centrality of human value

Upload: miguel-frota-rodrigues

Post on 04-Jun-2018

218 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/13/2019 Centrality of Human Value

    1/22

    This article was downloaded by: [b-on: Biblioteca do conhecimento online UC]On: 09 July 2012, At: 04:56Publisher: RoutledgeInforma Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registeredoffice: Mortimer House, 37-41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK

    Journal of Economic MethodologyPublication details, including instructions for authors and

    subscription information:

    http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/rjec20

    On the centrality of human valueTeresa Carla Oliveira

    a& Stuart Holland

    a

    aFaculty of Economics, CCIM, CEIS UC, University of Coimbra,

    Coimbra, Portugal

    Version of record first published: 22 Jun 2012

    To cite this article:Teresa Carla Oliveira & Stuart Holland (2012): On the centrality of human value,

    Journal of Economic Methodology, 19:2, 121-141

    To link to this article: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/1350178X.2012.683593

    PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE

    Full terms and conditionsof use: http://www.tandfonline.com/page/te rms-and-conditions

    This article may be used for research, teaching, and private study purposes. Anysubstantial or systematic reproduction, redistribution, reselling, loan, sub-licensing,systematic supply, or distribution in any form to anyone is expressly forbidden.

    The publisher does not give any warranty express or implied or make any representationthat the contents will be complete or accurate or up to date. The accuracy of anyinstructions, formulae, and drug doses should be independently verified with primary

    sources. The publisher shall not be liable for any loss, actions, claims, proceedings,demand, or costs or damages whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly orindirectly in connection with or arising out of the use of this material.

    http://www.tandfonline.com/page/terms-and-conditionshttp://dx.doi.org/10.1080/1350178X.2012.683593http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/1350178X.2012.683593http://www.tandfonline.com/page/terms-and-conditionshttp://dx.doi.org/10.1080/1350178X.2012.683593http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/rjec20
  • 8/13/2019 Centrality of Human Value

    2/22

    On the centrality of human value

    Teresa Carla Oliveira and Stuart Holland

    Faculty of Economics, CCIM**, CEIS UC***, University of Coimbra, Coimbra, Portugal

    The financial crash of 2008 following the selling of fictitious derivatives was a crisis ofboth rationality and values whose aftermath has thrown the legitimation of deregulatedmarkets, and governments, into question. This paper critiques the Becker metaphor ofhuman capital and submits that human value is central to and the fulcrum of botheconomic and social values. It illustrates that Hume and Adam Smith directlycountered the Hobbesian hypothesis that human nature is based only on self-interest,distinguishes market values from social values, explicit from implicit values andparallels Sen in adopting an ordinal ranking of what people value rather than a search

    for cardinality. It draws on cognitive psychology, neural research, revealed preferencetheory and a principle of implicit verification. It also outlines implications for whatAdam Smith centrally valued as concern for the welfare of the whole of society.

    Keywords: implicit; legitimation; preferences; tacit; values; verification

    There is one and only one social responsibility of business to use its resources and engage inactivities designed to increase its profits. (Milton Friedman, The New York Times Magazine,13 September 1970).

    He is not a citizen who is not disposed to respect the laws and to obey the civil magistrate; andhe certainly is not a good citizen who does not wish to promote, by every means in his power,

    the welfare of the whole society of his fellow-citizens. (Adam Smith, The Theory of MoralSentiments, 1759, Part VI, Section II, p. 339).

    1 Introduction

    With globalisation and deregulation, the hegemony of HobbesLeviathanhas passed from

    political sovereigns to markets. Much of this was abetted by Milton Friedman claiming

    that markets are more efficient than governments; that alone can maximise social welfare

    through self-interest countervailed by consumer sovereignty; that business has nothing to

    do with ethics; that its deregulation is the basis of a free society, and alleging support for

    this from both Adam Smiths invisible hand and Smiths recognition that it is not through

    benevolence that butchers, brewers or bakers sell us meat, beer or bread.Yet the presumption that markets are more efficient than governments has been

    challenged by the apocalypse of the financial crash of 2008, which itself was a crisis of

    both rationality and values. In Europe, since 2009, governments have reacted by cuts in

    expenditures and income to placate rating agencies which ranked toxic assets in banks

    and hedge funds of which they were clients as safe as US Treasury bonds until they

    collapsed, disregarding European Union (EU) treaty commitments to economic and

    ISSN 1350-178X print/ISSN 1469-9427 online

    q 2012 Taylor & Francis

    http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/1350178X.2012.683593

    http://www.tandfonline.com

    Corresponding authors. Email: [email protected]; [email protected]

    **Coimbra Centre for Innovative Management

    ***Centro de Estudos e Investigacao em Saude da Universidade de Coimbra

    Journal of Economic Methodology,

    Vol. 19, No. 2, June 2012, 121141

    y

    y

    http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/1350178X.2012.683593http://www.tandfonline.com/http://www.tandfonline.com/http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/1350178X.2012.683593
  • 8/13/2019 Centrality of Human Value

    3/22

    social cohesion and posed a major legitimation crisis for democracies in which it appears

    that markets rule while governments cannot govern.

    This paper relates this to a conceptual framework distinguishing market and social

    values. It claims that the market fundamentalism which since the Thatcher and Reagan

    eras came to dominate the political agenda of the West failed to recognise the values whichconcern most people in their daily lives and their perception of equity or inequity in

    economic and social institutions and outcomes. It submits that markets alone do not enable

    people to reveal their preferences for a more just and equitable society and that this is

    corrosive for democracy.

    In so doing it seeks to recover Adam Smiths neglected claim that functional economies

    depend on well functioning societies. It indicates that neoclassical economics has

    misrepresented Pareto on optimality and displaced recognition by Walras that competition

    can be dysfunctional, especially in finance, and his advocacy of mutual societies in banking

    and of public ownership of land and utilities. It draws on both Wittgenstein and neural

    research in claiming that neoclassical economics is an example of left hemispheric self-

    concern while displacing right hemispheric values and warnings of risk, and deploys

    revealed preference theory to introduce the concept of implicit verifiers of social values.

    The paper contrasts the concept of human value with Beckers metaphor of human

    capital, premised on the unhuman claim that people are identical. It relates human value

    not only to labour as a factor of production or values in market exchange but also to what

    people value in relationships and life experience. It follows Hume and Smith in countering

    the Hobbesian hypothesis that people are fundamentally motivated by self-interest and

    proposes that the concept of human rather than only economic value is central to both

    social and market relationships, to social contracts rather than only legal contracts and

    mutual advantage from non-reciprocal giving such as in Titmuss gift relationship.

    2 Hume, Smith and the Hobbesian hypothesis

    Whether Milton Friedman ever read Smiths (1759)Theory of Moral Sentiments may be

    open to question. He certainly is not renowned for citing the quotation from it at the outset

    of this paper, nor for Smiths following claim that:

    It does not follow that a regard to the welfare of society should be the sole virtuous motive ofaction, but only that, in any competition, it ought to cast the balance against all other motives.(Smith 1759, Part VII, Section II, p. 446)

    Yet Friedmans presumption that self-interest is all that should concern business isconsistent with the central claim by Thomas Hobbes in hisLeviathanthat human nature is

    fundamentally selfish and uncooperative. Thus, Hobbes (1651, chap. XIV) asserted that

    men have no pleasure (but on the contrary a great deal of grief) in keeping company

    where there is no power able to overawe them all and that society would be ungovernable

    unless it had a single undisputed hegemon. He was influenced in this by the English Civil

    War of the 1640s, for much of which he was in France advising the Crown Prince who, on

    the restoration of the monarchy, would become Charles II.

    Hobbes has been deemed to be one of the first moderns in political theory by a range

    of commentators from conservatives and liberals through to Marxists (Macpherson 1962).

