feeling better about moral dilemmas

14
This article was downloaded by: [UOV University of Oviedo] On: 31 October 2014, At: 05:04 Publisher: Routledge Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office: Mortimer House, 37-41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK Journal of Moral Education Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information: http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/cjme20 Feeling better about moral dilemmas Jason K. Swedene Corresponding author a a Lake Superior State University , USA Published online: 16 Aug 2006. To cite this article: Jason K. Swedene Corresponding author (2005) Feeling better about moral dilemmas, Journal of Moral Education, 34:1, 43-55, DOI: 10.1080/03057240500049307 To link to this article: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/03057240500049307 PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE Taylor & Francis makes every effort to ensure the accuracy of all the information (the “Content”) contained in the publications on our platform. However, Taylor & Francis, our agents, and our licensors make no representations or warranties whatsoever as to the accuracy, completeness, or suitability for any purpose of the Content. Any opinions and views expressed in this publication are the opinions and views of the authors, and are not the views of or endorsed by Taylor & Francis. The accuracy of the Content should not be relied upon and should be independently verified with primary sources of information. Taylor and Francis shall not be liable for any losses, actions, claims, proceedings, demands, costs, expenses, damages, and other liabilities whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in connection with, in relation to or arising out of the use of the Content. This article may be used for research, teaching, and private study purposes. Any substantial or systematic reproduction, redistribution, reselling, loan, sub-licensing, systematic supply, or distribution in any form to anyone is expressly forbidden. Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at http://www.tandfonline.com/page/terms- and-conditions

Upload: jason-k

Post on 07-Mar-2017

214 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Feeling better about moral dilemmas

This article was downloaded by: [UOV University of Oviedo]On: 31 October 2014, At: 05:04Publisher: RoutledgeInforma Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registeredoffice: Mortimer House, 37-41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK

Journal of Moral EducationPublication details, including instructions for authors andsubscription information:http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/cjme20

Feeling better about moral dilemmasJason K. Swedene Corresponding author aa Lake Superior State University , USAPublished online: 16 Aug 2006.

To cite this article: Jason K. Swedene Corresponding author (2005) Feeling better about moraldilemmas, Journal of Moral Education, 34:1, 43-55, DOI: 10.1080/03057240500049307

To link to this article: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/03057240500049307

PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE

Taylor & Francis makes every effort to ensure the accuracy of all the information (the“Content”) contained in the publications on our platform. However, Taylor & Francis,our agents, and our licensors make no representations or warranties whatsoever as tothe accuracy, completeness, or suitability for any purpose of the Content. Any opinionsand views expressed in this publication are the opinions and views of the authors,and are not the views of or endorsed by Taylor & Francis. The accuracy of the Contentshould not be relied upon and should be independently verified with primary sourcesof information. Taylor and Francis shall not be liable for any losses, actions, claims,proceedings, demands, costs, expenses, damages, and other liabilities whatsoeveror howsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in connection with, in relation to orarising out of the use of the Content.

This article may be used for research, teaching, and private study purposes. Anysubstantial or systematic reproduction, redistribution, reselling, loan, sub-licensing,systematic supply, or distribution in any form to anyone is expressly forbidden. Terms &Conditions of access and use can be found at http://www.tandfonline.com/page/terms-and-conditions

Page 2: Feeling better about moral dilemmas

Feeling better about moral dilemmas

Jason K. Swedene*

Lake Superior State University, USA

There has been a trend in contemporary ethics to believe that a morally admirable agent would feel

negative self-assessing emotions following even the best possible choice in a moral dilemma. A

commonly held reason for holding this position is that agents who are well-brought up are trained

to feel negative self-assessing emotions when they do something morally forbidden under ordinary

circumstances, and that agents acting for the best in a dilemma will nonetheless recognize their

deed as morally forbidden. I challenge this view and reach the conclusion that without the further

notion that the agent morally failed, negative self-assessing emotions ought to be discouraged in

favour of emotions such as grief and sadness, which are negative and self-conscious, but not self-

assessing. I then offer some cognitive strategies moral educators could impart to help persons feel

emotions that better reflect the nuances of moral dilemmas.

We ought to have been brought up in a particular way from our very youth, as Plato

says, so as to both delight in and to be pained by the things that we ought. (Aristotle,

Nicomachean Ethics, 1104b, 11–13)

Our world is such that we must make tough decisions, as we navigate the many

demands of modern life. There are indeed a plurality of values and a plurality of

situations in which we must choose between actions that embody competing and

irreducible values. When we need our morality most may turn out to be precisely the

time in which we likely will not feel pleasant about acting in accordance with it.

Since virtue is connected with how we feel about acting morally, should a virtuous

agent acting as morally as he can be expected to feel distress? What kind of distress?

