deconstructing information structure

67
1 Deconstructing Information Structure Angelika Kratzer & Elisabeth Selkirk University of Massachusetts Amherst & University College London * To the memory of Michael Rochemont Abstract The paper argues that the core of what is traditionally referred to as ‘Information Structure’ can be deconstructed into bona fide morphosyntactic features that have familiar types of meanings and just happen to be spelled out prosodically, rather than segmentally or tonally, in Standard American and British English. Setting aside topicality, we discuss two such features, [FoC] and [G]. [FoC] highlights contrasts and, in Standard American and British English, aims for highest prominence in a sentence. [G] is sensitive to discourse givenness and, in Standard American and British English, resists (phrase-level) prominence. There is no representation of newness. Apart from the idiosyncratic properties of [FoC] and [G], which guide their syntactic distribution, felicitous use, and phonological spellout, no special grammatical mechanisms or architectures have to be assumed to account for the many phonological, syntactic, semantic, and pragmatic manifestations of Information Structure notions related to givenness and focus. 1. Introduction: Deconstructing Information Structure Information Structure, as the term is commonly used, covers concepts related to focus, givenness, or topicality. In spite of many years of research, there is no common ground on how those concepts relate to each other, what their place in grammar is, or whether there is any theoretical unity or value to them. Here we will set aside topicality and limit our discussion to givenness and focus. In what follows we will make a case that Standard American English has two bona fide morphosyntactic features triggering discourse requirements related to givenness and contrast. One feature, Givenness marking ([G]- * University of Massachusetts Amherst: Kratzer, Selkirk. University College London: Kratzer.

Upload: others

Post on 28-Feb-2022

2 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: deconstructing information structure

1

DeconstructingInformationStructureAngelikaKratzer&ElisabethSelkirk

UniversityofMassachusettsAmherst&UniversityCollegeLondon*

TothememoryofMichaelRochemont

Abstract

Thepaperarguesthatthecoreofwhatistraditionallyreferredtoas‘Information

Structure’canbedeconstructedintobonafidemorphosyntacticfeaturesthathavefamiliar

typesofmeaningsandjusthappentobespelledoutprosodically,ratherthansegmentally

ortonally,inStandardAmericanandBritishEnglish.Settingasidetopicality,wediscuss

twosuchfeatures,[FoC]and[G].[FoC]highlightscontrastsand,inStandardAmericanand

BritishEnglish,aimsforhighestprominenceinasentence.[G]issensitivetodiscourse

givennessand,inStandardAmericanandBritishEnglish,resists(phrase-level)

prominence.Thereisnorepresentationofnewness.Apartfromtheidiosyncratic

propertiesof[FoC]and[G],whichguidetheirsyntacticdistribution,felicitoususe,and

phonologicalspellout,nospecialgrammaticalmechanismsorarchitectureshavetobe

assumedtoaccountforthemanyphonological,syntactic,semantic,andpragmatic

manifestationsofInformationStructurenotionsrelatedtogivennessandfocus.

1. Introduction:DeconstructingInformationStructure

InformationStructure,asthetermiscommonlyused,coversconceptsrelatedtofocus,

givenness,ortopicality.Inspiteofmanyyearsofresearch,thereisnocommongroundon

howthoseconceptsrelatetoeachother,whattheirplaceingrammaris,orwhetherthere

isanytheoreticalunityorvaluetothem.Herewewillsetasidetopicalityandlimitour

discussiontogivennessandfocus.InwhatfollowswewillmakeacasethatStandard

AmericanEnglishhastwobonafidemorphosyntacticfeaturestriggeringdiscourse

requirementsrelatedtogivennessandcontrast.Onefeature,Givennessmarking([G]-

* UniversityofMassachusettsAmherst:Kratzer,Selkirk.UniversityCollegeLondon:Kratzer.

Page 2: deconstructing information structure

2

marking),issensitivetowhetheranindividual,concept,orpropositionhasbeen

mentionedbeforeorisotherwisepresentinthecontext.Theotherfeature,FoCusmarking

([FoC]-marking),evokesalternativestoamentionedindividual,concept,orproposition,

andtherebybringsoutacontrast.

GivennessandcontrasthavebeendiscussedasdistinctcategoriesofInformationStructure

atleastsinceChafe(1976),withimportantinsightscontributedbythePragueSchool.1

Rochemont(2016)hasanin-depthdiscussionofgivennessinthesenseintendedhereand

distinguishesitfromkindrednotionslikepresuppositionality,definiteness,repetition,and

predictability.WewillfollowRochemontincapitalizingGivennesswheneverthetargeted

notionofgivennessistheoneresponsibleforthelackofprominenceoncontentwords

undercertaindiscourseconditionsinStandardAmericanandBritishEnglish.Inasimilar

vein,wewillusethespellingFoCuswhentheintendednotionoffocusistiedtothe

introductionofalternativestohighlightacontrast.2FoCusinthissenseneedstobe

distinguishedfrominformationfocus(‘newnessfocus’),whichappliestoexpressionsthat

merelypresentnewinformation.Wewilltakeupthistopicinsections4and5,wherewe

willgathertogetherevidencefromdifferentsourcesconfirmingthatGivennessandFoCus,

butnotinformationfocus,arerepresentedbymorphosyntacticfeaturesinStandard

AmericanandBritishEnglish.

1. IntheterminologyofthePragueSchool,constituentsthataregiveninoursensecorrespondto‘themes’,andthosethatarenewto‘rhemes’.Focusedconstituentsinoursenserelateto‘contrast’,andnon-focusedconstituentsto‘background’.Vallduví(2016)givesanoverviewofmodernconstrualsofthosenotionsandmakesclearthatboththe‘theme/rheme’andthe‘contrast/background’dichotomiesareneeded.2. Pretheoretically,we’llcontinuetousethestandardspellingsforgivennessandfocus,andthatincludesoccasionswhenwediscussexamplesfromsourcesthatdonotnecessarilyassumetheInformationStructurenotionswedo.

Page 3: deconstructing information structure

3

Examples(1)to(2)belowgiveafirstillustrationofGivennessandFoCusandtheir

representationvia[G]-markingand[FoC]-marking.3

(1) Me: Didanybodyeattheclementines?Ican’tfindtheminthepantry.

You: (Ithink)Paulamight[haveeatentheclementines]G.

(2) Me: Sarahmailedthecaramels.

You: (No),[Eliza]FoC[mailedthecaramels]G.

Inyouranswerin(1),theVPhaveeatentheclementinesisGiven.Theconceptofhaving

eatentheclementineshasjustbeenmentioned.ItsGivennessissignaledbytheabsenceof

prominenceoneatenandclementinesinStandardAmericanandBritishEnglish.The

contextofyouranswerin(1)discourages(butdoesn’texclude)aninterpretationwhere

PaulaisaFoCus.Onitsmostnaturalinterpretation,youaren’tevokingalternativesto

Paula,thatis,youaren’tcontrastingPaulawithotherpeoplewhomighthaveeatenthe

clementines.Paulaismerelynew,then.Anticipatingargumentsstilltocome,Paulaisn’t

markedwithanyfeaturein(1).In(2),theVPmailedthecaramelsinyourreplyisGiven,

too,butthesubjectElizaisnowaFoCus,notmerelynew.FoCusonElizaevokes

alternativestoEliza:otherpeoplewhomighthavemailedthecaramels.SinceSarahisone

ofthem,yourreplyhighlightsacontrastwithwhatIsaid.

Thephonologicalandsemantic/pragmaticpropertiesof[G]-markingand[FoC]-marking

willbediscussedindetailinsections6and7,sowewillnotgobeyondthisintroductory

illustrationof[G]-markingand[FoC]-markingfornow.

IfGivennessandFoCusarerealizedbygenuinemorphosyntacticfeatures,theywouldbe

expectedtohavetheusualpropertiesofmorphosyntacticfeatures.Theyshouldshow

syntacticbehaviorinatleastsomelanguages,liketriggeringmovementoragreement.

3. Technically,[FoC]and[G]arefeaturesassociatedwithsyntacticnodesandarepartoftheirlabeling.Forconvenience,theyareusuallytheonlylabelsweindicatewhenrepresentingsyntacticstructuresaslabeledbracketings.

Page 4: deconstructing information structure

4

Acrosslanguages,weshouldseevariationinthewaythefeaturesarespelledout:

segmentally,tonally,prosodically,throughacombinationofthose,ornotatall.Ifspelled

outsegmentally,thefeaturesmightinfluenceorbeinfluencedbythephonological

realizationoftheirenvironmentinrule-governedways.Ifspelledouttonallyor

prosodically,theymightinteractwiththetonalandprosodicpropertiesoftheirlinguistic

environment.TherewouldbenothingspecialaboutGivennessandFoCusaffectingthe

prosodicstructureofthesentencestheyoccurininStandardAmericanandBritishEnglish,

then.Aconnectionbetweenprosodyandmeaningwouldbeentirelywithintherangeof

possibilitiespermittedbyfamiliargrammaticalarchitectures

Historically,whathassettheinvestigationofInformationStructureapartfrom

investigationsofothersemanticandpragmaticphenomenalikespeechacts,

presuppositions,quantification,andwhathaveyou,seemstobepreciselythefactthat

importantInformationStructurenotionsarerealizedprosodically,ratherthansegmentally

infamiliarlanguageslikeEnglish.Thisapparentspecialrelationtoprosodyhasledto

proposedgrammaticalarchitectureswhereprosodicrepresentationsthemselvesare

bearersofmeaning.Ononeimplementation,whichcanbetracedbacktoLadd(1980),the

inputforthecomputationcalculatingthediscourseanaphoricimpactofprosodic

prominencearebinarybranchingmetricaltrees,asinLiberman&Prince(1977).4Metrical

treescanrepresentrelativeprominencerelationsbetweensisterconstituentsinsyntactic

representations.InEnglish,thedefaultisforaleft-handsistertobeweakandforaright-

handsistertobestrong.DeviationsfromthedefaultsignaltheimpactofInformation

Structure.Whenasisterthatshouldbeweakbydefaultisactuallystrong,wecaninferthat

itisaFoCus,andwhenasisterthatshouldbestrongisactuallyweak,weknowthatitis

Given.Onsuchanapproach,thecomputationofdiscourserequirementsattachedto

GivennessandFoCusmightonlyneedtotrackdeviationsfromthedefaultprominence

4. ThisapproachisalsoadoptedinWilliams(1996,2012),Wagner(2005,2012),Calhoun(2010),andBüring(2015).

Page 5: deconstructing information structure

5

pattern.5AseparaterepresentationofGivennessorFoCusviamorphosyntacticfeatures

mightseemsuperfluous.

However,asAboh(2010,2016)remindsus,InformationStructureCANhaveanimpacton

prosody,butdoesn’tHAVEto.ThereisnonecessarylinkbetweenprosodyandInformation

Structure.Cross-linguistically,InformationStructurenotionscanbespelledout

segmentally,prosodically,tonally,ornotatall,andcanmoreovershowsyntacticbehavior

liketriggeringmovementoragreement,evenwithouthavinganydistinctiveprosodic

properties.Giventhatprosodicrealizationisjustoneoptionforspellingoutnotionsrelated

toInformationStructure,proposedarchitectureswherethosenotionsarenecessarily

linkedtoprosodicrepresentationsdonotprovideanoptimalbasisforatypologythatmaps

outthefullrangeofpossiblerealizationsofInformationStructureinnaturallanguages.

Forillustration,Aboh(2007a,2007b,2010,2016)documentsthattheGbelanguage

Gungbe(spokeninBenin)usesovertparticlestomarktopicandfocus.Theparticles

appearinleft-peripheralpositionsandattracttopicalorfocusedconstituentstotheedgeof

theirprojections.3(a)and(b)illustrateconstructionswiththefocusparticlewɛ̀:6

(3) a. Sɛ́sínúwɛ̀dàÀsíàbá

SessinouFOCmarryAsiaba

‘SESSINOUmarriedAsiaba.’

5. Ladd(1996,2008)makesclearthat,ultimately,richerprosodicrepresentationsincludinginformationaboutprosodicphrasingwouldbeneeded.6. Glosses:FOCforfocusparticle.Hereandinallfollowingexamples,glossesandtranslationsareexactlyasgiveninthecitedsource,exceptforcapitalization.

Page 6: deconstructing information structure

6

b. Àsíàbáwɛ̀Sɛ́sínúdà

AsiabaFOCSessinoumarry

‘SessinoumarriedASIABA.’

Gungbe.Aboh(2007a:289).

AccordingtoAboh(personalcommunication),neitherhenorothernativespeakerswho

haveworkedonthoseconstructionsperceiveanyprosodicdifferencebetweenneutraland

focusedconstituents,buthecautionsthattherehasn’tyetbeenanysystematicresearchon

this.

ThefactthatmeaningsrelatedtoInformationStructurecanbespelledoutindifferent

ways,andcanmoreovertriggersyntacticbehaviorsupportsthehypothesisthatthose

meaningsareuniversallyintroducedbygenuinemorphosyntacticfeatures.Wewanttocall

thishypothesisAboh’sConjecture,afterAboh(2010,2016),whereitisexplicitly

entertained.TheconsequencesofAboh’sConjecturearemomentous.Onthephonological

side,whatmayseemtobemoreglobaleffectsofInformationStructureonprosodyin

languageslikeStandardAmericanorBritishEnglishwouldnowhavetobederivablefrom

theinteractionofidiosyncraticcontributionsofmorphosyntacticfeatureswith

independentlyattestedprinciplesofdefaultprosody.Thatis,anyconnectionbetween

prosodyanddiscourserelatedmeaningswouldhavetobefunneledthroughdedicated

morphosyntacticfeatures.

AsAboh(2016)iswellaware,hisviewonInformationStructuremaylookboldtothose

whoareprimarilylookingatIndo-Europeanlanguages.Takentoitsmostradical

conclusion,theviewsuggeststhatInformationStructuremaybenothingbutacollectionof

run-of-the-millmorphosyntacticfeatureswithdiscourserelatedmeaningsthathappento

bespelledoutprosodicallyinsomelanguageswehappentoknowwell.Inthenextsection,

we’llgatherfurthersupportforAboh’sConjecturebypresentingmoreexamplesfrom

languageswheretherealizationsoffocusbehavelikegenuinemorphosyntacticfeatures.

Page 7: deconstructing information structure

7

2. Representingfocuswithmorphosyntacticfeatures

Thissectionwillshowcaseafewselectedexamplessupportingtheconjecturethatnatural

languagesrepresentfocus-relatednotionsbygenuinemorphosyntacticfeaturesthatare

notnecessarilyspelledoutprosodically.Weneedtobeginwithacaveat,though.The

examplesinthissectionaredrawnfromtheliterature,sothereareboundtobe

terminologicalortheoreticalmisalignmentsbetweenthedifferentsources.Notallanalyses

assumethesamenotionsoffocus,andnotallanalysesmakeexplicitthesemanticor

syntacticpropertiesofthediscoursecontextsinwhichaputativefocusmightappear.We

areneverthelessconfidentthattheexampleswediscussillustratesomekindofFoCus,as

opposedtomereinformationfocus.We’llalsohavetosetasidegivennessinthissection,

forthesimplereasonthatthereislittledocumentationaboutthecrosslinguisticrealization

ofthisnotion.

Morphosyntacticfeaturesearntheirkeepbydrivingsyntacticbehaviorlikedisplacement

oragreement.WealreadysawthatinGungbe,focusedconstituentsmovetoleft-peripheral

positionsheadedbythefocusparticlewɛ̀.LikeGungbe,Wolof,anAtlanticlanguagespoken

inSenegalandtheGambia,hasaleft-peripheralfocusposition(Torrence2013)7:

(4) a. Xalebil-a-agis.

childtheXPL-COP-1SGsee

‘It’sthechildthatIsaw.’

b. Calekkoolbal-a-agis-eIsaa.

PschooltheXPL-COP-1SGsee-applIsaa

‘It’satschoolthatIsawIsaa.’

7. Glosses:1SGforfirstpersonsingular,APPLforapplicative,COPforcopula,MANNformannersuffix,XPLforexpletive.

Page 8: deconstructing information structure

8

c. Gaawl-a-aubbe-ebuntbi.

quicklyXPL-COP-1SGopen-manndoorthe

‘It’squicklythatIopenedthedoor.’

Wolof.Torrence(2013:182).

Torrence(2013)analyzesconstructionslike4(a)to(c)ascleftconstructionsthatarethe

resultofmovementofthecleftedconstituentintotheleftperiphery.Rialland&Robert

(2001)conductedacousticanalysesofseveralnaturalandelicitedWolofcorporaand

foundthatWolofhasnoprosodicmarkingoffocus:“TheoriginalityofWolofisthatithas

noprosodicmarkingoffocus,evenoptionally”(Rialland&Robert2001:937).Thereis

essentiallylevelpitchinallsentencetypes,exceptattheedgesofintonationalphrases,

wheretonalmorphemesindependentofinformationstructureappear.Rialland&Robert’s

acousticinvestigationofWolofestablishesthatthereisnonecessaryconnectionbetween

focusandprosody.InWolof,focusedconstituentsoccupydedicatedsyntacticpositions,

butsurfacewithflatintonationcontours.

Focuscantriggeragreementinsomelanguages.Inthe‘focusconcord’constructionsof

Sinhala,Pre-ModernJapanese,andtheJapanesedialectsspokenintheRyukyus(Aldridge

(2018),Kishimoto(2018),Slade(2018),Whitman(1997)),focusedphrasesaremarked

withaparticlethatcovarieswithspecialinflectiononthepredicate.(5)isanexamplefrom

Sinhala,anIndo-IranianlanguagespokeninSriLanka.8

(5) a. Ranjit[Chitraeepotǝtamaykieuwekiyǝla]dannǝwa.