    One of the bases for this was his contractual theory of sovereignty (Hampshire-Monk

    1998; Sen 2009). Yet Hobbes contract, pact or covenant was one-sided in being an

    obligation on people to obey a sovereign without reciprocal obligations which was not

    typical of Rousseaus (1762) social contract in which people should be sovereign. Hood

    T.C. Oliveira and S. Holland122

    y

    y

  • 8/13/2019 Centrality of Human Value

    4/22

    has argued in his The Divine Politics of Thomas Hobbes that despite Hobbes claims to

    contest medieval scholasticism, he emerged as a scholastic mechanist (Hood 1964, p. 19).

    Hume (1748b) was highly sceptical of Rousseaus social contract theory, despite

    regarding him highly enough to gain him a royal pension. Yet both he and Adam Smith

    contested Hobbes claim that people were motivated only by self-interest and that societywould be ungovernable without a Hobbesian hegemon. They were influenced in this by the

    political settlement of 1688, whereby the highest authority in the land became not

    the Crown, whose pretensions to unchecked power in the case of Charles I had caused the

    English Civil War, but parliament, its legislation and restraint of sovereign power through

    rule of law, even if the lawmakers were an unrepresentative oligarchy (Plumb 1950) and

    while Hume (1752) himself deemed many of them knaves.

    Yet Hume and Smith also observed that it was not due to the rule of law, or fear of it,

    that British society, trade and industry was flourishing in the eighteenth century in a

    manner that was unprecedented. Markets were working well not only because it paid to

    compete, but also because of trust. Smith (1759, 1776) realised that trust could avoid

    incurring costs from written contracts long before transaction cost theory surfaced 200

    years later (Coase 1978). Both he and Hume (1739, 1740, 1748a, 1751, 1779) valued trust

    not only on ethical grounds but because it was more functional than recourse to law and

    litigation, which has been echoed by Sen (2009) in his concept of functioning. Trust had

    to be gained, and confirmed from experience. It also might sometimes be misplaced. But in

    the main it worked, and worked better the more pervasive it was through society.

    In his Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals, Hume (1751, p. 298) explicitly

    countered what he identified as Hobbes selfish hypothesis as contrary both to common

    feeling and to our most unprejudiced notions. He argued that, however, prominent

    considerations of self-interest may be, we value benevolence in others, even when their

    benevolence is not, and never may be, directed towards us. In this regard, he influenced

    Smiths Theory of Moral Sentiments and the central role within it of hisconcept of sympathy,

    in claiming that benevolence was a manifestation of natural or social sympathy (Hume

    ibid.). His grounds for this was not a claim to natural rights such a made by Rousseau

    (1762). Rather, Hume based it on a feeling for humanity and valuing it in others.

    Smith (1776, IV, p. 400) only once used the metaphor of an invisible hand in The

    Wealth of Nations. By contrast, his concepts of sympathy and mutual sympathy in The

    Theory of Moral Sentiments are its founding premises as in his claiming that:

    How selfish so ever man may be supposed, there are evidently some principles in his nature,which interest him in the fortune of others, and render their happiness necessary to him, though

    he derives nothing from it but the pleasure of seeing it. (Smith 1759, Part 1, Section I, p. 3)

    Sentiment in Smiths usage differs from the current use of sentimental, implying

    unrealistic feelings or aspirations. For him, and for contemporaries such as Condorcet

    (Rothschild 2001), sentiments were integral both to feelings and to judgement, as in

    approbation or disapprobation of the behaviour of others whether these were individuals,

    or groups, or a profession such as lawyers or academics.

    How he then sought to demonstrate this was in line with the claim of Wittgenstein

    (1953) that meaning depends on understanding the use of language in context. He

    recognised that the variations of the use of sympathy and sentiment in different contexts

    are endless, and language wants names to mark them by . . . But still the general sentiment

    of friendship and familiar attachment which is common to them all may be ascertainedwith a sufficient degree of accuracy (Smith 1759, pp. 483 484). Such sentiment or

    feeling did not demand altruism in the sense of loving others more than oneself. It was

    Journal of Economic Methodology 123

    y

    y

  • 8/13/2019 Centrality of Human Value

    5/22

    closer to the biblical injunction, paralleled in other religions, to love thy neighbour as

    thyself, but without divine commandment. By contrast also with Friedmans (1970) claim

    that making profits was all that should concern business, Smith stressed that:

    The wise and virtuous man is at all times willing that his own private interest should be

    sacrificed to the public interest of his own particular order or society. Smith ( ibid., Part VI,Section II, p. 346)

    Nor was this concern in Smith a contradiction of his later and better known observation in

    The Wealth of Nations that it is not from benevolence rather than self-interest that butchers,

    brewersor bakers are in business, not least since he was well aware of the central role that the

    concept of benevolence played for Hume. Rather, like Hume, he saw them as

    complementary self-interest and advantage through competition and the creation of

    economic value; mutual interest and advantage in shared social values and functional

    societies.

    Smith also stressed that there were social dimensions of use value. Use value in the

    economic sphere can be served by division of labour. But there is also use value in thesocial sphere for a society which functions on the basis of reciprocal concern for others.

    This was to directly influence the later Utilitarians such as Bentham, and both James and

    John Stuart Mill (Macfie 1967; Rothschild 2001). It was also to have extensive echoes in

    Sens (2009) concept of functioning even though Sen had major reservations about a

    Benthamite reduction of values to happiness.

    For Hume and Smith, therefore, trust, benevolence and sympathy tend to promote

    individual and inter-personal well-being and also the welfare of society. But they also

    recognised that whether we are disposed to benevolence or sympathy for others depends

    on economic, social and political context. If a politics or economy is dysfunctional,

    societies also may become so and reduce what Maslow (1943) later was to identify as the

    hierarchy of human needs to self-interest merely in survival.

    3 The simulacrum of human capital

    As a metaphor, human capital has gained as near universal a currency as Smiths once

    only reference in The Wealth of Nations to an invisible hand. Becker (2006) has claimed

    that if politicians do not refer to it they do not get elected. They may be less aware that he

    also claimed that slavery was the only market, which accurately priced it (Becker 1964).

    But we submit that there are flaws in the unrealistic manner in which he conceptualised

    human capital, and in his premise-constrained pretensions to be able to measure it.

    For example, Becker claimed that all workers are identical, which is a distinctivelyunhuman characteristic. He needed this for his claim that life income streams correlate

    with investment in the human capital of formal education, rather than could be

    informally learned-from-life or relate to other less tangible factors than the costs of

    education, such as Schumpeters (1911, 1949) stress on differences in creative aptitude.

    He declined to recognise differences in abilities and skills despite their importance for

    employers, who rank them highly in personnel selection (Oliveira 2000, 2001, 2002, 2003,

    2006, 2007) and dismissed experience entirely since he found it too difficult to measure

    and therefore did not try (Oliveira & Holland 2007).

    This is apart from Becker (1964, 1975, 1993) in successive editions of his Human

    Capital neglecting that his initial correlations from macroeconomic data between formal

    education and income trajectories were dependent on a FordistKeynesian era in which

    governments were committed to full employment, and when higher education could assure

    a progressively higher income stream for life. Whereas globalisation, de-industrialisation,

    T.C. Oliveira and S. Holland124

    y

    y

  • 8/13/2019 Centrality of Human Value

    6/22

    rising structural unemployment and more flexible labour markets since the 1970s have

    diminished the life choices and the life chances of graduates in the USA and Europe,

    many of whom now are constrained to accept jobs on short-term contracts rather than

    expecting careers with assured income increments (Arnold and Cohen 2008).

