context and distance-to-disambiguation effects in ambiguity resolution: evidence from grammaticality...

25
JOURNAL OF MEMORY AND LANGUAGE 26, 714-738 (1987) Context and Distance-to-Disambiguation Effects in Ambiguity Resolution: Evidence from Grammaticality Judgments of Garden Path Sentences JOHNWARNERANDARNOLD L. GLASS Rutgers University This study investigated whether single or multiple structures are constructed at the level of syntactic analysis for ambiguous strings. To this end, three experiments were conducted to determine the effects of various types of snytactic and nonsyntactic information on gram- maticality judgments for garden path sentences. The results of Experiment 1, using a speeded grammaticality judgment task, were that context and length of the ambiguous re- gion influenced the probability of calling a garden path sentence grammatical. In Experi- ment 2, even when given unlimited time to make grammaticality judgments, 40% of all long garden path sentences that required a less preferred analysis were called ungrammatical. Experiment 3 extended the length effects found in Experiments 1 and 2 to some additional types of garden path sentences. The results support a parsing model that is influenced by context and that constructs only a single interpretation of an ambiguous string at a time. 0 1987 Academic Press, Inc When a sentence is comprehended, sev- eral different representations are con- structed, including phonological, syntactic, and semantic representations. Several im- portant questions that have yet to be fully answered concern how these representa- tions are constructed, how each exerts in- fluence on the construction of the others, as well as when these influences become active. A very broad range of models assume that a grammatical structure is first con- structed by the syntactic processor and is This study was originally presented as a Masters thesis by J. Warner, under the direction of A. Glass, whom he thanks along with the other members of his committee-Patricia Gildea and Elliot Noma-for their valuable suggestions, incisive criticism, and en- thusiasm. Both authors additionally express their grat- itude to Pat Carpenter, Scott Robertson, Laura Beck, Dirk Ruiz, Maria Slowiaczeck, and two anonymous reviewers for providing detailed and very helpful com- ments and criticisms of earlier drafts of this manu- script. Correspondence and reprint requests should be addressed to Arnold Glass at the Department of Psy- chology, Busch Campus, Rutgers University, New Brunswick, NJ 08903. then input to the semantic construction process (e.g., Ferreira & Clifton, 1986; Frazier & Fodor, 1978). A good overview of such syntactic processing systems is provided in Winograd (1983) and Harris (1985). This report will refer to the syn- tactic processor as the parser. Parsing and Ambiguity The study reported here will examine sentences in which there are two possible interpretations arising from some structural ambiguity in the sentence, but one and only one interpretation of the ambiguous con- stituent produces a grammatical analysis. When people first encounter such a sen- tence, they may fail to recognize it and call the sentence ungrammatical. If people can spend some time reanalyzing the sentence, especially if additional information is made available, they often will be able to recog- nize the sentence. These sentences are called “garden path sentences.” To be clear, we will use this term to refer to any sentence in which such a potential ambi- guity exists, regardless of whether the am- 714 0749-596X187 $3.00 Copyright 0 1987 by Academic Press, Inc. All rights of reproduction in any form reserved.

Upload: john-warner

Post on 21-Jun-2016

218 views

Category:

Documents


3 download

TRANSCRIPT

JOURNAL OF MEMORY AND LANGUAGE 26, 714-738 (1987)

Context and Distance-to-Disambiguation Effects in Ambiguity Resolution: Evidence from Grammaticality Judgments of

Garden Path Sentences

JOHNWARNERANDARNOLD L. GLASS

Rutgers University

This study investigated whether single or multiple structures are constructed at the level of syntactic analysis for ambiguous strings. To this end, three experiments were conducted to determine the effects of various types of snytactic and nonsyntactic information on gram- maticality judgments for garden path sentences. The results of Experiment 1, using a speeded grammaticality judgment task, were that context and length of the ambiguous re- gion influenced the probability of calling a garden path sentence grammatical. In Experi- ment 2, even when given unlimited time to make grammaticality judgments, 40% of all long garden path sentences that required a less preferred analysis were called ungrammatical. Experiment 3 extended the length effects found in Experiments 1 and 2 to some additional types of garden path sentences. The results support a parsing model that is influenced by context and that constructs only a single interpretation of an ambiguous string at a time. 0 1987 Academic Press, Inc

When a sentence is comprehended, sev- eral different representations are con- structed, including phonological, syntactic, and semantic representations. Several im- portant questions that have yet to be fully answered concern how these representa- tions are constructed, how each exerts in- fluence on the construction of the others, as well as when these influences become active.

A very broad range of models assume that a grammatical structure is first con- structed by the syntactic processor and is

This study was originally presented as a Masters thesis by J. Warner, under the direction of A. Glass, whom he thanks along with the other members of his committee-Patricia Gildea and Elliot Noma-for their valuable suggestions, incisive criticism, and en- thusiasm. Both authors additionally express their grat- itude to Pat Carpenter, Scott Robertson, Laura Beck, Dirk Ruiz, Maria Slowiaczeck, and two anonymous reviewers for providing detailed and very helpful com- ments and criticisms of earlier drafts of this manu- script. Correspondence and reprint requests should be addressed to Arnold Glass at the Department of Psy- chology, Busch Campus, Rutgers University, New Brunswick, NJ 08903.

then input to the semantic construction process (e.g., Ferreira & Clifton, 1986; Frazier & Fodor, 1978). A good overview of such syntactic processing systems is provided in Winograd (1983) and Harris (1985). This report will refer to the syn- tactic processor as the parser.

Parsing and Ambiguity

The study reported here will examine sentences in which there are two possible interpretations arising from some structural ambiguity in the sentence, but one and only one interpretation of the ambiguous con- stituent produces a grammatical analysis. When people first encounter such a sen- tence, they may fail to recognize it and call the sentence ungrammatical. If people can spend some time reanalyzing the sentence, especially if additional information is made available, they often will be able to recog- nize the sentence. These sentences are called “garden path sentences.” To be clear, we will use this term to refer to any sentence in which such a potential ambi- guity exists, regardless of whether the am-

714 0749-596X187 $3.00 Copyright 0 1987 by Academic Press, Inc. All rights of reproduction in any form reserved.

CONTEXT AND GRAMMATICALITY JUDGMENTS 715

biguity is “noticed” by the parser or whether the occurrence of the ambiguity leads to a misanalysis (cf Frazier & Rayner, 1982). Determining how the misanalysis occurs (and, as importantly, why it doesn’t always occur) should provide important clues to the operation of the parser.

Consider for a moment whether strings (a) through (d), below, are sentences:

(a) When the boys [strike] the dog kills.

(b) When the boys [strike] the dog <the horse kicks> the cat.

(c) When the boys [strike] the dog <the horse kicks> kills.

(d) When the boys [strike] the dog <the horse kicks> the cat kiffs.

Each of these strings contains at least one ambiguous constituent whose interpre- tation determines the grammaticality of the entire string. The constituent in square brackets is the first ambiguous constituent, the words contained in angle brackets are the second ambiguous constituent, and the italicized constituent is the one which re- solves the ambiguity. In all cases, the ambi- guity arises out of the question of how to close the preposed temporal clause (these types of sentence structures have been termed “late closure ambiguities” by Fra- zier and Rayner (1982) and others who have studied them).

In string (a), the ambiguous constituent is “strike.” If “strike” is encoded as in- transitive, then “the dog” becomes the subject of the main clause and string (a) is grammatical. However, if “strike” is en- coded as transitive, then “the dog” be- comes its object and string (a) is ungram- matical.

The word “strike” is also ambiguous in strings (b)-(d). However, encoding “strike” as intransitive in strings (b) and (d) leads to an ungrammatical string and encoding it as transitive in both strings makes a grammatical interpretation pos- sible. In string (c), as in string (a), “strike” must be encoded as intransitive.

In addition, each of the strings (b)-(d) has a second ambiguous constituent. In string (b), if “the horse kicks” is encoded as a relative clause modifying “the dog,” then this string will lack a main clause and be ungrammatical. But if “the horse kicks” is encoded as the main clause, then the string will be grammatical. In contrast, in strings (c) and (d), encoding “the horse kicks” as a relative clause leads to a gram- matical interpretation, while interpreting it as the main clause makes the string un- grammatical.

Models of Parsing for Ambiguous input

We place the different possible models for ambiguity handling in the parser along a continuum whose end points are defined by a Parallel Multiple Path parser and a Single Path parser. Briefly, a Parallel Mul- tiple Path parser makes use of all possible interpretations of an ambiguous constituent to construct multiple interpretations of the sentence in parallel (Kurtzman, 1985). A Single Path parser, on the other hand, orders the interpretations of the ambiguous constituent on the basis of syntactic and nonsyntactic information, but, in contrast to a Multiple Path parser, can only select one most highly valued interpretation to construct the remaining syntactic structure of the sentence.

Neither of these extremes provides a sat- isfactory explanation of the abundant evi- dence of garden pathing and parsing prefer- ence principles in human performance. The former is too powerful to account for the difficulty observed with garden path sen- tences, while the latter is too weak to ac- count for the degree to which people seem to be able to recover from such errors.

Between the end points defined by the Parallel Multiple Path and Single Path models lies a range of models that are formed by either attenuating the assump- tions of the former or augmenting the as- sumptions of the latter. We will propose here a model in which a Single Path parser is enhanced by assuming that, if the first

716 WARNER AND GLASS

interpretation of a constituent fails to pro- duce a grammatical structure, then there is some probability that the output of the parser will be checked and a second inter- pretation of the ambiguous constituent will be tried (Frazier & Rayner, 1982). We will refer to this model as an Augmented Single Path parser.

Figure 1 presents a flow-chart of the Augmented Single Path parser and the checking mechanism, beginning with the box labeled “access word.” Notice that the model delineates three critical steps in the processing of a sentence. First (Figure la), the syntactic representation of the word is retrieved from the lexicon. Second (Figure lb), an attempt is made to combine the constituent with the syntactic structure of the preceding portion of the sentence. If the constituent is combined with the syn- tactic structure of the rest of the sentence,

then the next word is accessed. Third, if at the end of the sentence all constituents have been incorporated successfully into the sentence structure and there are no more words, then the sentence is perceived as grammatical. However, if a constituent can not be combined with the rest of the sentence structure, then the sentence is perceived as ungrammatical. In this case, as suggested by Milne (1982) and Rayner, Carlson, and Frazier, (1983), the subject may check the input and attempt to recom- pute the syntactic structure of the sen- tence. This stage is indicated by the dotted box and line (Figure lc). Such a recompu- tation may lead to a sentence structure and to a “grammatical” decision.