RanjitChitrathatbookFOCread.Ethatknow.A

‘RanjitknowsthatitwasthatbookthatChitraread.’

8. Glosses:Afor-ainflection,Efor-einflection,FOCforfocus.

Page 9: deconstructing information structure

9

b. Ranjit[Chitraeepotǝtamaykieuwakiyǝla]danne.

RanjitChitrathatbookFOCread.Athatknow.E

‘ItisthatbookthatRanjitknowsthatChitraread.’

Sinhala.Kishimoto(2018:2).

In5(a)and(b),theparticletamaymarkseepotǝ(‘thatbook’)asafocus.Thescopeofthe

focusisindicatedbythe-eendingoftheverb,whichhastoappearhereinsteadofthe

default-aending.In5(a),thescopeofthefocusisjusttheembeddedsentence.5(a)

conveysthatRanjitknowsthatwhatChitrareadwasthatbook(andnotanythingelse).In

5(b),ontheotherhand,thescopeofthefocusisthewholesentence.5(b)conveysthat

whatRanjitknowsChitrareadisthatbook(andnotanythingelse).5(b),butnot5(a)

shouldthusbecompatiblewithasituationwhere,unbeknownsttoRanjit,Chitraalsoread

amagazine.

Hagstrom(1998,2004)andKishimoto(2018)assumethatthereisfeatureagreement

betweenthefocusparticletamayandthescopesiteoffocusmarkedbythee-formofthe

verbinexampleslike5(a)or(b).Bothauthorsargue(indifferentways)thatthenatureof

thisrelationforcesthefocusparticletomovetoitsscopesiteovertlyorcovertly.9(6)

wouldbetheresultofanovertinstanceofthismovement.

(6) [Ranjiteepotǝkieuwa]tamay

Ranjitthatbookread.AFOC

‘ItwasonlythatRanjitreadthatbook.’

Sinhala.Kishimoto(2018:3).

9. ForHagstrom,the-eformoftheverbhasanuninterpretablefocusfeaturethatneedstobechecked.ForKishimoto,themovementofthefocusparticleiscriterialinthesenseofRizzi(1997):theparticlemovesintoadedicatedfocuspositionintheCPlayerofthesentence.

Page 10: deconstructing information structure

10

In(6),tamayappearsclausefinallyandwiththea-formoftheverb.Inthisposition,tamay

doesn’tdelimitthefocusedconstituent,asin5(a)and(b),butmarksthescopesiteofthe

focus.(6)hasseveralinterpretationsdependingonwhichpartofthescopeoftamayis

understoodasfocused.ItmayconveythatitwasRanjitwhoreadthatbook,thatitwas

thatbookthatRanjitread,thatRanjitdidreadthatbook,andsoon.

Anagreementrelationbetweenparticlesthatmarkfocusedconstituentsandinflectionona

nearbypredicatehasalsobeenpositedforthekakari-musubiconstructionfoundin

PremodernJapaneseandinJapanesedialectsspokenintheRyukyus(Whitman1997).10

(7) Pito=kososira-nematu=pasiruramu.

Person=KOSOknow-NEG.IZpine=TOPknowMOD.RT

‘Thoughpeopledonotunderstand,thepinemayknow.’

OldJapanese.Aldridge(2018:7).

In(7),thecontrastivefocusparticlekosotriggerstheizen‘realis’inflectiononthe

predicate,whichwouldnotbeusedhereintheabsenceofkoso.Thisdependencebetween

afocusparticleandinflectiononthepredicatehasbeenanalyzedasfeatureagreementby

severalresearchers,includingIkawa(1998),Kuroda(2007),andAldridge(2018).

TheexamplesfromGungbe,Wolof,Sinhala,andOldJapaneseshowthat,crosslinguistically,

therepresentationsoffocus-relatednotionscanshowthesignaturebehaviorof

morphosyntacticfeatures:theycanappearasheadsofdedicatedsyntacticpositions,can

triggerdisplacement,andcanparticipateinagreementrelations.Takentogether,those

factssupporttheconjecturethatnaturallanguagesrepresentfocus-relatednotionsby

morphosyntacticfeatures.Wealsohaveseenevidencethat,cross-linguistically,those

10. Glosses:NEGfornegation,IZforizen‘realis’inflection,TOPfortopic,MODformodal,RTforrentai‘adnominal’inflection.

Page 11: deconstructing information structure

11

featuresdonothavetobespelledoutprosodically.Theconnectionbetweenprosodyand

InformationStructureisnotalinguisticuniversal.

3. AunifiedaccountfornewnessandFoCus?

Section1alreadyintroducedthemainclaimofthispaper,namelythatStandardAmerican

Englishhastwobonafidemorphosyntacticfeaturesimposingdiscourserequirements

relatedtoGivennessandFoCus:[G]-markingand[FoC]-marking.OurclaimthatStandard

AmericanEnglishhastwofeaturestomarkdiscourserequirementsrelatedtoFoCusand

GivennessfliesinthefaceoftheunifiedaccountsofRooth(1992,2016)andSchwarzschild

(1999).RoothandSchwarzschildfollowJackendoff(1972)andSelkirk(1984,1995)in

assumingthatconstituentsthatareFoCused(inoursense)andthosethataremerelynew

(hencenotGiveninoursense)areuniformly[F]-marked.Givenconstituentsremain

unmarked.Thisisillustratedin(1’)and(2’)below.

(1’) Me: Didanybodyeattheclementines?Ican’tfindtheminthepantry.

You: (Ithink)[Paula]Fmighthaveeatentheclementines.

(2’) Me: Sarahmailedthecaramels.

You: (No),[Eliza]Fmailedthecaramels.

OnereasonfavoringsuchauniformaccountisthatinEnglish,pitchaccentsareinvariably

associatedwithmaterialthatcanbeeitherFoCusedormerelynew.Thedistributionof

pitchaccentsthusseemstoindicatethatEnglishprosodytreatsFoCusedandmerelynew

phrasesthesame.

Asecondreasontoseriouslyconsiderauniform[F]-markingapproachisthatRooth(1992)

andSchwarzschild(1999)haveactuallyproposedsuccessfulaccountsthatcomputethe

discourserequirementsimposedbyFoCusandGivennessfromrepresentationsthatonly

have[F]-marking.ToillustratetheleadingideascommontoRoothandSchwarzschild,we’ll

usetheAlternativesSemanticsofRooth(1992,2016)tostatethediscourseanaphoric

Page 12: deconstructing information structure

12

requirementsforGivennessandFoCusinawaythatcloselymimicsthemethodof

Schwarzschild(1999).

Lookagainatyouranswerin(2’),repeatedhereas(8):

(8) [Eliza]Fmailedthecaramels.

(8)isnotacceptableasanout-of-the-blueutterance.TheVPmailedthecaramelsneedsto

beGiveninoursense,andthesentenceasawholeseemstoexpressacontrast,possibly

withsomethingthatwassaidearlier.Schwarzschild(1999)proposesaunified

characterizationofthosetwodiscourserequirementsintermsofamoregeneralnotionof

givennessthatsubsumesbothourGivennessandcontrast.Schwarzschildrequiresthatany

constituentthatisnot[F]-markedbegiveninthisgeneralsense.In(8),neithertheVPorits

parts,northesentenceasawholeare[F]-marked,hencethoseconstituentsallneedto

comeoutasgivenonhisapproach.

TheAlternativesSemanticsofRooth(1992,2016)providesaconvenientcounterpartof

Schwarzschild’sgeneralnotionofgivenness:A-Givennessfromnowon.11Aconstituent𝛼is

A-Given(inacontext)justincasethereisasalientdiscoursereferent(anindividual,

concept,orproposition)fromtheprecedingcontextthatisamemberofthealternativesset

associatedwith𝛼.InAlternativesSemantics,everyexpressionisassignedtwosemantic

values:itsO(rdinary)-value,anditsA(lternatives)-value,whichisitsalternativesset.For

example,theO-valueof(8)isjustthepropositionthatElizamailedthecaramels.ItsA-

valueisthesetofpropositionsin(9).

11. Schwarzschildstateshisnotionofgivennessintermsofaspecialversionofgeneralizedentailment.AsRooth(2016)pointsout,Schwarzschild’sgeneralizedentailmentconditionforgivennessissometimestooeasytosatisfy.Take(i):

(i) Every[cat]Fisacomplainer.ForSchwarzschild,(i)asawholeisgivenjustincase(ii)isentailedbypriorcontext:

(ii) ∃P[everyPisacomplainer].

Page 13: deconstructing information structure

13

(9) {‘Elizamailedthecaramels’,‘Sarahmailedthecaramels’,‘Leifmailedthecaramels’,

…}.

SincethepropositionthatSarahmailedthecaramelsisinthealternativesset(9)for(8)

and,inthecontextof(2’),hasjustbeenmentioned,(8)asawholeisA-Giveninthat

context.

Tocomputethealternativessetfor(8)compositionally,wecombinetheA-valuesofits

immediateconstituents,the[F]-markedsubject[Eliza]FandtheVPmailedthecaramels.

TheA-valueof[Eliza]Fisthesetofallindividuals:Eliza,Sarah,Leif,andanybodyelseinour

domainofdiscourse.WhatabouttheA-valueoftheVPmailedthecaramels,whichcontains

no[F]-marks?InRooth’sAlternativesSemantics,thatVP’sA-valueisasingletonset,theset

containingtheVP’sO-valueasitsonlymember.That’sthesingletonsetcontainingthe

propertyofhavingmailedthecaramels.TheA-valueof(10)asawholeiscomputedby

pointwisecombinationoftheA-valuesof[Eliza]FandtheVPmailedthecaramels:{Eliza,

Sarah,Leif,…}´{‘mailedthecaramels’}.Theresultisthealternativesset(9).

OurGivennessfallsoutasaspecialcaseofA-Givenness.SincetheVPmailedthecaramelsin

(8)hasasingletonalternativesset,itisA-Givenjustincaseitsonlymember,theproperty

ofhavingmailedthecaramels,issalientinthediscoursecontext,henceisGiveninour

sense.That,too,isthecaseinthecontextof(2’).

Rooth’sandSchwarzschild’ssystemsprovideunifiedaccountsofthediscourse

requirementstriggeredbyFoCusandGivenness.Itlooksliketherereallyaren’tTWOsuch

Butthepropertyofbeingacomplainerisawitnessfor(ii),hence(ii)istriviallytrueandisentailedbyanysentence.DefiningtherelevantnotionofgivennesswithinAlternativesSemanticsdoesnotrunintothisproblem.

Page 14: deconstructing information structure

14

discourserequirements.Givennessandcontrastseemtobetwosidesofthesamecoin.

Rooth’sandSchwarzschild’ssystemsonlyrequireasinglefocus-relatedfeature:[F]-

marking.NeitherFoCusnorGivennessneedtoberepresented.Thecaseforaunified

accountofGivennessandFoCusintermsof[F]-markingisstrong.Nevertheless,adiverse

rangeoffactsgoagainstit.Thefollowingsectionwillpresentdatasuggestingstronglythat

FoCusandnewnessshouldnotbelumpedtogetherintoasinglefeature.

4. AgainstaunifiedaccountofnewnessandFoCus

Overtheyears,syntacticians,phonologists,andphoneticians,havedocumenteddifferences

betweendifferenttypesoffocusinanumberoflanguages.Manyofthoseauthorshave

pointedtodifferencesinthewaylanguagesmarkconstituentsthataremerelynew

(newnessfocus,informationfocus),asopposedtoconstituentsthatevokealternativesand

therebyhighlightacontrast(FoCus).12Inthissection,wewilldiscusssomerepresentative

examples.Wewillconcludethatthoseexamplesposechallengesforsingle-feature

representationsofthesemantic/pragmaticandphonologicaleffectsofFoCusand

Givenness,whichrelyon[F]-markingalone.Wewillthenexplorewaysofovercoming

thosechallengeswithinatwo-featureapproach.

OurfirstexamplecomesfromKatz&Selkirk’sexperimentalmaterials(Katz&Selkirk

2011:802).

(10) Garyisanartdealer.Latelyhe’sbeenverypickyaboutwhichmuseumhedeals

with;hedoesn’tdobusinesswiththeMetropolitanortheGuggenheim.

SohewouldonlyofferthatModiglianitoMoMA.Hesaysthat’stheonlymuseum

withaspacegoodenoughtohangitin.

12. TheseauthorsincludeChafe(1976),Rochemont(1986,2013a,2013b),Pierrehumbert&Beckman(1988),D’Imperio(1997),Kiss(1998),Vallduví&Vilkuna(1998),Zubizarreta(1998),Frota(2000),Belletti(2001,2004),Selkirk(2002,2007,2008),Féry&Samek-Lodovici(2006),Aboh(2007a,2007b),Ameka(2010),Beaver&Velleman(2011),Katz&Selkirk(2011),amongmanyothers.

Page 15: deconstructing information structure

15

Ourtargetsentencewithin(10)is(11)13:

(11) HewouldónlyofferthatModigliánitoMóMA.

BothModiglianiandMoMAin(11)bearobligatorypitchaccentswhenreadaloudinthe

contextof(10).Butthereareimportantdifferencesbetweenthetwo.Inthecontextof(10),

MoMAintroducesalternativesandtherebysetsupacontrastwiththeMetropolitanandthe

Guggenheim,theothertwomuseumsmentioned.MoMAisaFoCus,then.Modigliani,onthe

otherhand,presentsmerelynewinformation.Itdoesn’tevokealternatives.Inthecontext

of(10),(11)impliesthatGarywouldn’tofferthatModiglianitotheMetropolitanorthe

Guggenheim.Modiglianithusdoesn’tassociatewithonly.Itdoesn’tcontributeany

alternativestothecomputationofthealternativessetthatonlyoperatesover.Thatsetis

illustratedin(12).

(12) {‘HewouldofferthatModiglianitoMoMA’,hewouldofferthatModiglianitothe

Metropolitan’,‘hewouldofferthatModiglianitotheGuggenheim’,…}

Sentence(11)istruejustincasethementionedalternative‘HewouldofferthatModigliani

toMoMA’istheonlyalternativein(12)thatistrue.

Thescenariodescribedin(10)alsoexcludesthepossibilitythatModiglianiinourtarget

sentencemightbeacontrastivetopicscopingoveronly.Inthecontextof(10),(11)can’tbe

understoodascontrastingthementionedModiglianipainting,whichGarywouldonlyoffer

toMoMA,withotherpaintingsofhisthathemightalsooffertotheMetropolitanorthe

Guggenheim.Suchaninterpretationwouldgoagainstwhatwearebeingtoldinthestory,

namelythatGarydoesn’tdobusinesswiththeMetropolitanortheGuggenheim.

13. Weuseacuteaccentstoindicatethelocationofpitchaccents.UnderliningonMóMain(11)indicatesgreaterphoneticprominence.

Page 16: deconstructing information structure

16

Katz&Selkirk’sexamplesshowthatthegrammarofstandardAmericanEnglish

distinguishesconstituentsthatareFoCusedfromthosethataremerelynew.Thedifference

canbedetectedininteractionswithFoCus-sensitiveoperatorslikeonly.Katz&Selkirk’s

paperisn’tprimarilyaboutthesemanticeffectsofalternativesfocus(FoCus)vs.

informationfocus,though.Katz&Selkirk(2011)isforemostaphoneticstudy.Theyshow

thatthereisasystematicphoneticdifferencebetweenFoCusedandmerelynewmaterial

which,crucially,isindependentofsyntacticposition.We’llcomebacktothisaspectoftheir

studyinsection6.

Withincurrent[F]-marking-onlyapproaches,bothModiglianiandMoMAinourtarget

sentence(11)(aspartof(10))wouldhavetobe[F]-marked,sincebothhaveapitchaccent.

Butthenwewouldhavenosyntacticrepresentationfromwhichtocomputetheright

alternativessetforonlyontheonehand,andtherightphoneticrealizationforModigliani

andMoMAontheother.14

Englishit-cleftconstructionscreateasimilardilemmafor[F]-marking-onlyapproaches.It-

cleftsconsistofacleftedconstituentfollowedbythecleftclause(thesubordinateclause),

asinyourreplyin(13):

(13) Me:Jane’slostherkeysandisreallyupset.

You:ItwasherphonethatJanelost.

Init-cleftsentencesthecleftedconstituentisaFoCus.In(13),Jane’sphoneiscontrasted

withherkeys.In(13),itsohappensthatthematerialinthecleftclauseisGivenandlacks

pitchaccent(s).ButasPrince(1978)observed,andHedberg(1990,2010,2013)discussed,

14. Rooth(2015)hasmoreexamplesofthiskind.Heproposesananalysisthathassyntacticfeaturesexclusivelydedicatedtotheprojectionofalternatives,inadditionto[F]-markingofterminalelements.Rooth’sprojectionfeaturesdonothavecredentialsasbonafidemorphosyntacticfeatures,hencewon’thelpwiththeagendawearepursuinginthispaper.

Page 17: deconstructing information structure

17

thematerialinthecleftclausemayalsobenew,henceaccented.(14)isoneoftheexamples

quotedbyPrince(herexample41(b)).15

(14) TheleadersofthemilitanthomophilemovementinAmericagenerallyhavebeen

youngpeople.Itwastheywhofoughtbackduringaviolentpoliceraidona

GreenwichVillagebarin1969,anincidentfromwhichmanygaysdatethebirthof

themoderncrusadeforhomosexualrights.

