton’s Theory of the Calculus.

Leibniz felt that knowledge through the senses is vague and cannot be relied on for accuracy. True knowledge is innate.

To Locke’s axiom that “there is nothing in intellect that was not previously in sense”, Leibniz added “except the intellect itself” and that comprised all general and reliable knowledge.

The activities of the mind are fundamental. The mind absorbs all things, not by receiving them, but purely by being in relation to them.

German Psychology in the 18th Century

The development of a national scholarly discipline, in general, and a strictly national psychology was slower in Germany than in the neighboring states.

Why? Education held to traditional scholastic forms until well into the 18th century. This is evident in the slow development of the use of German in scholarly books.

For example, Descartes and Hobbes were writing by preference in French and English in the 17th century. Leibniz, a generation later, still writes in Latin, or sometimes in French but never in his mother tongue.

This situation was partly due to the fact that German scholars were almost all connected with universities while French and English scholars were outside the scholastic atmosphere.

German Psychology in the 18th Century

The universities were state supported and controlled directly by the ministry of education in each state. They were conceived of as assemblages of scholars who were free to do as they pleased in their scholarly work but appointments were made by the central ministry. The lowest level (privatdozent) had permission to teach but had no stipend, save a portion of the fees paid by the students who attended his lectures. As openings were created by the death or resignation of his seniors, he was advanced by a rank and received a small salary and finally to the Full professor position. Appointments to the higher ranks were generally for life.

Christian Wolff (1679-1754)

He was the first academic psychologist and wrote the first two textbooks:

Psychologia Empirica (1734)

Psychologia Rationalis (1754)

He was a typical professor. Only one event disturbed his career. In 1723, the orthodox Pietist citizens secured his dismissal from the university because they regarded his teachings as atheistical. He was reinstated in 1740 by Fredrich the Great.

He organized the scattered writings of Leibniz and put them into a teachable form and his ideas replaced those of Aristotle in the universities of Germany.

For Wolff, mind was a greater force than it was for Leibniz and he also assigned a more significant role to the body.

Instead of merely mirroring events, the mind is a real, active force.

He holds to a psychophysical parallelism view (like Leibniz) to the effect that ideas run their course at the same rate as the corresponding bodily processes but neither is regarded as the determinant of the other.

He divides the mind into faculties:

i. Knowing ii. Feeling or Desire

a. perception or sensing a. pleasure or pain

b. imagination completes percept b. will

c. memory

d. understanding (considering what is possible)

e. pure reason (drawing conclusions)

In addition: Attention was the capacity for clearing up ideas. The field of attention varies with the degree of clearness; a wide field implies less clearness than a restricted field.

Law of Redintegration: One can control the course of recall by attending to ideas that are similar to or have on another occasion accompanied or preceded the idea that one desires to recall. When a present perception forms part of a past perception, the whole past perception tends to reinstate itself.

The will is a free agent, thus opposing Leibniz who gave G-d alone freedom in choosing one from among the many possible worlds.

He also used the term apperception to designate the clearness of ideas and connected it with attention.

AFTER 1750

There was a strong interest in the more popular aspects of morals and psychology. One aspect of this movement was partially scientific; another was merely individual. There were innumerable introspective records, diaries of the inner development of individuals called “secular confessions.’

Some studied their own day-to-day emotions. In Goethe, self-observation reached the level where experience is the best form of experiment.

The sentimental romance became the medium of self-expression (Rousseau)....like the Confessions of Saint Augustine.

This attitude also led to careful records of, for example, child-life (by Tiedemann).

Intermediate between the subjective cultivation of emotion and introspective analysis of the mind came the attempts to arrive at knowledge of abnormal states by the use of drugs. For example, De Quincey’s Confessions of an Opium Eater.

This work implied a growing belief in the close relations between mental changes and physical states during the decade 1770-1780: due to the progress made by physiology and the rise of a distinct group of physiological psychologists.

The dominant view is the recognition of activity which begins with Leibniz and, after being submerged by waves of empiricism, reappears as an assertion of the rights of form against matter and of the total life of the mind against particular contents.

In the last phase, the following points were made:

1. Association is only one aspect of a process which is ultimately the reconstruction of a total state of mind from a given part – redintegration.