The impetus for this brief essay is to respond to commonly held views that a virtuous

agent would feel painful self-assessing emotions, such as guilt or agent-regret, even

in cases wherein the agent acts for the best. The most accepted position, referred to

as the ‘habituation view’, celebrates dilemmatic negative self-assessing emotions as

by-products of a sound moral upbringing. I shall argue that while the habituation

view provides a useful explanation of why good agents often do feel badly even when

they have acted with moral responsibility, the habituation view cannot substantiate

itself unless it is supplemented with the claim that the dilemmatic action was

categorically wrong, a position few ethicists would support. The challenge now

*Lake Superior State University, Department of Arts, Letters and Social Sciences, 650 W.

Easterday Avenue, Sault Sainte Marie, MI, 49783, USA. Email: [email protected]

Journal of Moral Education

Vol. 34, No. 1, March 2005, pp. 43–55

ISSN 0305-7240 (print)/ISSN 1465-3877 (online)/05/010043-13

# 2005 Journal of Moral Education Ltd

DOI: 10.1080/03057240500049307

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

UO

V U

nive

rsity

of

Ovi

edo]

at 0

5:04

31

Oct

ober

201

4

Page 3: Feeling better about moral dilemmas

becomes how to integrate a revised emotional awareness into our moral instruction

so that we might be pained only at the things we ought.

Moral dilemmas and the virtuous agent’s emotional profile: the habituation

view

Emotions have a significant place in our moral lives. Our emotions inform us of

moral salience, contribute to deliberation, connect us with other human beings, and

alert us (sometimes painfully) that we have acted immorally. The self-assessing

emotions in particular bear so much on our moral lives because they function to

draw attention to the ways in which we interact with the world. Both guilt and agent-

regret, for example, alert us to moral wrongdoing. Guilt and agent-regret are

negative self-assessing emotions. By ‘negative self-assessing emotions’ I mean those

emotions which include a discomfort (hence, ‘negative’) directed at the self (hence,

‘self-assessing’). All self-assessing emotions seem to indicate that one’s character is

attuned to the world, one’s life, and one’s action. And, of course, the virtuous person

would be so attuned. All self-assessing emotions, and a fortiori all negative self-

assessing emotions, involve a cognition or belief about the self’s role in the greater

world. I might feel a negative self-assessing emotion in the aftermath of betraying the

trust of a friend. In that case, I would notice that such behaviour is wrong, harmful,

and that it was me who performed that wrong behaviour.

Granted that a virtuous agent would hold a proper belief about her role in the

action (an intellectual virtue) and react properly (a moral virtue), we might wonder

why she persists in experiencing a negative self-assessing emotion following

dilemmatic action. Would not a proper belief at least include the content that the

agent acted for the best, acted reasonably, or some other variant? Most of us would

grant that even as the dilemmatic virtuous agent acts for the best with compunction,

the agent would nonetheless believe that she acts appropriately given the

circumstances. And moreover, it is that very belief of propriety that allows her to

follow through with tough decisions even as competing imperatives pull her in

opposing directions. Yet a significant number of ethicists continue to defend the

thesis that negative self-assessing emotions in the wake of dilemmatic action are

warranted, perhaps even to be celebrated. For the remainder of this essay, I employ

examples of severe and tragic dilemmas frequently addressed in the literature. If an

agent may be emancipated from negative self-assessing emotions following his killing

an offspring, he certainly may be emancipated from such emotions following

breaking a promise to a colleague.

The habituation view considers negative self-assessing emotions as non-specific,

involuntary emotional responses constitutive of moral virtue. When an admirable

agent commits an action perceived to be incongruent with his integrity and moral

values, feeling a negative self-assessing emotion is inevitable. In fact, Daniel Statman

(1990) has argued that should the agent fail to feel such an emotion in response to

dilemmatic action, the agent must not have been brought up properly. The morally

admirable agent, so the claim runs, is sensitive to harm and authentic in

acknowledging his causing the harm. For Statman (1990, p. 199), ‘Dispositions

44 J. K. Swedene

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

UO

V U

nive

rsity

of

Ovi

edo]

at 0

5:04

31

Oct

ober

201

4

Page 4: Feeling better about moral dilemmas

cannot be switched on and off at will’. Once habituated to feel regretful, guilty, or

ashamed should he perform some prima facie wrong act, he cannot but experience

those emotions even when circumstances ‘force’ him to do it. This is essentially the

utilitarian R. M. Hare’s (1981) thinking too: emotions are instilled as an efficient

way of motivating behaviour in normal circumstances. Dilemmatic action may elicit

these emotional reactions inculcated by a sound moral upbringing.

Ruth Barcan Marcus (1980) claims that the agent who does not feel dilemmatic

guilt lacks moral awareness. The agent either has not internalized a moral principle

that should have been internalized or does not recognize that his action conflicts with

the moral principle. She writes:

Where an agent acknowledges conflicting obligations, there is sufficient overlap with

dilemma-free cases of moral failure to warrant describing the associated feelings where

present as guilt, and where absent as appropriate to an agent with moral sensibility.

