foucault gutting on

Upload: garddo

Post on 06-Apr-2018

213 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/3/2019 Foucault Gutting on

    1/8

    Gutting on Foucault (Intro to The Cambridge Companion to Foucault):

    No unifying theme can make sense of Fs work as a whole, although the demand

    for interpretation that his work makes encourages the search for such a theme

    (1).

    His work is fragmentary, ad hoc and incomplete (2); each work is determined by

    concerns and approaches specific to it. There is no progression.

    Tempted, though, by the thought that we can map two dimensions to his work:

    first, he is a philosophical historian who developed a series of complimentary

    methodsan archaeology of discourse (inHist Mad, The Birth of the Clinic, The

    order of things and The Archaeology of Know), a genealogy of power relations(Disc & Pun, The history of sexuality 1) and a problematization of ethics (The use

    of pleasure and The care of the self). The second dimension makes him a

    historicist philosopher offering successively deeper and complementary theories

    of knowledge, power and the self. Together these make for a tempting overall

    interpretation of F as offering a comprehensive understanding of human reality

    underpinned by new methods of historical analysis.

    He instances Dreyfus and Rabinows who see F as offering an interpretive

    analytics, (an analysis of the sources and legitimacy of our concepts interpreted

    by the historically given set ofpractices that express them) that is the most

    powerful (if not ahistorical) instrument of cultual analysis on offer.

    This wont do, however: Foucaults distinctive and most valued characteristics are

    his specificity and his marginality. The strength of each of his works is

    undermined if one tries to force all of them into an embracing and harmonising

    overall framework. F himself hardly ever refers to his own earlier works, even

    when he is returning to a topic hes dealt with earlier. He wants to show us

    liberating alternatives to specific realms of inevitabilityin psychiatry, medicine,

    the social sciences, for example. He wants to help us save ourselves (4).

    Foucault fights guerilla campaigns, construct[ing] theories and methods

    subordinated to the tactical needs of the particular analysis at hand (4).

  • 8/3/2019 Foucault Gutting on

    2/8

    Foucault is not offering us a reconstructed or even a new discipline: he is trying to

    alert us to and to move us away from the dangers of disciplines, and the

    apparently necessary truths they incline us to commit to.

    (The masked philosopher is an anonymous interview in which F describes his

    dream that books are no longer subjected to totalizing judgementsones that

    would sovereign or dressed in red [4].)

    On the other hand, Foucault does offer synoptic characterisations of his works

    (even if they vary as much as his works). a) in 1969 all his previous works were

    trying to sketch the approach to the analysis of discursive formations that he

    offers in theArch of know;b) in 1977 he sees himself as always having been

    interested in power; c) by 1982, it is not power, but the subject, which is the

    general theme of my research (4). [Of course, its not hard to see ways in which

    these three claims can be read as mutually consistenteven supporting.]

    Also, G presents textual evidence that when he wrote AK F was tempted to see

    himself as offering a new discipline (5).

    Overall, it is best to see him as like a skilled artesan, who produced a number of

    outstanding intellectual objects under the stimulus of specific circumstances. By

    looking thus, we can see that he produces three broad sorts: histories, theories and

    myths (6). And G goes on to characterise each of these sorts.

    The histories are driven by specificities and it is only in retrospect that these are

    idealised as coming in the archaeological v the genealogical forms. G proposes

    tracking them along four dimensions: the history of ideas, of concepts, of the

    present and of experience.

    * Although he disdains conventional history of ideas, F does quite a bit of it in his

    histories (7).

    * Yet Canguilhems history of concepts is central to F. Canguilhem insists on

    the distinction between the concepts that interpret scientific data and the theories

    that explain them, whereas Anglophones (Kuhn as much as Hempel) see theories

    as interpretations of data, which, therefore, define the concepts in terms of which

    the data are understood (7; he gives some egs pp7-8). [V interesting and links up

    with lots of important questions {see, especially, the discussion of Cuvier v

  • 8/3/2019 Foucault Gutting on

    3/8

    Lamarck as developing the idea at the heart of Darwins descent with

    modification; one should consult Hacking, here}, but it seems obvious that

    concept v theory of x wont do: one needs, at least,to consider concept v

    conception v theory of x.]

    Yet F also extended Cs methods: the latter saw concepts and disciplines as tied

    together [through the history of the discipline in which theoretical alternatives

    compete with one another], but F argues that apparently v different disciplines can

    have similar basic concepts, so that the various disciplines of one era can have

    more in common than each has with its successor discipline of the subsequent era.

    F holds that second orderphilosophicalconcepts held in common

    (representation, man, resemblance) are conditions of possibility of first order

    concepts and it is these that form the basis of the episteme, that system of

    concepts that defines knowledge the intellectual subconscious for a given

    intellectual era (8-9). [Very Durkheimian, in fact.] This enables the historian to

    define a discipline in terms other than those in which it defines itself.