Additional motivation for the checking mechanism comes from the study by Milne (1982). Sometimes, the ambiguity of the ambiguous constituent is not detected at all

no more words sentence structure complete +

Retrieve syntactic represen- tation of word

-___I all attempted structures

(B) ii sentence i structure IC, I

rpz = = = -“r, I II Attempt to II + - - -I II recompute II

I succeeds II sentence II - - - - - structure II

FIG. I. Schematic flowchart of the Augmented SingIe Path parsing model, which contains three main processing steps: (a) the syntactic representations of words are retrieved from the lexicon: (b) an attempt is made to combine the representation of the word with the sentence structure; (c) there is a failure at (b); the resulting sentence structure may be checked.

LX-G _--- _ + "UNGRAMMATICAL"

# of combinations >1

b-1

CONTEXT AND GRAMMATICALITY JUDGMENTS 717

and its dominant interpretation is inconsis- tent with the syntactic structure of the sen- tence. For example, Milne found that sub- jects had trouble with sentences such as The sentry stands are green, even though the disambiguating constituent “are” is ad- jacent to the ambiguity. Apparently the preferred interpretations of the ambiguous words (in this case, noun and verb rather than adjective and noun) were often so dominant that they were not perceived as ambiguous and the syntactic disambigua- tion process was aborted. The existence of such a checking mechanism might explain why people sometimes notice a garden path or ambiguous construction and sometimes do not. It depends on whether the parser’s initial output is recomputed and whether that recomputation produces a different re- sult.

Since the Augmented Single Path parser described above is one of a number of Par- allel and Single Path models whose predic- tions closely mimic each other, the fol- lowing approach to presenting the logic, re- sults, and conclusions of this study will be taken. Initially, predictions for the experi- ments will be derived only from the model described above. Then, after the results of each experiment are presented, it will be considered to what extent other augmenta- tions or attenuations might also account for our results. After setting out these alter- ations, a judgment will be made about which of the revised models is more plau- sible for explaining the data presented here.

Selection in the Augmented Single Path Model

How might a Single Path parser select an interpretation of an ambiguous constituent? There are several kinds of nonsyntactic in- formation that might influence the selec- tion.

First, there might be strong preferences built into the system. These preferences might be captured in the weighting of the rules or even in the lexical properties of the

input, or both (this is similar to some of the proposals of Ford, Bresnan, & Kaplan (1982)). So, for instance, the parser might have its rules ordered in a hierarchy or weighted to make a transitive analysis of verbs when the input was ambiguous, or it could be that, when the constituent is am- biguous and immediately local information fails to resolve it, preferences are dictated by features assigned to the lexical item it- self. Another possibility is that these pref- erences are expressed as strategies the parser itself uses to deal with ambiguities. For example, Frazier and Rayner (1982) have suggested two such strategies, Min- imal Attachment and Late Closure, both founded upon the assumption that the parser structures input as soon as it is re- ceived.

Second, there is the most recent inter- pretation of a similar nonambiguous con- stituent. For example, suppose string (a) (from (a) through (d), above) were pre- ceded by string (e) as shown below:

(e) When the girl sleeps the cat eats. (a) When the boys strike the dog kills.

The nonambiguous sentence (e) might in- fluence a similar parsing for string (a). Some evidence for this possibility is pro- vided by an earlier study (Frazier, Taft, Roeper, Clifton, & Ehrlich, 1984) in which it was found that, for conjoined conjunction sentences (e.g., “Joshua hit the girl with a book and the boy with a bat”), subjects had less difficulty (in terms of reading time) when the second conjoined clause had the same structure as the first clause. We will refer to such influences as “syntactic con- text.”

Third, there is the role of semantic plau- sibility. Semantic plausibility could influ- ence the syntactic selection in two ways. There is the context independent plausi- bility of the sentence itself, that is, the plausibility of boys striking dogs. The other factor is the plausibility of the sentence within the context that it appears in. For instance, strings (a) through (d) might ap-

718 WARNER AND GLASS

pear in a paragraph about newsboys going on strike, or in a paragraph about boys hit- ting dogs. An example may again make this clearer. Consider what might happen if a person encountered string (f) just prior to encountering string (a) as shown below:

(f) The dog becomes dangerous whenever boys attack.

(a) When the boys strike the dog kills.

As in the case of (a) and (e) before, where a recent nonambiguous syntactic analysis influenced the selection of an in- terpretation of the ambiguous constituent in (a), here the vaguer paraphrase may serve to prime an intransitive analysis for the ambiguous string which succeeds it. We will refer to this influence as “semantic context.” You will notice that the semantic context string (f) utilizes the same nouns as (a) with vaguer, more abstract verbs (e.g., instead of directly being described as killing, the dog is only said to be dan- gerous). Additionally, the clauses are re- versed so that meaning remains constant while, in fact, the overall syntactic struc- ture is altered.

It should be pointed out that one would expect these effects to work in both direc- tions, i.e., that any or all of these sources of information could be manipulated or ex- ploited to increase the likelihood of an in- correct analysis of (a). For instance, imagine if (g), below, were presented just before (a) in place of(e):

(g) If the girls pets the cat she sings. (a) When the boys strike the dog kills.

Where (e) unambiguously “models” the grammatical interpretation of (a), (g) sets up an expectation for a transitive analysis which, if applied to (a), might result in an ungrammatical interpretation.

Also consider if (h), below, were pre- sented before (a) in place of(f):

(h) Violence occurs because the boys attack the dog.

(a) When the boys strike the dog kills.

Like (f), (h) utilizes the same nouns as (a) with less concrete verbs. However, sen- tence (h) is altered so that there is an addi- tional NP (i.e., Violence) and the two nouns from (a) are set incorrectly in an actor-patient relation. Thus, both the syntax and the meaning of the target string (a) have been distorted in (h).

There are two other very obvious sources of information for resolving ambi- guities which we will not address here in great detail because they are so obvious and because they do little to distinguish be- tween possible parsing models as we have outlined them here.

The most obvious is the possible effect of surface punctuation, in the form of marks in text and intonation (changes in vocal stress or pauses) in speech. Hence, a comma in string (a) between “strike” and “dog” makes “strike” intransitive and string (a) grammatical.

Also, there is the frequency with which the different interpretations of the ambig- uous constituent appear in nonambiguous contexts. For example, if “strike” were used as a transitive verb 75% of the time in nonambiguous contexts, the parser might select it that often in ambiguous contexts (or it might select that interpretation 100% of the time if the parser maximized rather than matched the more likely probability). This would lead to errors, but lacking better information, such a scheme would select the correct structure most of the time for structures that are not too com- plex.

The purpose of this study was to ex- amine the effect of syntactic and semantic context on grammaticality judgments for garden path sentences similar to strings (a)-(d). Subjects were presented with lists of strings, both grammatical and ungram- matical. In each list were embedded garden path sentences preceded by context strings that provided information that could be used for resolving the ambiguity in the garden path strings. Some conditions pro- vided information which, if utilized, should

CONTEXT AND GRAMMATICALITY JUDGMENTS 719

result in a grammatical analysis while other conditions provided context which would make an ungrammatical analysis more likely.

EXPERIMENT 1

In this first experiment, subjects were tested under conditions that limited the availability of the input and placed the sub- jects under pressure to respond quickly. This was done to try to get at very early, on-line stages of the parsing process. We wanted to observe the effects of context in- dependent of later pragmatic or conceptual processes, and to establish whether such information were even available to the parser at such an early stage.

For a Single Path model, even aug- mented as we have proposed, such context information should bias subjects so that the proportion of garden path sentences called grammatical would change significantly in the predicted direction. That is, for positive context, more garden path sentences should be called grammatical and, since fewer outputs would need to be checked, reaction time (RT) may be decreased. The opposite effects would be expected for neg- ative bias.

Additionally, we decided to manipulate the length of the ambiguous region in order to gain more insight into possible attenua- tions or augmentations that might be at work and to more clearly distinguish be- tween possible Single Path and Multiple Path models. That is, if the parser has only limited flexibility in handling ambiguous input, it should further tax the system to increase the distance between the ambig- uous and the disambiguating constituents. A similar manipulation was attempted by Rayner, Carlson, and Frazier (1983, Exper- iment 2) with mean reading time per char- acter and mean eye-fixation duration be- fore and after the ambiguous region as the measures. In both cases, they failed to find any effects. However, it did not seem im- possible that length might affect the pro- portion of garden path sentences judged

grammatical without affecting either of their measures. If subjects found fewer long garden path sentences grammatical compared to short garden path sentences, it would indicate limits on how much infor- mation the Attenuated Parallel model can maintain in parallel, or how far back our Augmented model can look to resolve the ambiguity. Such information could be useful in comparing the models’ relative merits.

Method

Stimuli. Three types of sentence/strings were used in this experiment, as shown in Table 1. In the following description, “garden path sentences” are the critical items of interest for our predictions; “con- text string” refers to the unambiguous sen- tence that immediately preceded each garden path sentence and provided infor- mation that could be used in interpreting the garden path sentences; “filler strings” refers to the remaining unambiguous strings that did not provide information that might be used in interpreting the garden path sentences.