(Marcus, 1980, p. 132)

Since dilemmatic actions resemble non-dilemmatic actions, the well-disposed

cannot help but to feel guilt. Moral sensibility entails that guilt be felt.

If the habituation view held by Statman, Hare, and Marcus is correct, then

Aristotle may very well have missed something important when he proposed that we

should be habituated to experience pleasure in response to acting well and pain in

response to acting poorly. How would the virtuous ship captain feel after tossing

overboard treasured cargo to secure the lives of his crew? In Nicomachean Ethics

Book IV. 9, Aristotle (McKeon, 1941) argues that we would not praise an adult for

feeling a negative self-assessing emotion because that adult should not do anything

that calls for that feeling. Just because the conditional ‘If a good man did x, then he

would feel y’ is true does not entail that ‘A good man would feel y’ is true. A good

man would never do x’. (And the careful thinker would never affirm the

consequent!) Yet even Aristotle in Book III agrees that there are cases of dilemma

in which a good man might do something incongruent with his character, such as

doing something base under the orders of an unprincipled tyrant.

The psychological claim ‘morally admirable agents will feel y in circumstances z’

entails ‘those who aim to be morally admirable should cultivate the disposition to

feel y in circumstances z’. Thus, the psychological claim takes the imperative form of

a moral claim. Moral education is precisely for those who aim to be morally

admirable. I take issue with both the psychological and moral claims.

Moral dilemmas and the virtuous agent’s emotional profile: critique of the

habituation view

The habituation view is attractive for various reasons. Negative self-assessing

emotions are generated by an asymmetry between a morally admirable character and

some perceived feature of his moral act. An admirable moral agent would have been

brought up to recognize when his action produces harm. Following a moral

dilemma, the agent perceives a morally salient feature of his environment, the harm,

Feeling better about moral dilemmas 45

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

UO

V U

nive

rsity

of

Ovi

edo]

at 0

5:04

31

Oct

ober

201

4

Page 5: Feeling better about moral dilemmas

and the morally salient feature of the cause of that harm: himself. This elicits the

negative self-assessing emotion.

Of course, the admirable agent would notice certain features of his world which

bear upon morality, and react as one who noticed those features should react. The

noticed features neatly fall into two classes, each corresponding to an intentional

object of the self-assessing emotion. A first feature is that someone has been harmed

and a second is an acknowledgement that the self brought about that harm.

Regarding the first intentional object, the other person, we would have difficulty

justifying why an admirable agent would not attune himself to the harm done. Harm,

for our purposes, is defined as an effect that hinders or destroys another’s prospects

for living well. Recognizing harm is a good thing: one who is aware of harm is in the

best position to alleviate it and to prevent its further spread.

One could, of course, argue that recognizing some harms (for example, the

genocides and terror in Africa, abhorrent labour conditions, children being sold into

sexual slavery) might lead to an anxiety that makes worthwhile life impossible. On

this view, some harm must be ignored, and if it cannot be ignored, it must be

forgotten quickly lest it consume us. But such a view could hardly be sustained. Even

supposing a most disturbing example of harm, the carnage in Sierra Leone, I cannot

see why recognizing harm should ever be dissuaded. For much of the last decade

rebel forces in Sierra Leone massacred, raped, burned, and mutilated civilians, while

paramilitary forces responded in kind. The amount of human harm in the region is

undeniable. All morally sensitive persons would recognize the suffering and harm of

the civilians tragically caught in the terror of a civil war, but surely not all of them

respond to that recognition in the same way. Some may grow discouraged; others

may become motivated to work towards ending the suffering. Very few persons

become the radical altruist and commit the self-sacrifice of fully devoting themselves

to the cause. The point need not be pushed further: responses to harm are not

determined simply by our recognition of it. Whereas some recognition of harm may

lead one to take unreasonable or even unjust measures in response, desensitizing

ourselves to harm would make us callous, indecent, and morally blind.

Now we must consider whether one who recognizes oneself as a moral contributor

to dilemmatic harm is superior to one who does not. At first glance, the claim that one

should recognize oneself as the moral contributor to harm seems unproblematic,

perhaps even intuitively obvious. But for moral dilemmas which arise through no

fault of the agent’s own, the circumstances that necessitate a forced choice make up

the largest contributing source of harm. The Gestapo officer acting in the backdrop

of institutionalized genocide is certainly a more primary moral source of harm than

Styron’s (1976) Sophie. Sophie, recall, is compelled to choose which of her children

will die at the hands of the Nazis. If other forces conspire to compel the horrible

choice, then why overshadow that fact with the negative self-assessing emotion? The

negative self-assessing emotions, and in particular guilt and agent-regret, focus

moral censure onto the self disproportionately to the moral censure deserved by

other agents. Moreover, why must these emotions imply even the slightest self-

censure when we acted appropriately given the circumstances of dilemma?