    This archaeological approach really does contrast with std hist of ideas, with its

    emphasis on thinkers and their works and the influences upon one another. It

    allows F to construct a space, defined by a system of rules more fundamental

    than the assertions of individuals thinking in the space the study of which is

    usually thought to be most important, but which F dismisses as doxology (10).

    F also offers us histories of the present, notwithstanding the fact that by

    definition history is concerned with the past. F begins with a diagnosis that

    something is wrong in current circumstancessomething intolerableand then

    sets about trying to discover how it got to be so: to use an understanding of the

    past to understand something that is intolerable in the present (10): in short, to

    come up with an aetiology. G holds that this is not so unusual in historians,

    although the way F stresses this aspect of his work is, but points out that whereas

    they want to show how, given all the historical causes in operation, the present

    was inevitbale, F wishes to stress how contingent and therefore surpassable our

    present was. How could we do anything but put lunatics into asylums? Etc. F

    wants to show that the processes leading to our present practices and institutions

  • 8/3/2019 Foucault Gutting on

    4/8

    were by no means inevitable (10). [Evitability v inevitabilitynecessity v

    contingency even more soa trouble/muddle inducing opposition: cf determined

    v predetermined.] He wants to stress the social construction, and hence historicity,

    of our conceptions of, for example, madness, and their lack of privileged access

    to the truth of madness (11).

    [All this makes clear why G elsewhere {the SEP article: section three} says that F

    reverses Kants move of showing the necessity in the apparently contingent, by

    showing the contingent in the apparently necessary. {A formulation which, like

    those beautiful, voluptuous drag queens, is also nicely decked out to sow

    confusion and heartache.}]

    As for madness so with man, a concept that only came into existence after

    Kant distinguished thought from representation, by showing that representation

    could be treated as just one form of thought (12). [Is this clear? I suspect not,

    but see Gs SEP article.] F held that the concept of man as both finite, according

    to his representation in the sciences, yet also the source of representations (as

    both the source of the world and an object in the world) is a failure, for it cannot

    be made coherent. Counter-sciences, like anthropology and psychoanalysis.

    * The history of the present is one definition of genealogy: this represents the

    effort to question the necessity of our dominant categories and procedures (12).

    Foucault intended the term "genealogy" to evoke Nietzsche's genealogy of

    morals, particularly with its suggestion of complex, mundane, inglorious origins

    -- in no way part of any grand scheme of progressive history. The point of a

    genealogical analysis is to show that a given system of thought (itself uncovered

    in its essential structures by archaeology, which therefore remains part of

    Foucault's historiography) was the result of contingent turns of history, not the

    outcome of rationally inevitable trends. (SEP article.)

    * The history of experience was a notion F used at different points to characterise

    his histories (Hist of mad; The use of pleasure, for example); but he use it in

    different sensessometimes to refer to what might be available to an abstract,

    anonymous subject at a given point, and at others to refer to individual persons

  • 8/3/2019 Foucault Gutting on

    5/8

    (although these are always situated in fields of knowledge and systems of norms

    the objects uncovered by archaeology and genealogy).

    These dimensionssome constant, others not, depending on the object of enquiry

    can chart Fs histories, G claims (13-14). And just what criteria of assessment

    one should apply to his works varies with the relevance of each of these

    dimensions to the work in question (15). It would be wrong to judge a history of

    the present (the history of something he finds intolerable) in the same terms as an

    archaeological history of a human science. But every one of his historical claims

    needs to be justified on the basis of some set of facts accessible to standard

    historiography [lest his] claims be either gratuitous or not really historical

    (16).

    G then turns to Fs theories: he sees him as an impressive theoretician, but theory

    is not his central concern. He builds temporary scaffoldings for particular

    analytical purposes (and is happy to abandon them to whomever once he has

    finished the project: 16-20).

    * In Ord of things andArch of Know (published only three years apart), for

    example, F uses two very different theories of language (a Heideggerian

    historical ontology in the former, and a structuralist theory in the latter), which G

    sees as a matter of Fs using different intellectual tools to achieve the verydifferent aims of the two works (eschatological assessment based on what the past

    reveals versus a methodological concern to establish a general approach to the

    history of thought). G says [in an interesting argument] that F need not be

    antirealist about theories, nor feel he has phil grounds for rejecting the idea of a

    true theory, but that he is concerned about values theories may have quite apart

    from questions about their ultimate truth (19). [NB. Parts here relevant to

    discussion of Sahlins muddles about structuralist history.]

    * F, then is nonrealistabout theories (19), an insight that G feels helps make

    sense of Fs much discussed views of power (as inHist of sex). For example, his

    reversal of Clauswitzs aphorism about war as politics by another means is a gross

    over-simplification if one is wanting to understand Western history (19). F,

    though, wants to produce a different conception of power through the course of

  • 8/3/2019 Foucault Gutting on

    6/8

    the detailed analysis of the history of modern sexuality: and ifthatis illuminated

    by the non-standard approach to power, then its introduction will have been

    amply justified (20).