As shown in Table 1, two types of garden path sentences were used, those whose am- biguity was resolved by a transitive con- struction and those resolved by an intransi- tive construction. As also shown in Table 1, each type of garden path sentence was paired with five types of context. These context types were positive syntactic, in which the syntactic structure of the context string was unambiguously identical to the correct interpretation of the garden path sentence; negative syntactic, where the syntactic structure unambiguously mod- eled the ungrammatical interpretation; pos- itive semantic, wherein the sentence gives a paraphrase of the meaning of the gram- matical interpretation of the garden path sentence; negative semantic, where the paraphrase is designed to set up an expec- tation resulting in an ungrammatical anal- ysis of the garden path sentence; and, fi- nally, neutral context, which were simply

720 WARNER AND GLASS

TABLE I EXAMPLES OF STRING TYPES USED IN EXPERIMENTS 1 AND 2

Garden path sentences Intransitive

Short WHEN THE BOYS STRIKE THE DOG KILLS

Long BEFORE THE BOY KILLS THE MAN THE DOG BITES STRIKES

Transitive Short

AFTER THE DOG BITES THE MAN THE CAT KILLS Long

WHEN THE HORSE KICKS THE BOY THE DOG BITES THE MAN Context strings (for short intransitive garden path sentence)

Syntactic Positive

BEFORE THE MAN SLEEPS THE CAT EATS Negative

IF THE GIRLS PET THE CAT THEY SING Semantic

Positive THE DOG BECOMES DANGEROUS WHILE THE BOYS ATTACK

Negative VIOLENCE OCCURS BECAUSE THE BOYS ATTACK THE DOG

Control Neutral context

MEN HAVE TO BE PUT OUT Filler strings

Grammatical THE MAN IS BELIEVED TO HAVE HAD THE DOG THE CAT JUMPS ACROSS THE FENCE WHEN STARTLED

Ungrammatical RED IS TO BE UGLY TO RAPIDLY DOGS WHO IS STRONG KILLED THAT STRIKE MEN

additional filler strings. An example of each of the five types of context strings is given in Table 1. All context strings were con- structed to be as unambiguously grammat- ical as possible.

The two kinds of garden path sentences and the five kinds of context sentences were combined to form 10 basic subtypes of test list, each with a different garden path sentence-context string pairing. For each subtype, three different lists were constructed that were identical in design, but each of which contained completely different garden path sentences, context, and filler items from the other two. Thus, there were 30 test lists in all.

Each test list contained 18 items: 4 garden path sentences, 4 ambiguously

grammatical context strings, 1 unambigu- ously grammatical filler string, and 9 unam- biguously ungrammatical filler strings. Therefore, half the strings in each list were grammatical. Two of the garden path sen- tences in each list were short and 2 were long. In other words, as can be seen in Table 1, the number of intervening constit- uents in the ambiguous region between the ambiguous verb and the disambiguating constituent was varied. In the short garden path sentences, the ambiguous region con- tained two to four words; in the long garden path sentences, the ambiguous re- gion contained five to six words. As also shown in Table 1, the intransitive short garden path sentences had only one level of ambiguity; it only had to be determined

CONTEXT AND GRAMMATICALITY JUDGMENTS 721

whether the preposed temporal clause ter- minated in a transitive or intransitive con- struction. The short transitive and the longer garden path sentences had a second level of ambiguity; in order to resolve the transitive/intransitive ambiguity it had to be determined whether two adjacent nouns belonged together (wherein the second noun heads a relative clause modifying the first). The garden path sentences occurred at the 4th, 8th, 12th, and 16th list positions. Two of the lists of each subtype placed the garden path sentences in a short-long- short-long sequence while the third used a long-short-long-short sequence. The Ap- pendix provides a complete list of all garden path sentences and context sen- tences used in this experiment.

Finally, in addition to the experimental lists, a practice list of 40 strings was cre- ated. These were simple filler strings of which half were unambiguously grammat- ical and half were unambiguously ungram- matical.

Design. There were five experimental factors in this experiment. Two of the factors were within-subjects. Each subject was tested on three lists of 18 strings each. All three lists contained the same kind of garden path sentences. On one list (called the “precritical” list), all of the context sentences preceding the garden path sen- tences were neutral, but on the other two lists (called the “critical” lists) the context sentences introduced some level of bias (the same level for both of these lists). Thus list type is one within-subjects factor. In addition, each fist contained garden path sentences with both short and long ambig- uous regions. Thus length is also a within- subjects factor. The remaining three factors are between-subjects factors. They include sentence structure (intransitive vs transi- tive), context (syntactic vs semantic), and bias (positive vs negative). Hence, each subject was exposed to only one level of each of these three factors. For example, a subject in the “intransitive positive syn- tactic context group” viewed three lists

which contained both short and long garden path sentences that required an in- transitive analysis and, in the last two lists, context strings that modeled unambigu- ously only the grammatical interpretation of each ambiguous garden path sentence.

Finally, there were two additional groups that are not included under the above de- sign that served as control conditions. These are the intransitive and transitive neutral context groups. All the context strings in these groups were unambigu- ously grammatical sentences that were unrelated to the succeeding garden path sentences so that there was no level of ei- ther “context” or “bias” in these condi- tions. These two groups provided, for both the intransitive and transitive garden path sentences, a baseline measure of grammati- cality judgments in the absence of context.

To summarize, the experimental design included both a within-subjects (list type) and a between-subjects (context) measure of the effect of context on grammaticality judgments for garden path sentences.

Apparatus. For all subjects and groups, strings were presented on a 22.5cm diag- onal video monitor that was controlled by an Apple II+ computer. Strings were pre- sented one word at a time in uppercase and without punctuation in the center of the screen using the rapid serial visual presen- tation (RSVP) method. An asterisk pattern presented in the center of the screen was used both to mask the last word after presentation and to signal the subject to re- spond. The rate of presentation was ap- proximately 120 words per minute. Sub- jects indicated whether a string was gram- matical or ungrammatical by pressing one of two microswitches which were labeled “G” for grammatical and “U” for ungram- matical. “G” was always the right-hand microswitch and “U” was always the left- hand microswitch. The subject’s response was recorded by the control program as was the response latency, in milliseconds, from the onset of the asterisk pattern.

Procedure. A total of 90 Rutgers Univer-

722 WARNER AND GLASS

sity undergraduates participated in this ex- periment as part of an introductory course requirement or for extra credit. All subjects were native speakers of English, meaning that English was the first language they learned.

There were 10 groups of nine subjects in all. Five groups were presented with in- transitive garden path sentences and 5 groups were given transitive garden path sentences. Each of the 5 groups in both the transitive and intransitive conditions was given a different type of context string (as indicated under Stimuli, above). The fifth group in both the intransitive and the tran- sitive conditions was a control group in which all three trial lists contained filler strings in the list positions preceding the garden path sentences. These groups con- trolled for simple practice effects.

All subjects in all conditions received 20 practice strings. On these practice trials the subject was provided with feedback on the screen about the accuracy of their judg- ments. The purpose of the practice trials was to allow the subject to get used to the task of making grammaticality judgments as well as to let the subject learn well which hand controlled the “G” microswitch and which hand controlled the “U” micro- switch without having to look at the labels. No data was collected from the practice trials; however, if the subject made five or more errors and at least one error was made during the last 10 trials, the subject received a second block of 20 different practice trials with feedback. Out of 90 subjects, only 7 required the second block of practice trials.

For each subject, after the practice trials, each of the three lists of 18 strings was pre- sented for a total of 54 strings judged per subject. For all subjects, the first list was the “precritical” list containing only neu- tral context strings. For the eight experi- mental groups, the remaining two lists con- tained the context strings appropriate for that condition (the “critical lists”). In the two control conditions, all three lists con-

tained neutral context strings. Between lists were rest periods, which were termi- nated by the subject. There were no prac- tice trials between lists and there was no feedback to the subject about their accu- racy. Subjects were instructed to respond as quickly as possible and encouraged to base their response on their initial intuition or gut reaction rather than spending time thinking further about it. This was done to attempt to tap as early a stage of processing as possible and to discourage possible re- hearsal. Despite the accuracy feedback in the practice trials, the subjects were in- structed to “respond as quickly as pos- sible” once the asterisk pattern cue ap- peared.

Data analysis. The data analyzed were the percentages of garden path sentences judged grammatical (response data) and the RT for garden path sentences judged gram- matical for each subject.

The response data were analyzed using a four-way mixed-design analysis of variance that did not include the neutral context control groups but included length (short/ long ambiguous region) as a within-subjects factor. For this analysis, the two critical lists were pooled together. The three be- tween-subject factors, as indicated above, were garden path sentence structure (in- transitive/transitive), context (syntactic/se- mantic), and bias (positive/negative).

An additional four-way mixed Anova was calculated with list type (precriticah critical) as the within-subjects factor. The between-subjects factors were the same ones used above. The two critical lists were pooled together and compared to the pre- critical list and both levels of length were also pooled.

The RT data were analyzed using a three-way analysis of variance with struc- ture, context, and bias as between-subject factors (precritical RTs were not analyzed and the RTs were pooled across length for all subjects). The reaction times were summed across “grammatical” responses only.

CONTEXT AND GRAMMATICALITY JUDGMENTS 723

Results The mean percentage agreement (i.e.,

percentage of strings subjects called gram- matical when grammatical and ungrammat- ical when ungrammatical) when averaged across all subjects in all conditions was 93% for the context strings and 85% for the tiller strings. Table 2 lists, for each group, the mean percentage of garden path sen- tences judged grammatical across both crit- ical lists, as well as the standard error.

First, in the initial four-way Anova, there was clear evidence that a transitive anal- ysis was the preferred interpretation for the verbs used in this experiment. This was shown by the significant main effect of structure, indicating that overall perfor- mance was higher (more garden path sen- tences were called grammatical) when a transitive construction resolved the ambi- guity than when an intransitive structure was required (85% vs 66%; F(1,64) = 24.7, p < .OOl). There was a significant main ef- fect of bias, indicating that subjects were more likely to judge a string grammatical in a positive context than a negative context (87% vs 65%; F(1,64) = 32.3, p < .OOl). The main effect of context was not signifi- cant (73% vs 79%), suggesting that the overall likelihood of a grammatical re- sponse was the same for both syntactic and semantic contexts. However, it may be that

the present analysis lacks sufficient power to detect small effects and that even small differences are important. Significant inter- action effects showed that, in the intransi- tive conditions, garden path sentences with short ambiguous regions were judged gram- matical much more often (92%) than garden path sentences with long ambiguous re- gions (40%), but in the transitive conditions this difference disappeared (86% vs 85%; F(1,64) = 58.5, p < .OOl). This result is confirmed by a Newman-Keuls’ multiple range test that shows this was true for all four intransitive context groups (p < .Ol) but not for any of the transitive conditions.

