fundamentals of logic

52
Fundamentals of Logic 1. What is a valid argument or proof? 2. Study system of logic 3. In proving theorems or solving problems, creativity and insight are needed, which cannot be taught Chapter 2

Upload: rahim-chapman

Post on 04-Jan-2016

105 views

Category:

Documents


2 download

DESCRIPTION

Chapter 2. Fundamentals of Logic. 1. What is a valid argument or proof? 2. Study system of logic 3. In proving theorems or solving problems, creativity and insight are needed, which cannot be taught. 2.1 Basic connectives and truth tables. 2.1 Basic connectives and truth tables. - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Fundamentals of Logic

Fundamentals of Logic1. What is a valid argument or proof?2. Study system of logic3. In proving theorems or solving problems, creativity

and insight are needed, which cannot be taught

Chapter 2

Page 2: Fundamentals of Logic

2.1 Basic connectives and truth tables2.1 Basic connectives and truth tables

2.1 Basic connectives and truth tables

statements (propositions): declarative sentences that areeither true or false--but not both.

Eg. Margaret Mitchell wrote Gone with the Wind. 2+3=5.

not statements:

What a beautiful morning!Get up and do your exercises.

Page 3: Fundamentals of Logic

2.1 Basic connectives and truth tables

primitive and compound statements

combined from primitive statements by logical connectivesor by negation ( )

logical connectives:

p p,

(a) conjunction (AND): (b) disjunction(inclusive OR):(c) exclusive or: (d) implication: (if p then q)(e) biconditional: (p if and only if q, or p iff q)

p qp q

p qp q

p q

Page 4: Fundamentals of Logic

2.1 Basic connectives and truth tables

"The number x is an integer." is not a statement because itstruth value cannot be determined until a numerical value is assigned for x.

First order logic vs. predicate logic

Page 5: Fundamentals of Logic

2.1 Basic connectives and truth tables

Truth Tables

p q p q p q p q p qp q

0 0 0 0 0 1 1

0 1 0 1 1 1 0

1 0 0 1 1 0 0

1 1 1 1 0 1 1

Page 6: Fundamentals of Logic

2.1 Basic connectives and truth tables

Ex. 2.1 s: Phyllis goes out for a walk.t: The moon is out.u: It is snowing.

( )t u s : If the moon is out and it is not snowing, thenPhyllis goes out for a walk.

If it is snowing and the moon is not out, then Phylliswill not go out for a walk. ( )u t s

Page 7: Fundamentals of Logic

2.1 Basic connectives and truth tables

Def. 2.1. A compound statement is called a tautology(T0) if it is true for all truth value assignments for its component statements. If a compound statement is false for all such assignments, then it is called a contradiction(F0).

p p q

p p q

( )

( )

: tautology

: contradiction

Page 8: Fundamentals of Logic

2.1 Basic connectives and truth tables

an argument: ( )p p p qn1 2

premises conclusion

If any one of p p pn1 2, , , is false, then no matter whattruth value q has, the implication is true. Consequently,if we start with the premises p p pn1 2, , , --each with

truth value 1--and find that under these circumstancesq also has value 1, then the implication is a tautology andwe have a valid argument.

Page 9: Fundamentals of Logic

2.2 Logical Equivalence: 2.2 Logical Equivalence: The Laws of LogicThe Laws of Logic

Ex. 2.7

0011

0101

1100

1101

1101

p q p p q p q

Def 2.2 . logically equivalent

s s1 2

Page 10: Fundamentals of Logic

2.2 Logical Equivalence: The Laws of Logic

logically equivalent

)()(

)()()(

)()()(

)()()(

)(

qpqp

qpqpqp

pqqpqp

pqqpqp

qpqp

We can eliminate the connectives and

from compound statements.(and,or,not) is a complete set.

Page 11: Fundamentals of Logic

2.2 Logical Equivalence: The Laws of Logic

Ex 2.8. DeMorgan's Laws

( )

( )

p q p q

p q p q

p and q can be any compound statements.

Page 12: Fundamentals of Logic

2.2 Logical Equivalence: The Laws of Logic

( )

( ) ( )

( )

( )

( ) ( ) ( )

( ) ( )

1

2

3

4

p p

p q p q

p q p q

p q q p

p q q p

p q r p q r

p q r p q r

Law of Double Negation

Demorgan's Laws

Commutative Laws

Associative Laws

Page 13: Fundamentals of Logic

2.2 Logical Equivalence: The Laws of Logic

( ) ( ) ( ) ( )

( ) ( ) ( )

( ) ,

( ) ,

( ) ,

( ) ,

( ) ( ) , ( )

5

6

7

8

9

10

0 0

0 0

0 0 0 0

p q r p q p r

p q r p q p r

p p p p p p

p F p p T p

p p T p p F

p T T P F F

p p q p p p q p

Distributive Law

Idempotent Law

Identity Law

Inverse Law

Domination Law

Absorption Law

Page 14: Fundamentals of Logic

2.2 Logical Equivalence: The Laws of Logic

All the laws, aside from the Law of Double Negation, allfall naturally into pairs.