    A further limitation of Beckers claims for human capital is not only that people arenot identical but such life chances or what Sen (1987, 2009) has deemed capabilities

    are influenced by economic and social class. Becker (1964, p. 6) claimed in his first edition

    of Human Capital that the underlying distribution of opportunities and abilities is not

    easily identifiable. Yet other than a passing recognition that children of poorer families

    do less well in formal education, he has not even tried to relate this to income, despite the

    costs of higher education in the USA prohibiting access to the children of poorer families

    even if they do well in secondary education.

    Becker (1993) admitted also in the third edition of his Human Capitalthat he had not

    sought to analyse or evidence correlations between investment in medical education or

    training and trajectories of earnings in health on the basis that, a full analysis of the effects

    on earnings of investments in health is beyond the scope of this study (Becker ibid., p.

    55). Again, this would directly have raised the issue of social class granted that the high

    earnings of doctors in the USA could readily correlate with the premium fees they charge

    to the upper three-fifths of the population with access to private health insurance, but

    exclude others who either have no corporate health schemes, or cannot afford to pay for

    private health care on a personal basis.

    At the end of the introduction to his second edition ofHuman Capital Becker wrote that

    he anticipated that major insights into the benefits from schooling to women who do not

    participate in the labour force [and] the productivity of marriage... will result from an

    integration of the theory of human capital with the allocation of time, household production

    functions, and the theory of choice (Becker 1993, p. 10). Sen (1984) also has commented onBeckers conceptualisation of marriage as a two person firm, with one hiring the other, that

    this may have some foundation in some cases such as those of arranged marriages in Asia,

    yet it means that, in Beckers world:

    Market transactions take place within the family in an imagined way at imagined prices andimagined wages. (Sen 1984, p. 373)

    Pre-nuptial contracts, fashionable among the wealthy and specifying individual financial

    interests, do represent explicit market valuations, yet also assume lack of trust and

    breakdown. Without them, marriage is closer to an implicit psychological contract based

    on presumption of shared values and that the relationship will work rather than fail.

    What we are suggesting, in contrast with Beckers human capital metaphor, is thatwhat people implicitly value is central to whom they are and how they relate to others

    rather than only how markets may value them or whether they value themselves in

    financial terms. Also that human value is not only economic but primarily social. It is

    valued by individuals and valuable to others to whom they relate, whether in a family, or in

    social life or at work. Such human value is neither based on nor motivated only by

    financial gain. It is valued implicitly without being either capitalised or based on an

    assumption of being repaid for the investment in a relationship with others.

    4 Walras, Pareto and welfare

    There are near as many graduates in economics whom have been taught welfare economics

    in the context Walrasian general equilibrium and Paretian optimality as have never read

    either Walras or Pareto. Few therefore realise that both stressed that equilibrium and

    Journal of Economic Methodology 125

    y

    y

  • 8/13/2019 Centrality of Human Value

    7/22

    optimality were pure but abstract concepts and the radical degree to which they could

    differ from actual outcomes. Walras (1896, 1898) in his later work castigated a failure

    already evident in his time to recognise the difference. He also had stressed the degree to

    which there could be inefficiencies and social diseconomies from markets which needed

    countervailance by public policies with examples which, since the repeal of the Glass-Steagall Act, and the subprime crisis, could resonate now, such as banks speculating with

    depositors funds.

    There is virtually no reference in any neoclassical introduction to economics, whether

    Keynesian, monetarist or otherwise to Walras (1865) working for years in the cooperative

    movement before becoming an academic and publishing a treatise on its merits. Nor that

    he was an advocate of public ownership of land, utilities and infrastructure, including

    water, gas, electricity and railways, as well as of mutual societies and cooperatives in

    production, distribution and finance in a manner which later would come to be known as a

    mixed economy. Nor that he thereby advocated extensive social and public ownership

    while distinguishing between a socialism that may involve too much state intervention anda Manchesterism that does not intervene enough (Walras 1875).

    There also has been only a narrowed and misrepresentative citing of Pareto in

    neoclassical economics. He was trained as an engineer and fascinated by equilibrium when

    he found it, but not trapped by it. Evolving as both an economist and a sociologist Pareto

    (1896, 1897, 1909b), held that derivatives in calculus were not facts but a conceptual

    scheme of the mind and that derivation could be not only by algebra but also from

    discourse and its analysis (Pareto 1909a). Sen has critiqued the Paretian concept of

    optimality in the sense that a change in income distribution that can make someone better

    off without making others worse off as an extremely limited way of assessing social

    achievement (Sen 1987, p. 35) and has claimed the impossibility of being a Paretian

    liberal (Sen 1970). Yet there is another Pareto optimality principle, which has been

    deemed its weak version by some mainstream economists yet is stronger in terms of its

    social implications, i.e. that all individuals may gain from a change in income without any

    becoming worse off (Pareto 18967).

    This would be the case with policies which both can raise welfare and increase social

    inclusion not by fiscal transfers such as have been opposed by Germany as a response to

    the crisis of the Eurozone but by shifting savings into public investments from which the

    private sector gains from matrix and income multipliers. Theorists of rational expectations

    and efficient markets have also neglected that Pareto (1909a) stressed that to presume that

    past outcomes could be projected into the future was psychological displacement of risk

    and as unrealistic as Voltaires Dr Pangloss in his Candidesurveying the ruins of Lisbon

    yet still claiming that all was for the best in the best of all possible worlds.

    Neoclassical economics also has displaced Pareto and Walras recognition of external

    diseconomies since these can be nonlinear and asymmetric. Admitting them would deny

    decorating partial or general equilibrium analysis with calculus, and thereby its

    presumption to be a science such as physics. Yet negative externalities from unregulated

    markets not only may collapse banks and penalise whole societies, but also condemn

    humanity to extinction from global warming. Positive externalities from regulation of

    finance could safeguard savings from speculative folly. Public mortgage agencies such as

    Fannie Mae and Freddie Mac did so in the USA before deregulation, and mutual societies

    such as many British mortgage institutions did so before the aptly named Big Bangliberalisation of finance in the 1980s while enabling the joint agency and capability

    building stressed by Sen (1987, 1993, 2009).

    T.C. Oliveira and S. Holland126

    y

    y

  • 8/13/2019 Centrality of Human Value

    8/22

    5 Values and the matter of the mind

    Yet, other than a disposition to refer to rather than to read original texts, there are deeper

    reasons why neoclassical economics has sought to reduce values from those of the welfare

    of society or social preferences to individual choice. As summarised in Box 1, they are

    based in the matter of the mind and especially differences between the left and righthemispheres in brain functioning.

    Such differences were recognised by the mid-nineteenth century. The left hemisphere

    in terms of Brocas and Wernickes areas was found to be that of conceptualisation,

    conscious calculation and language, and the right that of sensing, feeling and intuition. But

    more recent neural research (Box 1) has taken this further and indicates striking parallels

    with neoclassical economics.

    Thus, left hemispheric reasoning is linear which is typical of neoclassical

    methodology. It also prefers what is either static or comparative statics, as does

    neoclassical growth theory (e.g., Samuelson 1947; Hicks 1965), whereas the right

    hemisphere can accept anomalies, asymmetries and flow. The left hemisphere prefers onlyone parameter or variable at a time, as did Solow (1970) in his one good or one product

    Box 1 Values and the matter of the mind.

    The left hemisphere of the brain is the area of conceptualisation, conscious calculation

    and language. The right is the area of imagination, sensing and feeling. They interact.

    But advances in neuroimaging indicate that they not only have different functions but

    different values.

    Kinship, partnership and cooperation are right hemispheric attributes, as are sympathy,

    empathy and moral sentiments (Smith 1759).

    Narrowing meanings is left hemispheric and typical of analytical philosophy, the

    attempt to reduce meaning to formal logic and algebra, the codification of laws, and a

    reduction of values to only those which are explicit.

    Right hemispheric brain functioning is typical of pre-Socratic philosophy, of the

    evolution of drama, music and poetry, imaginative narrative, metaphor, lateral thinking

    and also an implicit sense of justice.