46 J. K. Swedene

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

UO

V U

nive

rsity

of

Ovi

edo]

at 0

5:04

31

Oct

ober

201

4

Page 6: Feeling better about moral dilemmas

Admittedly, we may celebrate the habituation view for its description of the

perceptive capabilities of the virtuous agent. Specifically, its description of the

implications of habituation is laudable. A person who has been habituated properly

has the moral sensibility to notice, act, and react in ways that lead to a good life.

That granted, when a person is habituated, even habituated properly, there may be

times when he has to act contrary to disposition.

For Aristotle, habituation is the most effective means (and indeed the only means)

for instilling moral values in the inexperienced. Classroom learning is wasted on the

young for the reason that one must first develop a ‘second nature’, a programmed

system of responses to efficiently and effectively implement ethical imperatives. A

sound moral upbringing emphasizes family, truth, and human life. A sound moral

theory teaches why they are essential. Sophie’s guilt is seen as appropriate because

her guilt proceeds from a character which values the lives of her children. She has

been habituated to feel guilty when she acts against her disposition. Conversely,

Agamemnon’s lack of guilt at sacrificing Iphigenia for the sake of his crew and a

victory in Troy is often seen as inappropriate given the duties of a father towards his

offspring (see Lawall & Mack, 1999). An Agamemnon not saddled with guilt clearly

lacks the disposition to value his child.

On an explanatory level, the habituation view convincingly describes the products

of a firm and unchanging disposition. An agent who faces two mutually exclusive

and morally compelling act choices cannot help but have some aspect of his ultimate

choice go against his disposition. Certainly our dispositions should be averse to

killing family members. A world in which all of us hesitated before we put our family

members in mortal danger is a better world than one that is not such a world. How-

ever, arguments supporting dilemmatic self-assessing emotions go much further.

Marcus (1980) and Statman (1990) each claim that dilemmatic circumstances

and dilemma-free circumstances resemble each other in enough ways that negative

self-assessing emotions should follow both. However, locating the morally relevant

resemblance is paramount. Whereas a negative focus on the self, integral to negative

self-assessing emotions, is warranted by a dilemma-free case of moral failure, such a

focus is not warranted in a dilemma that has arisen through no fault of the agent’s

own. At best, the habituation view explains why it is understandable that an agent

might feel a negative self-assessing emotion, but we are looking for more than

arguments for why self-assessing emotions are ‘understandable’: we want to find out

whether they are warranted and therefore to be encouraged.

To begin to determine warrant, we might ask whether dilemmatic action

resembles dilemma-free cases with respect to moral failure. Did the dilemmatic

agent morally fail in a relevantly similar way as if she failed in a dilemma-free

circumstance? It seems unfair to say that Sophie, who came into a horrific situation

through no prior fault of her own, acted the best she could and yet still failed morally

in a relevantly similar way as if she chose to give her daughter to a killer without

duress. But of Sophie’s guilt, Greenspan (1983, p. 120) writes:

As an ethical reaction … it seems warranted. She knows she is responsible for doing

something wrong, something she could have avoided—even though she could not have

Feeling better about moral dilemmas 47

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

UO

V U

nive

rsity

of

Ovi

edo]

at 0

5:04

31

Oct

ober

201

4

Page 7: Feeling better about moral dilemmas

avoided doing wrong. The same would be true if she had chosen differently, and

allowed both children to be killed. It would be strangely insensitive for a mother in her

position not to experience guilt at either choice.

Notice that Greenspan goes further than to say that Sophie’s self-assessing

emotion is understandable: for Greenspan, ‘it seems warranted’ no matter which

option Sophie chooses. So for Greenspan, Sophie has no choice but to fail morally.

We could depart from Greenspan’s rationale and argue that Sophie fails by choosing

at all—thus making her a culpable collaborator along with the officer. We would thus

maintain a consistency that habituation view proponents do not, when they contend

that Sophie is morally required to choose and fail.

So, I submit here that there is no warrant for self-assessing emotions for cases of

dilemma. But there is room, however, to support a negative emotion. A virtuous

individual can be repulsed by a host of things, including the base actions of others. I

am repulsed as the old are mistreated. I am repulsed at the person who does so. Any

argument saying that the repulsion must take the form of self-assessing repulsion,

then, must be supplemented by additional claims about the moral relevance of self-

assessing emotions in dilemmatic circumstances. That is, a successful habituation

view must explain why personal moral responsibility must imply the repulsion.

Other reasons for endorsing dilemmatic self-assessing emotions

It is clear that negative self-assessing emotions felt under the right circumstances are

constitutive of moral virtue, so these emotions cannot be jettisoned without giving

up virtue itself. But, my own position differs from the habituation view as to what are

the right circumstances and the degree to which a virtuous agent can be expected to

adapt emotionally to the nuances of circumstance. We must remember that the

virtues have dispositional, affective, and intellectual aspects (Annas, 1993).