Def. 2.3 Let s be a statement. If s contains no logical connectivesother than and , then the dual of s, denoted sd, is thestatement obtained from s by replacing each occurrence ofand by and , respectively, and each occurrence of T0 and F0 by F0 and T0, respectively.

Eg. s p q r T s p q r Fd: ( ) ( ), : ( ) ( ) 0 0

The dual of is p q ( ) p q p qd

Page 15: Fundamentals of Logic

2.2 Logical Equivalence: The Laws of Logic

Theorem 2.1 (The Principle of Duality) Let s and t be statements.If , then .s t s td d

Ex. 2.10 P p q p q: ( ) ( ) is a tautology. Replace

each occurrence of p by r sP r s q r s q1: [( ) ] [ ( ) ] is also a tautology.

First Substitution Rule (replace each p by another statement q)

Page 16: Fundamentals of Logic

2.2 Logical Equivalence: The Laws of Logic

Second Substitution Rule

Ex. 2.11 P p q r

P p q r

: ( )

: ( )

1

Then, P P 1

because ( ) ( )p q p q

Ex. 2.12 Negate and simplify the compound statement ( )p q r

[( ) ] [ ( ) ]

[( ) ] ( )

( )

p q r p q r

p q r p q r

p q r

Page 17: Fundamentals of Logic

2.2 Logical Equivalence: The Laws of Logic

Ex. 2.13 What is the negation of "If Joan goes to Lake George,then Mary will pay for Joan's shopping spree."?

Because ( ) ( )p q p q p q

The negation is "Joan goes to Lake George, but (or and)Mary does not pay for Joan's shopping spree."

Page 18: Fundamentals of Logic

2.2 Logical Equivalence: The Laws of Logic

Ex. 2.15

p q0011

1101

1101

1011

1011

0101

p q q p q p p q

contrapositive of p q

converseinverse

Page 19: Fundamentals of Logic

2.2 Logical Equivalence: The Laws of Logic

Compare the efficiency of two program segments.z:=4;for i:=1 to 10 do begin x:=z-1; y:=z+3*i; if ((x>0) and (y>0)) then writeln(‘The value of the sum x+y is’, x+y) end

.

.

.if x>0 then if y>0 then …

rqp )( )( rqp

Number of comparisons?20 vs. 10+3=13

logically equivalent

Page 20: Fundamentals of Logic

2.2 Logical Equivalence: The Laws of Logic

simplification of compound statement

Ex. 2.16

pFp

qqp

qpqp

qpqp

qpqp

0

)(

)()(

)()(

)()( Demorgan's Law

Law of Double Negation

Distributive Law

Inverse Law andIdentity Law

Page 21: Fundamentals of Logic

2.3 Logical Implication: 2.3 Logical Implication: Rules of InferenceRules of Inference

an argument: ( )p p p qn1 2

premises conclusion

is a valid argument

( )p p p qn1 2 is a tautology

Page 22: Fundamentals of Logic

2.3 Logical Implication: Rules of Inference

Ex. 2.19 statements: p: Roger studies. q: Roger plays tennis.r: Roger passes discrete mathematics.

premises: p1: If Roger studies, then he will pass discrete math.p2: If Roger doesn't play tennis, then he'll study.p3: Roger failed discrete mathematics.Determine whether the argument ( )p p p q1 2 3 is

valid.p p r p q p p r

p p p q

p r q p r q

1 2 3

1 2 3

: , : , :

( )

[( ) ( ) ]

which is a tautology,the original argumentis true

Page 23: Fundamentals of Logic

2.3 Logical Implication: Rules of Inference

p r s0 0 0 0 1 1 10 0 1 0 1 1 10 1 0 0 1 0 10 1 1 0 1 1 11 0 0 0 1 1 11 0 1 0 1 1 11 1 0 1 0 0 11 1 1 1 1 1 1

p r ( )p r s r s [ (( ) )] ( )p p r s r s Ex. 2.20

a tautologydeduced or inferred fromthe two premises

Page 24: Fundamentals of Logic

2.3 Logical Implication: Rules of Inference

Def. 2.4. If p, q are any arbitrary statements such thatis a tautology, then we say that p logically implies q and we

p q

p q to denote this situation.write

p q means p q is a tautology.

p q means p q is a tautology.