Ourtargetsentencewithin(14)is15(a),andthecleftclauseis15(b).

(15) a. ItwasthéywhofoughtbáckduringavíolentpolíceraidonaGréenwich

Villagebárin´1969.

b. …whofoughtbáckduringavíolentpolíceraidonaGréenwichVillagebárin

´1969.

Thepronountheyin15(a)isaFoCus.Itsinglesoutyoungpeopleamongothergroupsof

peoplewhocouldhavefoughtbackduringthatraidonaGreenwichVillagebar.What’s

beingsaidaboutyoungpeoplein15(b)isallnewinformation,andthat’sreflectedinthe

distributionofpitchaccents.Tocomputetheinferencethatnootherrelevantgroup(apart

fromtheyoungpeople)foughtbackduringthatviolentpoliceraidonaGreenwichVillage

barin1969,wewanttogenerateanalternativessetlikethatin(16):

(16) {TheyoungpeoplefoughtbackduringaviolentpoliceraidonaGreenwichVillage

barin1969,theolderpeoplefoughtbackduringaviolentpoliceraidona

GreenwichVillagebarin1969,…}

Buthowarewegoingtogeneratethissetifeverythinginthecleftclause15(b)isnew

information,hencewouldhavetobe[F]-markedtoaccountforthedistributionofpitch

accents?Thedilemmaforan[F]-marking-onlyapproachisthatthemechanismcomputing

15. TheexampleisoriginallyfromthePennsylvaniaGazette,February1977,p.16.

Page 18: deconstructing information structure

18

thesetofFoCusalternativeswouldn’twanttohaveany[F]-marksinthecleftclause,while

themechanismcomputingtheprosodywouldneedthem.Onan[F]-marking-only

approachwewouldagainhavenosyntacticrepresentationfromwhichtocomputethe

rightalternativessetontheonehand,andtherightphoneticrealizationontheother.

Ourlastexampleinthissectionillustratesanalternationinanswerstowh-questionsthat

hasbeenreportedforseverallanguages,includingItalian(Kiss1998,Belletti2001),

Spanish(Zubizarreta1998),Finnish(Molnár2001),Gungbe(Aboh2007a,2007b),and

Kwalanguagesmoregenerally(Ameka2010).Forillustration,wewilllookatanItalian

example.InItalian,asimplewh-questionlike17(a)canbeansweredasin17(b)or17(c).

(17) a. Chihascrittoquestoarticolo?

Whohaswrittenthisarticle

Whowrotethisarticle?

b. L’hascrittoGennaro.

IthaswrittenGennaro

Gennarowroteit.

c. Gennarol’hascritto.

Gennaroithaswritten.

Gennarowroteit.

AsdiscussedbyKissandBelletti,aquestionlike17(a)canbeansweredwithapostverbal

subject,asin17(b),orapreverbalsubject,asin17(c),withasubtledifferenceinmeaning.

Asananswerto17(a),17(c)necessarilyexpressesacontrast.GennaromustbeaFoCus,it

can’tbemerelynew.FoCusonGennaroevokesotherpossibleauthorsforthisarticlewho

arebeingruledout.In17(b),GennarocouldbeaFoCus,butdoesn’thavetobe.Itcouldalso

bemerelynew.

Page 19: deconstructing information structure

19

Tobringoutintuitionsaboutpreverbalvs.postverbalsubjectsinItalianmoreclearly,

consider18(a)and(b)below,stillunderstoodasanswerstothequestionin17(a).16We

madetheanswerslonger,makingitharder(notimpossible)toaccommodateacontrastive

interpretationforthesubjectGennaro.Asaresult,thereispressureforGennarotoappear

postverbally.18(b)isjudgedinfelicitousasananswerto17(a).17

(18) a. Credochel’abbiascrittoGennaroquandoera

think.1SGthatithave.SUBJ.3SGwrittenGennarowhenbe.IMPF.3SG

inGraduateSchool.

inGraduateSchool.

IthinkGennarowroteitwhenhewasinGraduateSchool.

b.#CredocheGennarol’abbiascrittoquandoera

think.1SGthatGennaroithave.SUBJ.3SGwrittenwhenbe.IMPF.3SG

inGraduateSchool.

inGraduateSchool.

IthinkGennarowroteitwhenhewasinGraduateSchool.

KissandBellettiargue,followingRizzi(1997),thatthepreverbalsubjectsinsentenceslike

17(c)and18(b)occupyaleft-peripheralpositionreachedviamovement.Thepostverbal

positionofthesubjectiseitheritsoriginalposition(Kiss)oralowpositionintheverb’s

functionalprojection(Belletti).Eitherway,wecanconcludethatthesyntaxofItalian

makesadistinctionbetweenconstituentsthatareFoCusedandthosethataremerelynew.

16. Glosses:SGforsingular,SUBJforsubjunctive,IMPFforimperfective,1for1stperson,3for3rdperson.17. TheItalianexampleswereprovidedbyIlariaFrana.

Page 20: deconstructing information structure

20

TheItalianfactsareanotherchallengefor[F]-marking-onlyaccounts.Thesyntacticengine

forItalianneedstoknowthatitcan’tmovemerelynewconstituentsintotheleftperiphery

ofasentence.Butifthereisnothinginthesyntacticrepresentationthatwoulddistinguish

FoCusedphrasesfromthosethataremerelynew,it’shardtoseehowitcouldaccomplish

thattask.

Weconcludethatan[F]-feature-onlyaccountisn’tabletoconnectmeaning,syntax,and

phonologicalrealizationintherightway.Weneedtomakefinerdistinctions.Ifwewantto

holdontoAboh’sConjecture,weshouldconsiderthepossibilitythatlanguagesmightuse

twomorphosyntacticfeatures,ratherthanjustone,toproducethesemantic,pragmatic,

syntactic,andprosodiceffectsthatFoCus,Givenness,andnewnessareresponsibleforin

individuallanguages.

5. Blindtonewness

Thelastsectionconcludedthat,assumingAboh’sConjecture,weseemtoneedtwo

morphosyntacticfeaturestoexpressdiscourserequirementsconnectedtoGivennessand

Focus.Whichtwo?Wecan’tseemtodowithoutFoCus.WeneedaFoCusfeatureto

computealternativessetsforoperatorslikeonlyorcleftconstructions,weneedittodrive

movementintotheleftperipheryinItalian,andweneedittocomputetherightprosodyin

theKatz&Selkirkcases,forexample.Thechoicepoint,then,iswhethertohavea

morphosyntacticfeaturethatmarksmaterialthatisGiven([G]-accounts)or,alternatively,

amorphosyntacticfeaturethatmarksmaterialthatismerelynew([N]-accounts).If

newnessismarked,Givennesswouldbeunmarkedandviceversa.18

18. Moderntwo-featureproposalsareFéry&Samek-Lodovici(2006),Selkirk(2007,2008),andBeaver&Velleman(2011).Allthreeproposalsmarkfocus,withpossiblyslightlydifferentassumptionsaboutwhatfallsunderthisnotion.Beaver&Vellemanuse[N]-markingforconstituentsthatarenew(‘unpredictable’).Féry&Samek-Lodovici(2006)andSelkirk(2007,2008),ontheotherhand,representgivenness,ratherthannewness.

Page 21: deconstructing information structure

21

[G]-accountsand[N]-accountspositstrikinglydifferentrepresentationsforout-of-the-blue

utterances,whereeverythingisnewinformation.Inthosecases,[N]-accountsproduce

representationsthatlookminimallyasin19(a),whereas[G]-accountswouldposit

unmarkedrepresentations,asin19(b).

(19) Sárahmailedthecáramels.

(a) SarahNmailedNthecaramelsN. [N]-accounts

(b) Sarahmailedthecaramels. [G]-accounts

[N]-markingeverycontentwordin(19)isnecessarysincenewnessofaconstituentinno

wayimpliesthatanyofitsproperpartsarenewaswell.Representationswithmerely

broad[N]-markinglike(20)forout-of-the-blueutteranceswouldthusbeinadequate.

(20) [Sarahmailedthecaramels]N.

ThereisanasymmetrybetweenGivennessandnewness,then:Givennessofaconstituent

doesimplyGivennessofallofitsparts.Broad[G]-markingfortheGivenpartofyour

answerin(21)isthusentirelyjustified.

(21) Me: Sarahmailedthecaramels.

You: Ican’tbelíevethat[Sarahmailedthecaramels]G.

Weconcludethatiffeatureeconomyisaconsideration,[G]-accountshaveaslight

advantage.

Moreimportantly,thedifferencebetween19(a)and(b)hasconsequencesfortheSyntax-

Phonologyinterface.Onan[N]-account,theprosodyof(19)wouldhavetobereadoffthe

representation19(a),withallthose[N]-marks.Ona[G]-account,ontheotherhand,the

rightprosodyfor(19)wouldhavetobedeterminedonthebasisof19(b),whichdoesnot

containanyfeaturesrelatedtoFoCus,Givenness,ornewness.Thismeansthatif19(b)is

therightrepresentation,therehastobeadefaultprosodyforEnglishout-of-the-blue

Page 22: deconstructing information structure

22

utteranceswhoseprinciplesareindependentofanyimpactofInformationStructure.To

defenda[G]-account,then,wewouldneedtoshowwhatthatdefaultprosodyisandhowit

couldbederivedwithinanotherwiseplausiblegeneraltheoryofprosody.Supposesucha

demonstrationsucceeded.Wewouldthenbeinastrongpositiontoruleout19(a)on

conceptualgrounds:AllN-markingin19(a)wouldbecompletelysuperfluousasfaras

prosodyisconcerned.

AccountspresupposingtheexistenceofadefaultprosodyforEnglishthatisindependentof

InformationStructurehavebeenproposedsincetheearlieststudiesofprosodywithin

GenerativeGrammar(Chomsky&Halle1968,Bresnan1971,Chomsky1971).

Whiletheissuehasn’tbeenuncontroversial,thependulumisswingingtowardsdefault

prosodyinrecenttextbooks(Büring2016)andhandbookarticles(Truckenbrodt2016,

Zubizarreta2016).Wewilladdressthistopicinthenextsection,wherewewillfollow-up

onFéry&Samek-Lodovici(2006)andSelkirk(2007,2008)inworkingoutaparticular

versionofa[G]-account.Ona[G]-account,theprosodyofasentenceiscomputedoff

syntacticstructuresthatmayincludemorphosyntacticfeaturesforGivenness([G]-

marking)andFoCus([FoC]-marking),butdonotindicatenewness.Thegrammarisblindto

newness.TheapparentprosodicreflexesofnewnessinStandardAmericanandBritish

Englisharereflexesofadefaultprosodywhosebasicprinciplesdonotdependinanyway

onInformationStructure.

6. ThePhonologicalinterpretationof[FoC]and[G]

Thefateof[FoC]and[G]istobespelledoutbythePhonologyinsomeway,beit

prosodically,segmentally,ortonally.Morphosyntacticfeatures-whetherit’sfeaturesfor

FoCusorGivenness,orinflectionalfeatureslikethoseforpluralityorpasttense-are

phonologicallyinterpretedvialanguage-particularspelloutconstraintsspecifyingthe

phonologicalexpressionofthesefeatures.Thephonologicalexponencepropertiescalled

forbysuchspelloutconstraintsformpartoftheunderlyingphonologicalrepresentationof

asentence,whichistheinputtothephonologicalcomponentperse.Thesurface

phonologicalrepresentationderivedfromtheunderlyingrepresentationmayshow

phonologicalconstraint-drivenmodifications.Thisgeneralarchitectureisthesame,

Page 23: deconstructing information structure

23

whetherwearedealingwithprosodicspelloutof[FoC]and[G]inEnglish,orwith

segmentalspelloutofrelatedfeaturesinGungbe,forexample.

[FoC]and[G]inStandardEnglishdifferfromfeaturesforpluralityortenseinthattheyare

spelledoutnotassegments,butintermsofprominence.Theexponenceof[G]isthe

absenceofphrasalprominence.Theexponenceof[FoC]ishighestpossibleprominence.

Bothofthosefeaturesinvolvedivergencefromdefaultprominence.Atthepointofcontact

withthephonology,then,theyhavetointeractwithanunderlyingrepresentationthathas

informationaboutdefaultprominence.(22)belowillustratesanarchitecturethatmakes

thoseinteractionspossible.Inthearchitectureassumedin(22),thesolepointofinterface

betweensyntaxandphonologyinthegrammarisbetweenanoutputsyntactic

representationandtheunderlying(input)phonologicalrepresentation.Thisisaserialist

theoryofthesyntax-phonologyinterface,then.Therelationbetweensyntaxandthe

surfacephonologicalform,whichissubmittedtophoneticinterpretation,ismediatedbyan

underlyingphonologicalrepresentation.

Thesentencein22(a)ismeanttobeall-new,lackingany[FoC]-markingand[G]-marking.

Ourtaskinwhatfollowsistwofold:firsttoexplainexactlyhowunderlyingphonological

representationslike22(b)comeaboutand,second,toexplainhowsurfacephonological

representationslike22(c)arederivedfrom22(b).Thefirstsubtaskinvolvesallaspectsof

thesyntax-phonologyinterface,includingthespelloutofourtwomorphosyntacticfeatures

andthepropertiesofunderlyingphonologicalrepresentationtheyinteractwith.Forthe

secondsubtaskweareassuminganoptimalitytheoretic,constraint-based,account(Prince

&Smolensky2004[1993],McCarthy&Prince1999).

Page 24: deconstructing information structure

24

(22) a.Syntaxb.Underlyingphonologicalrepresentation

Clause i

/ \ / \

/ VP / j

/ / \ / / \

/ / \ / / \

NP / DP j / \

| / / | | / \

N V D NP ws w js

| | / | | | |

| | / N | | ws

Sarah mailed the caramels Sarah mailed the caramels

c. Surface phonological representation

i

/ \

/ j

/ / \

/ / \

j / \

| / \

ws w js

| | |

ƒs ƒs ws

/ \ | / \

ss s ss ƒs ƒ

| | | /\ |

| | | s ss s ss

Sarah mailed the caramels

H* L- H* L-

Page 25: deconstructing information structure

25

Inthesyntacticrepresentation22(a)theorthographicstringstandsfortheabstract

representationofthemorphemesandmorphosyntacticfeaturesofsyntactic

representationthataretobespelledoutintheunderlyingphonologicalrepresentation.

Theorthographicallyrepresentedterminalstringsin22(b)and(c)standforthe

phonologicalsegmentsthatgivephonologicalexpressiontotheterminalelementsof22(a).

Therearethreekeyaspectsoftheprosodyofsurfacephonologicalrepresentationsin

English:prosodicconstituency,prosodicprominence(stress),andtone.Prosodic

constituentsatlevelsw(prosodicword),j(phonologicalphrase),andi(intonational

phrase)haveaplaceintheunderlyingrepresentationin22(b),wheretheyreflectthe

word,phraseandclausestructureofthesyntacticrepresentationin22(a).Thepossibility

ofphonologicallydrivendivergence,ornon-isomorphism,betweenphonologicaland

syntacticconstituencyshowsthatprosodicconstituentsarenotsyntacticinkind(Nespor&

Vogel1986,Selkirk1986,2011,Truckenbrodt1999).

InMatchTheory(Selkirk2011),thephonologicalcategorytypesw,jandiarederived

fromthemorphosyntacticcategorytypesword,phraseandclause,respectively.The

constraintsMatchWord,MatchPhraseandMatchClause(Bennettetal.2017,Elfner2015,

Selkirk2011,thepapersinSelkirk&Lee2015)callforprosodicconstituentsin

phonologicalrepresentationthatcorrespondtotheconstituentsofasyntacticstructure

like22(a).Giventheserialorganizationofthegrammarassumedhere,wheresyntaxmeets

phonologyonlyintheunderlying(input)representationofthephonology19,itisinthe

underlyingphonologicalrepresentationthattheconstituentstructureofthesyntaxis

spelledoutbytheMatchConstraints.MatchPhraseisanexample:

(23) MatchPhrase

Aphraseofsyntacticstructurecorrespondstoaphonologicalphraseinunderlying

phonologicalrepresentation.

19. InSelkirk(2011)thisorganizationofgrammarwasnotassumed,andMatchconstraintswereconstruedasholdingatsurfacephonologicalrepresentation.

Page 26: deconstructing information structure

26

InEnglishonlyphrasesthatareheadedbyalexicalitem(noun,verb,adjective,andsome

prepositions)seemtocountforMatchPhrase.Thepositionoffunctionalcategoryheads

liketheinprosodicstructureisdeterminedbyphonologicalconstraints.

Reviewingthedistinctionsbetweenunderlyingandsurfacerepresentationin22(b)and(c),

ithappens(inthiscase)thatthesurfacerepresentationin22(c)hasfullyinheritedthe

prosodicw,j,andiconstituencyoftheunderlyingrepresentation22(b).Theappearanceof

prosodicfoot(ƒ)andsyllable(s)structurewithineachwin22(c),however,isdrivenby

phonologicalmarkednessconstraintsonsurfacephonologicalrepresentationthatorganize

segmentsintosyllables(Prince&Smolensky2004[1993],Zec2007)andsyllablesintofeet

(Hayes1995,Kager2007).