    Intuition and recognition are a right hemisphere attributes. Inhibition and denial are left

    hemisphere specialities.

    The right hemisphere can dismiss false premises and deductions as absurd. The left

    hemisphere sticks to the false premise as in thats what it says here in terms of both

    rules that have been taught and norms that are professionally expected.

    The left hemispheres world is self-consistent, because it is axiomatic as in

    Samuelsons (1947) Foundations of Economics but thereby displaces what can be

    most important in human behaviour including social rather than only market values.

    Crucially, in terms of the non-evolution of economics lamented by Veblen (1898), the

    right hemisphere learns up. The left hemisphere learns down.

    Main sources other than references to economics: Cutting (1997), Decety and Jackson(2004), Decety and Cacioppo (2010), McGilchrist (2009) and Panksepp (2003).

    Journal of Economic Methodology 127

    y

    y

  • 8/13/2019 Centrality of Human Value

    9/22

    macroeconomic model which not only displaced reality, but also the basic principle of

    neoclassical microeconomics of consumer choice.

    Theleft hemisphere sticks to formal logic and premise dependent reasoning. It prefers its

    own explicit virtual world. The right hemisphere can address and try to resolve what is

    implicit and can dismiss false premises and deductions as absurd. The left hemisphere sticksto a premise that may be false, as in thats what it says here, such as the presumption of

    perfect information or perfect competition, or Beckers premise that all people are

    identical. It is reductionist in simplifying its view of the external world, and is self-

    referential. The right hemisphere knows both tacitly and implicitly, as from informal

    learning from life (Cutting 1997; Panksepp 2003; McGilchrist 2009).

    The left hemisphere therefore functions in an abstract, decontextualised, disembodied

    world of its own imagination. It prefers and claims certainty even if this may be unreal, as in

    the logical atomism of the early Wittgenstein (1922) and neoclassical economics. The right

    hemisphere is more open to context in its sense-making (Wittgenstein 1953, 1958, 1980,

    1982) and to threats. It is on the look out rather than looking into, unlike theories of

    rational expectations and efficient markets.

    Neuro-imaging indicates that how and what we are disposed to think also affects

    synaptic growth and tends to reinforce how we then view and interpret the external world

    (Lee 2009; Nader and Einarssom 2010; Wang and Morris 2010; Alberini 2011). But this

    also means that the more we premise and teach that x correlates with y, the more we and

    others may presume that it will do so in future. As with the projection of past strings of

    prices and market values which was misinformed by rational expectations and efficient

    market theories and thereby displaced the Pareto Pangloss warning that this could be

    psychological displacement of realities.

    Damasio (1994) has deemed the concern of the West with only explicit reasoning as

    Descartes error. Goleman (1996) has paralleled this in stressing that many people, andmany managers, lack emotional intelligence. McGilchrist (2009) has claimed that left

    hemispheric dominance of thought, not only since Descartes, has been more typical of

    Western than of Eastern societies. Gaukroger (2006, 2011), a historian of science, has

    claimed that this reduced Western values to those which were conscious and explicit, rather

    than sensed or felt, which was exceptional in oriental cultures, despite their developing

    sophisticated advances in mathematics and science long before the Western Enlightenment,

    as also has been demonstrated extensively for China by Needham (1986).

    Spengler (1918, 1923) recognised the achievements of Western societies in science but

    argued that Cartesian rationalism is constrained by being premise dependent, not thinking

    outside its self-constructed domains and, especially, displacing human by market values inconstantly striving for profit rather than well-being. He also crticised its Faustian

    pretension in presuming to build a world oneselfto be oneself God (Spengler 1918, p. 43,

    his emphases). Of which a striking parallel in the sense that only gods are presumed to be

    all knowing is the neoclassical presumption of perfect information. Or a simulacrum

    such as Beckers human capital in the sense of A thing having the appearance but not the

    substance or proper qualities of something; a deceptive imitation or substance, a pretence

    [or] the worshipping of false gods (Oxford Shorter Dictionary).

    This has implications for both modes of thought and models of economic governance.

    For it is notable that China did not succumb to the left hemispheric pretension that subprime

    and other derivative markets were rational or implied value. Whether this was conscious or

    right hemispheric in terms of sensing and intuition may be open to question. But the

    outcome is verifiable. Following the subprime crisis and the near collapse of the western

    financial system, China emerged with three of the four largest banks in the world (FT 2009).

    T.C. Oliveira and S. Holland128

    y

    y

  • 8/13/2019 Centrality of Human Value

    10/22

    Moreover, these have operated on Walrasian principles within a mixed economy

    framework, channelling savings into investments in a Keynesian manner, financing growth

    and higher levels of employment (The Economist2012). Whereas the cost to the West of

    salvaging banks whose Friedmanite and Hobbesian self-interest should have maximised

    social welfare has meant a fiscal crisis inhibiting growth, a denial of the principles ofpostwar welfare capitalism and a legitimation crisis for Western democracies.

    6 On the centrality of human value

    What we are claiming is that such a crisis and the premise dependent response to it in the

    EU of seeking to placate bond markets by austerity reflects the displacement of social by

    market values. Also, the need in redressing this not only to adopt alternative policies, as

    the Roosevelt administration did in the 1930s New Deal (e.g. EESC 2012), but to gain

    centrality for human value rather than simulacra such as human capital. Napoleoni (1975)

    has stressed that Hume, Smith and Marx saw value not only in economic terms but in

    complementary multi-dimensional personal and social domains. Sens approach to

    value reflects this which is where he differs from both neoclassical economics and a

    utilitarianism which had derived only one principle, hedonic value pleasure from

    Smith. As he put it in Development as Freedom:

    To insist that there should be only one homogeneous magnitude that we value is to reducedrastically the range of our evaluative reasoning. It is not, for example, to the credit ofclassical utilitarianism that it values only pleasure, without taking any direct interest infreedom, rights, creativity or actual living conditions. To insist on the mechanical comfort ofhaving just one homogeneous good thing would be to deny our humanity . . . . (Sen 1999,p. 77)

    What he proposed instead is a plurality of values (Sen 1987) and making way for a varietyof human acts and states as important in themselves ( Sen 1993, p. 33). This includes not

    only hedonism but the Aristotelian principle ofeudaimoniaor purposeful living, which is

    consistent with Marxs (1844) concept of overcoming multiple dimensions of alienation

    rather than only the alienation of surplus value, Rousseaus stress on overcoming

    individual, social and political alienation (Rousseau 1752, 1757, 1762) and what Riesman

    1950, 1954) later was to express as self-direction rather than other-direction.

    What we are proposing is consistent with such plurality of values but also submits that

    human value is central to both the economic and social domains and the fulcrum of

    economic and social value. Reflecting this, Figure 1 allows that such value, like the value

    of both capital and labour, has multiple dimensions similar to the sets-within-sets ofmeaning such as have been central to the theory of capital and the value debate

    surrounding it, whether mainstream (e.g. Harcourt 1972), or Marxist (Mandel 1962, 1971;

    Olin Wright 1981), or Neo-Ricardian following Sraffa (Sraffa 1960; Steedman 1977;

    Hodgson 1981).

    The figure distinguishes between explicit market values and implicit social values, and

    relates also to left and right hemispheric brain functioning (Box 1). On its left side, the

    more one gets to market the more explicit is an exchange relationship, as with a contract

    to buy or sell, or of employment. The more one is concerned with property and property

    rights, the more explicit are the terms and conditions of such rights, again in formal

    contracts. Human and social rights also may be explicit, as in codes or conduct against

    ethnic or gender discrimination, or a charter of universal rights,1 but whether or not they

    are respected tends to depend on whether they are implicitly valued and have become tacit

    rules and implicit norms of behaviour (Oliveira 2007).