2. Form is distinct from content and is seen in the variety of arrangements which different minds give to the same ideas.

3. A science of the mind must unite, with the doctrine of its powers, a consideration of the body as the condition of all their manifestation.

The 18th century was the real end of the Medieval Period in the history of the sciences.

“Great Developments in the 19th Century”

One of the two main streams in intellectual development contrasted Naturalism versus Anti-Naturalism (Greeks) and The Enlightenment approach to knowledge with that of the German Rationalists. This is essentially a contrast between atomistic and holistic approaches. Today we will consider the implications of the atomistic approach for the development of scientific psychology.

The atomistic stream can be traced back to Greek Naturalism. We will recall the basic tenets of this Materialistic approach:

1. Monistic – rejects mind/matter distinction

- Matter is fundamental

- Explain all by physical laws

2. Atomistic – reduce complex to simple

- Reduce matter to smaller parts which are accepted as fundamental

3. Reduce quality to quantity

- Qualities such as red and blue, sweet and sour, warm and cold are reduced to wavelengths of light, chemical reactions in receptors and transmission of molecular motion.

- Qualities are secondary, to be restated eventually as quantitative differences in the behaviour of a single primary substance.

4. Reduce function to structure

- Organisms behave as if trying to maintain themselves, seeking appropriate food, defending against danger, selecting mates.- These are organismic functions with purpose.

- From a materialist viewpoint, purpose cannot exist in nature.

- Purposive functions must be explained in terms of structures which have evolved (through natural selection) in such a way that the species is preserved.

- The structure is inherited or built up through learning (e.g., structure of the eye)

- The fine distinctions of logicians refer to structural relations among cortical elements.

This approach was revived during the Renaissance by scholars in Italy and elsewhere who focused on nature in the absence of dogma as the real authority; the new naturalism. It was accompanied by major scientific revolutions including the new heliocentric theory proposed by Copernicus (1473-1543) and refined by Kepler’s (1571-1630) laws of planetary (elliptical) motion, Galileo’s (1564-1642) dynamics of moving bodies, and Newton’s (1642-1727) principle of gravitation, laws of motion, and analysis of white light as a mixture of colours.

PHYSIOLOGY

Biological science started as medical science which, with the Greeks and before then, was a mixture of anatomy, surgery and knowledge of medicinal plants, supplemented by magic and other dogmatic principles. The law forbade the dissection of human bodies so that advances in the correct knowledge of anatomy depended on animal dissection. So physiological knowledge was held back by ignorance of anatomy.

Major Figures in the Development of Physiology

1. Hippocrates (ca. 460-370 BC) – He was the “father of medicine” who showed rare objectivity toward medical facts but he lacked anatomical knowledge.

2. Galen (ca. 129-199 AD) – He was a good observer and limited experimenter. He: (i) localized the mind in the brain, and (ii) distinguished between sensory and motor nerves, an idea which was lost and rediscovered in the 19th century.

In the 16th century dissection of the body was being practiced, although with opposition from the Church. Both Leonardo da Vinci and Michelangelo performed dissection. In other words, artists were one step ahead of the scientists.

3. Andreas Vesalius (1514-1564) – Born in Belgium. He marked the triumph of observationover dogma in medicine. By 1537 he was lecturing to large

audiences in anatomy. It took another century to pick up on his work of which the church disapproved.

Vesalius was born into a family long associated with the medical care of the imperial dynasty, most notably being his father who was the pharmacist for Charles V of Germany. From an early age, Vesalius showed an inclination to follow in the family tradition through his dissection of dead birds and mice. He studied at the University of Leuven from 1530 until 1533, when he began his studies at the University of Paris under Jacobus Sylvius and Johann Guinter.

At the outbreak of the war between France and the Holy Roman Empire in 1536, Vesalius returned home to complete his studies at the University of Leuven, where he received his medical degree in 1537.

In the autumn of 1537, Vesalius enrolled in the medical school of the University of Padua, and received his doctorate of medicine shortly thereafter. Upon his graduation, he was immediately offered the chair of Surgery and Anatomy (explicator chirurgiae) at Padua, where he began giving public lectures. His innovative lectures and course plans were unique for two reasons. First, he performed his own dissections rather than reading aloud while a demonstrator did the dissection and second, because he used drawings to aide his teaching. These drawings became an integral part in his teaching, and later in his published works.