In22(b)and(c),stressisrepresentedwithans-subscriptonprosodicconstituents.Thes-

markingnotationisaconvenientalternativetothegridmarksofaconstituent-bracketed

metricalgrid(Hayes1995,andothers).Thedistributionofstress(prominence)inthe

sentenceisphonologicallypredictableinall-newsentences.Wewouldthusexpectitto

onlybepresentinsurfacephonologicalrepresentation,wereitnotforthefactthat[G]and

[FoC],bytheirverynature,havetointeractwithdefaultprominence.Thatcouldonly

happeninunderlyingrepresentation,giventheserialarchitectureweareassuming.

Ingeneral,eachconstituentofprosodicstructure(withthepossibleexceptionof

intonationalphrase,tobediscussedbelow)hasauniqueprominentdaughterconstituent.

Forphonologicalphrases,thisiscapturedbytheconstraintPhrasalProminence,which,in

English,isamarkednessconstraintonanyphonologicalrepresentation,beitsurfaceor

underlying.

(24) PhrasalProminence

Everyjhasexactlyoneprominentdaughter.

Page 27: deconstructing information structure

27

PhrasalProminencebelongstoafamilyofphonologicalmarkednessconstraintsthat

includesconstraintsfordefiningprominencewithinprosodicwordsandfeet.Inoptimality

theory,phonologicalmarkednessconstraintsarestandardlyconstruedasconstraintson

the‘ideal’natureofoutput/surfacephonologicalrepresentations.Butsince[G]and[FoC]

interferewithdefaultprosody,constraintslikePhrasalProminenceinStandardEnglish

needtoholdofunderlyingphonologicalrepresentation,too.

In22(b)and(c),PhrasalProminenceissatisfiedinallthreejs.Thenon-branchingjs

correspondingtothesubjectandobjectnounphrasesbothcontainasingles-marked

daughter.WithinthehigherjintherecursivejstructurecorrespondingtotheVPthe

daughterjiss-marked,ratherthanitswsister.Thisisnotyetaccountedfor.Itsuggestsan

additionalmarkednessconstraintprivilegingprominenceoncategoriesthatarehigherin

theprosodichierarchy.

(25) UnequalSisterProminence

Ifsistersinaprosodicrepresentationareofunequalcategory,thelower-level

one(s)intheprosodichierarchycannotbeprominent(s-marked).

Whataboutequalsisters,then?Herethesituationismorecomplicated.Languagesseemto

differ.Forexample,withinaprosodicwordthatcontainsasequenceoffeet,theprominent

footmaybetheright-mostortheleft-mostfoot,dependingonthelanguage.Lessisknown

aboutrelativeprominenceofequalsistersatthephrasallevel.Itisoftenassumedthatthe

right-mostphrasewouldreceiveprominenceinthiscase.Intheall-new(26),forexample,

thephrasecorrespondingtotheindirectobjectwouldthenbetheprominentone.20

(26) Syntax [I’ve[[sent]Vmy[[payment]N]NPtothe[[doctor]N]NP]VP]

20. Weareassumingasmall-clauseanalysisforpaymenttothedoctoralongthelinesofHarley(1995,2002).Theheadofthesmallclauseisafunctionalelement,hencethesmallclausedoesnotcorrespondtoaj.Asaconsequence,theprosodiccounterpartsofthetwoobjectsaresistersandarebothdaughtersofthejcorrespondingtotheVP.

Page 28: deconstructing information structure

28

UR (I’ve((sent)wmy((payment)ws)jtothe((doctor)ws)js)j)i

SR (I’ve((sent)wmy((payment)ws)jtothe(doctor)ws)js)j)i

H*L-H*L-

Weshouldmention,however,thattheexperimentalevidencefromKatz&Selkirk(2011)

doesnotnecessarilysupporttheprominenceasymmetryrepresentedin(26).Wetherefore

won’tcommitourselvestoamarkednessconstraintaboutprominenceofequalsistersin

phraseswithoutfurtherinvestigation.

Stressprominenceisknowntoaccountforthedistributionofstress-sensitivephonological

propertiesinEnglish.Predictablevowelreduction,forexample,takesplaceinStandard

AmericanEnglishinsyllablesthatareunstressed,thatis,nots-marked(seee.g.Chomsky&

Halle1968).Inthewordcáramèlsin22(c)theprominent(leftmost)syllable-daughterof

thefirstfoothastheunreducedvowelqualityofitsunderlyingrepresentation,asdoesthe

voweloftheprominentsoledaughterofthesecondfoot,butinthenon-s-markedsyllable

ofthefirstfootthereducedvowel[¶]appears.

Whileprominenceandprosodicconstituencyarenotcompletelypredictablefrom

phonologicalprinciplesalone,thedefaulttonesH*andL-are.Thisiswhytheyonlyappear

insurfacephonologicalrepresentationin(22)and(26).Thesetoneshavenomeaningthat

wouldwarrantthemaplaceinsyntacticrepresentationorinunderlyingphonological

representation.TheobligatoryH*pitchaccentsappearinginall-newsentencesarea

predictablereflexofthej-levelprominencestatus(ws)ofthewordbearingtheaccent.

(Selkirk1995,Ladd1996,Truckenbrodt2006).Thisphonologicalanalysisofthe

distributionoftheobligatoryH*pitchaccentexplainswhytheverbmailedlacksobligatory

pitchaccentin(22),whilethesubjectSarahandtheobjectcaramelsmustbearaH*.Asfor

theL-edgetones,whichcoincidewiththerighthandedgeofajin22(c),theyarealso

likelyapredictable,non-morphemicpropertyoftheprosody(Ladd1996).Wearemostly

Page 29: deconstructing information structure

29

leavingoutmorphemictonesinourrepresentations,likethesentencefinalH%orL%or

morphemicpitchaccentslikeL*+H,forexample(Pierrehumbert&Hirschberg1990).

Insum,thedefaultdistributionoftonesinsurfacephonologicalrepresentationinEnglish

comeswithphrase-levelprosodicconstituencyandprominencewithinthosephrases.

Generalphonologicalmarkednessconstraintsontherelationbetweentoneandprosodic

prominenceorprosodicconstituentedgeswillensuretheirpresenceinsurface

phonologicalrepresentation(Yip2002,2007).21

Wehavenowaddressedthethreeaspectsofsentenceprosodyfoundinall-new,unmarked,

sentences.Theprosodicpropertiesofthosesentencesarejointlydeterminedbygeneral

principlesofspelloutandgeneralconstraintsonphonologicalrepresentations.Thereis

thusnoroleforaputative[N]-feature.

WenextturntoexaminingtheeffectsofGivennessandFoCusonsentenceprosody.Let’s

lookfirstatthephonologyof[G]-marking.Whatisthephonologicalexpressionof

morphosyntactic[G]-markinginStandardEnglish?Sinceunderlyingphonological

representationisthesolepermittedcontactpointbetweensyntaxandphonologyinthe

serialistversionofthisinterfaceweareassuming,weproposethespelloutconstraintNo-

[G]-Prominenceasformulatedin(27):

(27) No-[G]-Prominence

Inunderlyingphonologicalrepresentation,thecounterpartofa[G]-marked

constituentmayneitherbe,orinclude,aphrase-levelprominence(anws).22

21. TheattractionofHtonetostressisfoundatthefootlevel(Zec1999),theprosodicwordlevel(Hellmuth2007),andthephonologicalphraselevel(Kisseberth1984,Gordon2003).22. Ladd’s(1980)originalproposalwasthatadiscourse-givenconstituentcouldn’tbethes-markedsisterinans/wlabelledmetricaltree.

Page 30: deconstructing information structure

30

No-[G]-Prominenceisaconstraintofthesyntax-phonologyinterfacethatcallsforthe

absenceofphrase-levelprominencewithGivenconstituentsinStandardEnglish.

Obviously,no-[G]-ProminenceconflictswithPhrasalProminence.Thisconflictcomesoutin

theURof(28).

(28) Me: Everythingokafteryouroperation?

You: Oh,yeah.

Syntax [I’ve[[sent]Vmy[[payment]N]NPtothe[[doctor]N]NP,G]VP]

UR (I’ve((sent)wmy((payment)ws)jstothe((doctor)w)j)j)i

SR ( I’ve ( (sent)w my ((payment)ws )js to the ( (doctor)w )j)j )i H* L- L%

No-[G]-Prominencerequirestheabsence,butPhrasalProminencerequiresthepresence,of

phrase-levelprominence(s-markingofw)fordoctorintheunderlyingrepresentationof

(28).PhrasalProminenceisthusviolated.Thereis,however,anotherpossibleunderlying

representationforthe[G]-markedphrasethatwouldavoidviolatingPhrasalProminence,

butwouldviolateMatchPhraseinstead.Thispossibilityisillustratedin(29):doctorhas

nowbeen‘dephrased’intheunderlyingrepresentationandPhrasalProminenceisno

longerapplicable.

(29) Me: Everythingokafteryouroperation?

You: Oh,yeah.

Syntax [I’ve[[sent]Vmy[[payment]N]NPtothe[[doctor]N]NP,G]VP]

UR (I’ve((sent)wmy((payment)ws)jstothe(doctor)w)j)i

SR ( I’ve ( (sent)w my ((payment)ws )js to the (doctor)w )j )i

Page 31: deconstructing information structure

31

H* L- L%

Ladd(1980,2008)providesevidenceforthedephrasingoftheprosodiccounterpartsof

[G]-markedphrases.(30)ishisexample23,analyzedwithinourcurrentframeworkof

assumptions.

(30) Me: Everythingokafteryouroperation?

You: Don’ttalktomeaboutit.

Syntax[The[[butcher]N]NP,G[[charged]Vmea[[thousand][[bucks]N]NP]NP]VP]

UR (The((butcher)w)j((charged)wmea((thousand)((bucks)ws)js)js)j)i

SR (The(butcher)w((charged)wmea((thousand)((bucks)ws)js)js)j)i

ø/H*H*L-L%

In(30),thereisanoptionalpitchaccentforthesubjectphrase.Laddsuggeststhatthe

observedlackofaL-toneattherightedgeofthesubjectphrasein(30)indicatesthatthis

phrasedoesnothavethestatusofajinsurfacephonologicalrepresentation.Thisabsence

ofjstatusforthephonologicalcounterpartsof[G]-markedconstituentsisnoteasily

discernablein(29)becauseoftheco-presenceofthemorphemicsentence-finalL%tone.

Wearenonethelessassumingthatallsurfacecounterpartsof[G]-markedconstituentsin

StandardEnglishare‘dephrased’insurfacerepresentation,violatingMatchPhrase.Match

PhraseisthussubordinatedtoNo-[G]-ProminenceandPhrasalProminence.

AnaccountisstillneededfortheoptionalpresenceofaH*pitchaccentwiththe[G]-

markedsubjectin(30).LaddreferstothisoptionalH*pitchaccentasa‘secondary’one,

whiletheH*thatappearsobligatorilywithwhatwearereferringtoasFoCusandnew

constituentsisa‘primary’accent.Theprimaryaccenthasalreadybeencharacterizedas

23. Example(24)inLadd(2008),300.

Page 32: deconstructing information structure

32

onewhichappearsbydefaultonthemostprominentsyllableofaj.Asforthesecondary

H*pitchaccent,itspresencecouldbedrivenbyaphonologicalconstraintcallingforthe

presenceofaHtoneonawordthatappearsattheleftedgeofaj.24There’sprecedentfor

theappearanceofsuchleft-edge-basedpitchaccentsinEuropeanPortuguese(Frota2000)

andIrish(Elfner2012,2015).Moreover,withinEnglishitselfthisinitialityeffectcan

explaintheoptionalpresenceofH*pitchaccentsontransitiveverbs,prenominalmodifiers,

andsoon,whicharepredictedtobenon-prominentinthedefaultcase.LocalizingtheHon

themain-stressedsyllableofthewordwouldbeachievedbymarkednessconstraintson

thetone-prominencerelation.

FurthereffectsofNo-[G]-Prominencearebroughtoutbyexample(31),alsofromLadd

(1980,2008).25

(31) Me: Everythingokafteryouroperation?

You: Don’ttalktomeaboutit.

Syntax [I’d[[like]Vto[[strangle]Vthe[[butcher]N]NP,G]VP]VP]

UR (I’d((like)wto((strangle)wsthe(butcher)w)j)j)i

SR (I’d((like)wto((strangle)wsthe(butcher)w)j)j)i

H*L-L%

In(31),becauseofPhrasalProminenceattheVP-level,theabsenceofprominenceonthe

prosodiccounterpartofthe[G]-markedobjectresultsinnecessaryphrasalprominenceand

apitchaccentonthecounterpartoftheverbintheunderlyingrepresentation.

24. Bolinger(1965),Shattuck-Hufnageletal.(1994).25. Example(22)ofLadd(2008),300.

Page 33: deconstructing information structure

33

Turningto[FoC]-marking,startingwithJackendoff(1972),itisusuallyassumedin

accountsofEnglishsentenceprosodythata[FoC]-markedsyntacticconstituentis

phonologicallyexpressedwiththehighestpossibleprominence(stress)ofthesentence.

WeproposetheFoCusProminenceconstraintin(32),whichassumesthatthe

morphosyntacticfeature[FoC]isspelledoutinStandardEnglishintheunderlying

phonologicalrepresentationofasentence.

(32)FoCusProminence

Theprosodiccounterpartofa[FoC]-markedconstituenthasthehighestpossible

prominenceinunderlyingphonologicalrepresentationthatitcanhavewithout

violatingotherconstraints.

Inthesyntacticrepresentationin33(a)below,thesubjectphraseis[FoC]-markedandthe

VPismerelynew.TheFoC-newsequencein33(a)couldhavethemeaningofthecleft

sentenceItwasSarahwhomailedthecaramels,spokeninacontextwheremailedthe

caramelsisnotsalientinthecurrentdiscourse,sonot[G]-marked.

Page 34: deconstructing information structure

34

(33) a. Syntax b. Underlying phonological representation

Clause i

/ \ / \

/ VP / j

/ / \ / / \

/ / \ / / \

NPFoC / DP ® js / \

| / / | | / \

N V D NP ws w js

| | / | | | |

| | / N | | ws

Sarah mailed the caramels Sarah mailed the caramels

Inthissimplecase,thejcounterpartofthe[FoC]-markedphraseSarahcarriesthehighest-

levelprominenceinthesentence.It’stheprominentdaughteroftheintonationalphrase

(i),whichisthehighestprosodicconstituent.Theprominenceofcaramelsisdeterminedby

PhrasalProminence.BoththisprominenceandFoCus-relatedprominencewouldbe

inheritedinthesurfacerepresentation,whichisnotgivenhere.Thephrase-level

prominenceandsurfacedistributionofH*andL-for(33)wouldthusbethesameasinan

all-newsentence.Onouraccount,thei-levelprominenceofthe[FoC]-markedconstituent

inphonologicalrepresentation(markedwithanarrow)isthesourceforthejudgmentby

speakersofEnglishthatthe[FoC]-markedconstituentofasentenceismoreprominent

relativetoother,non-[FoC]-marked,constituentsofthesamesentence.

Directexperimentalphoneticevidencefortheexistenceoftheintuitedrelativeprominence

patternsinsentenceswith[FoC]isprovidedinKatzandSelkirk(2011),whichinvestigates

thephoneticsofsentenceswith[FoC]-markedconstituentsthatprecedeorfollownon-

[FoC]-marked,merelynew,constituents,asin34(a)and(b),aswellasthephoneticsofall-

newsentenceslikethatin34(c).

Page 35: deconstructing information structure

35

(34) a. FoC-New:Theyonlyproduced[linen]FoCin[Nineveh].

b. New-FoC:Theyonlyproduced[linen]in[Nineveh]FoC.

c. New-New:Theyproduced[linen]in[Nineveh].

Katz&Selkirkfoundthatthesurfacephonologicalrepresentationsofthepost-verbal

phrasesin34(a)to(c)showthetypicaldefaultsurfaceH*L-tonepatternofaj,whetheror

notoneortheotherphrase,orneither,isalso[FoC]-marked.Thisbaselineidentityinthe

tonalcontentandphonologicalphrasingofthesentencesofsuchminimaltripletsprovides

aperfectlaboratoryforexaminingphoneticpatternsofrelativeprominenceinthepitch,

duration,andintensitydimensionsofthesuccessivepost-verbalphrases.Theresults

showedasignificantthree-waydifferenceinpatterningofrelativeprominence,onewhich

canbeillustratedbythearrowsin(35).

(35)Phonologicalrepresentationwithphoneticpitchdownstep/upsteppatterns:

a. …..(produced)w((linen)ws)jsin((ßNineveh)ws)j

H*L- H*L-

b. …..(produced)w((linen)ws)jin(((­)Nineveh)ws)js

H*L- H*L-

c. …..(produced)w((linen)ws)jin((¯Nineveh)ws)j

H*L- H*L-

Theall-newcasein35(c)reflectsthephoneticbaseline,namelythepresenceofsome

degreeofdownstep(indicatedby¯)betweenthepitchvaluesoftheH*pitchpeaksofthe

twosuccessivediscourse-newphrases(Liberman&Pierrehumbert1984onEnglish,Grabe

Page 36: deconstructing information structure

36

1998,Truckenbrodt2004onGerman).IntheFoC-newcasein35(a),thereisasignificantly

greaterdegreeofdownstep(indicatedbyß)betweentheH*peaksofthetwophrases.