The purpose of the second four-way analysis (with list type as a factor) was to serve as a within-subjects control to con- firm that context indeed changed perfor- mance and that bias determined the direc- tion of that change. This was confirmed by the interaction effect showing that positive context increased (73% vs 87%) and nega- tive context decreased (71% vs 65%) the number of garden path sentences called “grammatical” (F(1,64) = 30.0, p < .OOl). All between-subject effects exactly repli- cated the results of the previous analysis. The mean percentage of change (including the direction) for each mean from the cor- responding precritical mean is also shown in Table 2.

TABLE 2 MEAN~ERCENTAGEOF GARDEN PATHSENTENCESJUDGEDGRAMMATICAL(+STANDARDERROROFTHE

MEAN) FOR THE CRITICAL TRIAL LISTS (COMBINED) IN EXPERIMENT 1

Syntactic Semantic Control,

Bias: Positive Negative Positive Negative Neutral

Length: S L S L s L s L s L

Intransitive Mean SE % Change from precritical

Transitive Mean SE % Change from precritical

94 47 94 28 97 61 83 22 100 25 4 5 4 11 3 10 7 12 0 I1

i-33 +41 -6 0 +8 +28 0 -6 0 +3

100 100 56 61 97 97 89 83 89 92 0 0 9 11 3 3 6 9 8 8

-6 0 -22 -17 -3 +8 0 0 -11 -2

724 WARNER AND GLASS

The analysis of the reaction time data revealed no significant main effects or in- teractions. The means are presented in Table 3.

tive and intransitive interpretations of all ambiguous sentences and hence predicts no preference for either interpretation.

Discussion

The results of this experiment clearly support the Augmented Single Path parsing model with the checking mechanism that we have proposed here. First, context was shown to significantly affect the propor- tions of garden path sentences called gram- matical. Additionally, these shifts in pro- portion were in the direction predicted by the bias. Thus, presenting context that pro- vided information about the grammatical interpretations of the garden path sen- tences increased the likelihood that sub- jects would call them grammatical, while presenting context that provided informa- tion about the ungrammatical interpreta- tions of the garden path sentences de- creased the likelihood of their being called grammatical. These differences were re- flected both in changes of level of perfor- mance across lists from precritical to crit- ical and, overall, in comparisons between performance in the critical lists of the posi- tive context conditions and corresponding performance in the negative conditions.

The Attenuated Parallel Multiple Path model. Let us consider a moment what at- tenuations would be necessary for a Par- allel Multiple Path model to explain our re- sults. For example, if it is assumed that all possible interpretations are not always car- ried to completion by the Parallel Multiple Path model but rather that some lesser valued paths are terminated after some number of constituents beyond the ambig- uous one are processed, then the model no longer predicts that a grammatical interpre- tation will be found for every word string for which one is possible. A model atten- uated in this way will be called an Atten- uated Parallel Multiple Path model.

If, for the verbs used in this experiment, the transitive interpretation is more highly valued than the intransitive interpretation, and hence more likely to be carried to com- pletion, then this would explain the advan- tage for the transitive interpretation. Fur- thermore, if all structures are begun but not updated indefinitely, then it explains why the difference in grammatical judgments for transitive and intransitive structures was greater for long than for short constituents.

There was also a very powerful prefer- However, in order to fit the quantitative ence for a transitive construction. In four results, a Parallel Multiple Path model must out of five conditions, intransitive sen- be so severely attenuated that it remains tences were more likely to be misinter- only nominally parallel in its underlying as- preted as transitive than the reverse. This sumptions; in fact, it is functionally a bias is inconsistent with the Multiple Path Single Path model beyond about three con- model, which would construct both transi- stituents since after this point only a single

TABLE 3 MEAN REACTION TIME (ms) FOR MAKING A CORRECT JUDGMENT OF “GRAMMATICAL” FOR THE GARDEN

PATH SENTENCES IN THE CRITICAL LISTS (COMBINED) FOR EXPERIMENT 1

Bias:

Syntactic Semantic Control.

Positive Negative Positive Negative Neutral

Intransitive Mean SE

Transitive Mean SE

600 439 483 548 463 101 68 76 Ill 127

344 511 352 516 415 94 107 52 IO5 93

CONTEXT AND GRAMMATICALITY JUDGMENTS 725

interpretation of the sentence is available. Also, there were significant differences (to be specified below) among the RT distribu- tions that are not explained by an Atten- uated Parallel Multiple Path model. As will be seen below, the tails of the RT distribu- tions for those strings that elicited high per- centages of ungrammatical responses were consistently longer than for RT distribu- tions that did not elicit high percentages of ungrammatical responses. This model does not predict such a finding.

The checking mechanism. Our results are most consistent with the Augmented Single Path parser with a checking mecha- nism that acts on the output of the parser to select an alternative interpretation of the ambiguous constituent. An important prop- erty of this checking mechanism is sug- gested in our results. So long as the disam- biguating constituent occurs within three constituents after the ambiguity, it seems relatively easy for the checking mechanism to find the alternate structure. If more than three constituents have intervened, it be- comes more difficult to tear down the erro- neous structure and resegment the input. In fact, such an attempt may not succeed.

Let us first consider how these predic- tions emerge from the model we have pro- posed (above, and in Figure I), and then we will show how each prediction is con- firmed in the data.

First, notice that, as shown in Figure lb, when an ambiguous word that has more than one possible way of being combined into the sentence structure (for example, the verb in the preposed clause in our garden path sentences) is accessed, an ini- tial resolution is selected on the basis of whatever preferences are used by the parser (in this case, a transitive analysis is selected). If, as we have suggested, it is also the case that within three constituents, recomputing an alternative structure re- mains relatively easy, then we would ex- pect both the short intransitive and the short transitive garden path sentences in this study to be judged grammatical equally

often, as often as unambiguous grammat- ical sentences. In fact, this was the result obtained on the precritical lists for all sub- jects in the experiment. For the short strings, the proportion of “grammatical” responses was nearly the same for both in- transitive and transitive garden path sen- tences, 87 and 92%, respectively. Also, the proportions of the unambiguous grammat- ical sentences included in the intransitive and transitive conditions that were called grammatical were 92 and 94%, respec- tively. Additional evidence comes from the two critical lists in the neutral conditions. This time, the proportions of “grammat- ical” responses for short intransitive and transitive garden path sentences were 100 and 89%, respectively. The corresponding proportions of “grammatical” responses to the unambiguous grammatical sentences used in these conditions were 93 and 90%, respectively.

What about the situation where the dis- tance between the ambiguity and the dis- ambiguating constituent is greater than three? We have suggested that, in the ab- sence of sufficient additional information, when a misanalysis of the ambiguity oc- curs, it may be difficult to recompute an al- ternate structure before a judgment is made. This would result in most of the long intransitive garden path sentences being judged “ungrammatical” while most of the long transitive garden path sentences would be judged “grammatical.” The re- sults of the precritical list were that long in- transitive garden path sentences were called grammatical only slightly more often than unambiguous ungrammatical strings (23% vs 16%) and long transitive garden path sentences were called “grammatical” as often as unambiguous grammatical sen- tences (89% vs 93%). Once again, this evi- dence is confirmed by looking at the crit- ical lists of the neutral conditions. This time, the proportions of grammatical re- sponses to the long intransitive and transi- tive garden path sentences were 25 and 92%, respectively. The proportion of

726 WARNER AND GLASS

“grammatical” responses to the unambig- uous ungrammatical strings in the intransi- tive neutral condition was 25% and the pro- portion of “grammatical” responses to un- ambiguous grammatical sentences in the transitive neutral condition was 90%.

Although the RT analysis revealed no significant effects, there are a number of potential problems with the analysis, given the relatively small number of observations per subject, that require caution in inter- preting these results. First, there were far fewer “grammatical” responses in the in- transitive conditions than the transitive conditions, making it likely the intransitive means are less stable. Second, because so few intransitive long garden path sentences were judged grammatical, length had to be pooled for each group of subjects. Thus, this Anova is likely to be quite insensitive. Nonetheless, we may be able to obtain some valuable information about the model from the distributions of RT.

Figures 2 and 3 show the RT distribu- tions for all unambiguous grammatical sen- tences and all unambiguous ungrammatical strings for the critical lists in all 10 condi- tions, thus providing a large number of ob- servations on which to base conclusions.

Recall that, as shown in Figure lc, if a grammatical structure is not found for an input string, then there is some probability that the structure will be checked before a response is made. The assumption of a pos- sible checking process predicts a longer tail for the RT distributions for ungrammatical strings than for grammatical sentences be- cause the latter are usually not checked. In fact, this is confirmed by Figures 2 and 3.

The tail of the RT distribution for re- sponses to ungrammatical strings (Figure 3) is much thicker. For Figure 2 (pooling all responses), only 1% of the distribution lay beyond 2000 ms, whereas, for Figure 3,6% of the distribution (all responses pooled) was located beyond 2000 ms. This differ- ence in proportions (Bruning & Kintz, 1977) was significant (z = -5.90, p < .OOl). Also important is the relationship of the correct to error RTs shown in the figures. For the grammatical sentences in Figure 2, for responses greater than 1000 ms, an error was virtually never made. In contrast, for ungrammatical strings, as shown in Figure 3, the frequency of an in- correct “grammatical” response remained nearly constant throughout the distribu- tion. This pattern can be explained by as-

400

RT hterval UMisecds x 11100)

FIG. 2. RT distribution of responses to the unambiguous grammatical sentences for all conditions combined. 0, “Grammatical” response + “ungrammatical” response.

CONTEXT AND GRAMMATICALITY JUDGMENTS 727

RT Interval (Milliseconds x I/ 100)

FIG. 3. RT distribution of responses to the unambiguous ungrammatical strings for all conditions combined. 0, “Grammatical” response vs “ungrammatical” response.

suming that there is some probability of checking an “ungrammatical” decision and of changing the response so that the tails of the RT distributions for responses to un- grammatical strings will consist of those decisions that have been checked. Thus the tails of the distributions of “grammatical” and “ungrammatical” responses to un- grammatical strings will be equally long, as shown in Figure 3.

This general prediction is also supported in the patterns observed for the intransitive and transitive neutral conditions. Although the number of observations here are much fewer, rendering the RT distributions quite noisy and thus requiring caution in inter- pretation, the prediction we have made above would suggest that, for the long in- transitive garden path sentences, there should be a longer tail since there will be more “ungrammatical” responses that have some probability of being checked and possibly changed. Such a tail would be evidenced by a further positive skewing of the distribution, resulting in an increase in both the mean and the distance between the mean and the median of the distribu- tion. However, for both types of short garden path sentences (intransitive and

transitive) as well as for the long transitive garden path sentences, we would expect the distance of the mean from the median to be much smaller.