Soon thereafter, Vesalius became interested in the validity of Galen's findings, and began his study on human anatomy and his major work, De humani corporis fabrica. In 1539, a Paduan judge became interested in Vesalius' work, and madebodies of executed criminals available for dissection. His collection of detailed anatomical diagrams grew, many were produced by artists and were of better quality than previous diagrams. His diagrams became known as the first accurate set to be produced.

4. William Harvey (1578-1657) – He did for physiology what Vesalius had done for anatomy. Through observation and experiment, he worked out the exact connection of the cavities of the heart with each other and with the lungs, the arteries, and the veins. The connections and the valves showed the way the blood must be flowing.

Harvey’s work appears very modern: he experimented and obeyed the injunction of the Paduan anatomists to see for oneself. ‘I profess to learn and teach anatomy not from books but from dissections,’ he declared, ‘not from thetenets of Philosophers but from the fabric of Nature.’ But that is only half true; certainly he looked for himself (and without the aid of the microscope), but he saw through Aristotelian spectacles. Harvey did not, as sometimes supposed, conceive of the body in a ‘modern’ mechanical fashion: it was too a machine, but was moved by vital forces.

In discussing the circulation, he wrote, drawing on traditional macrocosm/microcosm correlations, that it was to transport life-giving blood to the periphery and then to return it to the heart where it could be re-enlivened.

There was no burst of good work in scientific physiology right after Harvey nor in fact in the 18th century. In the 19th century there was a chain reaction, one discovery making another possible, one enthusiasm setting off another. This work in the 19th century laid the foundation for experimental physiological psychology.

Interestingly, this kind of work appealed more to the Germans than to the English or French scholars… Why did scientific psychology begin in Germany? It began as taxonomic description. While we associate Germans with a phenomenological approach, its real foundation has to do with description, classification and induction which contrasts with the mathematical and deductive approaches. This requires the attitude of a painstaking and methodological culture.

Biology was not yet ready to lend itself to great generalizations. So the Germans took up the task of collecting observational facts that were sound, detailed, conscientious and thorough. So psychology joined the family of sciences because the Germans had faith in collecting data and welcomed biology into the circle of science. The French and English hesitated because biology did not fit with the scientific pattern set by physics. The holistic attitude of the Germans saved the day.

Physiology in the First Half of the 19th Century

There are 9 major developments between 1800 and 1850 all but two of which belong as much in the history of physiology. None of these findings were made by scholars who considered themselves to be psychologists.

1. Sensory and Motor Nerves

Sir Charles Bell (1774-1842) re-discovered the fact of the differences between sensory and motor nerves in the spinal cord – that they were anatomically and functionally discrete.

Rule: The posterior or dorsal roots of the spinal cord contain only sensory fibres and the anterior roots only motor fibres.

Bell later showed that some cranial nerves are entirely sensory, some entirely motor, and some mixed.

He later established the law of forward direction in the nervous system which holds that conduction in a nerve normally flows in one direction.

The significance of this work:  We could no longer regard the nerves as transmitting both the powers of sensation and of motion. [Note that Francois Magendie made the same discovery independently but later and he had the more convincing experiment. He was also a notorious vivisector whose shocking dissections of live animals led in England to anti-vivisection laws.]

2. Reflex Action

This research was basic to the conception of reflex action and the reflex arc. Bell published the results privately in 1811 in a pamphlet (100) for his friends and colleagues.

In 1751, Robert Whytt, a Scot (1714-1766), described experiments with frogs showing that the spinal cord was both necessary and sufficient for many automatic movements which occur in response to stimulation when the spinal cord is severed from the brain. He distinguished between:

i. Voluntary movement, which is an act of will

ii. Involuntary spontaneous movement which occurs instantaneously with no time for the exercise of reason but it was dependent on sensation in the nervous system.

M. Hall (1790-1857) distinguished between conscious voluntary movement and involuntary movement dependent only on the spinal cord, independent of the brain and consciousness.

The unconscious reflexes were relegated to physiology. The new physiological psychology, which got under was around 1850, was organized as a psychology of conscious voluntary action and reaction time.