FollowingTruckenbrodt(2007b),KatzandSelkirk(2011)seethislargedownstepasa

phoneticreflexofthehigherdegreeofprosodic/phonologicalprominenceonthej

correspondingtothe[FoC]-markedconstituent,whichisinitialinthesequence.Asforthe

new-FoCcase35(b),thereissomevariabilityinthepatternobserved.Theremaybeasmall

upstepofthecounterpartoftheFoCusedphrasewithrespecttotheprecedingphrase,or

thepitchheightofthetwomaybemoreorlessonapar.Baselinedownsteppingis

counteractedinthephoneticinterpretationoftheprominenceofthecounterpartofthe

[FoC]-markedconstituentin35(b).26

Theexperimentalresultsshowthatthepatternsofrelativephoneticprominenceinnew-

FoCandnew-newaresignificantlydifferent.Thisdissimilarityhasledustohypothesize

thatthereisnoprominentjsstatusforthecounterpartofthesecondverbalcomplementin

anall-newsentencelike35(c).Butwhywouldn’tani-levelprosodicmarkednessconstraint

thatistheanalogueofPhrasalProminencecallforoneofthedaughtersofitobe

prominent?Oursuggestionisthatprominenceatthei-levelinunderlyingrepresentationis

availableonlyastheexpressionof[FoC]-marking.Tocapturethisrequiresaddinga

constraintonthesyntax-phonologyinterfaceinStandardEnglish:

(36)FoCusPrivilege

Adaughterofiisprominentonlyifitscounterpartinsyntacticrepresentation

dominatesa[FoC]-markedconstituent.

26. Katz&Selkirk(2011)didnotindicatethejcorrespondingtotheVPin35(a)to(c).Iftherewassuchaj,PhrasalProminencewouldcallforoneofitsdaughterstobeprominent,andthatwouldpresumablybetheright-most.Thatlowerjwouldnotbeinapositiontocarryi-level prominence, however.

Page 37: deconstructing information structure

37

FoCusPrivilegewouldcomplementtheconstraintFoCusProminence,theotherconstraint

relevantto[FoC]-marking.FoCusProminenceisspecifictothegrammarofStandard

English.PerhapsFoCusPrivilegeistoo.

Thereisadditionalevidenceforthephonologicalrepresentationof[FoC]prominencefrom

caseswheretheFoCusfallsonaword,ratherthanaphrase.In(37),a[FoC]-markedverb

precedesadiscourse-newobject.

(37)(Guesswhat!)

a. [[Sarah][[mailed]FoC[thecaramels]].(Shedidn’tFed-Exthem.)

b. (((Sarah)ws)j(((mailed)ws)jsthe((caramels)ws)j)js)i

H*L-H*L-H*L-

(37)mightbeutteredinasituationwherebothspeakerandhearerknowthatSarah

plannedtosendoffaboxofcaramelsyesterday,andwhentheysaweachothertoday,the

firstthingthatwasreportedabouteitherSarahorthecaramelswaswhatisexpressedin

(37),where,semantically,acontrastwithrespecttothemodeofsendingthecaramels

(mailing(bythepostalservice)vs.sendingbyFedEx)comesintoplay.NeitherSarahorthe

caramelswouldbesalientinthisdiscourseandthereforethereisno[G]-markinginthis

firstexchangeoftheday.

Thefactualobservationisthat,whena[FoC]-markedverbisfollowedbyadiscourse-new

object,the[FoC]markedverbhasthestatusofaphonologicalphraseinsurface

representation.27Boththeverbandtheobjectinthegrammaticalsurfacerepresentationof

(37)carryanobligatoryH*pitchaccent,whichisareflexofj-levelprominence.Moreover,

therightedgeoftheverbcoincideswithaL-tone,whichisadefaultpropertyoftheright

edgeofaj.Whatforcestheprominentverbtoacquirethestatusofaphrase?Thereason,

wepropose,isthat,iftheverbdidn’tacquirejstatus,therewouldbeaviolationof

27. Selkirk(2002)providesexperimentalevidenceforthissortofpatternfromrightnoderaisingsentences,whereaFoC-markedverbisfollowedbyadiscoursenewobject.

Page 38: deconstructing information structure

38

UnequalSistersProminence:thewcorrespondingtotheverbiss-markedduetoFoCus

Prominence,butithasaphrasalsister(correspondingtotheverb’sdirectobject),which

shouldbetheprominentoneaccordingtoUnequalSistersProminence.

ConsidernextcaseswithtwoFoCusconstituentsinthesamesentence.Anexamplewould

be(38),whichisaconfigurationnottestedinKatz&Selkirk(2011).(38)couldbeafollow

uptoaprecedingall-newsentenceTheyproducedtapestriesinBabylon.

(38) FoC-FoC:Andthey[produced[linen]FoCin[Nineveh]FoC]VP.

Wehavetosayattheoutsetthatwedonotknowwhatthefullpictureofprominenceisin

thiscase.Tobesure,thereisatleastphrasalstatusandphrasalprominenceforlinenand

Nineveh,hencetwoH*pitchaccentswithfollowingL-edgetones.Whatwedonotknowis

whetheroneFoCusedphraseismoreprominentthantheotherandwhattheprominence

levelis.Hereishowwewouldapproachtheissueonouraccount.FoCusProminenceaims

forthehighestpossibleprominencefortheprosodiccounterpartsof[FoC]-marked

constituents.Themoststraightforwardwayofsatisfyingthisrequirementfor(38)would

be39(b),wherethecounterpartsofboth[FoC]-markedphraseshavei-levelprominence.

(39) a. FoC-FoC:Andthey[produced[linen]FoCin[Nineveh]FoC]VP.

b. (…..((produced)w((linen)ws)jsin((Nineveh)ws)js)js)i

H*L- H*L-

However,39(b)violatesPhrasalProminence.ThejcorrespondingtotheVPhastwos-

markeddaughters.Theremedyinsuchacasewouldbedephrasing,thatis,theelimination

ofthejcorrespondingtotheVP,asshownin40(b):

(40) a. FoC-FoC:Andthey[produced[linen]FoCin[Nineveh]FoC]VP.

Page 39: deconstructing information structure

39

b. (…..(produced)w((linen)ws)jsin((Nineveh)ws)js)i

H*L- H*L-

40(b)obeysFoCusProminenceandPhrasalProminence,buttherearenowtwostrong

daughtersofi.Wedonotknowwhetherthisisthecorrectresult,butitshouldbepossible

tosortoutexperimentallywhetherphoneticdataonrelativeprominencesupportsthis

analysis:ifcorrect,40(b)wouldbepredictedtobedistinctfromeachofthethree

configurationstestedbyKatz&Selkirk(2011).

Ifthe[FoC]-featurecallsforprominenceatthehighestpossiblelevel,whilethe[G]-feature

bansphraselevelprominence,whatdoesthisimplyforconfigurationswherea[FoC]-

markedphraseappearswithina[G]-markedphrase?Examplesarecasesofso-called

‘SecondOccurrenceFocus’illustratedin(41)below.Thecontextdescriptionand41(a)are

fromBeaveretal.(2007:256,example9).We’veadded41(b)andtheannotations.

(41) BothSidandhisaccomplicesshouldhavebeennamedinthismorning’scourt

session.Butthedefendantonlynamed[Síd]FoCincourttoday.

a. Even[thestateprósecutor]FoC[onlynamed[Sid]FoCincourttoday]G.

b. Even[thestateprósecutor]FoC[onlynamed[him/*’m]FoCincourttoday]G.

In41(a)and(b),apitchaccentH*ismissingonthe[FoC]-markedphrasewithinthe[G]-

markedphrase,afactconfirmedforanalogouscasesinBeaveretal.(2007)andother

experimentalstudiessinceRooth(1996).Themissingpitchaccentisexpected,givenour

formulationofFoCusProminence.In41(a),[FoC]-markingofSidrequiresthatSidhave

prominenceatthehighestpossiblelevel,thatis,atthehighestlevelitcanreachwithout

violatingotherconstraints.SinceSidisenclosedina[G]-markedconstituent,thehighest

possibleprominencelevelforSidisatthew-level(ans-markedfoot):theprosodic

Page 40: deconstructing information structure

40

counterpartsof[G]-markedconstituentscannotincludej-levelprominence(ans-marked

w).SinceH*requiresj-levelprominence,theabsenceofH*forSidin41(a)follows.

It’snotthat[G]-markingsimplynullifies[FoC]-marking.41(b)showsthatthereisarolefor

FoCusProminenceevenwhena[FoC]-markedphraseisenclosedina[G]-markedone.As

observedbySusanneTunstallandreportedinvonFintel(1994),anEnglishpronounin

configurationslike41(b)mustappearinitsstrong,stressed,form.Thefull-bodiedpronoun

himisrequiredhereinsteadoftheweakform‘m,whichispronouncedeitherasasyllabic

nasal,orasareducedvowelfollowedbythenasal.Reducedpronunciationslikethoseof

theweakformshaveasyllablethatcarriesnoprosodicprominenceatall.The

correspondingstrongformshaveminimallyfoot-levelprominence,andcouldthusbethe

locusofmainwordstressaswell.Thereisaprosodiceffectof[FoC]-marking,then,even

withina[G]-markedconstituent.Thiscaseprovidessupportfortheformulationin(32)of

FoCusProminence,whichpermitsvariationinthelevelofprosodicprominenceof[FoC]-

markedconstituents.

WeconcludethatthehypothesisthatFoCusandGivennessarerepresentedbytwo

morphosyntacticfeatures[FoC]and[G]yieldsaninsightfulaccountofthephonological

(andphonetic)effectsofthosetwoInformationStructurenotionsinStandardAmerican

andBritishEnglishwithinplausibleassumptionsofprosodicphonology.Atthesametime,

ouraccountmakesclearthat,cross-linguistically,phonologicalexponenceofthetwo

featuresviapropertiesrelatingtoprosodicprominenceisjustonepossibleoption,an

optionthatsetsthosevarietiesofEnglishapartfromothervarietiesandmanyother

languageswherethesametwofeaturesmaysurfaceindifferentwaysornotatall.Prosodic

spelloutisjustonelanguage-particularwayofspellingoutthosefeatures.

Inthenextsection,wewillshowthatthereisalsonothingspecialorexceptionalaboutthe

meaningofthetwofeatures[G]and[FoC].[FoC]isaclosecousinofthe[wh]-feature,and

[G]resemblesdiscourseparticlesinlanguageslikeGerman.Positingthosetwo

morphosyntacticfeatures,then,requiresnonewassumptionsaboutthekindsofmeanings

thatcanbecarriedbymorphosyntacticfeaturesinnaturallanguages,oraboutpossible

Page 41: deconstructing information structure

41

semanticorpragmaticarchitecturesthatthosefeaturesinteractwith.Themany

observationsaboutfocusandgivennessthatsemanticistshavegatheredovertheyearscan

benaturallyaccountedforbyinteractionsof[G]and[FoC]withtherestofthegrammar.

7. TheMeaninganddistributionof[FoC]and[G]

Both[G]-markingand[FoC]-markingimposerequirementsonthecurrentdiscourse.[G]-

markingtargetsmatcheswithwhatwassaidbeforeorisotherwisesalientinthediscourse

context.[FoC]-markingintroducesalternativestorepresentacontrast.Tostatethe

discourserequirementstriggeredby[G]and[FoC],wewillcontinuetorelyonthe

AlternativesSemanticsofRooth(1992,2016).Wesawalreadythat,inAlternatives

Semantics,expressionsareassignedtwosemanticvalues:O-values(ordinarymeanings)

andA-values(alternativessets).Oursemanticvaluesalsodependonarepresentationof

thediscoursecontextC.Amongotherthings,discoursecontextsdeterminewhatthe

availablediscoursereferentsare.Wearenotassuminganyparticularrepresentationof

discoursecontextshere,aslongastheyprovideanupdatablerecordofavailablediscourse

referents.DiscourseRepresentationTheory,fromitsverybeginninginKamp(1981),has

exploredhowdiscoursereferentsofvarioustypesareorganizedintostructured

representationsofdiscoursecontextsandmadeavailablefordiscourseanaphoricrelations

ofvariouskinds.

Withourfeaturerepertoire,it’sthe[FoC]-feature,ratherthanRooth’s[F]-feature,that

introducesalternatives:

(42) Themeaningofthe[FoC]-feature

O-values:

⟦[𝛼]Foc⟧O,C=⟦𝛼⟧O,C.

Page 42: deconstructing information structure

42

A-values:

For𝛼oftypet,

⟦[𝛼]FoC⟧A,C=Dt(thesetofallpossibleentitiesoftypet).

ThisisstandardRoothianAlternativesSemantics:ThecomputationoftheO-valueof[𝛼]Foc

overlooks[FoC]-marksandoutputstheO-valueof𝛼.For𝛼ofsemantictypet,theA-value

of[𝛼]FoCisthesetofallpossibleentitiesoftypet.28Theonlychangeweneedtoimplement

comeswiththe[G]-feature.The[G]-featureplacesaGivennessrequirementonthe

discoursecontext:

(43) Givenness

Anexpression𝛼isGiveninacontextCifthereisadiscoursereferent(individual,

property,proposition)inCthatentails⟦𝛼⟧O,C.

(43)saysthatforanexpressiontobeGiven,itsordinaryvaluemustbeentailedbya

discoursereferentintherecordofthecurrentdiscoursecontext.Thediscoursereferent

maybeaprecedinglinguisticantecedentorwhateverentitymaybesalientinthediscourse

contextwithouthavingbeenexplicitlymentioned.(43)reliesonacross-categorialnotion

ofentailmentthatrelatesindividuals,properties,andpropositions.Wecanassumethat

individualsentaileachotherwhentheyareidenticalandthenuseastandardrecursive

definition(vonFintel1999):

(44) Cross-categorialentailment29

Therelationofcross-categorialentailment⟹holdsbetweenentities𝔞and𝔟justin

caseoneofconditions(i)to(iii)applies:

28. SeeKatzir(2013)forargumentsthatthegenerationofalternativesshouldbeaspermissiveasstatedandnotberestrictedfurther.29. ThetypesystemisGallin’s(Gallin1975),withbasictypese,t,ands.ThedefinitioncanbemadesensitivetoinfluencesofcontextbyassumingthatacontextCmightconstrain

Page 43: deconstructing information structure

43

(i) 𝔞,𝔟ÎDe,and𝔞=𝔟.

(ii) 𝔞,𝔟ÎDt,and𝔞=0or𝔟=1.

(iii) 𝔞,𝔟ÎD<𝜏𝜎>,andforall𝔠inD𝜏,𝔞(𝔠)⟹𝔟(𝔠).

(43)isnon-committalaboutwhatittakesforanentitytobecomeadiscoursereferentina

context.Thisisdeterminedbyacombinationoflinguisticandextra-linguisticfactorsthat

donothavetoconcernushere.WithacharacterizationofGivennessinplace,wecanstate

thecontributionofthe[G]-featureasin(45):

(45) Themeaningofthe[G]-feature

O-values

⟦[𝛼]G⟧O,Cisdefinediff𝛼isGiveninC.

Ifdefined,⟦[𝛼]G⟧O,C=⟦𝛼⟧O,C.

A-values

⟦[𝛼]G⟧A,C=⟦𝛼⟧A,C.

The[G]-featureintroducesaGivennessrequirementthatisappliedtotheutterance

context,regardlessofhowdeeplyembeddedthefeaturemaybe.[G]doesnotcontribute

anythingtothetruth-conditionalcontentoftheexpressionsitattachesto,then,nordoesit

affectthecomputationofalternatives.Itscontributionisuse-conditionalorexpressivein

thesenseofKaplan(1999),Kratzer(1999,2004),Potts(2003),andGutzmann(2015).In

thatrespect,[G]resemblesdiscourseparticleslikeGermanjaordoch,assuggestedin

Kratzer(2004).Wechosetoimplementthecontributionof[G]asacontextual

presupposition,butweremainopentothepossibilitythatuse-conditionalmeaningsarea

distinguishedclassofmeaningsrequiringtheirownarchitecture,asarguedinPotts(2003).

thebasicdomainsDe(individuals)andDs(possibleworlds).Thisversionofgeneralizedentailmentdoesn’trunintotheproblemofSchwarzschild’s(1999)definitionmentionedinfootnote11.

Page 44: deconstructing information structure

44

Toillustratethesystem,we’llcomputeO-valuesandA-valuesforyouranswerintheby

nowfamiliarexample(2).

(2) Me: Sarahmailedthecaramels.

You: (No),[Eliza]FoC[mailedthecaramels]G

(46) Samplecomputation:[FoC]-markedname

O-value

⟦[Eliza]Foc⟧O,C=⟦Eliza⟧O,C=Eliza.

A-value

⟦[Eliza]FoC⟧A,C={Eliza,Sarah,Leif,…}

Samplecomputation:[G]-markedVP

O-value:

DefinediffmailedthecaramelsisGiveninC,thatis,iffthereisadiscoursereferent

inCthatentails⟦mailedthecaramels⟧O,C=𝝀x.𝝀w.mailed-the-caramels(x)(w).If

defined,⟦[mailedthecaramels]G⟧O,C=⟦mailedthecaramels⟧O,C=𝝀x.𝝀w.mailed-the-

caramels(x)(w).

A-value:

⟦[mailedthecaramels]G⟧A,C=⟦mailedthecaramels⟧A,C={𝝀x.𝝀w.mailed-the-

caramels(x)(w)}.

TocomputetheO-valueandA-valueforyouranswerin(2)asawhole,wecombinetheO-

valuesandA-valuesoftheirimmediateconstituents.TheO-valuesarecombinedvia

functionalapplication.TheA-valuescombineviapoint-wisefunctionalapplication:

(47) Samplecomputationofyouranswerinexample(2)

O-value:

Definediff⟦[mailedthecaramels]G⟧O,Cis.