In fact, these are the patterns observed in the data. For the short intransitive, short transitive, and long transitive garden path sentences in the neutral conditions (all re- sponses pooled), the distances between the mean and median were 85, 160, and 127 ms, respectively. The distance between the mean and the median in the RT distribution for the long intransitive garden path sen- tences in the neutral condition (all re- sponses pooled) was 326 ms. Thus, in this respect, the RT distributions for the short intransitive, short transitive, and long tran- sitive garden path sentences all resemble the distribution of RT (all responses pooled) for the unambiguously grammatical strings in the neutral condition (distance between mean and median = 119 ms) and the distribution for the long intransitive garden path sentences resembles the RT distribution (all responses pooled) for the unambiguously ungrammatical strings in the neutral conditions (distance between the mean and the median = 182 ms; the differences for the unambiguous strings

728 WARNER AND GLASS

seem less dramatic because the greater number of observations stabilize the means somewhat).

The important point to be made here is that the results observed here (particularly in Figures 2 and 3), predicted by the Aug- mented Single Path model with a checking mechanism, would not be predicted by an Attenuated Parallel Multiple Path model. This model would predict that, while a less valued interpretation of an ambiguous con- stituent might take longer to process, once the parser has moved some number of con- stituents beyond the ambiguity and those less valued paths are terminated, there would be no changing of the output before making a decision. Thus, for the unambigu- ously ungrammatical strings as well as the long intransitive garden path sentences, the RT distribution would move to the right, increasing the mean, but the degree of skew would remain similar to the RT distri- bution for the unambiguously grammatical strings.

The model of the checking mechanism that is shown in Figure 1 is a probabilistic model; depending on various factors (e.g., the relative strength of an alternative or the length of an ambiguous region), it may or may not compute an alternative structure for a string judged ungrammatical. Hence, the complete model of explaining decisions about garden path sentences is a hybrid containing both Single Path and Multiple Path components. However, the conceptu- alization of these components is quite dif- ferent. The Single Path component models the activity of the parser itself, i.e., the process by which constituents are con- catenated and the syntactic structure is built. The Multiple Path component models the activity of a process that checks the output of the parser and which may influ- ence the processing of the parser by af- fecting its input, but it is not the parser it- self (cf Rayner, Carlson, and Frazier’s (1983) “Thematic processor”).

We assume that the check and recompu- tation process that we have inferred from

the long tails of the RT distributions is a conscious process that is an expression of the subject’s general problem solving ability. The results in this study can be ex- plained by assuming that what a subject does in the recomputation of a sentence is simply to impose a segmentation pattern on the input string different than was implied by the preferred interpretations of the lex- ical items.

Finally, we are left with the question of how context exerted its influence on sen- tence processing. There are two possibili- ties within the framework of the Aug- mented Single Path model. Either context could influence the initial selection of a verb’s interpretation or it could influence the probability that the resulting sentence structure would be checked and recom- puted. These alternatives predict different patterns in the RT data. Unfortunately, due in part to the low power of the between- subjects design, the differences for the crit- ical comparisons were not significant. Thus, further data collection will be re- quired to establish the loci of context ef- fects.

This will be an important issue to ad- dress, particularly in resolving the differ- ences between the Augmented Single Path model and the Attenuated Parallel Multiple Path model. If context influences the initial selection, context could in effect cause the Multiple Path model to terminate all but the primed interpretation, resulting in a Single Path model but with more complexity without more explanatory power. One of the assumptions that seems to motivate many parallel models is that context does not have an influence of initial selection, that all interpretations of an ambiguous word are activated initially even if the dura- tion of these multiple activations are short, and context then affects which interpreta- tion(s) are maintained. More recently, even this assumption has been called into ques- tion, at least for ambiguous words in naming and lexical decision tasks (Kiger & Glass, 1983; Van Petten & Kutas, 1987).

CONTEXT AND GRAMMATICALITY JUDGMENTS 729

In summary, the Augmented Single Path model with a checking mechanism is.sup- ported by four main findings in this experi- ment: (1) Garden path sentences in which the disambiguating constituent followed within three constituents of the ambiguous verb were perceived as grammatical as often as unambiguous grammatical sen- tences. (2) In contrast, for these garden path sentences, when the disambiguating constituent followed the ambiguous verb by more than three constituents, the verb was always interpreted as transitive, so that long garden path sentences requiring a transitive interpretation were called “gram- matical” as often as unambiguous sen- tences but long garden path sentences re- quiring an intransitive interpretation were called “ungrammatical” as often as un- grammatical strings. (3) The probability of a response to a garden path sentence was influenced by both its syntactic and se- mantic context. (4) The tails of the RT dis- tributions for those strings that elicited high percentages of ungrammatical responses were consistently longer than for RT distri- butions that did not elicit high percentages of ungrammatical responses. An Atten- uated Parallel Multiple Path model may be able to account for the first three findings, but it can not account for the fourth.

EXPERIMENT 2

The purpose of using a rapid, on-line form of presentation in Experiment 1 was to make the syntactic judgments as free as possible of the more time-and-resource- consuming top-down conceptual processes which are brought into play in normal reading and language comprehension. It has been said that the results obtained here lend support to an Augmented Single Path parsing mechanism. However, it might be suggested that the real effect of using a rapid, on-line task wherein subjects were encouraged to respond quickly was to arti- ficially terminate syntactic processing. Thus, while the human parsing mechanism might well be a Multiple Path model, the

task constraints turned it into an Single Path parser by pressing for a response be- fore processing was completed. Even if the appropriate model is the Attenuated Par- allel Multiple Path model, the degree of at- tenuation might be far less severe than re- flected in the previous experiment.

To examine this issue, a second experi- ment presented the lists used in Experi- ment 1 in a paper-and-pencil subject-paced task in which time constraints were elimi- nated. If the subjects now called all the garden path sentences grammatical, the Multiple Path parsing model would be sup- ported and doubt would be cast on the re- sults of Experiment 1. If, however, the re- sults followed the same general pattern as for the speeded task, it would suggest grammaticality judgment was measured in the first experiment.

Method

Stimuli, design, and apparatus. Ten lists of 54 strings were generated, one for each of the intransitive and transitive context conditions, and printed on paper. To the far right of each string on the list were printed the symbols “G” (for grammatical), “7” (for uncertain), and “U” (for ungrammat- ical). These printed lists were identical to the material presented to subjects over the course of three trial lists in Experiment 1 except that there was no “precritical” list. The strings were printed in all uppercase letters, as they had been when presented on the video monitor in Experiment 1. No punctuation was indicated. The design was identical to Experiment 1.

Procedure. The subjects were 100 Rutgers University undergraduates who participated in the experiment to fulfill a re- quirement for Introductory Psychology or for extra credit. Additionally, some sub- jects had previously participated in Experi- ment 1 or a similar task. Some (25) were actually subjects in Experiment 1 who were randomly selected to carry out the addi- tional task immediately after completing the RSVP on-line grammaticality judgment

730 WARNER AND GLASS

task. Some other subjects (25) had pre- viously participated in a pilot experiment very similar to Experiment 1, approxi- mately 1 month before. All subjects were randomly assigned to conditions. No at- tempt was made to assign the subjects who had already participated in Experiment 1 to the same condition they were in previously.

Subjects were asked to look over each string and to circle “G” if they were cer- tain it was a grammatical sentence, “?” if they were not sure, and “U” if they were certain it was an ungrammatical string. Ad- ditionally, if subjects circled “?” or “II,” they were requested to make some simple indication of what might make the string grammatical. All subjects were encouraged to take as much time as they needed.

Results and Discussion

Table 4 shows the mean percentages of grammaticality judgments for all groups. Across the whole experiment, the propor- tion of agreement (strings judged grammat- ical when grammatical and ungrammatical when ungrammatical) was 95% for the con- text strings and 93% for the tiller strings.

A four-way mixed Anova was performed on the data. As in Experiment 1, length (short/long) was a within-subjects factor and the three between-subjects factors were structure (intransitive/transitive), context (syntactic/semantic), and bias (pos- itive/negative).

First, the differences in level of perfor-

mance on the garden path sentences be- tween the intransitive and transitive lists did not diminish (70% vs 96%), as indicated by a strong main effect of structure (F( 1,74) = 43.7, p < .OOl). Second, there was a sig- nificant four-way within-subjects interac- tion that indicated, for long intransitive garden path sentences with syntactic con- text, that bias had a significant effect (58% vs 18%, p < .Ol, Newman-Keuls’ test) whereas for long intransitive sentences with semantic context and all transitive path sentences there were no significant ef- fects (F(1,74) = 110.3, p < .OOl). Finally, other within-subjects interaction effects replicated the finding from Experiment 1 that for the four intransitive context condi- tions, more short garden path sentences were judged grammatical than long garden path sentences (99% vs 42%, p < .Ol, Newman-Keuls’ test), while in the transi- tive conditions there was no effect of length (96% vs 97%).

Clearly, the structure effect remained quite robust, demonstrating that there is a marked preference for a transitive analysis even when there is no time constraint. This result provides strong support for a Single Path parsing model over a Multiple Path model. In spite of reflection, including re- flection in which considering alternate structures was encouraged (i.e., when asked to consider how to make the string grammatical), without context the gram- matical interpretation in the intransitive

TABLE 4 MEAN PERCENTAGE OF GARDEN PATH SENTENCES JUDGED GRAMMATICAL FOR EXPERIMENT 2

Syntactic Semantic Control,

Bias: Positive Negative Positive Negative Neutral

Length: S L S L S L S L S L

Intransitive Mean 100 58 100 18 98 48 98 43 95 33 SE 0 10 0 10 2 11 2 14 3 9

Transitive Mean 97 93 96 96 100 100 92 97 98 90 SE 3 5 4 3 0 0 6 2 2 4

CONTEXTANDGRAMMATICALITYJUDGMENTS 731

condition was available much less often than for the transitive garden path sen- tences. In a pattern similar to that found for Experiment 1, in the neutral conditions we find that for the short garden path sen- tences, both intransitive and transitive, and for the transitive long garden path sen- tences, the proportions of “grammatical” responses were 95, 98, and 90%, respec- tively. For the long intransitive garden path sentences, however, the proportion of “grammatical” responses was only 33%. This prompted a closer look at the raw data. When the actual forms were reexam- ined to see what corrections the subjects had made, of the 40 subjects in the intransi- tive conditions who called two or more of the garden path sentences ungrammatical, 37 made corrections that converted the structure to a transitive one. One subject made corrections to the long intransitive garden path sentences by deleting the sub- ordinate NP, but maintaining an intransitive interpretation of the verb. Two subjects failed to clearly indicate their changes.