Habituationists seem to forget about the intellectual aspects when they argue that

dispositions cannot be switched off at will. To say that a virtuous agent would not

have the intellect to have a true belief about his role in dilemmatic circumstances is

not to have much faith in our virtuous agent.

One could argue that emotions should be felt, since the agent is causally

responsible for the ‘rejected alternative’. Marcus’s (1980, pp. 132–133) words are

typical:

Granted that, unlike agents who fail to meet their obligations simpliciter, the agent who

was confronted with a moral dilemma may finally act on the best available reasons. Still,

with respect to the rejected alternative he acknowledges a wrong in that he recognizes

that it was within his power to do otherwise.

Each option is in a sense wrong, regardless of whether the agent acts for the best or

not. The agent’s well-intentioned method or rationale for choosing cannot offset the

fact that what he chooses, ultimately, will be wrong. Some wrongdoing is

inescapable. Some wrongdoing is intractable. Hence it is quite conceivable to some

that a virtuous agent may act for the best, perform wrong, and blame himself for his

choice.

48 J. K. Swedene

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

UO

V U

nive

rsity

of

Ovi

edo]

at 0

5:04

31

Oct

ober

201

4

Page 8: Feeling better about moral dilemmas

But should not negative self-assessing emotions follow only those scenarios in

which the agent bears both causal responsibility and moral responsibility? The

former responsibility, though, is still in question. Commitment to certain moral ends

does not imply that we bear moral responsibility when those ends are not attained.

All of our choices are limited by circumstances and, by their being made, limit future

choices. It would seem destructive (and silly) to go through life feeling negative self-

assessing emotions every time that our characters are not fully represented by the

things we cause.

Perhaps negative self-assessing emotions show that we value something, and

consequently should be endorsed as useful communications of our true intentions. If

Agamemnon felt guilty even though he acted for the best, he would then have shown

the world that he valued his daughter and his role as protector. But, surely there are

other, more effective ways to express our true values. For example, instead of feeling

badly that one has lied to protect innocent life, one may more effectively

communicate honesty by regularly keeping promises and compensating for broken

promises (Strasser, 1987). And such behaviours do not rely on unwarranted negative

self-assessment. Behavioural consistency (over a lifetime) and compensation for

transgressions seem better indicators of true character than emotional display. Our

‘true feelings’ are notoriously difficult to detect. We cannot be sure whether

apparent emotions accurately represent character. Epictetus (Baird & Kauffman,

2003, p. 514) comes to mind: ‘Do not hesitate to sympathize with him so far as

words go, and, if the occasion offers, even groan with him; but be careful not to

groan also in the center of your being’.

But perhaps we act consistently and compensate better with the aid of negative self-

assessing emotions. Marcus (1980), Greenspan (1995), Rorty (1980), and Statman

(1990) laud ‘anticipatory’ guilt and agent regret for their power to prevent future

wrongs because we seek to avoid the emotional fallout. But to celebrate anticipatory

negative self-assessing emotions in order to justify them for dilemmas misses the

point.

Some might seek warrant in the fact that after the action is done, the agent who

feels morally responsible for it would be more likely to make reparations for harm.

Once a transgression is committed, guilt or agent regret can provide that extra push

to make up for the (mis)deed. Even if this were true, it would not explain why such

emotions are warranted because of dilemmatic action. Surely negative self-assessing

emotions are not warranted merely as catalysts of future moral behaviour.

The moral emotions and cognitivism

Practical wisdom guides the life of the truly virtuous. The virtuous walk by reason,

not by program. The cognitivist theory of emotions gives proper attention to the

intellectual complexity of self-assessing emotions and may be used in prescribing

strategies to better control them. Historically speaking, cognitivism culminates the

general shift from considering feeling as the primary component of emotion to

considering thought as primary (Deigh, 1994). The question over whether feeling or

Feeling better about moral dilemmas 49

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

UO

V U

nive

rsity

of

Ovi

edo]

at 0

5:04

31

Oct

ober

201

4

Page 9: Feeling better about moral dilemmas

thought is primary may be construed as odd given that emotions are frequently

experienced as feeling (e.g., many instances of anger). But even anger, an emotion

notoriously associated with feeling, not thinking, can be primarily cognitive. As

Solomon (1980, p. 254) puts it, ‘One can be angry without feeling angry: one can be

angry for three days or five years and not feel anything identifiable as a feeling of

anger continuously through that prolonged period’.

Circumstances often help shape which emotions we feel. An elation that one will

be promoted at work quickly melts into the background (or into extinction) when

one receives a diagnosis of stage four cancer and will work no longer. Pride that one

owns a lavish five bedroom beach house likewise fades when one learns that an

electrical fire has reduced it to ashes. The circumstances per se do not have some

special power to create human emotions. Rather, it is our cognitions about the

circumstances that, when present, affect the emotions. Vary the cognition and the

emotion varies.