Page 45: deconstructing information structure

45

Ifdefined,⟦[Eliza]FoC[mailedthecaramels]G⟧O,C=

⟦[mailedthecaramels]G⟧O,C(⟦[Eliza]FoC⟧O,C)=

𝝀x𝝀w.mailed-the-caramels(x)(w)(Eliza)=

𝝀w.mailed-the-caramels(Eliza)(w).

A-value:

⟦[Eliza]FoC[mailedthecaramels]G⟧A,C=

⟦[mailedthecaramels]G⟧A,C×⟦[Eliza]FoC⟧A,C=

⟦mailedthecaramels⟧A,C×⟦[Eliza]FoC⟧A,C=

{𝝀x𝝀w.mailed-the-caramels(x)(w)}×{Eliza,Sarah,Leif,…}= {𝝀w.mailed-the-caramels(Eliza)(w),𝝀w.mailed-the-caramels(Sarah)(w),

𝝀w.mailed-the-caramels(Leif)(w),…}.

Bynowacrucialdifferencebetween[G]and[FoC]hasemerged.[G]imposesadiscourse

requirementrelatedtoGivenness.[FoC]allbyitselfdoesnottriggeranydiscourse

requirement,itmerelyintroducesalternatives.FollowingRooth(1992),weareassuming

thatthecontrastrequirementthatcomeswith[FoC]-markingisintroducedbyaseparate

operator(the‘squiggle’)markingthescopeoftheFoCus.The~operatorhasadetectable

presenceinsyntax.Forexample,wesawinsection2thatSinhalahasverbalinflection

markingthescopeofapossiblydistantfocusedconstituent,suggestingaconfiguration

similartowh-constructions.Thepositionofthe~operatoralsoseemstobeatargetfor

movement,assumingthatthereisfocusrelatedmovement,asarguedasearlyasChomsky

(1976)andreconfirmedmostrecentlyinErlewine&Kotek(2018).30

Whilespeakersarefreeto[FoC]-markjustaboutanythingtheyplease,[FoC]-marked

constituentsmustbec-commandedbya~operator.FoCusing,then,alwayscarriesa

30. The~operatordoesn’tseemtohaveanycounterpartinprosodicstructure.Assumingourserialarchitecture,thesemanticscopeor‘domain’ofFoCuscouldnotplayanyroleindeterminingtheprosodicdomainforFoCusprominence,then,contrarytowhatisproposedinTruckenbrodt(1995),andreflectedinFéry&Samek-Lodovici‘s(2006)constraintStress-FocusandinBüring’s(2016)FocusRealizationcondition.

Page 46: deconstructing information structure

46

commitmenttocontrastinthetechnicalsensedefinedbelow(spelledContrastfromnow

on).Amorefleshed-outrepresentationofyourresponsein(2)is(48).

(48) Me: [Sarahmailedthecaramels]𝔞.

You: (No),~𝔞[[Eliza]FoC[mailedthecaramels]G]

The~operatorcomeswithanindex𝔞thatestablishesalinktoamatchingdiscourse

referentoftherighttype,which,inourexample,isthepropositionthatSarahmailedthe

caramels.ThatpropositionisdistinctfromthepropositionthatElizamailedthecaramels

andisalsoamongthealternativesdeterminedbythescopeofthe~operator.Inthisway

yourreplyin(48)representsaContrastwithwhatIsaidbefore.(49)isafirstattemptto

definethenotionofContrastrepresentationthatweareafter.

(49) Contrastrepresentation(notfinal)

Anexpression𝛼representsaContrastwithadiscoursereferent(individual,

property,proposition)𝔞justincaseconditions(i)and(ii)aresatisfied:

(i) 𝔞∈⟦𝛼⟧A,C.

(ii) 𝔞≠⟦𝛼⟧O,C.

Themeaningdefinitionforthe~operatorcanbestatedasin(50):

(50) The~operator

O-values

⟦~𝔞𝛼⟧O,Cisonlydefined,if𝛼representsaContrastwith𝔞,where𝔞isadiscourse

referentinC.Ifdefined,⟦~𝔞𝛼⟧O,C=⟦𝛼⟧O,C.

A-values

⟦~𝔞𝛼⟧A,C={⟦𝛼⟧O,C}.

AsinRooth(1992),the~operatorusesthealternativesdeterminedbyitsscopetoimpose

aContrastrequirement.Itthenblocksaccesstothosealternativesforhigheroperators.

Page 47: deconstructing information structure

47

Technically,itdoessobysettingtheA-valueof~𝔞𝛼backtoasingletonsetcontainingthe

O-valueof𝛼asitsonlymember.TheA-valueof𝛼isthusnolongervisibletofurther

computations.

UnlikeRooth(1992),ournotionofContrasthasnoprovisionforantecedentsthatare

questions.Thisisasitshouldbe.WhenwelookedattheItaliandatainsection4,wesaw

thatquestionsallbythemselvesdonotnecessarilytriggeraFoCusintheanswer.Krifka

(2004)presentsanadditionalargumentthatshedsseriousdoubtsontheassumptionthat

question-answercongruenceisarelationofContrast.(51)and(52)illustrate.

(51) Me: Lucieplantedthisbush.

a. You: (No),she[prunedthistrée]FoC.

b. You: (No),she[prúned]FoC[thistrée]FoC.

(52) Me: WhatdidLuciedo?

a. You: Sheonly[prunedthistrée]FoC.

b. You:#Sheonly[prúned]FoC[thistrée]FoC.

Both51(a)and(b)areacceptablereplies,andareexpectedtobe,sincebothrepresenta

ContrastwithwhatIsaidaccordingtoourdefinition.31Yetonly52(a)wouldbecongruent

withmyquestion.

Krifkapointsoutthat,ifalternativessetsareaspermissiveasRoothtakesthemtobe(and

Katzir(2013)saystheyhavetobe),thealternativessetforthe(a)-repliesin(51)and(52)

winduptobethesameasthoseforthe(b)-replies.Toseethis,takeanypropertyof

individualsPofsemantictype<e<st>>.PisinthealternativessetoftheVP[prunedthis

tree]FoC.Butnowconsider𝜆x.P,theconstantfunctionthatmapsanyindividualtothe

31. Sincethealternativessetsarethesameforbothofyourrepliesin(51),thereviseddefinitionofContrastrepresentationin(56)belowwillstillallowbothrepliestorepresentaContrastwiththeantecedentproposition.

Page 48: deconstructing information structure

48

propertyP.Beingoftype<e<e<st>>>,thisfunctionisinthealternativessetofthetransitive

verb[pruned]FoC,hencePisinthealternativessetoftheVP[[pruned]FoC[thistree]FoC].

KrifkaconcludesthatAlternativesSemanticsisunfittohandlequestion-answer

congruence:itcan’tdistinguishtheacceptable52(a)fromtheunacceptable52(b).From

ourperspective,thoseverysameobservationsdonotdiscreditAlternativesSemantics,

rathertheyconfirmourearlierconclusionthatquestionanswer-congruenceisnota

relationofContrasttobeginwith.

Question-answercongruenceisestablishedviatheGivenpartofanswersonourapproach.

ImportantinsightsabouttheconnectionbetweenInformationStructureandquestions

(Roberts1996,2012)thusremainuntouched.Thereisalessontobelearned,though:The

investigationofquestion-answerpairscannotbeusedtodiagnoseFoCus.Ifwedrawa

distinctionbetweenwhat’sFoCusedandwhat’smerelynewbyrepresentingGivenness,

ratherthannewness,thenotionofananswerfocusisnolongeranobviousone.Nowit’s

Givenness,notFoCus,thatisreliablydiagnosedwithquestion-answerpairs.32

GoingbacktoourdefinitionofContrastrepresentationin(49),itturnsoutthatitistoo

liberal.AsobservedinSchwarzschild(1993)andreportedinTruckenbrodt(1995),

definitionslike(49)allowoverFoCusingandthusincorrectlypredictthat53(b)represents

aContrastwiththepropositionexpressedby53(a),forexample.TheO-valuesof53(a)and

(b)aredifferent,andtheO-valueof53(a)isamemberoftheA-valueof53(b).Thisisnot

good.33

32. Féry&Samek-Lodovici(2006)andBüring(2016)haveboth[F]-markingand[G]-marking,yetstillholdontothenotionofananswerfocus.Question-answerpairsarediscussedasprototypicalinstancesoffocusinFéry&Ishihara(2016),whichsetsthestagefortheotherarticlesintheFéry&Ishiharahandbook.33. 53(b)canbeusedtocontradict53(a)ifstrawberriesisunderstoodasacontrastivetopic,withcharacteristic,rising,contrastivetopicintonation.That’snotthecontrastrelationthatwearetryingtocapture.

Page 49: deconstructing information structure

49

(53) a. JohnpickedstrawberriesatMary’sfarm.

b. Johnpicked[strawberries]FoCat[Sandy’s]FoCfarm.

Schwarzschild(1993:examples9(a)and(c),usingthecurrentnotation).

Schwarzschild(1993)alsoprovidesaremedyagainsttheover-FoCusingillustratedin(53).

Adaptedtoourframework,Schwarzschild’sContrastConstraintdeliversacriterionfor

disqualifyinganexpression𝛼fromrepresentingaContrastwithanentity𝔞ifaContrast

with𝔞couldalsoberepresentedbywhatwewillcalla“FoC/G-variant”of𝛼withasmaller

alternativesset.TwoexpressionsareFoC/G-variantsofeachotheriftheyareidentical

exceptfor[FoC]-markingand[G]-marking.54(a)to(e)illustratetheideabehind

Schwarzschild’sContrastConstraint.Since[G]-markingdoesnotaffectthecomputationof

A-values,weareneglecting[G]-markingpossibilities.

(54) 𝔭=thepropositionthatJohnpickedstrawberriesatMary’sfarm.

a. Johnpickedstrawberriesat[Sandy’s]FoCfarm.

b. Johnpickedstrawberriesat[Sandy’sfarm]FoC.

c. Johnpicked[strawberries]FoCat[Sandy’s]FoCfarm.

d. Johnpicked[strawberries]FoCat[Sandy’sfarm]FoC.

e. John[pickedstrawberriesatSandy’sfarm]FoC.

54(a)to(e)areFoC/G-variantsofeachother.Accordingto(49),theyshouldallrepresenta

Contrastwiththeproposition𝔭thatJohnpickedstrawberriesatMary’sfarm.Hereiswhy.

54(a)to(e)allhavethesameO-value,whichisthepropositionthatJohnpicked

strawberriesatSandy’sfarm.Thatpropositionisdifferentfrom𝔭,hencecondition(ii)of

(49)issatisfied.Condition(i)issatisfiedaswell,since𝔭isamemberoftheA-valuesof

54(a)to(e):SandyisanalternativeofMary,Sandy’sfarmisanalternativeofMary’sfarm,

strawberriesareamongthealternativesofstrawberries,andpickingstrawberriesat

Sandy’sfarmisanalternativeofpickingstrawberriesatMary’sfarm.Intuitively,only54(a)

representsagoodcontrastwith𝔭,however.AlltheothercasesareoverFoCused:Theyhave

eithertoomanyortoobigconstituentsthatareFoCused.

Page 50: deconstructing information structure

50

Tofindacriterionfordisqualifying54(b)to(e)fromrepresentingaContrastwith𝔭,we

comparetheirA-valuestothatof54(a).WhatweseeisthattheA-valueof54(a)isaproper

subsetofalltheothers:

(55) ⟦54(a)⟧A,C⊂⟦54(b)⟧A,C⊂⟦54(d)⟧A,C⊂⟦54(e)⟧A,C

⟦54(a)⟧A,C⊂⟦54(c)⟧A,C⊂⟦54(d)⟧A,C⊂⟦54(e)⟧A,C

Amongthechoicesin54(a)to(e),weshouldthuspicktheonewiththesmallest

alternativessetasrepresentingaContrastwith𝔭.IncorporatingSchwarzschild’sContrast

Constraint,ourdefinitionofContrastrepresentationcannowbeamendedasin(56):

(56) Contrastrepresentation(finalfornow)

Anexpression𝛼representsaContrastwithadiscoursereferent(individual,

property,proposition)𝔞justincaseconditions(i)to(iii)aresatisfied:

(i) 𝔞∈⟦𝛼⟧A,C.

(ii) 𝔞≠⟦𝛼⟧O,C

(iii) ThereisnoFoC/G-variant𝛽of𝛼suchthat⟦𝛽⟧A,C⊂⟦𝛼⟧A,Cand𝔞∈⟦𝛽⟧A,C.

Somecontrastsseemtrivial.In57(a)to(c),forexample,everywordispartofa[FoC]-

markedconstituentandthereareno[G]-markedorunmarked(new)parts.

(57) a. [Eliza]FoC[[mailed]FoC[thecaramels]FoC]

b. [Eliza]FoC[mailedthecaramels]FoC

c. [Eliza[mailedthecaramels]]FoC

It’stooeasyforthoserepresentationstosatisfytheContrastrequirementforFoCus,since

thealternativessetsgeneratedforsuch[FoC]-markingconfigurationsarecompletely

unrestricted:theycontainanyentitywhatsoever,aslongasitisoftherighttype.Definition

(56)doesn’tmake57(a)to(c)ineligibleforrepresentingContrasts,andrightlyso.57(a)to

(c)shouldn’tbedisqualifiedoffhand.57(a)mightbeutteredbyagradeschoolteacher

Page 51: deconstructing information structure

51

givingdictation,forexample,andtheconfigurationsin57(b)and(c)arenaturalinthe

contextof(58).

(58) Whatdidyourchildrendoforthecommongoodtoday?

a. SarahworkedattheSurvivalCenterallday,[Eliza]FoConly[mailedthe

caramelstoGrandpa]FoC.

b. Theonlythingworthmentioningisthat[Elizamailedthecaramelsto

Grandpa]FoC.

Aswewilldiscussshortly,thereispressureinStandardAmericanandBritishEnglishto

representContrastswithdiscoursereferentsfromtheprecedingcontext.Thatpressureis

unlikelytoextendtotrivialContrasts,though.Configurationslikethatin39(c),for

example,aresuretobeexemptfromwhateverpressurethereisforrepresentingContrasts.

SpeakersofEnglishwouldn’tevenbeabletodetectwhetherthereisa[FoC]-markin39(c).

AtwhatpointdoContrastsbecometootrivialtobeanorganizingforceindiscourse?

Whereexactlyisthecut-offpoint?Thequestionneedsmoreinvestigation.

FoCusingdoesn’talwaysrequireanantecedentintheprecedingdiscourse.Contrasting

discoursereferentscanbeaccommodatedonthespot,asinEllenPrince’scleftexample,

whichwelookedatearlier:

(14) TheleadersofthemilitanthomophilemovementinAmericagenerallyhavebeen

youngpeople.~𝔭[Itwas[they]FoCwhofoughtbackduringaviolentpoliceraidona

GreenwichVillagebarin1969],anincidentfromwhichmanygaysdatethebirthof

themoderncrusadeforhomosexualrights.

In(14),thepronountheyreferstotheyoungpeopleintherelevantdomain.FoCusingthey

evokesasanalternativethecomplementsetinthatdomain,thepeoplewhoarenolonger

young.Asaresult,thesentenceconveysthatyoungpeople,ratherthanolderpeople,were

theoneswhowerefightingbackduringthatpoliceraid.SincetheContrastingantecedentis

accommodated,theunFoCusedpartofthescopeoftheFoCusin(14)isnewinformation,

Page 52: deconstructing information structure

52

notGiven.WhileFoCusandGivennessoftentraveltogether,(14)standsasareminderthat

GivennessisinnowayanecessaryingredientforContrastrepresentation.

FoCusontheytriggersanexclusiveinterpretationin(14):thegroupofpeoplewhofought

backisrepresentedasagroupexcludingolderpeople.Wheredoesthisexclusive

interpretationcomefrom?(59),whichisinspiredbyanexamplefromWagner(2005,

2012),showsthatexclusiveinterpretationsdonotnecessarilyhavealocalsource.

(59) Me: DoesSallystilldrivethatexpensiveconvertibleherunclegaveherasa

weddingpresent?

You: Idon’tknow.WhatIcansaywithconfidenceisthatshedrivesa[réd]FoC

[convertible]G.

WhentellingmethatSallydrivesaredconvertibleyoudidn’tmeantoexcludethe

possibilitythatherconvertiblemightalsobeexpensive.Whatyoudidexcludewasthatyou

couldsaywithconfidencethatsheisdrivinganexpensiveconvertible.Theintendedscope

oftheFoCusonredstretchesallthewayuptothematrixclausein(59’),then,andthereis

againan(atleastpartially)accommodatedantecedent:

(59’) ~𝔭[WhatIcansaywithconfidenceisthatshedrivesa[réd]FoC[convertible]G].

Itmightbetemptingtothinkthatthe~operatoristhesourceoftheexclusive

interpretationin(59’).Butthatcan’tberight.FoCusdoesn’talwaystriggeranexclusive

interpretation:

(60) Me: Guesswhat!Oliverpassedthebarexam.

You: If[Oliver]FoC[passedthebarexam]G,barexamshavebecometooeasy.

In(60),FoCusonOlivertriggersascalar,ratherthananexclusive,interpretation,which

couldalsobebroughtoutbyanoverteven.What(60)isconveyingisthatOliverisatthe

lowerendofascalethatrankscandidatesaccordingtotheirchancestopassthebarexam.