The distinction broke down with (1) Pavlov’s demonstration that unconscious movements can be learned (conditioned reflex) and (2) Freud’s discovery of unconscious motives and thinking.

3. Electrical Nature of the Nerve Impulse

The 17th century furnished a means for generating static electricity and the 18th century made it more available by the invention of the Leyden Jar (1745).

Galvani began experiments on the stimulation of frog’s legs by electric discharges. In 1791 he produced a kick in the frog’s leg with an electric charge and concluded that animal tissues generate electricity.

Volta showed that this kind of electricityelectricity can be had without animal tissues by creating an inorganic battery. He thought that he had disproved animal electricity.

du Bois-Reymond developed a theory of the polarization of animal tissues in 1848-49. He argued that muscles and nerves consist of electrically charged particles with a positive charge on one face and a negative charge on the opposite oriented like a magnet. This relates to the modern concept of polarization. He brought the nervous impulse out of the mystical realm of animal spirits and into material science suggesting to Helmholtz that the activity of the impulse may not be instantaneous but finite and measurable.

4. Velocity and Conduction of the Nerve Impulse

It had been supposed that the velocity of the nervous impulse was so rapid as to be practically immeasurable.

i. 9000 ft/min

ii. 32,400 ft/min

iii. 57,600 ft/sec which is 60 times the velocity of light.

Haller’s estimate of 150 ft/sec is close to the truth which is 3-400 ft/sec depending on the diameter of the conducting fibre.

It is important for psychology to determine that transmission is not instantaneous but relatively slow.

To separate the movement of a finger in time from the event of will that caused it was in a sense to separate the body from the mind.

So bodily motion becomes part of a series of events and this contributed to the materialist view of the psycho-physical organism that was the essence of 19th century science.

Other developments:

Electrical depolarization – Bernstein (1866)

-Wave of negativity passing along the nerve.

All or none principle – Bowditch (1871)

-A nerve fibre supplies the energy for an impulse and is completely discharged when excited.

5. Specific Energy of Nerves

Müller (1826) – The central principle is that (1) we are directly aware, not of the object, but of our sensory nerves themselves. So the idea is that the mind is the result of a reaction excited in the eye or brain and not of anything received. The operation of the mind is determined by the kinds of senses that we have. (2) There are five kinds of nerves (specificity); each kind imposes its specific quality on the mind.

So the quality of sensation depends not upon the nature of the cause but upon the nature of the nerve which the cause affects.

Now we know that qualitative differences lie not in the nerve excitation themselves but rather different central effects.

6. Phrenology

Phrenology relates to the problem of where the mind is located in the body. It was not commonly held that the mind was in the brain. Phrenology tried to establish that:

(1) The brain is the organ of the mind.

(2) Particular parts of the brain are associated with separate mental faculties.

HISTORY

Aristotle: Mind

Egyptians: Thought ; Judgment

Pythagoras: Seat of mind and intellect

Plato: Seat of mind

Alexandrian anatomists: Seat of mind Also brain

Descartes: Soul in the entire body but specifically the pineal gland, did not identify the brain with the mind.

The modern idea of the brain as the seat of the mind emerged in the 19th century. It was prepared in the late 18th century by Jean Baptiste Pinel. After Pinel possession was treated as a disease. To recognize the mind as subject to disease orients us towards the idea of the mind’s dependence on the body, the usual seat of disease.

A Little History

The first humane impulse of any considerable importance in this field seems to have been aroused in America. In the year 1751 certain members of the Society of Friends founded a small hospital for the insane, on better principles, in Pennsylvania. To use the language of its founders, it was intended “as a good work, acceptable to God.‘” Twenty years later Virginia established a similar asylum, and gradually others appeared in other colonies.

But it was in France that mercy was to be put upon a scientific basis, and was to lead to practical results which were to convert the world to humanity. In this case, as in so many others, from France was spread and popularized not only the scepticism which destroyed the theological theory, but also the devotion which built up the new scientific theory and endowed the world with a new treasure of civilization.

In 1756 some physicians of the great hospital at Paris known as the Hotel-Dieu protested that the cruelties prevailing in the treatment of the insane were aggravating the disease; and some protests followed from other quarters. Little effect was produced at first; but just before the French Revolution, Tenon, La Rochefoucauld-Liancourt, and others took up the subject, and in 1791 a commission was appointed to undertake a reform.