The main tenet of cognitivism is that one’s emotion is grounded in a propositional

attitude, belief, or judgement. That one believes she will be promoted forms the

basis for elation directed at her work situation. Upon getting medical results, one

judges she soon will die from cancer, and her grief is directed at her tenuous hold on

life. If additional tests show that the seemingly cancerous cysts were merely blotches

on the previous x-ray, then her grief at her immanent death is unfounded. However,

the experience may have conjured up disturbing, and often-ignored thoughts about

her mortality. So, in the end, she may feel more grief than she did before the x-ray

debacle, but nevertheless any grief is now directed at a different object (her

mortality). The emotion-instance that results is a new one, since the object has

changed. As the cognition varies, so does the emotion.

Since there are many species of emotions, from startle to forlornness, a proof

concluding that cognitivism accounts for all emotions is too complex for the scope of

this essay. But whether or not all emotions per se can be explained in cognitivist

terms, I think that anyone who acknowledges that emotions have moral worth must

in the end acknowledge that the moral emotions are best explained in such terms of

propositional attitude, belief, and judgement. This is especially the case when it

comes to self-assessing emotions. As Elster (1999, p. 149) remarks, the self-assessing

emotions have ‘cognitive antecedents’ which ‘include beliefs about what the subject

is, has, or does’. And if moralists desire us to heed their emotional prescriptions, they

must presuppose that we have some control over our emotions. In short, there must

be some way to control emotions properly defined as moral. Anyone who has ever

said ‘You should be ashamed of yourself’ seems committed to this underlying

assumption.

Cognitivism and control

Recommendations of how to feel must confront the still-powerful belief that we are

passive before our emotions, that they happen to us, and that they are out of our

control. But cognitivists ably defend how emotions can be developed, quelled, or

altered. Moral emotions may be described as ‘indirectly voluntary’: they can be

50 J. K. Swedene

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

UO

V U

nive

rsity

of

Ovi

edo]

at 0

5:04

31

Oct

ober

201

4

Page 10: Feeling better about moral dilemmas

controlled over time even if they cannot be controlled at our immediate behest.

Normal liver function is involuntary: no conscious effort will influence it. Looking

upwards to the sky is directly voluntary insofar as it is fully under our immediate

volition. Moral emotions fall somewhere in between the two categories of the

involuntary and the directly voluntary. Whereas we cannot usually control a spell of

indignation or jealousy at the moment when it occurs, we do not have to sit idly by

and accept these emotions as unwelcome guests for our entire lives.

Three approaches to controlling the emotions may be offered. The first approach

emphasizes that we made a voluntary choice at some point in the past, which in

effect initiated our emotional patterns. A jealous person, for example, at one time

chose a path of interpreting certain relationship triangles as threatening. The jealous

person is therefore responsible for cultivating a jealous disposition and the emotion-

instances that follow from it. The point here is that our initial interpretation was

once under our direct control. The way we interpret present situations, emotionally

(and otherwise), is a result of ways in which we voluntarily chose to interpret past

ones (Louden, 1992).

A second approach to indirect voluntary emotional control emphasizes our ability

to alter future emotional expressions. That is, while we may not be able to control

them at a given moment, we are able to employ longer-term strategies for the future.

A person with dispositions to react in certain uninvited ways can commence a

conscious strategy to become more comfortable reacting in other, more upstanding

ways (Annas, 1993). It may take time to prove successful, but nevertheless such a

conscious plan could work given adequate time.

Robert Solomon (1980) offers a third approach to control of the emotions.

Solomon argues that emotions are essentially nondeliberate choices. Every

emotional response, according to Solomon, contains a normative judgement. For

example, if Janice feels shame for having a sexual encounter with someone she just

met, then Janice judges herself as debased. While Solomon thinks that emotions are

judgements (which may be referred to as a type of action: a judging action), he stops

short of saying that they are directly voluntary. He writes:

We cannot simply have an emotion or stop having an emotion, but we can open

ourselves to argument, persuasion, and evidence. We can force ourselves to be self-

reflective, to make just those judgments regarding the causes and purposes of our

emotions, and also to make the judgments that we are all the while choosing our

emotions, which will ‘defuse’ our emotions. (Solomon, 1980, p. 270)

Solomon’s view is not that we control (or choose) our emotion. The emotions are

not subject to our direct volition. It is that we choose our thoughts, which are the

antecedents of emotions. Self-examination reveals certain thoughts to be the

sufficient cause of the emotion and one may be able to extinguish it by extinguishing

the thought.1 In Solomon’s (1980, p. 260) words:

Our emotions change with our knowledge of the causes of those emotions. If I can

discover the sufficient cause of my anger, in those cases in which the cause and the

object are different (and in which the newly discovered cause is not itself a new object

for anger, as often happens), I can undermine and abandon my anger.