    Journal of Economic Methodology 129

    y

    y

  • 8/13/2019 Centrality of Human Value

    11/22

    Yet Figure 1 also relates to the meanings-in-use and context of concepts (Wittgenstein

    1953) and their relation to both explicit and implicit sets and subsets of meaning (Matte

    Blanco 1975, 1988) as follows.

    . Capital has historic value, anticipated future value, exchange value and use value.

    But so does human and social value.

    . People value what they have gained from personal and social relationships in the

    past, and may anticipate it in future with greater or lesser justification. They also can

    explicitly exchange or implicitly transfer values to others such as children and finduse value in both economic and social relationships.

    . Market values sanction inequality, and tend to promote it. Human value relates

    centrally to issues of equity and of procedural and distributive justice, as in the

    manner stressed by Sen (1987, 2009).

    . Market exchange can enhance welfare but also may minimise it if, in labour

    markets, this is at subsistence levels of well-being (Smith).2

    . Property rights may reinforce or contradict social rights depending on context and

    the private or social basis of ownership of property and how it is managed.

    . Social value is consistent with Humes concept of benevolence or Smiths sympathy

    and mutual sympathy.

    . Shared social values enable functional societies in the sense of both Hume and

    Smith and may enhance capabilities (Sen 1987, 2009), whereas lack of them may

    prove dysfunctional.

    The Centrality of Human Value

    Left Hemispheric Right Hemispheric

    Human

    ValueSocial

    Value

    Economic

    Value

    Property

    Rights Social Norms

    Market Exchange Social Exchange

    Competitive

    Advantage

    Mutual

    Advantage

    Formal Knowledge Informal Knowledge

    Market Innovation Social Innovation

    Welfare

    Welbeing

    MARKET DOMAIN SOCIAL DOMAIN

    EXPLICIT VALUE IMPLICIT VALUE

    INEQUALITY EQUITY

    Psychologicaland SocialContracts

    LegalContract

    PrivateGain

    SocialGain

    Figure 1. The centrality of human value.

    T.C. Oliveira and S. Holland130

    y

    y

  • 8/13/2019 Centrality of Human Value

    12/22

  • 8/13/2019 Centrality of Human Value

    13/22

  • 8/13/2019 Centrality of Human Value

    14/22

    with others, echoing Walras, has analysed as an associative economy or more generally

    has been deemed a third sector.

    8 Implicit values and implicit verifiersYet if implicit values make sense in terms of the well functioning of both economies and

    societies, how can one verify them whether with a verification principle such as that of

    logical positivism (Carnap 1934; Ayer 1936) or falsify them in terms of Poppers (1959)

    falsification principle? As Hume (1740) stressed and Smith (1759) echoed, all perception

    and cognition is subjective. Whatever Kants claims forsynthetic a prioripropositions that

    are universally valid, and in the search for which he was provoked by Hume, or Rawls

    concern to demonstrate a transcendental justice, ought cannot be derived from is

    (Hume 1739, 1740; Kant 1781, 1783, 1788; Rawls 1971, 1993, 2001).

    Poppers claim that something cannot be verified rather than falsified stemmed from

    his finding that both Freudian and Adlerian analysts in the Vienna of his youth alwayswere ready to claim that pathological behaviour proved their theories, although they

    were different.3 Yet there is a difference between claiming to prove a theory and finding

    consistency in what people perceive, sense or feel in terms of values. Thus, if with less

    profile now in this regard than Poppers stress on falsification, Hayek observed that finding

    that different people:

    perceive different things in a similar manner . . . must be regarded as a significant datum ofexperience which must be the starting point in any discussion of human behaviour. Hayek(1937, p. 37)

    This both is consistent with Paretos alternative principle of derivation from what people

    actually say, and compares directly with Smiths observation in his Theory of MoralSentiments that:

    It is by finding, in a vast variety of instances, that one tenor of conduct constantly pleases in acertain manner, and that another constantly displeases the mind, that we form the general rulesof morality. Smiths (1759, p, 470)

    Thus, when people attribute value to something or someone this is subjective. But if

    it is found that what they value is shared by and common to the experience of others

    it becomes a datum which in this regard is as objective as other data in social analysis and

    whose consistency may indicateboth statistical and social significance in such commonality.

    Sen (1974, 1976, 1982, 1985) has shown that consistency can be found in ordinal

    ranking both of poverty and of well-being. Ordinal ranking also can avoid whatWittgenstein (1953), with reason, claimed could be asking the wrong question in asking

    for a cardinal or absolute criterion for value or seeking truth in a Kantian transcendental

    sense of a synthetic a priori axiom or Rawls (1971, 1993, 2001) search for a

    transcendental criterion of justice.

    Rather, finding implicit verifiers for what is true for people in their own or shared

    contexts, through discourse, is inductive in terms of deriving conclusions from what can be

    found empirically and also analytic in relating it to either already known or new concepts,

    such as those of learning-from-life and of learning-from-work rather than only lifelong

    learning, reported below. It is both synthetic anda posteriori in the sense of identifying

    what people have derived from their experience, and precisely what Hume and Smith did

    in observing and finding evidence for benevolence and trust in human behaviour. It gains a

    cognitive and conceptual connection with peoples understanding of their own realities

    (Hume 1740; Smith 1759) and needs no metaphysical search for a priori cardinality.

    Journal of Economic Methodology 133

    y

    y

  • 8/13/2019 Centrality of Human Value

    15/22

    9 Values and implicit learning

    In illustrating that consistency can be found in ordinal ranking in the measurement of both

    poverty and well-being, Sen (1974, 1976, 1982, 1985), has cited consistent responses to

    questionnaire-based surveys (e.g. Mack and Lansley 1985). A similar approach

    (Oliveira 2003), but based on one-to-one discourse rather than a questionnaire, was afour-country case study which was the outcome of a remit to the European Commission from

    the Lisbon European Council to identify and deconstruct the concept of lifelong learning

    which, at the time, lacked much deeper meaning in use by governments than serial retraining.

    The methodology in the case study was informed by the claims of Reber and others for

    implicit learning (Reber 1989, 1993; Berry 1997) and those of Nonaka and Takeuchi

    (1995), Baumard (1999) and Ambrosini and Bowman (2001) that tacit knowing can be

    surfaced by discourse. But it was also informed by Polanyis (1962) claim that there is a

    tacit coefficient in any statement, the case of Matte Blanco (1975) for interfacing conscious

    and unconscious logic in sets-within-sets of meaning, and the parallel case of Cleeremans

    (1997) that implicit learning is an interface between conscious and unconscious processes.The case study also drew on sets of criteria drawn from the theory of candidate choice in

    personnel selection such as knowledge, abilities and skills or KAS, and values, beliefs and

    personality or VBP (Anderson and Shackleton 1990, 1993; Anderson 1997; Guion 1997;

    Anderson, Lievens, van Dam, and Ryan 2004; and Figure 2). The methodology was of

    semi-structured interviews with 240 persons, age and gender balanced, in Italy, Ireland,

    Hungary and Portugal.

    To operationalise concepts such as values learned-from-life or learned-from-work

    meant training the researchers in the project to identify implicit meanings and sets-of-

    meanings in discourse. In coding transcripts of one-to-one discourse, they were encouraged

    to distinguish subsets within the domains of implicit learning from childhood, education,

    recreation and relationships in both work and life as illustrated in Figure 2 of which four such

    domains from life experience are social and one work both economic and social rather

    than exclusively economic.

    The findings from the four-country case study are given in Table 1. Of these the most

    outstanding are that values ascribed to learning-from-life at over 75% massively outstrip

    those of,3% learned from the formal education that Becker assumes is investment in

    human capital.