What seems to be operating here is that, despite the time allowed to bring in prag- matic information and other processes, there is such a strong preference for a pure transitive construction when presented with direct action verbs that the preferred analysis takes over. This supports the Aug- mented Single Path parsing model and also suggests that, even when the stimulus is available for reparsing, the decision to do so may be highly influenced by the degree of preference or some other measure of confidence attached to that structural as- signment that resulted in an ungrammatical analysis.

Bias (with the exception of syntactic context on intransitives) did not have an ef- fect in this experiment. This may be be- cause the unlimited reaction time allowed was sufficient to reduce or eliminate any initial context-induced bias. It might also be that the semantic effects were less stable than syntactic effects because the subject perceives the task as a syntactic task-that

is, the subject was given no reason to be- lieve that the meaning of any two pairs of strings might be connected, or that one string might imply another.

EXPERIMENT 3

We considered it extremely significant that subjects failed to find the grammatical interpretation of a garden path sentence even when they were given unlimited time to ponder its structure. This result suggests that the parser does not have the capability to exhaustively construct all possible struc- tures for an ambiguous input. The purpose of Experiment 3 was to generalize this re- sult to other types of garden path sen- tences, not used in Experiments 1 and 2.

Three types of garden path sentences were tested, as shown in Table 5. For each type, both a long and a short version were generated for both of two possible resolu- tions of the ambiguity. Thus, for each sen- tence set, versions (a) and (c) are resolved by the same analysis of an ambiguous con- stituent while (b) and (d) versions are re- solved by the alternate resolution of the ambiguous constituent. For sentence set (1) in Figure 5, the ambiguity is simply the tense assignment for put our, which can only be resolved by checking for agreement with the main verb of the second clause (strikes in (la) and (lc) or struck in (lb) and (Id). Sentence set (2) presents a reduced relative ambiguity, similar to the minimal/ nonminimal attachment ambiguities studied by Rayner, Carlson, and Frazier (1983) and Ferreira and Clifton (1986), in which the men believed to strike . . . can either be in- terpreted as a main verb followed by a phrase describing what the men believed or, alternately, it may be analyzed as a re- duced relative phrase describing what was believed about the men. This ambiguity is resolved by determining agreement be- tween the men and the final verb (is in (2a) and (2~) and are in (2b) and (2d)). Finally, in sentence set (3), it must be determined whether the man who . . . begins a im- bedded relative clause (as in (3a) and (3~))

732 WARNER AND GLASS

TABLE 5 THEGARDENPATHSENTENCESUSEDINEXPERIMENT~

Long (1) a. THE BOYS PUT OUT THE DOGS THAT ARE STRONG WHEN THE MAN WHO IS VERY

UGLY STRIKES THE CLOCK b. THE BOYS PUT OUT THE DOGS THAT ARE STRONG WHEN THE MAN WHO IS VERY

UGLY STRUCK THE CLOCK (2) a. THE MEN BELIEVED TO STRIKE THE VERY RED DOG THAT KILLED THE CAT IS UGLY

b. THE MEN BELIEVED TO STRIKE THE VERY RED DOG THAT KILLED THE CAT ARE UGLY (3) a. THE GIRLS BELIEVE THE MAN WHO BELIEVES THE VERY STRONG UGLY BOYS

STRUCK THE DOGS KILLED THE CATS b. THE GIRLS BELIEVE THE MAN WHO BELIEVES THE VERY STRONG UGLY BOYS WHO

STRUCK THE DOGS WHO KILLED THE CATS Short

(1) c. THE BOYS PUT OUT THE DOGS WHEN THE MAN STRIKES THE CLOCK d. THE BOYS PUT OUT THE DOGS WHEN THE MAN STRUCK THE CLOCK

(2) c. THE MEN BELIEVED TO STRIKE THE DOG IS UGLY d. THE MEN BELIEVED TO STRIKE THE DOG ARE UGLY

(3) c. THE GIRLS BELIEVE THE MAN WHO STRUCK THE DOGS KILLED THE CATS d. THE GIRLS BELIEVE THE MAN WHO STRUCK THE DOGS WHO KILLED THE CATS

or whether it is the beginning of a recursive right-branching structure (as in (3~) and W)).

Method

Four lists of 24 strings were generated. Each list was identical except that each had a different version of the three types of garden path sentences shown in Table 5. One list had the three (a) sentences, an- other the (b) sentences, the third the (c) sentences, and, finally, the fourth list had the three (d) sentences. Each list also had three strings which were identical to the three garden path sentences on that list ex- cept that the ambiguous constituent was replaced with a constituent that made them unambiguous. For garden path sentences (la-Id) in Table 5, this meant substituting kill (in la) and (1~)) and killed (in (1 b) and (Id) for put out (present tense) and put out (past tense). For sentences (2a)-(2d), be- lieved to strike in (2a) and (2~) was changed to believed that to strike, and the men be- lieved in (2b) and (2d) was changed to the men who are believed. Finally, for garden path sentences (3a)-(3d), believe in (3a) and (3~) was changed to believe that, and believe in (3b) and (3d) was changed to struck. Because of the results of the pre-

vious two experiments showing context ef- fects, all unambiguous versions of the garden path sentences were placed at the very end of the list, after the ambiguous strings.

The filler strings, which were the same in all four lists, were strings generated to be unambiguously either grammatical or un- grammatical. These lists were of the same form as the printed lists used in Experiment 2. To the far right of each string on the list were printed the symbols “G” (for gram- matical) , “?” (for uncertain), and “U” (for ungrammatical). These strings were printed in all uppercase letters and no punctuation was indicated.

Each list was completed by a different group of 14 Rutgers University undergrad- uates who were native speakers of English, for a total of 56 subjects. Each subject re- ceived extra credit toward their grade and none were told the purpose of the ratings beyond the fact that we were interested in looking at people’s “grammatical intu- itions.” They were asked to look over each string and to circle “G” if they were cer- tain it was a grammatical sentence, “?” if they were not sure, and “U” if they were certain it was an ungrammatical string. Ad- ditionally, if they circled “?” or “U,” they

CONTEXTANDGRAMMATICALITYJUDGMENTS 733

were requested to make some simple indi- cation of what might make the string gram- matical. They were encouraged to take as much time as they needed.

Results and Discussion

The ratings for the strings on each list were tabulated and the ratings for each am- biguous garden path sentence and its unam- biguous version were collected. The per- centages of subjects calling each garden path sentence and its unambiguous version grammatical were compared by obtaining a z score for the difference between propor- tions and determining whether the differ- ence was significant (Bruning & Kintz, 1977). Table 6 lists the percentage of sub- jects calling each garden path sentence and its unambiguous equivalent version gram- matical.

The predictions of the model were again supported, although the results for sen- tence set (2) were somewhat unexpected. We will first discuss sentence sets (1) and (3). For both sets, the percentages of sub- jects calling short garden path sentences (the (c) and (d) sentences in Table 5) gram- matical did not differ significantly between the sets or with their unambiguous ver- sions. However, in both cases, the long garden path sentences were judged gram- matical significantly less often than the short garden path sentences (p < .02 for set (1); p < .OOl for set (3)) or their unambig- uous versions (JJ < .02 for set (1); p < .002 for set (3)). Also, as in Experiments 1 and

TABLE6 PERCENTAGE OF SUBJECTS CALLING EACH OF THE THREE GARDEN PATH SENTENCES FROM TABLE 5 AND ITS UNAMBIGUOUS VERSION GRAMMATICAL

Garden path Unambiguous

Long Short Long Short ___ ____

a b c d a b c d

1. 64 100 100 100 100 100 100 100 2. 43 93 36 100 100 100 100 100 3. 43 71 loo loo 93 93 loo loo

2, there seemed to be a strong preference for one resolution of the ambiguity over an- other as reflected by a greater percentage of grammatical judgments for the (b) long garden path sentences compared to the (a) versions, although this only emerges clearly in sets (1) and (2) (the difference in set (3) is nonsignificant).

Sentence set (2) presents unexpected re- sults, although they are not a problem for the model we have discussed. There seems to be a powerful preference on the part of subjects to make a reduced relative anal- ysis, even with short garden path sen- tences, despite the expectation from pre- vious studies (e.g., Ferreira & Clifton, 1986) that a simple main verb analysis is preferable. A close examination of sub- jects’ corrections confirmed this. In most cases, subjects replaced is with are (they had not seen the other version). However, we would hesitate to suggest that this item presents counter-evidence to the minimal attachment principle since this was not the intent of the experiment. Further, on re- flection, it seems quite possible that an event (i.e., striking a dog) may not be a pragmatically acceptable NP to be de- scribed as “ugly,” in which case the sub- jects were constrained to favor the non- minimal attachment structure.

GENERALDISCUSSION

All three experiments showed that there is a low frequency of detecting the gram- matical interpretation of long garden path sentences when it requires the less pre- ferred interpretation of an ambiguous con- stituent. These results demonstrate that only a single interpretation of the sentence is available beyond about three constit- uents. The long tails of the RT distributions indicate that a checking mechanism is at work when the structure produced is un- grammatical. Together, these results pro- vide evidence that an Augmented Single Path parser with a checking mechanism is the most plausible model of the parsing process beyond about three constituents.

734 WARNER AND GLASS

This leaves open the question of what occurs from when the ambiguous constit- uent is first encountered to the point at which the parser must restrict its pro- cessing capacity to a single interpretation. We now turn to this issue.

Augmented Single Path Models

There are at least three variations on the Single Path model that differ in what is as- sumed to occur at the onset of an ambig- uous constituent, the crucial difference among them being the degree of augmenta- tion (and, thus, the level of complexity) re- quired to predict the same results.