Page 25: Fundamentals of Logic

2.3 Logical Implication: Rules of Inference

rule of inference: use to validate or invalidate a logicalimplication without resorting to truth table (which will beprohibitively large if the number of variables are large)

Ex 2.22 Modus Ponens (the method of affirming) or the Rule of Detachment

[ ( )]p p q q p

p q

q

Page 26: Fundamentals of Logic

2.3 Logical Implication: Rules of Inference

Example 2.23 Law of the Syllogism

[( ) ( )] ( )p q q r p r

p q

q r

p r

Ex 2.25 p

p q

q r

r

Page 27: Fundamentals of Logic

2.3 Logical Implication: 2.3 Logical Implication: Rules of InferenceRules of Inference

Ex. 2.25 Modus Tollens (method of denying)

[( ) ]p q q p p q

q

p

p r

r s

t s

t u

u

p

p s

p

example:

s tt u

s u

p u

Page 28: Fundamentals of Logic

2.3 Logical Implication: Rules of Inference

Ex. 2.25 Modus Tollens (method of denying)

[( ) ]p q q p p q

q

p

p r

r s

t s

t u

u

p

ts

p s

p

example:

another reasoning

Page 29: Fundamentals of Logic

2.3 Logical Implication: Rules of Inference

fallacy p q

q

p

(1) If Margaret Thatcher is the president of the U.S., then she is at least 35 years old.(2) Margaret Thatcher is at least 35 years old.(3) Therefore, Margaret Thatcher is the president of the US.

Page 30: Fundamentals of Logic

2.3 Logical Implication: Rules of Inference

p q

p

q

fallacy

(1) If 2+3=6, then 2+4=6.(2) 2+3(3) Therefore, 2+4

6 6

Page 31: Fundamentals of Logic

2.3 Logical Implication: Rules of Inference

Ex 2.26 Rule of Conjunctionp

q

p q

Ex. 2.27 Rule of Disjunctive Syllogism

p q

p

q

Page 32: Fundamentals of Logic

2.3 Logical Implication: Rules of Inference

Ex. 2.28 Rule of Contradiction

p F

p0

Proof by Contradiction

( )p p p qn1 2 To prove

we prove 021

021

)(

))((

Fqppp

Fqppp

n

n

qp

qp

qp

)(

)(

Page 33: Fundamentals of Logic

2.3 Logical Implication: Rules of Inference

Ex. 2.29 p r

p q

q s

r s

r p r q

r s

Page 34: Fundamentals of Logic

2.3 Logical Implication: Rules of Inference

Ex. 2.30p q

q r s

r t u

p t

u

( )

( )

p, t

qr, s

t u

u

No systematic way to prove except by truth table (2n).

Page 35: Fundamentals of Logic

2.3 Logical Implication: Rules of Inference

Ex 2.32 Proof by Contradiction

p q

q r

r

p

p q

q r

r

p

F0

qr

F0

Page 36: Fundamentals of Logic

2.3 Logical Implication: Rules of Inference

p

p

p

q rn

1

2

p

p

p

q

r

n

1

2

p q r

p q r

p q r

p q r

p q r

p q r

( )

( )

( )

( )

( )

( )

reasoning

Page 37: Fundamentals of Logic

2.3 Logical Implication: Rules of Inference

Ex 2.33u r

r s p t

q u s

t

q p

( ) ( )

( )

u r

r s p t

q u s

t

q

p

( ) ( )

( ) u s u, s

r p t

p

Page 38: Fundamentals of Logic

2.3 Logical Implication: Rules of Inference

How to prove that an argument is invalid?Just find a counterexample (of assignments) for it !

Ex 2.34 Show the following to be invalid.p

p q

q r s

t r

s t

( )

0

1

s=0,t=1

p=1

r=1 ( )r s 0

q=0

Page 39: Fundamentals of Logic

2.4 The Use of 2.4 The Use of QuantifiersQuantifiers

Def. 2.5 A declarative sentence is an open statement if(1) it contains one or more variables, and(2) it is not a statement, but(3) it becomes a statement when the variables in it are replaced by certain allowable choices.

examples: The number x+2 is an even integer. x=y, x>y, x<y, ...

universe

Page 40: Fundamentals of Logic

2.4 The Use of Quantifiers

notations: p(x): The number x+2 is an even integer.

q(x,y): The numbers y+2, x-y, and x+2y are even integers.

p(5): FALSE, p( )7 : TRUE, q(4,2): TRUE

p(6): TRUE, p( )8 : FALSE, q(3,4): FALSE

For some x, p(x) is true.For some x,y, q(x,y) is true.