By great good fortune, the man selected to lead in the movement was one who had already thrown his heart into it - Jean Baptiste Pinel. In 1792 Pinel was made physician at Bicetre, one of the most extensive lunatic asylums in France, and to the work there imposed upon him he gave all his powers. Little was heard of him at first. The most terrible scenes of the French Revolution were drawing nigh; but he laboured on, modestly and devotedly - apparently without a thought of the great political storm raging about him.

His first step was to discard utterly the whole theological doctrine of ``possession,'' and especially the idea that insanity is the result of any subtle spiritual influence. He simply put in practice the theory that lunacy is the result of bodily disease.

It is a curious matter for reflection, that but for this sway of the destructive philosophy of the eighteenth century, and of the Terrorists during the French Revolution, Pinel's blessed work would in all probability have been thwarted, and he himself excommunicated for heresy and driven from his position. Doubtless the same efforts would have been put forth against him which the Church, a little earlier, had put forth against inoculation as a remedy for smallpox; but just at that time the great churchmen had other things to think of besides crushing this particular heretic: they were too much occupied in keeping their own heads from the guillotine to give attention to what was passing in the head of Pinel. He was allowed to work in peace, and in a short time the reign of diabolism at Bicetre was ended.

What the exorcisms and fetiches and prayers and processions, and drinking of holy water, and ringing of bells, had been unable to accomplish during eighteen hundred years, he achieved in a few months. His method was simple: for the brutality and cruelty which had prevailed up to that time, he substituted kindness and gentleness. The possessed were taken out of their dungeons, given sunny rooms, and allowed the liberty of pleasant ground for exercise; chains were thrown aside. At the same time, the mental power of each patient was developed by its fitting exercise, and disease was met with remedies sanctioned by experiment, observation, and reason. Thus was gained one of the greatest, though one of the least known, triumphs of modern science and humanity.

Phrenology emerged due to the work of Franz Joseph Gall (1758-1828) who was an anatomist. As a schoolboy, he observed a relationship between mental qualities of his school mates and shapes of their heads (e.g., prominent eyes and good memories). His doctrine gained public attention and the church tried to have the government of Austria force him to discontinue his lectures. He moves to France!

The Basic Propositions

1. Phrenologists must show conformation of exterior to interior skull and brain.

2. The mind can be meaningfully analyzed into a number of faculties or functions.

3. Faculties and powers of the mind are localized in the brain and an excess of any faculty is correlated with an enlargement of the corresponding place in the brain. So a protrusion of the brain would indicate an excess in the particular faculty.

Phrenology flourished for a century. There were 29 societies in Great Britain and several journals. But it was never accepted as a science even though it retained popular appeal even though knowledge of the brain physiology rendered it impossible.

The importance of phrenology lies in its effect on scientific thought of the period.

From a negative standpoint:

(1) Physiologists disbelieved the relation of the skull to the brain.

(2) Philosophers objected to analysis of the mind into faculties because it violated the principle of unity of mind.

But, while essentially wrong, it furthered scientific thought by:

(1) Establishing the brain as the organ of the mind.

(2) It suggested localization of function in the brain.

It mediated between the Cartesian concept of an unsubstantiated soul and the concept of mere material neural function. Phrenology was wrong only in detail.

7. Physiology of the Brain

A. The French physiologist Bichat (1771-1802) assumed a connection between the mind and brain. He felt that the brain is the centre for intelligence, perception, imagination and judgment but that emotions are centred in the internal organs.

Gall’s specific psychophysiology made a radical but less extreme view seem conservative. He prompted Pierre Flourens to associate different functions with the cerebrum, cerebellum, medulla and spinal cord. So Flourens mediated between the too vague tradition of Descartes and the too specific doctrine of the phrenologists. His conclusions were based on experimentation.

Moment in scientific wisdom. He said “There is a great secret behind being brief. That is to be clear.” Flourens substituted carefully planned experiments for nature’s experiments that occur in accidental lesions and disease. Using animals, his method was the extirpation of parts and he looked for a correlation between brain area and function. For example, the function of the cerebral cortex is willing, judging, and seeing. He distinguished six parts.