Feeling better about moral dilemmas 51

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

UO

V U

nive

rsity

of

Ovi

edo]

at 0

5:04

31

Oct

ober

201

4

Page 11: Feeling better about moral dilemmas

Each of these three approaches advocates some level of emotional control short of

full direct control. Morality, whatever else may be said about it, is about things for

which we can control with an aim towards bettering human life. The notion that we

can and should control or modify some emotions at some point qualifies certain

emotions as moral. We do not have a moral theory about normal liver function

because we are not responsible for controlling it. Efforts to reassert the importance

of the moral emotions necessitate shifting our view of emotions from something

primarily reactive, physiological, and passive to something primarily evaluative,

cognitive, and active.

A revised outlook on moral education: cognitivism in practice

Rather than the habituation view’s emphasis on the automatic, generalized, and

involuntary, it is important that we instil the kind of moral perception that

emphasizes the conscious, specific, and voluntary. If we can get pupils of morality to

vary their beliefs, their emotions will not be far behind. I argued that the dilemmatic

agent is not morally responsible for his action and therefore should not feel a

negative self-assessing emotion as if he were morally responsible.

The moral educator must encourage a self-examination strategy that considers

whether negligence led to the dilemma, whether the results of the action were

intended, and whether the agent could have made a better choice. If the agent

answers affirmatively to any of these, some negative self-assessment is warranted

proportional to the offence. By endorsing cognitive strategies, both moral educator

and contemporary virtue ethicist offer a vision of moral life more in line with

Aristotle’s view that virtue includes reason and more in line with the complexities

and demands of modern life.

Castelfranchi and Miceli (1998, p. 311) agree that people can indeed think

themselves out of guilt working from the premise, defended in this essay, that:

‘Humans have some control over their emotions. To some extent, they are able to

induce, repress, reorient, manipulate them, and to inhibit or stimulate their

expression’. The cognitive psychologists note that:

In a social context, the person who wanted the event to happen is commonly regarded

as the true causal agent. Even when aware of the effects of one’s action, the executor

may not have the goal that such effects should come about. (Castelfranchi & Miceli,

1998, p. 302)

The ‘true causal agent’ is roughly equivalent to the persons or circumstances

responsible for the dilemma. With adequate reflection on why his dilemma troubled

him at its inception and how he feels towards those persons or values that become

the casualties of his choice, the agent should recognize that he is not to blame.

Without the belief to sustain it, guilt will dissolve.

The moral agent who utilizes these strategies when they are appropriate is on the

path to true moral excellence. The process may likely begin with some outside advice

or perhaps internal uneasiness that he feels an unwarranted self-assessing emotion.

He will then proceed with some investigation. He will reconstruct his moral dilemma

52 J. K. Swedene

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

UO

V U

nive

rsity

of

Ovi

edo]

at 0

5:04

31

Oct

ober

201

4

Page 12: Feeling better about moral dilemmas

from start to consummation. He will hopefully recall that it was forced upon him,

that he felt uneasy about his action-options from the start, that he acted with

compunction (for he still cared about the moral ends his action sacrificed), and he

did not intend any of the objectionable consequences that resulted from his act.

Comparing his honest assessment of his action with his negative self-assessing

emotion, he notices an incongruence: he is not morally responsible and yet his

emotion proceeds from a belief that he is. He revises his belief to better fit the facts

and the emotion alters to something more suitable.

But the agent’s awakening, while a positive step, is not my final end here. It is my

hope that the agent will view his world accurately from the start: recognize his duress

in the face of forced options, act for the best possible outcome, and blame only those

morally responsible for his forced act. And, those who aim to be admirable should

follow the examples of admirable agents to prevent the onset of unwarranted guilt,

for the time and energy to rid oneself of unwarranted emotions can be extremely

taxing.

Moral educators, then, have a few more responsibilities. The first is to develop

more nuanced theories that take into account all relevant circumstantial considera-

tions. This will generally help those whose moral traditions are strongly influenced

by such theories. The second is to inculcate strategies for the self-examination of

emotions. This may be done in journals, but it needs to be emphasized by all who

have a role in shaping moral life. Instead of teaching that feelings are neither right

nor wrong, we should be teaching that feelings are malleable to the beliefs we have,

and that some feelings better reflect the facts of action.

Widespread promotion of these ideas, some might argue, will lead to the

undesirable consequences that persons eager to spare themselves emotional distress

will learn to rationalize themselves out of their just emotional deserts. Admittedly,

this may happen from time to time, but inauthentic people have always rationalized

unrighteous behaviour and will continue to do so. But good persons who act for the

best have too often held themselves captive to irrational negative self-assessing

emotions.

Good persons may actually find themselves feeling more negative self-assessing

emotions as they examine their roles as voters, business persons, and car drivers.

Voters might choose social safety nets over a truly equitable tax structure, business

persons might choose profit over workers’ rights, and car drivers might continue to

choose expediency of travel over potential for pedestrian harm. These are value

trade-offs we make every day without the duress that makes the negative self-

assessing emotions inappropriate for dilemmatic agents.