Page 53: deconstructing information structure

53

Weconcludethatifthereisjustasingle~operator,itcan’tcomewithahard-wired

exclusiveinterpretation.Eitherthereisawholefamilyof~operatorsthatuseFoCus

alternativesindifferentways,or,moreplausibly,thereisasingle~operator,anddifferent

flavorsofFoCusaretheresultofseparateovertornon-overtoperatorsinteractingwithit,

asRooth(1992)proposed.34EitherpossibilityiscompatiblewiththetheoryofFoCus

representationadvocatedforhereandwithourcurrentknowledgeofFoCus-sensitive

operatorsthatmightcontributetothevariousflavorsofFoCusfoundacrosslanguages:

exhaustivityoperators(discussede.g.inSpector2016),scalaroperators(asine.g.Lahiri

1998),contrastivetopicoperators(asine.g.Constant2014),ormirativeoperators

(Bianchietal.2016).

Wehavenowlaidoutthesemanticpropertiesof[G]-markingand[FoC]-marking,butwe

haven’tyetsaidanythingaboutwhento[FoC]-markor[G]-mark,orhowthosetwo

featuresinteract.Williams(1997)discussescaseswhereconstituentsareGiven,butare

neverthelessobligatorilyFoCused.(61)illustrateswithanexamplethatisavariationof

onebyWilliams.

(61) Me: Romandoubtedthatitwouldbehotandpredictedthatitwouldbecold.

# You: [Máx]FoC[doubted]G[thatitwouldbecold]G.

Yourreplyin(61)isdeviantinthegivencontext,andseverelyso.AccordingtoWilliams

(1997:599),theproblemwithcaseslike(61)isthat“cumulativedestressingisnot

allowed.Onecannotdestressonephraseandthendestressitsneighbor,withseparate

licensingofeach.”Williams(1997,2012),Schwarzschild(1999),andWagner(2005,2012)

haveaccountsthat,eachintheirownway,convergeonWilliams’diagnosisofwhatis

wrongwithcaseslike(61).Rephrasingthediagnosisinourownwords,thereappearstobe

aproblemwhentwosisterconstituents𝛼and𝛽lackprominencewithouttheirmother

34. SeeBeck(2016)forageneraloverviewofFoCus-sensitiveoperatorsandtheirinteractionwiththe~operator.

Page 54: deconstructing information structure

54

constituent𝛼𝛽beingGiven.Inyourreplyin(61),bothdoubtedandthatitwouldbecoldare

Given,butdoubtedthatitwouldbecoldasawholeisnot.

Williams’diagnosisdoesn’tseemquiterightyet.62(a)and(b)goagainstit.35

(62) a. SallyranintoMaxbeforegettingmoneyfromtheATM.Sheendeduplénding

[[Max]G[someofthemoney]G].36

b. TheBorsalinoshopishavinganamazingsaleonhats.ButMax’spartner

wouldn’tlét[[Max]G[getaBorsalinohat]G].

62(a)and(b)areacceptablewithoutprominenceonanyoftheGivenconstituents,even

thoughMax’sgettingsomeofSally’smoneyorthepossibilityofhisgettingaBorsalinohat

arenotunderstoodtobecontextuallyimpliedbytherespectivestretchesofpreceding

discourse.Butthen62(a)and(b)haveconfigurationswheretwosisterconstituentslack

prominencewithouttheirmotherconstituentbeingGiven.What,then,isthedifference

betweenthedeviantexample(61)ontheonehand,andtheacceptable62(a)and(b)onthe

other?

Ourassessmentofthedevianceofyourreplyin(61)isthatinStandardAmericanand

BritishEnglish,thereispressureforrepresenting(non-trivial)Contrastswithsalient

discoursereferentsfromtheprecedingcontext.(61)isdeviantbecauseopportunitiesfor

35. Williamswouldruleout62(a)and(b)asviolationsofhisDisanaphoraLaw.ForSchwarzschild,hisGivennessrequirementwouldbeviolated,andforWagnerhisRelativeGivennessrequirement.36. Weareassumingthat[Maxsomeofthemoney]isaconstituentin62(a).ThisiscompatiblewithHarley(1995,2002)andotheranalysesofdoubleobjectconstructions.WithGreen(1974)andHarley,weassumefurtherthatthedoubleobjectconfigurationhereincludesasilentHAVE,sothatwehaveaconstituent[Max[HAVEsomeofthemoney]].

Page 55: deconstructing information structure

55

representingContrastshavebeenoverlooked.Thereweretwosuchopportunities,which

arerepresentedin(63)and(64).

(63) Me: Romandoubtedthatitwouldbehotand[(he)predictedthatitwouldbe

cold]𝔭.

You: ~𝔭[[Máx]FoC[dóubted]FoC[thatitwouldbecold]G].

(64) Me: [Romandoubtedthatitwouldbehot]𝔭andpredictedthatitwouldbecold.

You: ~𝔭[[Máx]FoC[doubted]Gthatitwouldbe[cóld]FoC].

62(a)and(b)wereconstructedsoastonotprovideopportunitiesforrepresenting(non-

trivial)Contrastswithsalientdiscoursereferentsfromtheprecedingcontext.Without

thoseopportunities,thepressureforrepresentingContrastsseemsoff.Thepressureis

pressurefromthediscoursecontext,then.It’sapushfordiscoursecoherence.Wepropose

theprinciplein(65),whichforces[FoC]-markingwhenthereareopportunitiesfor

representing(non-trivial)Contrasts:

(65) PressureforContrast

Represent(non-trivial)Contrasts.

Examples(63)and(64)notonlyillustratehowPressureforContrastcanforce[FoC]-

marking,theyalsoraisethequestionwhetherPressureforContrastcanblock[G]-marking.

(63)hasaFoCusedoccurrenceofdoubted,forexample,butthatoccurrenceofdoubtedis

alsoGivenaccordingtoourdefinition.Wemaywonder,then,whetheritshouldn’tbe[G]-

marked.Likewise,theFoCusedadjectivecoldin(64)ispartofasententialcomplement

thatisalsoGiven,sothereisagainaquestionwhetherthatcomplementshouldn’tbe[G]-

marked.Thatthose[G]-marksaregenuinelymissingissuggestedbytheprosodyof(63)

and(64),whichshowsnoimpactof[G]-marking,noteventheslightesthintofthereduced

prominencecharacteristicofSecondOccurrenceFoCus.Wetakethisisanindicationthat,

generally,[FoC]-markedconstituentscan’talsobe[G]-marked.Thisdoesn’texclude[FoC]-

markedconstituentsfrombeingproperlycontainedwithin[G]-markedconstituents,of

Page 56: deconstructing information structure

56

course,or[G]-markedconstituentsfrombeingproperlycontainedwithin[FoC]-marked

constituents.

Therearetwootherconstraintsfor[G]-markingthatourrepresentationshavebeen

conformingtowithoutmuchdiscussion.Oneisthatfunctionwords(asopposedtocontent

words)andstringsoffunctionwordsaregenerallynot[G]-marked.Thesecondonebars

redundantnestingof[G]-marks:aGivenconstituentisnot[G]-markedifitisproperly

containedinanotherGivenconstituent.Aswesawearlier,nested[G]-markingis

unnecessarysinceanypartofaGivenconstituentisGiven,too.Wehavethen:

(66) Pressurefor[G]-marking

[G]-markaGivenconstituent𝛼unlessoneof(i)to(iii)holds:

(i) 𝛼is[FoC]-marked.

(ii) 𝛼containsnocontentword.

(iii) 𝛼isproperlycontainedinaGivenconstituent.

Forourfinalexample,we’llputPressureforContrastandPressurefor[G]-markingtowork

toshedlightonanoldpuzzleabouttheroleofFoCusinforcingorblockingcoreference.37

(67)and(67’)illustrate.

(67) [BillblamedAmanda’sfather]𝔭andthen

a.[Amánda]FoC[[blamed]G[hím]FoC].

b.[Amánda]FoC[blamedhim]G.

Theonlydifferencebetween67(a)and(b)isthathimisFoCusedin67(a),butnotin67(b).

WeobservethathimhastorefertoBillin67(a),andtoAmanda’sfatherin67(b).Hereis

howwecanderivethisresult.PressureforContrasttellsusthat67(a)and(b)must

representaContrastwiththeantecedentproposition𝔭.SupposehimreferredtoAmanda’s

father.Inthatcase,67(a)wouldbeoverFoCused.ItwouldnotrepresentaContrastwith𝔭,

37. AnearlydiscussionofthephenomenonisinLakoff(1971).

Page 57: deconstructing information structure

57

since𝔭isalsointhealternativessetof67(b),whichisaFoC/G-variantof67(a)andhasa

smalleralternativesset.67(a)wouldalsoviolatePressurefor[G]-Marking,sincethe

propertyofblamingAmanda’sfatherisGiven.Therightrenditionwouldbe67(b),then.On

theotherhand,ifhimreferstoBill,67(a)doesrepresentaContrastwith𝔭.Thistimeround,

67(b)wouldberuledoutasviolatingboththeGivennessrequirementfor[G]-markingand

PressureforContrast:TheVPblamedhimisnotGiven,andtheantecedentproposition𝔭is

notinthealternativessetof67(b).

AquestionthatisnowonthetableiswhytherearesuchprinciplesasPressurefor

ContrastandPressurefor[G]-marking.Whatisitthatmakes[G]-markingandcertain

instancesof[FoC]-markingobligatoryinAmericanandBritishEnglish?Itmaybetempting

toinvoketheprinciple‘MaximizePresuppositions’,whichwasconsideredinHeim(1991).

AsHeimwaswellaware,though,suchaprinciplewouldneedtobeformulatedvery

carefully.Inourcase,wewouldhavetoexplain,forexample,whydiscourseparticleslike

Germanjaanddoch,whichonlyhaveuse-conditionalmeanings,too,arenotobligatory,

evenwhentheconditionstheyplaceonthediscoursecontextaremet.Whyshould

presencevsabsenceof[G]-markingorpresencevsabsenceof[FoC]-markingbedecidedby

MaximizePresuppositions,whilepresencevsabsenceofadiscourseparticlewouldnotbe?

Wewillhavetoleavethisquestionunansweredfornow.

Thissectionhaslaidoutthesyntacticandsemanticpropertiesofthefeatures[G]and

[FoC]:Whattheymean,whentheyhavetobeused,andwhentheycan’t.[FoC]islikethe

[wh]-featureinthatitformsoperatorstructuresandmaytriggermovementandverbal

agreement.The[G]-featureresemblesdiscourseparticleslikeGermanjaordoch(Kratzer

2004).Unlike[FoC]or[wh],butlikediscourseparticles,itdoesn’tformoperator

structures,butimposesitsdiscourserequirementdirectly.Whether[G]canalsodrive

movementortriggeragreementisstillanopenquestion.Existingworkonwordorder

variationreflectingapparentgivennesstendstonotdistinguishGivennessfromrelated

notionslikepresuppositionalityordefiniteness.Ifthedistinctionismade,asinFanselow

(2012,2016)andKučerová(2012),theobservedvariationisusuallyattributedtofactors

otherthanmereGivenness.AnexceptionisŠimíkandWierzba(2015),whoargue(against

Page 58: deconstructing information structure

58

Kučerová)thatGivenness,notpresuppositionality,isreflectedinCzechwordorder

variation.AccordingtoŠimíkandWierzba,CzechGivenphrasesavoidstress,but,unlike

EnglishGivenphrases,theymovetoleft-peripheralpositionstoescapethecanonical,

rightmost,stresspositioninCzech.ŠimíkandWierzba’sworkestablishesabridgetothe

workofReinhart(2006)andSzendröi(2001,2005,2017),andpointstothepossibilitythat

the[G]-feature,andpossiblyalsothe[FoC]-featureinsomelanguages,mightdrive

movementthataimsatcreatingaphonologicallymoredesirableinput.

8. Conclusion

Wehavearguedourcaseandshownwhatwesetouttoshowinthisarticle:Thecoreof

whathasbeentradedunderthename‘InformationStructure’canbedeconstructedinto

morphosyntacticfeaturesthathavefamiliartypesofmeaningsandarespelledout

prosodically,ratherthansegmentallyortonally,inStandardAmericanandBritishEnglish.

[FoC]-markinghighlightsContrastsandaimsforhighestprominenceinasentence.[G]-

markingissensitivetoGivennessandresists(phrase-level)prominence.Apartfromthe

idiosyncraticpropertiesofthosefeatures,whichguidetheirsyntacticdistribution,

felicitoususe,andphonologicalspellout,nospecialgrammaticalmechanismsor

architectureshavetobeassumedtoaccountforthemanyphonological,syntactic,

semantic,andpragmaticmanifestationsofnotionsrelatedtoGivennessandFoCus.

Theproposedfeaturesystemwith[G]and[FoC]isafarcryfromthesystemofSelkirk

(1984,1995),withitsbaroquenestedfeaturestructuresandadhocfocusprojection

principles.Wenowhavetwogenuinemorphosyntacticfeaturesthatfitintothetypologyof

grammaticalfeatures.EnglishisnolongeranobstacleforAboh’sConjecture.

Page 59: deconstructing information structure

59

References

Aboh,EnochO.2007.FocusedversusNon-FocusedWh-Phrases.FocusStrategiesinAfrican

Languages:TheInteractionofFocusandGrammarinNiger-CongoandAfro-Asiatic,ed.by

K.Hartmann&M.Zimmermann,287-314.Berlin:DeGruyterMouton.

—.2007.LeftwardFocusversusRightwardFocus:TheKwa-BantuConspiracy.SOASWorking

PapersinLinguistics15.81-104.

—.2010.InformationStructureBeginswiththeNumeration.Iberia:AnInternationalJournalof

TheoreticalLinguistics2.12-42.

—.2016.InformationStructure:ACartographicPerspective.TheOxfordHandbookofInformation

Structure,ed.byC.Féry&S.Ishihara,147-64.Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress.

Aldridge,Edith.2018.C-TInheritanceandtheLeftPeripheryinOldJapanese.Glossa3(1):article

26.1-22.

Ameka,FelixK.2010.InformationPackagingConstructionsinKwa:MicrovariationandTypology.

TopicsinKwaSyntax,ed.byE.O.Aboh&J.Essegbey,141-76.Dordrecht:Springer.

Beaver,David&DanVelleman.2011.TheCommunicativeSignificanceofPrimaryandSecondary

Accents.Lingua121.1671-92.

Beaver,DavidI.,BradyClark,EdwardStantonFlemming,T.FlorianJaeger&MariaWolters.2007.

WhenSemanticsMeetsPhonetics:AcousticalStudiesofSecond-OccurrenceFocus.

Language83.245-76.

Beck,Sigrid.2016.FocusSensitiveOperators.TheOxfordHandbookofInformationStructure,ed.

byC.Féry&S.Ishihara,227-50:OxfordUniversityPress.

Belletti,Adriana.2001.InversionasFocalization.SubjectInversioninRomanceandtheTheoryof

UniversalGrammar,ed.byA.C.J.Hulk&J.-I.Pollock,60-90.Oxford:OxfordUniversity

Press.

—.2004.AspectsoftheLowIPArea.TheStructureofCPandIP.TheCartographyofSyntactic

Structures,Volume2,ed.byL.Rizzi,16-51.Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress.

Page 60: deconstructing information structure

60

Bennett,Ryan,EmilyElfner&JamesMcCloskey.2016.LightesttotheRight:AnApparently

AnomalousDisplacementinIrish.LinguisticInquiry47(2).169-234.

Bianchi,Valentina,GuilianoBocci&SilvioCruschina.2016.FocusFronting,Unexpectedness,and

EvaluativeImplicatures.Semantics&Pragmatics9:article3.1-54.

Bolinger,Dwight.1965.PitchAccentandSentenceRhythm.FormsofEnglish:Accent,Morpheme,

Order,ed.byI.Abe&T.Kanekiyo,139-80.Tokyo:Hokuou.

Bresnan,Joan.1971.SentenceStressandSyntacticTransformations.Language47.257-81.

Büring,Daniel.2015.UnalternativeSemantics.Proceedingsofthe25thSemanticsandLinguistic

TheoryConference,ed.byS.D'Antonio,M.Maroney&C.R.Little,550-75.Stanford

University:LinguisticSocietyofAmericaandCornellLinguisticsCircle.

—.2016.IntonationandMeaningOxford:OxfordUniversityPress.

Calhoun,Sasha.2010.TheCentralityofMetricalStructureinSignalingInformationStructure:A

ProbabilisticPerspective.Language86.1-42.

Chafe,WallaceL.1976.Givenness,Contrastiveness,Definiteness,Subjects,TopicsandPointof

View.SubjectandTopic,ed.byC.N.Li,27-55.NewYork:AcademicPress.

Chomsky,Noam.1971.DeepStructure,SurfaceStructure,andSemanticInterpretation.Semantics.

AnInterdisciplinaryReaderinPhilosophy,LinguisticsandPsychology,ed.byD.D.

Steinberg&L.A.Jakobovits,183-216.Cambridge:CambridgeUniversityPress.

—.1976.ConditionsonRulesofGrammar.LinguisticAnalysis2.303-50.

Chomsky,Noam&MorrisHalle.1968.TheSoundPatternofEnglish:TheMITPress.

Constant,Noah.2014.ContrastiveTopic:MeaningandRealization:UniversityofMassachusetts

Amherst.