The simplest version is the Single Path model with no augmentation other than the checking mechanism. According to this model, the sooner the misinterpretation of an ambiguous constituent is detected, the more likely that the sentence structure will be recomputed. Hence, a grammatical in- terpretation is more likely to be made for a short garden path sentence than for a long one. If the misinterpretation is detected within three constituents, the correct inter- pretation is nearly always found.

One alternative is the Buffer model, a Single Path parser with a three constituent buffer. When an ambiguous constituent occurs, it and the succeeding constituents are placed in a buffer until either the buffer is filled or a disambiguating constituent is encountered. In the former case, the path is selected by the listener’s preference as biased by the context. In the latter case the path is selected by the disambiguating con- stituent. This model is similar to the deter- ministic parser, PARSIFAL, of Marcus (1980) that utilizes a three constituent buffer. Although this model can account for our data, since the previous model requires no buffers it seems simpler and is, thus, more immediately compelling. On the other hand, a buffer model would require less structure rebuilding since it searches for- ward for the disambiguating constituent be- fore committing itself to an interpretation of the ambiguous constituent.

Another alternative is to simply combine the previously considered Attenuated Par- allel Multiple Path model with the checking mechanism that we have proposed. Be- cause of the severity of attenuation needed to account for our length effects, this is really a hybrid Parallel Multiple Path1 Single Path parser in that it very quickly terminates all but one, the most highly valued or activated path. Thus, such a model may be equally well considered an Attenuated Parallel Multiple Path model or an Augmented Single Path model. In this model, whenever an ambiguous constituent is encountered, multiple structures may be begun in parallel for more than one possible interpretation. These are all continued until either the limit of the system to maintain parallel structures is reached or the disam- biguating constituent is encountered. In the former case, which appears to be about three constituents, the path is selected by the listener’s preference as biased by con- text. This is then some probability that the output of the parser will be checked before an ungrammatical decision is made. This model is close to a proposal made by Kurtzman (1985).

The hybrid model is both more complex and requires more computation than either of the other two models to perform the same function. The additional processing required by the model appears even less plausible when it is considered how rarely syntactic ambiguities occur that are not re- solvable by intonation and/or semantic context. If persisting ambiguous syntactic structures are rare, then it becomes less plausible that a powerful ability to compute multiple syntactic structures or to store constituents in buffers has evolved just for the rare occasion when an ambiguity is cre- ated in the input.

Constituent Size and Hierarchical Processing

For the model proposed here, it was sug- gested that the more syntactic constituents between the point of ambiguity and the de-

CONTEXT AND GRAMMATICALITY JUDGMENTS 735

tection of the syntactic mismatch, the less the likelihood that a new syntactic struc- ture would be computed. This raises the question of what counts as a constituent. If a constituent is defined as a word, then the Single Path model predicts that the phrase The very red . . . will exhaust the parser’s scope. However, if a constituent is defined as a noun phrase or verb, then the single long noun phrase Twelve very important looking tuxedoed and top-hatted gentlemen . . * will not exceed that scope. Neither of these alternatives seem intuitively plau- sible, as has been noted elsewhere (e.g., Frazier (1985), footnote 14).

However, these problems may be sur- mountable. Glass and Warner (1987) have proposed a hierarchical parser in which syntactic representations of contiguous words that form phrasal constituents are reduced to those phrasal constituents be- fore the phrasal constituents are concate- nated. Hence, for the word string The very red . . . , “very red” would form a single constituent and the phrase would not ex- haust the scope of the parser’s structure building. On the other hand, the word string Twelve very important looking tuxe- doed and top-hatted gentlemen . . . would form at least four constituents--“twelve,” “very important looking,” “tuxedoed,” “and”--0 it would exceed the parser’s scope. This may in fact explain why the ef- fects of the length manipulation were sig- nificant in all three experiments when a previous study, mentioned above, at- tempting the same manipulation, failed to find any effects (Rayner, Carlson, & Fra- zier, 1983). An examination of the materials utilized in the Rayner et. al. study reveals that the ambiguous regions of their sen- tences were extended primarily with simple noun modifiers which would be easily col- lapsed into a single constituent like “the very red . . .” above by a hierarchical pro- cessing model. Thus, the length manipula- tion of the Rayner et. al. study may have been too small to show an effect.

In summary, a hierarchical processing

model produces plausible constituents that may vary from individual words to whole phrases. Together, the Augmented Single Path and hierarchical processing models provide a persuastive description of human parsing.

APPENDIX

Garden Path Sentences Used for Experiments I and 2, with Their Matched

Context Strings

Short and long versions are alternated in the same pattern as the subject would en- counter them and are designated by ‘s’ or ‘1’ after the number. Context strings are designated as follows: a = positive syn- tactic; b = negative syntactic; c = positive semantic; d = negative semantic; e = neu- tral context.

Intransitive Garden Path Sentences Is.

21.

3s

BEFORE THE MEN KILL THE BOY STRIKES

la. WHEN THE GIRL SLEEPS THE CAT EATS

Ib. WHILE THE WOMAN PETS THE CAT SHE SINGS

lc. MEN BECOME DANGEROUS BE- CAUSE THE BOY ATTACKS

Id. VIOLENCE OCCURS BECAUSE THE MEN ATTACK THE BOYS

le. IS THE DOG BELIEVED TO BE UGLY

IF THE HORSE KICKS THE BOY THE DOG BITES KILLS

2a.

2b.

2c.

2d.

AFTER THE MAN GOES THE DOG THE NEIGHBOR OWNS BARKS AFTER THE MAN FEEDS THE COW THE GIRL SIGHS LOUDLY THE HORSE REACTS BEFORE THE BOY THAT THE DOG HURT ATTACKS THE HORSE HURTS THE BOY BE- FORE THE DOG ATTACKS

2e. THE GIRL HAS TO BE OUT OF THE HOUSE BEFORE THE CAT

WHEN THE BOYS STRIKE THE DOG KILLS 3a. BEFORE THE MAN SLEEPS THE CAT

EATS 3b. IF THE GIRLS PET THE CAT THEY

SING 3c. THE DOG BECOMES DANGEROUS

WHILE THE BOYS ATTACK 3d. VIOLENCE OCCURS BECAUSE THE

BOYS ATTACK THE DOG 3e. MEN HAVE TO BE OUT

736 WARNER AND GLASS

41. AFTER THE MEN KILL THE BOY THE COW KICKS STRIKES 4a.

4b.

4c.

4d.

4e.

WHILE THE GIRL GOES THE DOG THE NEIGHBOR OWNS BARKS WHEN THE GIRL FEEDS THE HORSE THE DOG BARKS LOUDLY MEN ARE VIOLENT BEFORE THE BOY THAT THE COW HURT ATTACKS THE MEN ATTACK THE BOY BEFORE THE COW IS VIOLENT THE DOG THAT CHASES CATS IS FED BY THE WOMAN

8d. VIOLENCE OCCURS BECAUSE THE HORSE ATTACKS THE BOY

8e. THE GIRL PUT THE DOG OUT

9s. WHILE THE COW KICKS THE MAN KILLS 9a. WHEN THE DOG SLEEPS THE BOY

PLAYS 9b. IF THE BOY PETS THE CAT HE SINGS 9c. THE MAN ATTACKS BECAUSE THE

COW IS VIOLENT 9d. VIOLENCE OCCURS BECAUSE THE

COW ATTACKS THE MAN 9e. TWELVE OUT OF TWELVE MEN ARE

51. WHILE THE BOYS STRIKE THE DOG THE UGLY

HORSE KICKS KILLS 101. WHEN THE DOG BITES THE MAN THE CAT 5a.

Sb.

SC.

Sd.

5e.

BEFORE THE MAN GOES THE DOG THE NEIGHBOR OWNS BARKS BEFORE THE MAN FEEDS THE CAT THE GIRL SIGHS LOUDLY THE BOYS ARE VIOLENT WHEN THE DOG THAT THE HORSE HURTS AT- TACKS BOYS ATTACK THE DOG WHENEVER HORSES ARE VIOLENT THE CLOCK VERY AWKWARDLY STRUCK TWELVE

SCRATCHES KILLS 10a. BEFORE THE WOMAN GOES THE

DOG THE NEIGHBOR OWNS BARKS lob. AFTER THE BOY FEEDS THE CAT THE

GIRL SIGHS LOUDLY 10~. THE DOG IS VIOLENT WHILE THE

MAN THAT THE CAT HURT ATTACKS 10d. THE DOG HURTS THE MAN WHILE

THE CAT ATTACKS 10e. THE WOMAN IN THE RED CAR

DRIVES RAPIDLY

6s. WHEN THE DOG BITES THE MAN KILLS 11s. IF THE BOY KILLS THE MAN STRIKES

6a. AFTER THE BOY SLEEPS THE CAT lla. WHILE THE CAT SLEEPS THE GIRL

EATS PLAYS

6b. BEFORE THE BOY PETS THE CAT HE 11 b. WHILE THE GIRL PETS THE CAT SHE

SINGS SINGS

6c. THE MAN ATTACKS BECAUSE THE llc. THE MAN ATTACKS WHEN THE BOY

DOG IS VIOLENT IS VIOLENT

6d. VIOLENCE OCCURS BECAUSE THE lid. VIOLENCE OCCURS WHEN THE BOY

DOG ATTACKS THE MAN ATTACKS THE MAN

6e. THE GIRL HAS BOYS HAVE CATS 1 le. THAT VERY GIRL OWNS THE HORSE

121. BEFORE THE BOY STRIKES THE MAN THE 71. BEFORE THE BOY KILLS THE MAN THE HORSE KICKS KILLS

DOG BITES STRIKES 12a. 7a.

7b.

7c.

7d.

7e.

WHEN THE GIRL GOES THE DOG THE NEIGHBOR OWNS BARKS IF THE GIRL FEEDS THE CAT THE WOMAN SIGHS LOUDLY THE BOY IS VIOLENT AFTER THE MAN THAT THE DOG HURTS AT- TACKS THE BOY ATTACKS THE MAN AFTER THE DOG IS VIOLENT TO BE BELIEVED THE WOMAN MUST FIND THE LETTER

12b.

12c.

12d.

12e.