    KASKnowledgeAbilitiesSkills

    VBPValues

    BeliefsPersonality

    Context

    CRITERIA

    Identifying learning-from-work and learning-from-life

    Childhood

    Relationships

    Education

    RecreationWork

    DOMAINS

    Figure 2. Identifying learning-from-work and learning-from-life.

    T.C. Oliveira and S. Holland134

    y

    y

  • 8/13/2019 Centrality of Human Value

    16/22

  • 8/13/2019 Centrality of Human Value

    17/22

    allegedly New Public Management in the National Health Service (NHS) (Le Grand

    1991; Le Grand and Barteltt 1993).

    Yet, Le Grands recommendations of quasi-markets for the NHS in terms of criteria

    for performance management were less new than Taylorist in terms of time and motion

    studies, Fordist in terms of increasing patient throughput and hierarchical in a Weberiansense that bureaucracy was rational but also soulless, and needed direct democracy to

    challenge its alienation of employees. Such New Public Management assumed that

    change could be imposed top-down without dialogue with health professionals or

    delving down to learn up on what their own experience and values represented in terms

    what they believed in, what motivated them and the degree to which this was based on a trust

    relationship with patients (Oliveira and Holland 2007).

    Such quasi-markets also, in Sens terms, as well as those of Hume and Adam Smith,

    did not assure functional social outcomes, but proved dysfunctional. By presuming that

    health professionals were knaves and could not be trusted and introducing Taylorist

    performance criteria within a Foucauldian context of surveillance rather than Hume and

    Smiths presumption of trust, administrative costs as a share of total costs by needing new

    layers of management for performance evaluation and surveillance in the NHS near

    doubled its administrative costs, just as Titmuss had foreseen if the NHS were to replicate

    the administrative costs in private sector health provision in the USA (Leys and Player

    1911; Titmuss 1971; Pollock 2004; Oliveira and Holland 2007).

    Since when a series of studies have shown that health service workers in the UK have

    come deeply to resent the presumption that they only were only self-interested suppliers of

    health as a commodity. Nurses have resented the implication that they were doing a job

    for clients rather than committed to and valuing health care as a public service

    (Bolton 2004; Pollock 2004) as have doctors and medical ancillary staff (Arnold 2009).

    11 Conclusion

    This paper has drawn on the central role attributed to human values by both David Hume and

    AdamSmith, including that trust, benevolence and sympathy werevital for well-functioning

    societies. It has claimed that the Smiths famous claim that it was not through benevolence

    that butchers, brewers or bakers sell us meat, beer or bread was not a contradiction of this but

    that, like Hume, he saw self-interest and mutual interest as complementary self-interest

    and advantage through competition and the creation of economic value; mutual interest and

    advantage in shared social values and functional societies.

    It has challenged the metaphor of human capital on the grounds that it is unrealistic inassuming that all people are identical and that in neglecting learning from experience

    Becker has missed that most learning, including the learning of values, has been from life

    rather than formal education. It has shown the mainstream neoclassical theory has presumed

    to be Walrasian and Paretian yet displaced their stress on the importance of distinguishing

    theory from actual outcomes and the manner in which Walras understood both limits to

    welfare from markets and advocated social and mixed economy policies including mutual

    and cooperative ownership and control of finance.

    But it has suggested a deeper criticism of neoclassical economics in that its displacement

    of values other than market values has been typical of left rather than right hemispheric brain

    functioning and has been pathological in that its premise dependent principles have been

    self-referential rather than inferential and displaced realities including both externalities

    and risk. It has not sought a cardinal or transcendental criterion for values but has

    demonstrated that an ordinal ranking of values basis is empirically verifiable.

    T.C. Oliveira and S. Holland136

    y

    y

  • 8/13/2019 Centrality of Human Value

    18/22

    In doing so it has submitted that Popper was wrong in claiming that there can be no

    verification rather than falsification, and Hayek right in the counter claim that when there

    is evidence that people share a common experience this becomes a datum capable of

    verification. In drawing on concepts such as implicit logic it also has introduced the

    principle of implicit verification. It has qualified but paralleled Samuelsons principle ofrevealed preference by drawing on evidence of the feasibility revealing tacit and implicit

    values.

    The paper has challenged a misrepresentation of Hume in the case for the introduction

    of quasi-markets through allegedly New Public Management in the UK by Julian Le

    Grand and his premise that public sector workers are fundamentally self-interested rather

    than committed to values of public service and vocational concern for the well-being of

    others. One of its main implications is the case for recovering the centrality of human

    value rather than the simulacrum of human capital, and gaining legitimation from this in

    democratic processes which can assure more direct democracy within organisations, as

    advocated by Weber, especially in the public and social domains where governments

    could commit to this, as well as the need for political democracies to gain legitimation

    from ensuring that markets serve people rather than that people serve markets.

    Notes

    1. Such as the UN Charter of Human Rights and the right to well-being in the sense of the UNDPcriteria of health, longevity, education and standard of living which Sen has played a key role inboth instigating and developing.

    2. Which Smith recognised in theWealth of Nationsin the tendency of markets to reduce wages toa subsistence level, and recommending the legalisation of working men associations tocountervail this.

    3. The Adlerian analysts included Adler himself, whom Popper knew well.4. Humes text continues

    . . .

    When there offers, therefore, to our censure and examination anyplan of government, real or imaginary, where the power is distributed among several courts andseveral orders of men, we should always consider the separate interest of each court and eachorder; and if we find that, by the skilful division of power, this interest must necessarily in itsoperation concur with the public, we may pronounce that government to be wise and happy(Hume ibid.).

    References

    Alberini, C.M. (2011), The Role of Reconsolidation and the Dynamic Process of Long-TermMemory Formation and Storage,Frontiers in Behavioral Neuroscience, 5, 1 10.

    Ambrosini, V., and Bowman, C. (2001), Tacit Knowledge: Some Suggestions for Operationaliza-

    tion, Journal of Management Studies, 38(6), 811 829.Anderson, N. (1997), The Validity and Adverse Impact of Selection Interviews, Selection and

    Development Review, 13(5), 1317.Anderson, N., and Shackleton, V. (1990), Decision-Making in the Graduate Selection Interview,

    Journal of Occupational Psychology, 63, 63 76.Anderson, N., and Shackleton, V. (1993), Successful Selection Interviewing, Oxford: Blackwell

    Publishers.Anderson, N., Lievens, F., van Dam, K., and Ryan, A.M. (2004), Future Perspectives on Employee

    Selection: Key Directions for Future Research and Practice, Applied Psychology, 53(4),487501.

    Archibugi, F. (2000), Associative Economy, Houndmills: Macmillan.Arnold, J. (2009), The Boundaryless and Protean Career Concepts What are They and are They

    Useful?, Presentation to the 3rd International Seminar Series on Innovative Management:Proactive Responses in a Global Era. Coimbra Centre for Innovative Management, July 24th.

    Arnold, J., and Cohen, L. (2008), The Psychology of Careers in Industrial and OrganisationalSettings, International Review of Industrial and Organisational Psychology, 23, 144.

    Journal of Economic Methodology 137

    y

    y

  • 8/13/2019 Centrality of Human Value

    19/22

    Ayer, A.J. (1936), Language, Truth and Logic, London: Gollancz.

    Baumard, P. (1999), Tacit Knowledge in Organisations, London: Sage.

    Becker, G.S. (1964, 1975, 1993), Human Capital, Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Becker, G. (2006), Lunch with the FT, The Financial Times, June 17th18th.

    Berry, D.C., (ed.) (1997), How Implicit is Implicit Learning? Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Bolton, S.C. (2004), A Simple Matter of Control? NHS Nurses and New Management,Journal ofManagement Studies, 42(2), 316333.

    Carnap, R. (1934),Logische Syntax der Sprache, Leipzig: Felix Meiner Verlag. Translated (1939) as

    The Logical Syntax of Language, London: Kegan Paul.