Even children could be educated to recognize their circumstances, intentions, and

beliefs. Certainly any child capable of experiencing the complex moral emotions of

self-assessment is already aware of notions of harm and blame. When we raise our

children to internalize that events caused by unpredictable accidents do not receive

the same moral weight, we have already begun them on the proposed road to

internalize that events caused by a forced choice should not reflect on the moral

worth of the good person. And even with children, as with adults, a new emphasis on

Feeling better about moral dilemmas 53

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

UO

V U

nive

rsity

of

Ovi

edo]

at 0

5:04

31

Oct

ober

201

4

Page 13: Feeling better about moral dilemmas

thought and moral emotion may produce more experiences of negative self-assessing

emotions inasmuch as children will learn how to better evaluate their own roles in all

actions, not just in moral dilemmas.

John Wilson (2001) points out that negative self-assessing emotions, such as guilt

and shame, express that one recognizes one’s shortcomings of behaviour and

character and that to not feel them when appropriate implies that one does not

recognize them at all. Habituationists would agree that a dilemmatic agent acting for

the best does not make a mistake or have a defect.

We ought to celebrate the appropriateness of negative emotions that are not self-

assessing, such as grief, sadness, regret, and even anger. These emotions indicate

that the agent feels a connection to the harm suffered by others and a wish that

things had worked out otherwise. These emotions are self-conscious in that the agent

acknowledges he is part of the interplay between persons, events, and actions. But

these emotions do not imply the self-censure of guilt. Feeling bad may be called for

sometimes, but one’s distress should not indicate a distortion of the appropriate

object of blame.

Acknowledgements

I wish to acknowledge Carolyn Korsmeyer, Jiyuan Yu, Pablo De Greiff, Michael

Donovan and the JME referees for incisive commentary throughout various stages of

this essay’s preparation.

Note

1. Against the notion that emotions are things that happen to us (i.e., things that we suffer),

Robert Solomon’s brand of cognitivism (judgmentalism) is that emotions contain normative

judgements, for which we are responsible. They are our choices insofar as we can seek out any

normative judgement embedded in them and go on to extinguish it. See also Solomon (1976).

References

Annas, J. (1993) The morality of happiness (New York and Oxford, Oxford University Press).

Baird, F. & Kaufmann, W. (Eds) (2003) Encheiridion (W. Oldfather, Trans., originally published

1928) in: Ancient philosophy (4th edn) (Upper Saddle River, NJ, Prentice Hall).

Castelfranchi, C. & Miceli, M. (1998) How to silence one’s conscience: cognitive defenses against

the feeling of guilt, Journal for the Theory of Social Behavior, 28(3), 287–318.

Deigh, J. (1994) Cognitivism in the theory of emotions, Ethics, 104(4), 824–854.

Elster, J. (1999) Alchemies of the mind: rationality and the emotions (Cambridge, Cambridge

University Press).

Greenspan, P. (1983) Moral dilemmas and guilt, Philosophical Studies, 43(1), 117–125.

Greenspan, P. (1995) Practical guilt (Oxford, Oxford University Press).

Hare, R. (1981) Moral thinking: its levels, method, and point (Oxford, Oxford University Press).

Lawall, S. & Mack, M. (Eds) (1999) Agamemnon (R. Fagles, Trans.) in: The Norton anthology of

world masterpieces (New York and London, W. W. Norton & Company), 521–566.

Louden, R. (1992) Morality and moral theory: a reappraisal and reaffirmation (New York and

Oxford, Oxford University Press).

Marcus, R. B. (1980) Moral dilemmas and consistency, Journal of Philosophy, 77(3), 121–136.

54 J. K. Swedene

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

UO

V U

nive

rsity

of

Ovi

edo]

at 0

5:04

31

Oct

ober

201

4

Page 14: Feeling better about moral dilemmas

McKeon, R. (Ed.) (1941) Nicomachean ethics (W. Ross, Trans.) in: The basic works of Aristotle

(New York, Random House), 935–1126.

Rorty, A. (1980) Agent regret, in: A. Rorty (Ed.) Understanding emotions (Berkeley, Los Angeles,

CA and London, University of California Press).

Solomon, R. (1976) The passions (Garden City, NY, Anchor Press/Doubleday).

Solomon, R. (1980) Emotions and choice, in: A. Rorty (Ed.) Understanding emotions (Berkeley,

Los Angeles, CA and London, University of California Press).

Statman, D. (1990) The debate over the so-called reality of moral dilemmas, Philosophical Papers,

19(3), 191–211.

Strasser, M. (1987) Guilt, regret, and ‘prima facie duties’, Southern Journal of Philosophy, 25(1),

133–146.

Styron, W. (1976) Sophie’s choice (New York, Random House).

Wilson, J. (2001) Shame, guilt and moral education, Journal of Moral Education, 30(1), 71–81.

Feeling better about moral dilemmas 55

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

UO

V U

nive

rsity

of

Ovi

edo]

at 0

5:04

31

Oct

ober

201

4