IF THE GIRL GOES THE DOG THE NEIGHBOR OWNS BARKS WHEN THE WOMAN FEEDS THE CAT THE MAN SIGHS LOUDLY THE BOY IS VIOLENT WHEN THE MAN THAT THE HORSE HURTS AT- TACKS THE BOY ATTACKS THE MAN BE- CAUSE THE HORSE IS VIOLENT THAT CAT IS THE CAT THE GIRL WAS TO PUT OUT

8s. AFTER THE HORSE KICKS THE BOY Transitive Garden Path Sentences

STRIKES 1s. AFTER THE DOG BITES THE MAN THE 8a. IF THE GIRL SLEEPS THE CAT EATS CAT KILLS 8b. WHEN THE GIRL PETS THE CAT SHE la. IF THE STUDENT COMPLETES HER

SINGS WORK THE CLOCK CHIMES 8c. THE HORSE IS VIOLENT BEFORE lb. IF THE BOY SWIMS THE CAT THAT

THE BOY ATTACKS THE MAN OWNS PLAYS

CONTEXT AND GRAMMATICALITY JUDGMENTS 737

IC.

Id.

le.

THE CAT IS VIOLENT BECAUSE THE DOG ATTACKS THE MAN THE DOG IS VIOLENT BEFORE THE MAN IS ATTACKED BY THE CAT IS THE DOG BELIEVED TO BE UGLY

21. WHILE THE COW KICKS THE MAN THE BOY STRIKES THE GIRL 2a. AFTER THE WOMAN CONTACTS THE

POLICE THE COP ARRESTS THE SUS- PECT

2b. BEFORE THE GIRL SLEEPS THE CAT THAT THE MAN BROUGHT CRIES

2c. THE BOY ATTACKS THE GIRL WHEN THE COW HURTS THE MAN

2d. THE GIRL ACTS BECAUSE THE COW HARMS THE MAN THAT THE BOY AT- TACKS

2e. THE GIRL HAS TO BE OUT OF THE HOUSE BEFORE THE CAT

3s. IF THE BOYS STRIKE THE DOG THE HORSE KICKS

3a.

3b.

3c.

3d.

3e.

WHEN THE MEN COMPLETE THEIR WORK THE CLOCK CHIMES WHEN THE MEN SWIM THE DOGS THAT THE GIRLS OWN PLAY THE HORSE IS VIOLENT WHEN THE BOYS ATTACK THE DOG BOYS ARE VIOLENT WHEN THE DOG IS ATTACKED BY THE HORSE MEN HAVE TO BE OUT

41. AFTER THE BOY KILLS THE MAN THE CAT STRIKES THE DOG

4a. IF THE GIRL CONTACTS THE POLICE THE COP ARRESTS THE SUSPECT

4b. IF THE MAN SLEEPS THE DOG THAT THE BOY BROUGHT CRIES

4c. THE CAT ATTACKS THE DOG BE- CAUSE THE BOY HARMS THE MAN

4d. THE DOG ACTS WHEN THE BOY HARMS THE MAN THAT THE CAT AT- TACKS

4e. THE DOG THAT CHASES CATS IS FED BY THE WOMAN

51. WHILE THE MEN KILL THE BOY THE COW KICKS THE DOG

5a. BEFORE THE WOMAN CONTACTS THE POLICE THE COP ARRESTS THE SUSPECT

5b. IF THE GIRL SLEEPS THE CAT THE MAN BROUGHT CRIES

SC. THE COW IS PANICKED BY THE DOG WHEN THE MEN ATTACK THE BOY

Sd. THE DOG ACTS WHEN THE MEN AT- TACK THE BOY THAT THE COW HARMS

5e. THE CLOCK VERY AWKWARDLY

6s. WHEN THE GIRLS STRIKE THE CAT THE HORSE KICKS

6a.

6b.

6c.

6d.

6e.

AFTER THE WOMEN COMPLETE THEIR WORK THE CLOCK CHIMES BEFORE THE MAN SWIMS THE DOG THAT THE BOY OWNS BARKS THE HORSE LASHES OUT BECAUSE THE GIRLS ATTACK THE CAT THE GIRLS ARE VIOLENT WHEN THE CAT IS HURT BY THE HORSE THE GIRL HAS BOYS HAVE CATS

71. BEFORE THE BOYS STRIKE THE DOG THE HORSE KICKS THE CAT

7a. AFTER THE MAN CONTACTS THE PO- LICE THE COP ARRESTS THE SUS- PECT

7b. WHILE THE MAN SLEEPS THE CAT

7c.

7d.

7e.

THAT THE GIRL BROUGHT CRIES THE HORSE ATTACKS THE CAT WHILE THE BOYS PLAN TO HIT THE DOG THE CAT ACTS AFTER THE BOYS AT- TACK THE DOG THAT THE HORSE HURTS TO BE BELIEVED THE WOMAN MUST FIND THE LETTER

8s. AFTER THE HORSE KICKS THE BOY THE DOG BITES

8a. WHILE THE MAN COMPLETES HIS WORK THE CLOCK CHIMES

8b. WHEN THE WOMAN SWIMS THE CAT THAT THE MAN OWNS PLAYS

8c. THE DOG IS VIOLENT BECAUSE THE HORSE ATTACKS THE BOY

8d. THE HORSE IS VIOLENT BEFORE THE BOY IS ATTACKED BY THE DOG

8e. THE GIRL PUT THE DOG OUT

9s. AFTER THE COW KICKS THE GIRL THE HORSE BITES

9a. WHILE THE BOY COMPLETES HIS WORK THE CLOCK CHIMES

9b. WHILE THE BOY SWIMS THE DOG THAT THE MAN OWNS PLAYS

9c. THE HORSE IS VIOLENT BECAUSE THE COW HARMS THE GIRL

9d. THE COW IS VIOLENT BEFORE THE GIRL IS ATTACKED BY THE HORSE

9e. TWELVE OUT OF TWELVE MEN ARE UGLY

101. IF THE DOG BITES THE MAN THE BOY KILLS THE HORSE 1Oa. WHEN THE BOY CONTACTS THE PO-

LICE THE COP ARRESTS THE SUS- PECT

lob. WHEN THE BOY SLEEPS THE CAT STRUCK TWELVE THAT THE MAN BROUGHT CRIES

738 WARNER AND GLASS

10~. THE BOY ATTACKS THE HORSE WHEN THE DOG HURTS THE MAN

1Od. THE HORSE ACTS BECAUSE THE DOG HARMS THE MAN THAT THE BOY AT- TACKS

10e. THE WOMAN IN THE RED CAR DRIVES RAPIDLY

11s. WHILE THE BOY KILLS THE MAN THE CAT STRIKES lla. BEFORE THE GIRL COMPLETES HER

WORK THE CLOCK CHIMES llb. BEFORE THE GIRL SWIMS THE

HORSE THAT THE BOY OWNS TROTS Ilc. THE CAT ATTACKS BECAUSE THE

BOY HARMS THE MAN lld. THE BOY ATTACKS WHEN THE MAN

IS HURT BY THE CAT 1 le. THAT VERY GIRL OWNS THE HORSE

121. WHEN THE HORSE KICKS THE BOY THE DOG BITES THE MAN 12a.

12b.

12c.

12d.

12e.

WHILE THE WOMAN CONTACTS THE POLICE THE COP ARRESTS THE SUS- PECT WHILE THE WOMAN SLEEPS THE CAT THAT THE GIRL OWNS CRIES THE DOG ATTACKS THE MAN BE- CAUSE THE HORSE INJURES THE BOY THE MAN ACTS WHEN THE HORSE HURTS THE BOY THAT THE DOG AT- TACKS THAT CAT IS THE CAT THE GIRL WAS TO PUT OUT

REFERENCES

BRUNING, J. L., & KINTZ, B. L. (1977). Computa- tional handbook of statistics. Glenview, IL: Scott, Foresman.

CLIFTON, C., FRAZIER, L., & CONNINE, C. (1984). Lexical expectations in sentence comprehension. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 23, 696-708.

FERRE~RA, F., & CLIFTON, C. (1986). The indepen- dence of syntactic processing. Journal of Memory and Language, 25, 348-368.

FORD, M., BRESNAN, J., & KAPLAN, R. M. (1982) A competence-based theory of syntactic closure.

In J. Bresnan (Ed.), The mental representation of grammatical relations. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

FRAZIER, L. (1985). Syntactic complexity. In D. Dowty, L. Karttunen, & A. Zwicky (Eds.), Nat- ural language parsing. New York: Cambridge Univ. Press.

FRAZIER, L., & FODOR, J. D. (1978). The sausage ma- chine: A new two-stage parsing model. Cognition, 6, 291-325.

FRAZIER, L., & RAYNER, K. (1982). Making and cor- recting errors during sentence comprehension: Eye movements in the analysis of structurally am- biguous sentences. Cognitive Psychology, 14, 178-210.

FRAZIER, L., TAFT, L., ROEPER, T., CLIFTON, C., & EHRLICH, K. (1984). Parallel structure: A source of facilitation in sentence comprehension. Memory & Cognition, 12, 421-430.

GLASS, A. L., & WARNER, J. (1987). A hierarchical bottom-up model of syntactic parsing. Unpub- lished Ms.

HARRIS, M. D. (1985). Introduction to natural lan- guage processing. Reston, VA: Reston.

KIGER, J. L., & GLASS, A. L. (1983). The facilitation of lexical decisions by a prime occurring after the target. Memory & Cognition, 11, 356-365.

KURTZMAN, H. S. (1985). Studies in syntactic ambi- guity resolution. Doctoral thesis, MIT.

MARCUS, M. P. (1980). A theory of syntactic recogni- tion for natural language. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

MILNE, R. W. (1982). Predicting garden path sen- tences. Cognitive Science, 6, 349-373.

RAYNER, K., CARLSON, M., & FRAZIER, L. (1983). The interaction of syntax and semantics during sentence processing: Eye movements in the anal- ysis of semantically biased sentences. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 22, 358-374.

VAN PETTEN, C., & KUTAS, M. (1987). Ambiguous words in context: An event-related potential anal- ysis of the time course of meaning activation. Journal of Memory and Language, 26, 188-208.

WINOGRAD, T. (1983). Language as a cognitive pro- cess. Vol. 1: Syntax. Reading, MA: Addison- Wesley.

(Received May 4, 1987) (Revision received July 1, 1987)