    Cleeremans, A. (1997), Principles for Implicit Learning, inHow Implicit is Implicit Learning? ed.

    Dianne C. Berry, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 196234.

    Coase, R. (1978), The Nature of the Firm, Economica, 4, 386 405.

    Cutting, J. (1997),Principles of Psychopathology, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Damasio, A. (1994), Descartes Error: Emotion, Reason and the Human Brain, New York:

    Grosset and Dunlap.

    Decety, J., and Cacioppo, J. (2010), Frontiers in Human Neuroscience: The Golden Triangle and

    Beyond, Perspectives on Psychological Science, 5(6), 767771.

    Decety, J., and Jackson, P.L. (2004), The Functional Architecture of Human Empathy,Behavioral and Cognitive Neuroscience Reviews, 3(2), 71100.

    EESC (2012), Restarting Growth, Economic and Social Committee of the European Union,

    ECO/307. February 23rd.

    Fried, B. (2011), Mandelas Lessons in Truth for City High Flyers, The Financial Times, April 8th.

    Friedman, M. (1970), The Social Responsibility of the Firm is to Increase Its Profits, The New York

    Times Magazine, September 13th.

    FT (2009), Global 500. FT Weekend Magazine, The Financial Times, June 28th29th.

    Gaukroger, S. (2006), Emergence of a Scientific Culture: Science and the Shaping of Modernity,

    Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 12101685.Gaukroger, S. (2011),Collapse of Mechanism and the Rise of Sensibility: Science and the Shaping of

    Modernity, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 16801760.

    Goleman, D. (1996), Emotional Intelligence: Why It Can Matter More Than IQ, London:Bloomsbury.

    Guion, R.M. (1997), Criterion Measures and the Criterion Dilemma, in International Handbook of

    Selection and Assessment, eds. N. Anderson and P. Herriot, Chichester: Wiley, pp. 267286.

    Hampshire-Monk, I. (1998),A History of Modern Political Thought: Major Political Thinkers from

    Hobbes to Marx, Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Harcourt, G.C. (1972), Some Cambridge Controversies in the Theory of Capital, Cambridge:

    Cambridge University Press.

    Hicks, J. (1965), Capital and Growth, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Hirschman, A. (1970), Exit, Voice and Loyalty, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Hobbes, T. (1651), Leviathan, London: (1960) Dent.

    Hodgson, G. (1981), Critique of Wright 1: Labour and Profits, in The Value Controversy, eds.

    I. Steedman, P. Sweezy, S. Mohun, A. Shaik, G. Hodgson, E. Olin Wright, P. Pandyopadhyay,M. De Vroey, M. Itoh and G.A. Cohen, London: Verso Books, pp. 7599.

    Holland, S. (1995), LEurope, le Welfare et les etats Providence, inLEtat, la Finance et le Social,

    ed. B. Theret, Paris: La Decouverte, 516533.

    Hood, F.C. (1964), The Divine Politics of Thomas Hobbes, Oxford: The Clarendon Press.

    Hume, D. (1739, 1740), A Treatise on Human Nature: Being an Attempt to Introduce the

    Experimental Method of Reasoning into Moral Subjects, 2 vols, London: Dent (1911).

    Hume, D. (1748a), Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, ed. L.A. Selby-Bigge, Oxford:

    The Clarendon Press (1978).

    Hume, D. (1748b), On the Original Contract, in Social Contract: Locke, Hume, Rousseau, ed.

    Ernest Barker, London: Oxford University Press, 209236.

    Hume, D. (1751), Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals, 3rd ed. (1975), ed. P.H. Nidditch

    L.A. Selby-Bigge, Oxford: Clarendon Press.Hume, D. (1752), On the Independency of Parliament, in Essays, Moral, Political and Literary,

    eds. T.H. Green and T.H. Gross, Vol. I, London: Longmans, 117121.

    Hume, D. (1779),Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion, Edinburgh: William Blackwood (1907).

    T.C. Oliveira and S. Holland138

    y

    y

  • 8/13/2019 Centrality of Human Value

    20/22

    Kant, I. (1781), The Critique of Pure Reason, ed. Nowell Kemp Smith, London: Allen and Unwin,1918.

    Kant, I. (1783), Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics that Will Be Able to Present Itself as aScience, ed. P.G. Lucas, Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1953.

    Kant, I. (1788), Critique of Practical Reason, ed. M. Gregor, Cambridge: Cambridge University

    Press, 1997.Lee, J.L.C. (2009), Reconsolidation: Maintaining Memory Relevance, Trends in Neurosciences,

    32(8), 413420.Le Grand, J. (1991), Equity and Social Choice, London: Harper-Collins. (1997a), Knights, Knaves or Pawns? Human Behaviour and Social Policy, The Journal of

    Social Policy, 26(2), 149169. (1997b), Afterword, in The Gift Relationship: From Human Blood to Social Policy, ed.

    R.M. Titmuss, London: LSE Books, New York: The Free Press, pp. 333339.Le Grand, J., and Barteltt, W. (1993), Quasi-Marlets and Social Policy, Houndmills: Macmillan.Leys, C., and Player, S. (1911), Plot Against the NHS, London: Merlin Press.Macfie, A.L. (1967),The Individual in Society: Papers on Adam Smith, London: Allen and Unwin.Mack, J., and Lansley, S. (1985), Poor Britain, London: Allen & Unwin.

    Macpherson, C. (1962), Political Theory of Possessive Individualism: Hobbes to Locke, Oxford:Clarendon Press.Mandel, E. (1962), Marxist Economic Theory, London: Merlin Press. (1971), Formation of the Economic Thought of Karl Marx , London: New Left Books.Marx, K. (1844), Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts, eds. T.B. Bottomore and M. Rubel,

    London: Watts, 1963.Maslow, A.H. (1943), A Theory of Human Motivation, Psychology Review, 50, 370396.Matte Blanco, I. (1975), The Unconscious as Infinite Sets, London: Duckworth. (1988), Thinking, Feeling and Being, London: Routledge.McGilchrist, I. (2009),Master and His Emissary: The Divided Brain and the Making of the Western

    World, New Haven and London: Yale University Press.Nader, K., and Einarssom, E.O. (2010), Memory Reconsolidation: An Update, Annals of the

    New York Academy of Sciences, 1191(1), 2741.

    Napoleoni, C. (1975),Smith, Ricardo and Marx, Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Needham, J. (1986), Science and Civilization in China, in Mathematics and the Sciences of the

    Heavens and the Earth, Vol. 3, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Nonaka, I., and Takeuchi, H. (1995), Knowledge-Creating Company: How Japanese Companies

    Create the Dynamics of Innovation, New York: Oxford University Press.Olin Wright, E. (1981), The Value Controversy and Social Research, in The Value Controversy,

    eds. I. Steedman, P. Sweezy, S. Mohun, A. Shaik, G. Hodgson, E. Olin Wright,P. Pandyopadhyay, M. De Vroey, M. Itoh and G.A. Cohen, London: Verso Books, pp. 3674.

    Oliveira, T.C. (2000), Implicit Logic in Unstructured Interviewing, Selection and DevelopmentReview, British Psychological Society, London 16(2), 1014.

    (2001), Power in Panel Interviewing, Selection and Development Review, BritishPsychological Society, London 17(3), 710.

    (2002), Procedural Justice in Selection, Selection and Development Review, BritishPsychological Society, London 18(2), 37.

    (2003), An Architecture and Methodology for a European Certificate of Informal Learning,Report to the Education and Cultural Affairs Directorate General of the Commission of theEuropean Union (Socrates-Leonardo 20020579/01001 JAC).

    (2006), Implicit Logic in Managerial Discourse: A Case Study in Choice of SelectionCriteria, Notas Economicas, Faculty of Economics, University of Coimbra 23, 5371.