He also distinguished “action propre” from “action commune”.

“Action propre” or exact localization implies a special function for each of the 6 parts (in the direction of Gall).

“Action commune” or field theory implies a general function such that the removal of one part reduces the energy of every other. This is related to the unity of mind which philosophers had contended.

B. The improvement of the microscope around 1830 led to histological research. Luigi Rolando first thought (1824) of cutting thin sections of brain tissue chemically hardened for microscopic examination. This procedure was important because Flourens had divided the brain into a few gross parts each with its own function. But he didn’t analyze further within each part. The histological work led the brain to be considered as composed of an almost infinite number of separate cells which connect in a complicated network. This view of the brain bore a close resemblance to the picture of the mind adhered to by the Associationists, the dominant psychology of the period which held that the mind consisted of an infinitude of ideas. These ideas are bound together into more complex ideas by association, just as the nerve cells are connected by fibres. In sum, the new knowledge of the division of the brain into many tiny interconnected units implied that further separation of localized mental functions should be sought. Later research localized functions such as hearing, somesthesis, and sensation.

Two Important Discoveries Outside the Field of Physiology

8. Hypnotism

While this phenomenon was intentionally induced in tribal religious ceremonies, the scientific discovery had other origins. It used to be regarded as a mysterious natural force.

The Doctrine of Animal Magnetism: Van Helmont (1577-1644) maintained that a magnetic fluid radiates from all men that can be guided by will to influence the mind and bodies of others. For the next century and a half, men appeared around Europe who purported to have curing skills.

Mesmerism: Friedrich Anton Mesmer (1734-1815) was a physician in Vienna who discovered how to produce these phenomena. He started by trying to explain the effects of stars on people and sought a principle in the universe associated with electricity or magnetism. This led him to stroke people’s bodies with magnets and he found that he could induce what we call hypnosis. In 1776, he abandoned the use of metal magnets and spoke only of animal magnetism.

Mesmer cured many psycho-neurotic patients. His work was ignored by official circles and so he moved to Paris in 1778. A French government commission declared that animal magnetism was not magnetism in the normal sense. They assumed he possessed the secret of another force and offered him 20,000 Francs to share it with them. He refused since he believed that a magnetic power within himself was the source of his ability. He fell into disrepute, conservative scientists rejecting his results, he moved to Switzerland.

John Elliotson (1791-1868), a famous English physician of radical temperament, explored the use of Mesmerism in spite of professional opposition. He was initially interested in the therapeutic value of Mesmerism to cure hysterical diseases but shifted his interest toward its use as an anaesthetic agent. In 1846, this idea was superceded by the development of ether which was more reliable.

The term hypnotism comes from James Braid (1795-1860). He was not regarded as a Mesmerist and described the trance as a “nervous sleep” (neurypnology short for neurohypnology or hypnotic). Braid was a hypnotist which was more acceptable and he discovered the roots of Mesmerism. He could induce an artificial sleep in the members of his family and friends by having them stare fixedly at some bright object above the line of vision and he developed a physiological theory of the elevator muscles of the eyelids. This related to a more psychological emphasis on fixity of attention. Later, he recognized the role of suggestion for inducing this phenomenon.

So physiological thought of the 19th century took up the problem of Mesmerism. It is part of the psychology of motivation but was treated as part of abnormal psychology.

9. The Personal Equation

Astronomers were concerned with the physiological or psychological source of error in their measurement of the times of stellar events. At Greenwich in 1796, Maskelyne dismissed his assistant because the latter observed the time of stellar transits across the Meridian at Greenwich a second later than he did. So mental processes take time.

Bessel discovered (1) the personal equation - a difference between two observers and (2) variability in the personal equation. Astronomers could then correct for them (from 1/4 sec to 1 sec). The personal equation also varied for sun and stars.

In the 1850s, the absolute personal equation emerged as a measure. It is the reaction time of a subject making a movement a rapidly as he can after perceiving a signal.

The idea that mental processes take time was central to research in the 1860s and 1870s.

This led to the psychological problem of reaction time and fit with Helmholtz’s idea that nerve conduction takes time.

Researchers found that expectations, preparation, and attention are important factors.

In addition, it takes time to process or attend to events in the brain.