    Foucaults myths are no less important than the scholarship and brilliant

    theorising to the success of his books. These deeply emotional themes take the

    form of monsters [and their victims?] and heroes (20). G gives many examples,

    but says the monsters are all manifestations of the grand bogeyman of French

    intellectuals since Flaubert: bourgeois society (21). The myths give his work

    much of their power and intensity, but also make him insensitive to nuance in

    that which he despises. G discusses Fs concern with transgression and intensity

    (22-3) and then notes how, byDisc and punish his heroes are no longer the great

    transgressive artists but those fighting and suffering on the margins of ordinary

    Western life (24).

    * But in his last two books, the unexpectedly different studies on Greek and

    Roman sexuality (The use of pleasure and The care of the self), Fs style and

    tone abruptly change. There we get a cool exploration of alternative aesthetic

    forms of human existence, [which indicate] a calm humanity not found in his

    previous work (24). It is not possible to know what this meant or what it might

    have led to, G avers.

    Flynn on Fs mapping of history (Chap 1)

    All Fs works are histories of a sort: archaeologies, genealogies or (the last two

    books) problematizations. No conflict here; genealogies make explicit what was

    implicit in archaeologies, just as problematizations make explicit what was

    implicit in boththe issue of truth and subjectivity (28).

    Flynn wants to consider these three forms and then say what is distinctive aboutFs approach to history, which he thinks inheres in Fs nominalism, his approach

    to the historical event, his spatialization of Reason and his conception of

    problematization: these themes serve to critique, respectively, Platonists,

    historians of culture, dialecticians and traditional historians (of the battles-and-

    treaties variety).

  • 8/3/2019 Foucault Gutting on

    7/8

    Fs three archaeologies (of madness, clinical medicine and the human sciences)

    examine the systems that establish statements as events (with their own

    conditions and domain of appearance) and as things (with their own possibility

    and field of use) (AK: 128). These statements represent the discourses that

    condition what counts as knowledge in a particular period (29). These

    statements, though, are not langue [how could they be?]; rather they are forms of

    practice, and they represent the archive [consider the etymology] that in a given

    period constitutes the historical a priori (29).

    Flynn suggests that F views discourses in the same way Witt viewed languge

    gamespreconceptual, anonymous, socially sanctioned body of rules that

    govern ones manner of perceiving, judging, imagining and acting; these form

    the background of intelligibility to actions (30). They do so by defining what is to

    be done (and rationalise it with rules and norms) andthey render true/false

    discourse possiblethey arejudicative and veridicative. (So power/knowledge

    couple is set up is here and the later focus on it is merely an elaboration.)

    So the archive is the locus of the rules and prior practices forming the conditions

    of inclusion or exclusion that enable certain practices and prevent others from

    being accepted as scientific or moral, or whatever other social rubric may be in

    use at a particular epoch (30). Different epochs, different archives; and thepractices that they comprise are not deduced but discovered; they are

    positivities to be encountered rather than texts or documents to be interpreted

    (30). This positivism he never abandoned.

    His early archaeologies are of borderline sciences, where epistemic breaks

    suddenly make new disciplines appear. The post factum necessity that these

    breaks assume is misleading: they could not have been predicted beforehand and

    they involve chance events; he wantedeven at this stageto make chance a

    category in the production events (AK:231)an ambition that becomes more

    important with the genealogies. [Sahlins and his structure of the conjuncture is

    similarly struggling with chance and necessityhe even mentions Monod, I

    think; he and F both misconstrue the distinction as an opposition, as do the

    legions of current writers who fetishize contingency.]

  • 8/3/2019 Foucault Gutting on

    8/8

    F gives a special termepistemeto those aspects of the archive that constitute

    the veridicative function of a scientific practice. It was the way this and cognate

    terms were used in Fs early work that led readers to see him as a structuralist,

    especially as he too wrote against subjectivist/humanist thought. Flynn, though,

    says that his nominalism, positivism and his Nietzschean inclinations all make

    him a post-structuralist.

    The four works of the archaeological period show a curious unity-within-

    diversity in addrssing practices that make the exclusions needed to gain the

    honorific science and revealing a sense of the unspoken and unspeakable

    relationships between such apparently disjointed areas as clinical medicine,

    medicalization of madness and the scientific status of various social inquiries

    which are pronounced to have more in common with each other than with their

    presumed precursors in traditional historical accounts (31).

    Bachelards notion of an epistemic break is important to the archaeological

    picture: the world is perceived in different ways either side of such a breaknew

    objects for investigation come into being and others fall away (the brain or a

    corpse were different objects before and after the end of the Classical Age [clouds

    of confusion condensed into a drop]). [Note the Whorfian/Saussurean tenor of

    this, but its a mistake to assimilate F to these {just as its a mistake to associateWhorf and Saussure, except in so far as they appeal to a certain simple

    relativism}. His is still a processual rather than a structural model.]