    (2007), Delving Down to Learn Up, Plenary Presentation to the Sloan MIT-PortugalConference on New Developments in Management, Lisbon, June.

    Oliveira, T.C., and Holland, S. (2006), Innovation-by-Agreement: Activating the Lisbon Agenda,Notas Economicas, Faculty of Economics, University of Coimbra 24, 6681.

    (2007), Beyond Human and Intellectual Capital: Profiling the Value of Knowledge, Skills

    and Experience,Comportamento Organizacional e Gestao, 13(2), 237260.Panksepp, J. (2003), At the Interface of the Affective, Behavioral and Cognitive Neurosciences:Decoding the Emotional Feelings of the Brain, Brain and Cognition, 52(1), 414.

    Pareto, V. (18967), Cours dEconomie Politique, 3 vols Geneva and Paris: Droz, 1964.

    Journal of Economic Methodology 139

    y

    y

  • 8/13/2019 Centrality of Human Value

    21/22

    (1909a), Les Principes Generale de levolution Sociale, inManuel deconomie Politique2vols. Paris: Giard et Briere, 1909 (4th ed.), Geneva and Paris: Droz, 1981.

    (1909b), Trattato Di Sociologia Generale, Rome: Boringhieri. Translated (1935) asThe Mind and Society. New York: Harcourt, Brace.

    Plumb, J.H. (1950), England in the Eighteenth Century, Harmondsworth: Penguin Books.

    Polanyi, M. (1958), Personal Knowledge, Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press. (1962), Tacit Knowing: Its Bearing in Some Problems of Philosophy, Review of Modern

    Physics, 34(4), 601616. (1968), Tacit Dimension, London: Routledge.Pollock, A.M. (2004),NHS plc, London: Verso Books.Popper, K. (1959), Logic of Scientific Discovery, London: Routledge.Rawls, J. (1971), A Theory of Justice, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. (1993), Political Liberalism, New York: Columbia University Press. (2001), Justice as Fairness: A Restatement, ed. E. K elly, Cambridge, MA:

    Harvard University Press.Reber, A.S. (1989), Implicit Learning and Tacit Knowledge, Journal of Experimental Psychology,

    118, 219 235.

    (1993), Implicit Learning and Tacit Knowledge: An Essay on the Cognitive Unconscious,New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press.Riesman, D. (1954), Individualism Reconsidered and Other Essays, Glencoe, IL: The Free Press.Riesman, D., Glazer, N., and Deney, R. (1950), The Lonely Crowd, CT: Yale University Press.Rothschild, E. (2001), Economic Sentiments: Adam Smith, Condorcet and the Enlightenment,

    Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Rousseau, D.M. (1995), Psychological Contracts in Organisations: Understanding Written and

    Unwritten Agreements, Newbury Park, CA: Sage. (1998), The Problem of the Psychological Contract Considered, Journal of

    Organizational Behavior, 19, 665671.Rousseau, J.-J. (1752), Discours sur lOrigine de lInegalite Parmi les Hommes, Republished

    (1961), Paris: Garnier. (1757), Emile, ou de lEducation, Republished (1961), Paris: Garnier.

    (1762), Du Contrat Social, Republished (1961), Paris: Garnier.Rousseau, D.M., and Tinsley, K. (1997), Human Resources are Local: Society and Social Contracts

    in a Global Economy, inHandbook of Selection and Appraisal, eds. N. Anderson and P. Herriot,London: Wiley, 3962.

    Samuelson, P.A. (1938), A Note on the Pure Theory of Consumers Behaviour, Econometrica, 5,353354.

    (1947), Foundations of Economic Analysis, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press,Republished 1983.

    Schumpeter, J. ([1911] (1949)), The Theory of Economic Development, Cambridge, MA: HarvardUniversity Press, 1st published in German in 1911, with a revised English edition in 1934.References in this text are to the 1949 Harvard University Press edition.

    Sen, A. (1970), The Impossibility of a Paretian Liberal, Journal of Political Economy, 78(1),

    152157. (1971), Choice Functions and Revealed Preference,Review of Economic Studies, 38(115),

    307317. (1974), Choice, Orderings and Morality, in Practical Reason, ed. S. Korner, Oxford: Basil

    Blackwell, 5467. (1976), Poverty: An Ordinal Approach to Measurement, Econometrica, 44, 219231. (1982), Choice, Welfare and Measurement, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press,

    pp. 84108. (1984), Economics and the Family, in Resources, Value and Development,

    Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1426. (1985),The Standard of Living, Tanner Lectures on Human Values, Cambridge: Clare Hall. (1987), On Ethics and Economics, Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    (1993), Capability and Well-being, inThe Quality of Life, eds. Martha C. Nussbaum andAmartya Sen, Oxford: The Clarendon Press and The United Nations University, pp. 3053. (1999), Development as Freedom, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (2009), The Idea of Justice, London: Allen Lane.

    T.C. Oliveira and S. Holland140

    y

    y

  • 8/13/2019 Centrality of Human Value

    22/22

    Simon, H.A. (1957),Models of Man: Social and Rational, New York: Wiley. (1978), Rationality as a Process and Product of Thought,American Economic Review, 68,

    116. (1983), Reason in Human Affairs, Stanford: Stanford University Press.Smith, A. (1759), The Theory of Moral Sentiments, References in this paper are to the edition by

    Henry Bohn of 1853, where the pagination is from the original text, rather than that byD.D. Raphael and A.L. Macfie (1979) Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    (1776), An Enquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations , London: HenryBohn, and multiple subsequent editions including London: Methuen, 1904.

    Solow, R.M. (1970), Growth Theory: An Exposition, Oxford: The Clarendon Press.Spengler, O. (vol I, 1918, vol II, 1923), Der Untergang des Abendslandes, translated in abridged

    editions asthe Decline of the West, Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press (1926, 1928,1932).

    Sraffa, P. (1960), Production of Commodities by Means of Commodities, Cambridge:Cambridge University Press.

    Steedman, I. (1977).Marx After Sraffa, London: New Left Books.The Economist (2012), The Rise of State Capitalism: The Emerging Worlds New Model,

    January 21st27th.Titmuss, R.M. ([1971], (1997)), The Gift Relationship: From Human Blood to Social Policy,

    London: LSE Books, New York: The Free Press.Veblen, T. (1898), Why is Economics Not an Evolutionary Science? Quarterly Journal of

    Economics Vol 12, inThe Portable Veblen, ed. M. Lerner, New York: The Viking Press (1948),pp. 373397.

    von Hayek, F. (1937), Economics and Knowledge, Economica, IV, 3354.Walras, L. (1865), Les Associations Populaires de Consommation, de Production et de Credit,

    Paris: Economica, 1990. (1875), LEtat et les Chemins de fer. Republished iin Etudes Deconomie Politique

    Appliquee: Theorie de la Production de la Richesse Sociale, Lausanne: Rouge, 1898 and Rome:Bizzari, 1969.

    (1896), Elements Deconomie Politique Pure ou, Theorie de la Division de la Richesse

    Sociale(3rd retitled ed.), Lausanne: Rouge. (1898), Etudes Deconomie Politique Appliquee: Theorie de la Production de la Richesse

    Sociale, Rome: Bizzari, 1969.Wang, S.-H., and Morris, R.G.M. (2010), Hippocampal-Neocortical Interactions in Memory

    Formation, Consolidation, and Reconsolidation, Annual Review of Psychology, 61, 49 79.Wittgenstein, L. (1922), Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. (1953), Philosophical Investigations, Oxford: Blackwell. (1958), The Blue and Brown Books, Oxford: Blackwell. (1980, 1982), Remarks on the Philosophy of Psychology, Oxford: Blackwell.

    Journal of Economic Methodology 141

    y

    y