For some x, is true.For some x,y, is true.

p x( )q x y( , )

Therefore,

Page 41: Fundamentals of Logic

2.4 The Use of Quantifiers

existential quantifier: For some x:universal quantifier: For all x:

x

x

x in p(x): free variablex in : bound variablex p x, ( ) x p x, ( ) is either

true or false.

Page 42: Fundamentals of Logic

2.4 The Use of Quantifiers

Ex 2.36

p x x

q x x

r x x x

s x x

( ):

( ):

( ):

( ):

0

0

3 4 0

3 0

2

2

2

x p x r x TRUE

x p x q x TRUE

x p x q x TRUE

x q x s x FALSE

x r x s x FALSE

x r x p x FALSE

[ ( ) ( )]:

[ ( ) ( )]:

[ ( ) ( )]:

[ ( ) ( )]:

[ ( ) ( )]:

[ ( ) ( )]:

x=4

x=1

x=5,6,...

x=-1

universe: real numbers

Page 43: Fundamentals of Logic

2.4 The Use of Quantifiers

Ex 2.37 implicit quantification

sin cos2 2 1x x x x x(sin cos )2 2 1is

"The integer 41 is equal to the sum of two perfect squares."is m n m n[ ]41 2 2

Page 44: Fundamentals of Logic

2.4 The Use of Quantifiers

Def. 2.6 logically equivalent for open statement p(x) and q(x)

x p x q x[ ( ) ( )]

p(x) logically implies q(x)

x p x q x[ ( ) ( )]

, i.e., p x q x( ) ( ) for any x

Page 45: Fundamentals of Logic

2.4 The Use of Quantifiers

Ex. 2.42 Universe: all integers

r x x

s x x

( ):

( ):

2 1 5

92

then x r x s x[ ( ) ( )] is false

but xr x xs x( ) ( ) is true

Therefore, x r x s x[ ( ) ( )] xr x xs x( ) ( )

but x p x q x xp x xq x[ ( ) ( )] [ ( ) ( )]

for any p(x), q(x) and universe

Page 46: Fundamentals of Logic

2.4 The Use of Quantifiers

For a prescribed universe and any open statements p(x), q(x):

x p x q x xp x xq x

x p x q x xp x xq x

x p x q x xp x xq x

xp x xq x x p x q x

[ ( ) ( )] [ ( ) ( )]

[ ( ) ( )] [ ( ) ( )]

[ ( ) ( )] [ ( ) ( )]

[ ( ) ( )] [ ( ) ( )] Note this!

Page 47: Fundamentals of Logic

2.4 The Use of Quantifiers

How do we negate quantified statements that involve a singlevariable?

[ ( )] ( )

[ ( )] ( )

[ ( )] ( )

[ ( )] ( )

xp x x p x

xp x x p x

x p x xp x

x p x xp x

Page 48: Fundamentals of Logic

2.4 The Use of Quantifiers

Ex. 2.44 p(x): x is odd.q(x): x2-1 is even.

Negate x p x q x[ ( ) ( )] (If x is odd, then x2-1 is even.)

[ ( ( ) ( )] [ ( ( ) ( ))]

[ ( ( ) ( ))] [ ( ) ( )]

x p x q x x p x q x

x p x q x x p x q x

There exists an integer x such that x is odd and x2-1 is odd.(a false statement, the original is true)

Page 49: Fundamentals of Logic

2.4 The Use of Quantifiers

multiple variables

x yp x y y xp x y

x yp x y y xp x y

( , ) ( , )

( , ) ( , )

Page 50: Fundamentals of Logic

2.4 The Use of Quantifiers

BUT

Ex. 2.48 p(x,y): x+y=17.

x yp x y( , ) : For every integer x, there exists an integer y such that x+y=17. (TRUE)

y xp x y( , ) : There exists an integer y so that for all integer x, x+y=17. (FALSE)

),(),( yxxpyyxypx Therefore,

Page 51: Fundamentals of Logic

2.4 The Use of Quantifiers

Ex 2.49

[ [( ( , ) ( , )) ( , )]]

[ [( ( , ) ( , )) ( , )]]

[( ( , ) ( , )) ( , )]

[ [ ( , ) ( , )] ( , )]

[( ( , ) ( , )) ( , )]

x y p x y q x y r x y

x y p x y q x y r x y

x y p x y q x y r x y

x y p x y q x y r x y

x y p x y q x y r x y

Page 52: Fundamentals of Logic

Sources

R.S. Chang