D'Imperio,Mariapaola.1997.BreadthofFocus,Modality,andProminencePerceptionin

NeapolitanItalian.OSUWorkingPapersinLinguistics50.19-39.

Elfner,Emily.2012.Syntax-ProsodyInteractionsinIrish:UniversityofMassachusettsAmherst

PhDdissertation.

—.2015.RecursioninProsodicPhrasing:EvidencefromConnemaraIrish.NaturalLanguageand

LinguisticTheory33.1169-208.

Fanselow,Gisbert.2012.ScramblingasFormalMovement.ContrastsandPositionsinInformation

Structure,ed.byI.Kučerová&A.Neeleman,267-95.Cambridge:CambridgeUniversity

Press.

Page 61: deconstructing information structure

61

—.2016.SyntacticandProsodicReflexesofInformationStructureinGermanic.TheOxford

HandbookofInformationStructure,ed.byC.Féry&S.Ishihara,621-41.Oxford:Oxford

UniversityPress.

Féry,Caroline&ShinichiroIshihara.2016.Introduction.TheOxfordHandbookofInformation

Structure,ed.byC.Féry&S.Ishihara,1-15.Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress.

Féry,Caroline&VieriSamek-Lodovici.2006.FocusProjectionandProsodicProminenceinNested

Foci.Language82.131-50.

vonFintel,Kai.1994.RestrictionsonQuantifierDomains:UniversityofMassachusettsAmherst

PhDDissertation.

—.1999.NPILicensing,StrawsonEntailment,andContextDependency.JournalofSemantics16.

97-148.

Frota,Sonia.2000.ProsodyandFocusinEuropeanPortuguese:PhonologicalPhrasingand

IntonationNewYork:GarlandPublishing.

Gallin,Daniel.1975.IntensionalandHigher-OrderModalLogicAmsterdam:North-Holland.

Gordon,MatthewK.2003.ThePhonologyofPitchAccentsinChickasaw.Phonology20.173-218.

Grabe,Esther.1998.ComparativeIntonationalPhonology:EnglishandGerman:Universiteit

NijmegenPhDdissertation.

Green,Georgia.1974.SemanticsandSyntacticRegularityBloomington:IndianaUniversityPress.

Gutzmann,Daniel.2015.Use-ConditionalMeaningOxford:OxfordUniversityPress.

Hagstrom,Paul.1998.DecomposingQuestions.MITPhDdissertation.

—.2004.ParticleMovementinSinhalaandJapanese.ClauseStructureinSouthAsianLanguages,

ed.byV.Dayal&A.Mahajan,227-52.Dordrecht:KluwerAcademicPublishers.

Hamblin,CharlesL.1973.QuestionsinMontagueEnglish.FoundationsofLanguage10.41-53.

Harley,Heidi.1995.Subjects,Events,andLicensing:MITPhD.

—.2002.PossessionandtheDoubleObjectConstruction.YearbookofLinguisticVariation2.29-

68.

Hayes,Bruce.1995.MetricalStressTheoryChicago:TheUniversityofChicagoPress.

Hedberg,Nancy.1990.DiscoursePragmaticsandCleftSentencesinEnglish:Universityof

Minnesota.

—.2010.TheReferentialStatusofClefts.Language76.891-920.

Page 62: deconstructing information structure

62

—.2013.MultipleFocusandCleftSentences.CleftStructures,ed.byK.Hartmann&T.Veenstra,

227-50.Amsterdam:JohnBenjaminsPublishingCompany.

Heim,Irene.1991.ArtikelundDefinitheit.Semantik/Semantics.AnInternationalHandbookof

ContemporaryResearched.byA.vonStechow&D.Wunderlich,487-535.Berlin:de

Gruyter.

Jackendoff,RayS.1972.SemanticInterpretationinGenerativeGrammarCambridge/Mass.:The

MITPress.

Kager,René.2007.FeetandMetricalStress.TheCambridgeHandbookofPhonology,ed.byP.de

Lacy,195-227.Cambridge:CambridgeUniversityPress.

Kamp,Hans.1981.ATheoryofTruthandSemanticRepresentation.FormalMethodsintheStudy

ofLanguage.Part1,ed.byJ.Groenendijk,T.Janssen&M.Stokhof,277-322.Amsterdam:

MathematischCentrum.

Kaplan,David.1999.TheMeaningof'Ouch'and'Oops'.PaperpresentedattheCornellConference

onContextDependency,CornellUniversity,IthacaNewYork.

Katz,Jonah&ElisabethSelkirk.2011.ContrastiveFocusvs.Discourse-New:Evidencefrom

PhoneticProminenceinEnglish.Language87.771-816.

Katzir,Roni.2013.ANoteonContrast.NaturalLanguageSemantics21.333-43.

Kishimoto,Hideki.2018.SinhalaFocusConcordConstructionsfromaDiscourse-Syntactic

Perspective.Glossa3.1-25.

Kiss,KatalinÉ.1998.IdentificationalFocusversusInformationFocus.Language74.245-73.

Kisseberth,Charles.1984.DigoTonology.StudiesinBantuTonology,ed.byG.N.Clements&J.A.

Goldsmith,105-82.Dordrecht:Foris.

Kotek,Hadas&MichaelYoshitakaErlewine.2018.CovertFocusMovementwithPied-Piping:

EvidencefromTanglewood.LinguisticInquiry49.441-63.

Kratzer,Angelika.1999.Beyond'Ouch'and'Oops'.PaperpresentedattheCornellConferenceon

ContextDependency,CornellUniversity,IthacaNewYork.

—.2004.InterpretingFocus:PresupposedorExpressiveMeanings?TheoreticalLinguistics30.

123-36.

Krifka,Manfred.2004.TheSemanticsofQuestionsandtheFocusationofAnswers.Topicand

Focus:ACross-LinguisticPerspective,ed.byC.Lee,M.Gordon&D.Büring,139-51.

Dordrecht:KluwerAcademicPublishers.

Page 63: deconstructing information structure

63

Kučerová,Ivona.2012.GrammaticalMarkingofGivenness.NaturalLanguageSemantics20.1-30.

Kuroda,Sige-Yuki.2007.OntheSyntaxofOldJapanese.CurrentIssuesintheHistoryand

StructureofJapanese,ed.byB.Frellesvig,M.Shibatani&J.C.Smith,263-317.Tokyo:

KurosioPublishers.

Ladd,RobertD.1980.TheStructureofIntonationalMeaning.EvidencefromEnglishBloomington

&London:IndianaUniversityPress.

—.1996.IntonationalPhonologyCambridge:CambridgeUniversityPress.

—.2008.IntonationalPhonology.SecondEdition.Cambridge:CambridgeUniversityPress.

Lahiri,Utpal.1998.FocusandNegativePolarityinHindi.NaturalLanguageSemantics6.57-125.

Lakoff,George.1971.PresuppositionandRelativeWell-formedness.Semantics.An

InterdisciplinaryReaderinPhilosophy,Linguistics,andPsychology,ed.byD.D.Steinberg&

L.A.Jakobovits,329-40.Cambridge:CambridgeUniversityPress.

Liberman,Mark&JanetPierrehumbert.1984.IntonationalInvarianceunderChangesinPitch

RangeandLength.LanguageSoundStructure,ed.byM.Aronoff&R.Oehrle,157-233.

Cambridge/Mass.:TheMITPress.

Liberman,Mark&AlanPrince.1977.OnStressandLinguisticRhythm.LinguisticInquiry8.249-

336.

McCarthy,John&AlanPrince.1999.FaithfulnessandIdentityinProsodicMorphology.The

ProsodyMorphologyInterface,ed.byR.Kager,H.vanderHulst&W.Zonneveld,218-309.

Cambridge:CambridgeUniversityPress.

Molnár,Valéria.2001.ContrastfromaContrastivePerspective.PaperpresentedtotheESSLLI

2001WorkshoponInformationStructure,DiscourseStructureandDiscourseSemantics,

Helsinki,2001.

Neeleman,Ad&KrisztaSzendröi.2004.SupermanSentences.LinguisticInquiry35.149-59.

Nespor,Marina&IreneVogel.1986.ProsodicPhonologyDordrecht:Foris.

Pierrehumbert,Janet&MaryBeckman.1988.JapaneseToneStructureCambridge/Mass.:TheMIT

Press.

Pierrehumbert,Janet&JuliaHirschberg.1990.TheMeaningofIntonationalContoursinthe

InterpretationofDiscourse.IntentionsinCommunication,ed.byP.Cohen,J.Morgan&M.

Pollack,271-311.Cambridge/Mass.:TheMITPress.

Potts,Christopher.2003.TheLogicofConventionalImplicatures:UCSantaCruz.

Page 64: deconstructing information structure

64

Prince,Alan&PaulSmolensky.1993.OptimalityTheory:ConstraintInteractioninGenerative

Grammar.Unpublishedmanuscript.RutgersUniversity&UniversityofColoradoat

Boulder.

—.2004.OptimalityTheory:ConstraintInteractioninGenerativeGrammar.Oxford:Blackwell

Publishing.

Prince,Ellen.1978.AComparisonofWh-CleftsandIt-CleftsinDiscourse.Language54.883-906.

Reinhart,Tanya.2006.InterfaceStrategies:OptimalandCostlyComputationsCambridge/Mass.:

TheMITPress.

Rialland,Annie&StéphanieRobert.2001.TheIntonationalSystemofWolof.Linguistics39.893-

939.

Rizzi,Luigi.1997.TheFineStructureoftheLeftPeriphery.ElementsofGrammar,ed.byL.

Haegeman,281-337.Dordrecht:Springer.

Roberts,Craige.1996.InformationStructure:TowardsanIntegratedFormalTheoryof

Pragmatics.OSUWPLVolume49:PapersinSemantics,ed.byJ.H.Yoon&A.Kathol,91-136.

—.2012.InformationStructure:TowardsanIntegratedFormalTheoryofPragmatics.Semantics

&Pragmatics5:article6.1-69.

Rochemont,Michael.1986.FocusinGenerativeGrammarAmsterdam:JohnBenjaminsPublishing

Company.

—.2013.DiscourseNew,Focused,andGiven.ApproachestoHungarian.Volume13:Papersfrom

the2011LundConference,ed.byJ.Brandtler,V.Molnár&C.Platzack,199-228.

Amsterdam:JohnBenjaminsPublishingCompany.

—.2013.DiscourseNew,F-Marking,andNormalStress.Lingua136.38-62.

—.2016.Givenness.TheOxfordHandbookofInformationStructure,ed.byC.Féry&S.Ishihara,

41-63.Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress.

Rooth,Mats.1992.ATheoryofFocusInterpretation.NaturalLanguageSemantics1.75-116.

—.1996.OntheInterfacePrinciplesforIntonationalFocus.ProceedingsofSALTVI,ed.byT.

Galloway&J.Spence,202-26.Ithaca,NewYork:CornellUniversity.

—.2015.RepresentingFocusScopingoverNew.NELS45,ed.byT.Bui&D.Özyıldız,1-15.

Amherst,Massachusetts:GLSA.

—.2016.AlternativeSemantics.TheOxfordHandbookofInformationStructure,ed.byC.Féry&S.

Ishihara,19-40.Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress.

Page 65: deconstructing information structure

65

Schwarzschild,Roger.1993.TheContrastivenessofAssociatedFoci.Unpublishedmanuscript.

RutgersUniversity.

—.1999.GIVENness,AvoidFandOtherConstraintsonthePlacementofFocus.NaturalLanguage

Semantics7.141-77.

Selkirk,Elisabeth.1984.PhonologyandSyntax.TheRelationBetweenSoundandStructure

Cambridge/Mass.:TheMITPress.

—.1986.OnDerivedDomainsinSentencePhonology.Phonology3.371-405.

—.1995.SentenceProsody:Intonation,StressandPhrasing.TheHandbookofPhonological

Theory,ed.byJ.A.Goldsmith,550-69.Oxford:Blackwell.

—.2002.ContrastiveFOCUSvs.PresentationalFocus:ProsodicEvidencefromRightNodeRaising

inEnglish.PaperpresentedtoSpeechProsody2002:ProceedingsoftheFirstInternational

ProsodyConference,Aix-en-Provence,2002.

—.2007.ContrastiveFocus,Givenness,andtheUnmarkedStatusofDiscourse-New.

InterdisciplinaryStudiesonInformationStructure,ed.byC.Féry,G.Fanselow&M.Krifka,

125-45.Potsdam:UniversitätsverlagPotsdam.

—.2008.ContrastiveFocus,Givenness,andtheUnmarkedStatusof“Discourse-New”.Acta

LinguisticaHungarica55.1-16.

—.2011.TheSyntax-PhonologyInterface.TheHandbookofPhonologicalTheory.2ndEdition,ed.

byJ.A.Goldsmith,J.Riggle&A.Yu,435-84.Oxford:Wiley.

Selkirk,Elisabeth&SeunghunJ.Lee(eds)2015.ConstituencyinSentencePhonology.Thematic

issueofPhonology32(1).

Shattuck-Hufnagel,Stefanie,MariOstendorf&KennethRoss.1994.StressShiftandEarlyPitch

AccentPlacementinLexicalItemsinAmericanEnglish.JournalofPhonetics22.357-88.

Šimík,Radek&MartaWierzba.2015.TheRoleofGivenness,Presupposition,andProsodyinCzech

WordOrder:AnExperimentalStudy.SemanticsandPragmatics8.1-103.

Slade,Benjamin.2018.HistoryofFocus-ConcordConstructionsandFocus-AssociatedParticlesin

Sinhala,withComparisontoDravidianandJapanese.Glossa3(1):article2.1-28.

Spector,Benjamin.2016.ComparingExhaustivityOperators.SemanticsandPragmatics9.1-33.

Szendröi,Kriszta.2001.FocusandtheSyntax-PhonologyInterface:UniversityCollegeLondonPhD

Dissertation.

Page 66: deconstructing information structure

66

—.2005.FocusMovement(withSpecialReferencetoHungarian).TheBlackwellCompanionto

Syntax,ed.byM.Everaert&H.v.Riemsdijk,270–335.Oxford:Blackwell.

—.2017.TheSyntaxofInformationStructureandthePFInterface.Glossa2(1):article32.1-28.

Torrence,Harold.2013.APromotionAnalysisofWolofClefts.Syntax16.176-215.

Truckenbrodt,Hubert.1995.PhonologicalPhrases-theirRelationtoSyntax,Focus,and

Prominence:MIT.

—.1999.OntheRelationbetweenSyntacticPhrasesandPhonologicalPhrases.LinguisticInquiry

30.219-55.

—.2004.FinalLoweringinNon-FinalPosition.JournalofPhonetics32.313-48.

—.2006.PhrasalStress.EncyclopediaofLanguageandLinguistics.2ndedition,ed.byK.Brown,

572-79.Oxford:Elsevier.

—.2007a.TheSyntax-PhonologyInterface.TheCambridgeHandbookofPhonology,ed.byP.de

Lacy,435-56.Cambridge:CambridgeUniversityPress.

—.2007b.UpstepofEdgeTonesandofNuclearAccents.TonesandTunes.Volume2:

ExperimentalStudiesinWordandSentenceProsody,ed.byC.Gussenhoven&T.Riad,349-

86.Berlin:Mouton.

—.2016.Focus,Intonation,andTonalHeight.TheOxfordHandbookofInformationStructure,ed.

byC.Féry&S.Ishihara,461-82.Oxford:OxfordUniversity Press.Vallduví,Enric.2016.InformationStructure.TheCambridgeHandbookofFormalSemantics,ed.

byM.Aloni&P.Dekker,728-55.Cambridge:CambridgeUniversityPress.

Vallduví,Enric&MariaVilkuna.1998.OnRhemeandKontrast.SyntaxandSemantics29.The

LimitsofSyntax,ed.byP.Culicover&L.McNally,79-108.SanDiego:AcademicPress.

Wagner,Michael.2005.ProsodyandRecursion:MIT.

—.2012.FocusandGivenness:AUnifiedApproach.ContrastsandPositionsinInformation

Structure,ed.byI.Kučerová&A.Neeleman,102-47.Cambridge:CambridgeUniversity

Press.

Whitman,John.1997.KakarimusubifromaComparativePerspective.Japanese/KoreanLinguistics

6,ed.byH.-M.Sohn&J.Haig.Stanford:CenterfortheStudyofLanguageandInformation.

Williams,Edwin.1997.BlockingandAnaphora.LinguisticInquiry28.577-628.

Page 67: deconstructing information structure

67

—.2012.TheLocalityofFocusingandtheCoherenceofAnaphora.ContrastsandPositionsin

InformationStructure,ed.byI.Kučerová&A.Neeleman,148-74.Cambridge:Cambridge

UniversityPress.

Yip,Moira.2002.ToneCambridge:CambridgeUniversityPress.

—.2007.Tone.TheCambridgeHandbookofPhonology,ed.byP.deLacy,229-51.Cambridge:

CambridgeUniversityPress.

Zec,Draga.1999.FootedTonesandTonalFeet:RhythmicConstituencyinaPitchAccent

Language.Phonology16.225-64.

—.2007.TheSyllable.TheCambridgeHandbookofPhonology,ed.byP.deLacy,161-94.

Cambridge:CambridgeUniversityPress.

Zubizarreta,MaríaLuisa.1998.Prosody,Focus,andWordOrderCambridge/Mass.:TheMITPress.

—.2016.NuclearStressandInformationStructure.TheOxfordHandbookofInformation

Structure,ed.byC.Féry&S.Ishihara,163-84.Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress.