buridan davidson akrasia

Upload: lamaildierica9188

Post on 01-Jun-2018

223 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/9/2019 Buridan Davidson Akrasia

    1/22

    John Buridan and Donald Davidson on "Akrasia"Author(s): Risto SaarinenSource: Synthese, Vol. 96, No. 1, Studies in Early Fourteenth-Century Philosophy (Jul., 1993),pp. 133-153Published by: SpringerStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/20117803 .

    Accessed: 22/12/2013 08:35

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

     .JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of 

    content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms

    of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

     .

    Springer  is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Synthese.

    http://www.jstor.org

    This content downloaded from 130.251.200.3 on Sun, 22 Dec 2013 08:35:30 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=springerhttp://www.jstor.org/stable/20117803?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/20117803?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=springer

  • 8/9/2019 Buridan Davidson Akrasia

    2/22

    RISTO SAARINEN

    JOHN

    BURIDAN

    AND DONALD

    DAVIDSON

    ON AKRASIA

    1.

    INTRODUCTORY

    REMARKS

    This article has

    two

    objectives.

    First,

    it is

    my

    aim

    to

    outline

    some

    medieval views

    concerning

    the

    acts

    that

    oppose

    one's

    better

    judgment.

    I will

    use

    Aristotle's

    term

    akrasia

    to

    denote

    the

    moral

    state

    of

    an

    agent

    behaving

    in this

    way.

    John Buridan's

    (1285-1349)

    treatment

    of akrasia

    is

    especially

    relevant

    here.

    Second,

    it will

    be

    argued

    that

    some

    impor

    tant

    philosophical

    ideas

    proposed

    recently by

    Donald

    Davidson,

    in his

    influential

    study

    'How is

    Weakness of the Will

    Possible?',1

    are

    antici

    pated

    in

    the medieval

    discussion.

    Aristotle's

    akrasia,

    or

    ''weakness of the

    will ,

    has

    recently

    received

    increasing scholarly

    attention.2

    The

    problems

    concerning

    akrasia arise

    ifwe adopt the view of Socrates, according to which no one can know

    the

    good

    and will

    evil.3

    Given

    this,

    how

    is

    it

    possible

    to

    explain

    the

    seemingly

    common

    phenomenon

    of

    acting

    against

    one's better

    judg

    ment? Aristotle's discussion of

    akrasia

    in the

    seventh book

    of

    his

    Nico

    machean

    Ethics

    has

    become

    a

    paradigmatic

    example

    of how

    a

    classical

    problem

    is

    actually

    perennial

    and

    can

    arise

    again

    in modern

    thought.

    Many

    recent

    treatments

    of the weakness

    of the will

    combine historical

    interpretation

    of

    Aristotle with

    developments

    in

    analytical

    philosophy,4

    thus

    demonstrating

    the

    importance

    of historical

    awareness

    even

    in mod

    ern

    action

    theory.

    Although

    this awareness has

    undoubtedly

    been instructive both for

    historians

    and

    philosophers,

    one

    important

    aspect

    of the

    historical di

    mension,

    as

    far

    as

    I

    can

    see,

    has been

    almost

    completely

    neglected.

    The

    modern

    studies and

    textbooks

    on

    akrasia first

    deal

    extensively

    with ancient

    Greek

    philosophy

    and

    then

    immediately

    proceed

    to

    the

    twentieth-century

    discussion.

    The

    remaining

    gap

    of 2000

    years

    of

    philo

    sophical

    reflection is

    sometimes filled with

    short

    references

    to

    Augus

    tine,

    Aquinas,

    Leibniz,

    and

    Kant.5

    One does

    find

    sophisticated

    philosophical

    discussions

    on

    akrasia,

    or

    incontinence

    (Lat.

    incondnenda),6

    however,

    both in

    medieval

    Synthese

    96:

    133-154,

    1993.

    ?

    1993

    Kluwer

    Academic

    Publishers.

    Printed in

    the Netherlands.

    This content downloaded from 130.251.200.3 on Sun, 22 Dec 2013 08:35:30 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Buridan Davidson Akrasia

    3/22

    134

    RISTO SAARINEN

    scholastic

    philosophy

    and in sixteenth- and

    seventeenth-century

    neo

    scholasticism.7

    The

    conceptual

    refinement of

    the

    fourteenth-century

    medieval discussion

    makes contributions that

    are

    wholly

    comparable

    to

    those

    of

    twentieth-century

    philosophers.

    The

    neglect

    of medieval authors

    is rather

    surprising,

    as

    it

    is well

    known that

    many

    of them

    wrote

    lengthy

    commentaries

    on

    the Nicoma

    chean

    Ethics.

    Nevertheless,

    Justin

    Gosling,

    e.g.,

    wrote

    in

    his

    recent

    historical

    introduction

    to

    Weakness

    of

    the Will that so far

    as

    I

    know

    there is

    no

    literature

    on

    the

    problem

    in

    medieval

    philosophers .8

    Al

    though some preliminary studies have been done,9 the medieval dis

    cussion

    has

    obviously

    been

    neglected.

    The

    short

    chapter

    on

    Aquinas

    and Others

    in

    Gosling's

    own

    monograph10

    is,

    in

    any

    case,

    not

    very

    illuminating,

    because he

    only

    pays

    attention

    to

    Anselm of

    Canterbury,

    Thomas

    Aquinas,

    and

    John

    Duns

    Scotus,

    none

    of whom

    wrote

    compre

    hensive

    treatises

    on

    akrasia}1

    Although

    the

    simplest

    explanation

    for this

    state

    of affairs

    might

    be

    that

    medieval

    texts

    are

    largely

    unknown

    to

    modern

    philosophers,

    per

    haps

    a

    more

    likely

    reason

    for

    it is the

    common

    prejudice

    that

    the

    Judaeo-Christian notion

    of 'free will' does

    not

    allow

    any proper

    philo

    sophical

    discussion of akrasia.

    According

    to this

    prejudice,

    akrasia has

    no

    special

    philosophical

    interest,

    since

    Christian

    psychology

    considers

    the

    will

    an

    autonomous

    faculty

    in human action. Such

    an

    autonomous

    faculty

    is

    not

    bound

    to

    any

    intellectual

    judgment;

    therefore

    the

    will

    need

    not

    obey

    reason's

    commands.12

    Although

    the Greek

    notion of 'will'

    certainly

    differs from its Judaeo

    Christian

    counterpart,

    the

    supposition

    of

    the above-named

    prejudice

    is

    proved

    historically

    false.

    In

    medieval

    Aristotelianism,

    e.g.,

    acting

    against

    one's

    better

    judgment

    was

    a

    difficult

    phenomenon

    to

    grasp

    philosophically,

    since it

    was

    commonly regarded

    that

    the

    will,

    being

    a

    rational

    capacity,

    follows

    the

    practical

    intellect. Aristotle's

    problems

    with

    akrasia

    are

    in

    fact

    discussed

    extensively

    in

    medieval

    commentar

    2.

    THE

    DEVELOPMENT

    OF AKRASIA IN MEDIEVAL

    THOUGHT

    2.1.

    Augustine's

    Two Wills :

    Doing

    Something Only Reluctantly

    The

    complete

    text

    of Aristotle's

    Ethics

    was

    introduced

    to

    Western

    philosophy by Robert Grosseteste

    in

    the

    1240s. Before that time

    Augus

    This content downloaded from 130.251.200.3 on Sun, 22 Dec 2013 08:35:30 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Buridan Davidson Akrasia

    4/22

    JOHN BURIDAN

    AND DONALD DAVIDSON

    ON

    AKRASIA

    135

    tinian

    psychology

    dominated the ethical

    discussion.14

    Although

    Augus

    tine

    (354-430)

    had

    no

    familiarity

    with

    Aristotle's

    ethical works and

    although

    he used the Latin

    term

    incontinentia

    only

    to

    denote the

    lack

    of

    chastity

    and

    temperance,15

    he

    often

    analyzed

    examples

    of moral

    conduct

    that

    are

    similar

    to

    those found

    in

    Nicomachean Ethics.

    In De

    spiritu

    et

    litera

    Augustine

    comes

    to

    the

    conclusion

    that

    good

    actions,

    if

    performed

    only

    unwillingly

    or

    reluctantly (invitus),

    do

    not

    count

    as

    true

    merits.

    If,

    for

    example,

    a

    person

    does

    something against

    his

    primary

    wishes

    only

    in order

    to

    avoid

    punishment,

    his

    action

    is

    not

    meritorious.16 Only if the person acts wholeheartedly does he receive

    the

    merit

    toward

    a

    true

    reward.

    Nonetheless,

    Augustine

    also

    asserts

    that

    by

    acting

    reluctantly

    a

    person

    can

    be held

    responsible

    for both his

    external

    act

    and his

    intention.17

    This reluctant

    acquiescence

    bears

    some

    analogy

    to

    Aristotle's

    enkrateia,

    since

    in

    both

    a

    person

    does

    something

    right

    and

    manages

    to

    thwart his evil desire

    to

    do otherwise.

    In his

    Confessiones Augustine

    speaks

    also

    of

    doing

    evil

    reluctantly.

    Immediately

    before his

    own

    conversion,

    the church father

    continued

    his bad habits

    only

    reluctantly,

    because his will could

    already

    see

    the

    right

    alternatives.18

    It

    is

    no

    wonder that

    some

    modern authors have

    seen here a counterpart to Aristotle's akrasia.19 But unlike Aristotle,

    Augustine

    thinks that the

    agent

    in

    some

    sense

    chooses

    his

    own

    inconti

    nent

    behavior,

    however reluctant

    this

    assent

    and

    choice20

    may

    be.

    Moreover,

    Augustine's

    psychological explanation

    of 'weakness

    of

    the

    will'

    differs

    significantly

    from

    Aristotle's doctrine.

    Augustine

    speaks

    of

    two

    wills

    struggling

    within the

    same

    person.

    He

    is

    not

    referring

    here

    to two autonomous

    wills,

    but rather

    to two

    initial tendencies of the

    human

    appetite.21

    He

    stresses

    that this

    disintegration

    of

    the motives

    takes

    place

    within

    the

    same

    mind and its

    single

    will.

    Moreover,

    the

    act

    of

    willful choice

    creates

    a

    unity

    and

    wholeness

    within

    the

    will.22

    Another

    important

    element in

    Augustine's thought

    is his view of the

    hierarchy

    of desired ends.

    The

    highest

    goals

    are

    to

    be

    willed for the

    sake of their

    own,

    inherent

    goodness.

    But

    some

    lower ends

    are

    to

    be

    willed

    only

    for

    the

    sake

    of the

    higher

    and

    final

    goals.23

    This distinction

    between

    willing something

    for its

    own

    sake

    (propter se)

    and

    for

    the

    sake of

    something

    else

    (propter aliud)

    will

    become

    an

    integral

    part

    of

    medieval discussions

    concerning

    akrasia.

    Augustine's

    model

    is

    further

    qualified by

    his

    theological

    presupposi

    tions. He tends

    to

    think

    that God is the

    only

    rational

    agent

    who

    never

    acts

    reluctantly.24 Moreover,

    his

    use

    of

    continentia is conditioned

    by

    This content downloaded from 130.251.200.3 on Sun, 22 Dec 2013 08:35:30 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Buridan Davidson Akrasia

    5/22

    136

    RISTO SAARINEN

    the

    Vulgate

    translation of

    Sapientia

    Salomonis

    8,

    21:

    And

    as

    I

    knew

    that

    I

    could

    not

    otherwise

    be

    continent,

    except

    God

    gave

    it .

    For

    Augustine,

    this

    verse

    is

    universally

    valid:

    no

    man

    can

    be

    continent

    without God's

    grace.25

    Thus in

    Augustinian theology

    the

    state

    of

    being

    'incontinent'

    (mainly

    in

    the

    realm

    of

    sexuality)

    becomes the

    fate of

    every

    human

    being. Although

    the

    Aristotelian

    scholastics

    gave up

    much

    of this

    Augustinian background,

    the

    presupposed

    universality

    of 'incon

    tinent' behavior

    is

    one

    reason

    why

    the

    topic

    was

    so

    extensively

    discussed

    in

    the later Middle

    Ages.

    2.2.

    Anselm and

    Abelard

    on

    Reluctant Actions

    In

    his De

    lib?rtate

    arbitrii Anselm

    of

    Canterbury (1033-1109)

    radicalizes

    Augustine's

    theory

    of will.

    For

    Anselm,

    the

    freedom of

    the will'

    (libertas arbitrii)

    does

    not

    imply

    the

    ability

    to

    sin

    but

    only

    the

    ability

    to

    carry

    forward rational

    decisions.

    The

    freedom of

    a

    rational

    being

    means

    acting

    in

    accordance

    with

    reason.26

    Anselm holds that

    a

    rational

    being

    can

    will

    irrational evil

    only

    so

    that he in

    principle

    could resist

    it

    (ut

    possit

    quidem

    nolle)27

    Because Anselm

    argues

    strongly

    that the

    freedom of the will is a rational

    capacity,

    we cannot

    explain

    our ir

    rational behavior

    against

    our

    better

    judgment

    by

    simply

    referring

    to

    this

    freedom.

    In

    this

    way

    the

    Augustinian

    theory

    of will

    becomes

    com

    patible

    with

    Anselm's

    intellectualistic

    action

    theory.

    In his

    Ethics,

    Scito

    teipsum,

    Peter Abelard

    (1079-1142)

    discusses

    what

    actually

    happens

    when

    people

    act

    reluctantly

    or

    against

    their

    better

    judgment.

    He

    wants

    to

    show

    that the actual

    committing

    of

    a

    sin

    does

    not

    increase its

    degree

    of

    sinfulness

    in

    respect

    to

    the

    mere

    consent

    to

    commit

    sin. This idea leads

    him

    to

    distinguish

    between

    'will' and

    'consent'.

    The

    distinction

    is

    relevant

    in

    examples

    that

    resemble Aristot

    le's

    akratic

    behavior.

    For

    instance,

    a man

    who

    falls

    into

    longing

    for

    a

    woman

    or

    for fruit

    that

    does

    not

    belong

    to

    him

    has

    the will which

    lacks

    consent .28

    Abelard

    is also

    interested

    in

    cases

    where the

    consent

    can

    be

    under

    stood

    as

    allowing

    something

    to

    happen

    for the

    sake of

    something

    else

    (propter

    aliud)

    that

    is

    actually

    willed.

    For

    example,

    if

    somebody

    bears

    a

    painful operation

    in

    order

    to

    be

    healed,

    we

    don't

    say

    that he

    wants

    the

    pain.

    He

    doesn't

    will

    it,

    but

    only

    allows

    it

    to

    happen

    for

    the

    sake

    of

    something

    else.

    Such

    behavior

    is for

    Abelard

    a

    passio ,

    in which

    a

    person endures what he does not will (quod

    non

    vult tol?rai) in

    This content downloaded from 130.251.200.3 on Sun, 22 Dec 2013 08:35:30 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Buridan Davidson Akrasia

    6/22

    JOHN BURIDAN

    AND DONALD DAVIDSON ON AKRASIA

    137

    order

    to

    reach

    something

    else.29

    The

    topic

    of

    willing

    propter

    aliud

    derives

    from

    Augustine,

    but Abelard

    interprets

    it

    as

    enduring

    or

    suffering ,

    in which the

    will

    orders itself

    to

    remain in

    a

    passive

    state.30

    2.3.

    The

    Semantics

    of

    Will

    in

    Peter

    of

    Poitiers

    Anselm's and

    Abelard's

    ideas

    are

    reflected

    in

    many

    twelfth-century

    discussions

    that aim

    at

    deepening

    the

    conceptual

    understanding

    of

    Au

    gustinian

    topics,

    such

    as

    acting reluctantly

    and

    willing something

    propter

    aliud.31 Some significant developments took place in the Sentendae of

    Peter of

    Poitiers

    (1130-1205).

    At least three

    distinct

    points

    are

    here

    of

    interest.

    One,

    Peter

    adheres

    to

    the Anselmian

    view that

    a

    rational

    being

    must

    always

    to

    some

    extent

    possess

    knowledge

    of the

    right.

    For

    him,

    the

    so

    called

    synteresis

    is

    the small

    spark

    of

    reason

    (scindllula

    rationis),

    which

    cannot

    be

    extinguished.32

    But

    if

    an

    evil

    person

    simply

    wills

    evil,

    how

    can we

    claim that his

    synteresis

    is

    still

    functioning?

    Peter solves

    this

    problem

    by

    distinguishing

    between

    counterfactual

    wishes

    (vellem)

    and actual

    willing

    (volo).

    Some counterfactual

    good

    wishes

    remain

    in

    the sinner, even if he doesn't actually want to do the right thing. So

    we

    can

    say

    that

    such

    people

    in

    some

    weak

    and counterfactual

    sense

    would like

    to

    behave

    rightly

    (vellet

    declinare

    a

    malo).33

    Two,

    another

    way

    of

    describing

    the

    plurality

    of

    desires within the

    same

    will

    is

    to

    say

    that

    some

    things

    are

    willed

    without

    qualification

    (simpliciter),

    whereas others

    are

    willed

    only

    if

    some

    pre-condition

    is

    present

    (cum

    quaedam

    conditione).

    For

    example,

    Peter

    says

    that

    we

    want

    the death

    of

    Christ

    not

    for its

    own

    sake but under the

    pre

    condition

    that

    it

    is

    part

    of

    God's

    salvatory

    plan.34

    Three,

    according

    to

    Peter,

    willing

    the antecedens

    does

    not

    necessarily

    imply

    that the

    consequens

    is also willed. In other

    words,

    N(p ?>q)

    and

    Wap

    together

    do

    not

    imply

    Waq

    (N

    =

    'it

    is

    necessary

    that',

    W= 'to

    will',

    Wap

    =

    'a

    wills

    that

    p')35

    Peter's

    example

    is

    classical: consider

    thatp

    stands for 'a is

    showing

    penitence'

    and

    q

    stands

    for

    'a has

    sinned'.

    Now

    N(p

    .-*

    q)

    is

    correctly

    formed,

    because sins

    cannot

    be

    repented

    unless

    they

    have been

    committed.

    However,

    it

    does

    not

    follow

    from

    a's

    willing

    to

    show

    penitence

    (Wap)

    that

    a

    wills

    to

    have sinned

    (Waq).36

    Points

    one

    and

    two

    above

    are

    sometimes

    connected

    in

    medieval

    discussions

    so

    that

    the

    counterfactual

    wishing

    (vellem,

    velleitas)

    is

    understood

    as

    readiness

    to

    will

    something

    under

    given pre-conditions

    This content downloaded from 130.251.200.3 on Sun, 22 Dec 2013 08:35:30 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Buridan Davidson Akrasia

    7/22

    138

    RISTO SAARINEN

    (promptitudo

    volendi

    sub

    conditione)

    31

    Point three

    above is

    very

    con

    troversial,

    because

    it

    seems

    to

    say

    that the

    side-effects

    of

    willing

    a

    goal

    are

    not

    necessarily

    themselves willed. This idea in

    turn

    leads

    to

    dis

    cussion about the

    possibility

    of

    doing

    evil

    to

    achieve

    good .38

    How

    ever,

    we

    will

    only

    here follow the

    results of Peter's

    analysis

    insofar

    they

    are

    relevant for the

    explanation

    of akrasia.

    2.4.

    Albert the Great and the

    Problem

    of

    Moral

    Certainty

    Albert the Great (1200-80) was the first Latin writer to treat compre

    hensively

    Aristotle's notion

    of

    akrasia. Albert

    was

    well trained both

    in

    Augustinian

    tradition and

    in

    Aristotle.

    His

    two

    commentaries

    on

    Nicomachean Ethics

    give

    a

    congenial

    picture

    of

    Aristotle's akrasia inso

    far

    as

    they

    teach

    that it is

    impossible

    to act

    against

    clear and

    distinct

    knowledge

    of

    a

    moral

    goal.39

    Albert

    preserves

    the

    Augustinian-Chris

    tian

    theological

    stance

    in

    his

    analysis by

    arguing

    that

    all sin

    is due

    more

    or

    less

    to

    ignorance.40

    He also

    recognizes

    the

    Aristotelian idea that the

    akrates

    acts

    against

    his

    own

    choice

    (elecdo,

    prohairesis).41

    In

    Augustin

    ian

    tradition,

    as we

    have

    seen,

    the

    reluctant actions

    were

    nevertheless

    due to a

    partial

    assent or choice.

    One of

    Albert's

    many

    original

    contributions

    in

    his discussion of akra

    sia

    is

    the

    distinction between various

    degrees

    of

    moral

    certainty.

    A

    historical

    happenstance

    aided

    him in

    making

    this

    distinction. The Latin

    translator of Nicomachean

    Ethics,

    Robert

    Grosse

    teste,

    rendered Aris

    totle's akribeia

    ( precision )

    as

    certitudo

    and his endoksos

    ( a

    reputable

    opinion )

    as

    probabilis.

    Thus,

    when the

    Greek

    philosopher

    in

    Nicoma

    chean Ethics 1104al-6 holds

    that

    an

    account

    of

    matters

    of conduct

    can

    be

    given only

    in

    outline

    and

    not

    precisely,

    Albert understands

    Aristotle

    to

    mean

    that

    the

    science

    of ethics does

    not

    possess

    the

    same

    degree

    of

    certainty

    (certitudo)

    as some

    other branches

    of

    science.42

    Moreover,

    Albert

    grasps

    the

    meaning

    of

    Aristotle's

    endoksa

    as

    implying

    that ethics

    does

    not

    attain strict

    demonstration,

    but

    must

    rely

    on

    reputable opin

    ions

    in

    a

    probabilist

    manner.43

    Before

    solving

    the

    problems

    connected

    with

    akrasia,

    Albert

    in

    his

    first

    commentary

    discusses

    whether ethics

    ever

    attains absolute

    certainty

    (certitudo)

    as

    presupposed

    in Aristotle's notion

    of

    scientia. Albert ad

    heres

    to

    the Aristotelian view

    that

    we

    have scientific

    knowledge

    of

    some

    universal

    principles

    of

    ethics,

    but the

    judgments

    concerning

    particular

    actions

    must

    remain

    opinions,

    because

    they

    are

    more

    or

    less

    probable

    This content downloaded from 130.251.200.3 on Sun, 22 Dec 2013 08:35:30 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Buridan Davidson Akrasia

    8/22

  • 8/9/2019 Buridan Davidson Akrasia

    9/22

    140

    RISTO

    SAARINEN

    theory

    in

    which the

    agent's thought

    and

    decision-making

    process

    is

    analyzed

    into three

    parts.

    Each

    of

    these

    parts

    causes

    some

    activation

    in

    the

    will. The

    first

    act

    of the will is the

    act

    of

    complacence

    and/or

    displacence

    (actus

    complacentiaeldisplicentiae),

    which

    emerges

    as a re

    sult of the

    primary

    judgment

    of the

    practical

    intellect.

    According

    to

    Buridan,

    this first

    act

    does

    not

    yet

    lead into action.

    Moreover,

    a

    plu

    rality

    of

    such

    acts

    which

    are

    incompossible

    in

    respect

    to

    their realization

    may

    reside

    simultaneously

    in

    the soul. As the first

    act

    is

    something

    like

    a

    passive

    reception

    of sense-data offered

    by

    the

    intellect,

    the will

    at

    this point possesses no freedom. The second act of the will is called the

    act

    of

    acceptation

    of

    refutation

    (actus acceptationis/refutationis).

    The

    freedom

    of

    the

    will

    pertains

    to

    its

    second

    act:

    it

    can

    either follow the

    action

    proposed

    by

    the intellect

    or

    it

    can

    defer

    its

    act.

    The third

    act

    is

    the external manifestation

    of

    the

    action

    (prosecutiolfuga).52

    Buridan's

    first and second

    acts

    of the will

    are

    rather

    analogous

    to

    the

    Stoic-Augustinian

    distinction between desire

    and

    consent.

    Moreover,

    he himself

    connects

    them with the volo-vellem distinction

    presented

    by

    Peter of

    Poitiers and others.

    The

    first

    act

    of the will is the

    hypothetical

    velleitas;

    only

    the

    second

    act

    can

    be called the

    act

    of

    the

    will in

    a

    proper

    sense.53

    In the seventh book

    of his

    commentary

    Buridan defines enkrateia

    (continentia)

    as a

    moral

    disposition

    that

    helps

    us

    to

    stick

    to

    right

    reason

    and

    thus

    to

    resist the

    passions suggesting

    deviant behavior.

    But these

    passions

    cause

    an

    additional

    resisting

    impulse,

    namely,

    that

    of

    the

    first

    act

    of the will

    (displicentia),

    to

    become

    connected

    with

    our

    actual

    behavior.54

    Correspondingly,

    in akratic behavior the

    resisting

    displac

    ency

    defending right

    reason

    remains

    in

    some

    sense

    within the

    agent.55

    According

    to

    Buridan,

    akrasia and enkrateia

    occur

    in situations

    in

    which

    two

    or

    more

    conflicting,

    simultaneous

    first

    acts

    of the will

    are

    active within

    the

    agent's

    mind. The

    incompossible

    alternatives A and

    B

    are

    both

    presented

    to

    the

    agent

    sub ratione

    boni, i.e.,

    as

    being

    desirable.

    Buridan

    calls this

    a

    situation of double

    inclination

    (inclina

    tio

    duplex).56

    Buridan

    shares

    the

    view of Albert and

    of Aristotle

    that it is

    impossible

    to act

    against

    knowledge

    of the

    good

    in

    the

    strict

    sense

    (scientia

    per

    fecta).

    Such

    'clear-eyed

    akrasia' is

    impossible.

    But he

    repeatedly

    stresses

    that in

    practical

    decision-making

    the

    agent

    normally

    does

    not

    possess

    such

    perfect

    scientia but

    operates

    within

    a

    framework of

    conflicting

    reasons.57 It is

    no

    wonder, therefore, that he pays attention

    to

    the

    This content downloaded from 130.251.200.3 on Sun, 22 Dec 2013 08:35:30 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Buridan Davidson Akrasia

    10/22

    JOHN BURIDAN

    AND DONALD DAVIDSON ON AKRASIA

    141

    decision-making

    process

    in situations of 'double inclination'.

    Buridan's

    main

    interest

    in his discussion of akrasia

    is

    directed toward

    situations

    marred with

    some

    ambiguity.

    He thus refines Albert's

    concept

    of moral

    certainty.

    Double

    inclination

    makes

    akratic

    judgment

    weak

    (iudicium

    debile

    seu

    formidinale).

    Accordingly,

    the second and

    proper

    act

    of the

    will,

    the

    act

    of

    acceptation,

    also remains

    weak

    (acceptatio

    debilis).58

    The

    weakness

    of

    the akratic

    judgment

    can

    be

    seen

    in the fact

    that

    the

    two

    inclinations

    become

    successively

    actual

    in

    the akratic

    person:

    after

    committing sin he suffers regret.59 Like Albert, Buridan too develops

    a

    gradation

    of moral

    certainty

    and concludes that it is

    impossible

    to act

    against

    a

    completed

    judgment

    (iudicium completum).

    In

    order

    to

    explain

    what

    a

    completed

    judgment

    is,

    Buridan

    presents

    a

    fourfold

    gradation

    of

    completion

    in

    judgment.

    In

    judging

    between

    A

    and

    B,

    the

    weakest

    case

    arises

    (1)

    when

    no reason

    supports

    either

    A

    or

    B;

    another

    weak

    case

    arises

    (2)

    when

    equal

    reasons

    support

    both

    A and B. In the

    third

    case

    (3)

    there

    is

    a

    stronger

    reason

    for A

    than

    for

    B;

    but

    some

    other

    reason

    nevertheless

    promotes

    B.

    For

    Buridan,

    even

    the

    judgment

    concerning

    this

    third

    case

    remains weak

    and

    incomplete.

    Only

    in

    case

    (4), where all doubts, however small, are removed, can we reach a

    completed

    judgment.

    In this

    case,

    A

    is

    categorically supported

    over

    B.60

    Buridan also

    speaks

    of

    uncertain

    (dubium)

    and certain

    (certum)

    judgments. Only

    when

    a

    judgment

    possesses

    absolute

    certainty

    is it

    not

    possible

    to

    act

    against

    it.

    But

    if there is

    any

    reason,

    however

    small and

    insignificant,

    against

    a

    judgment

    concerning

    the

    probable right,

    it

    is

    possible

    to

    act

    akratically.61

    Buridan's

    emphasis

    on

    the

    uncertainty

    of moral

    judgments

    is

    con

    nected with

    his

    idea

    that

    the will's freedom consists

    mainly

    in its

    capacity

    to withdraw its own act. Buridan shares the medieval view that the free

    will is

    a

    rational

    capacity.

    But

    then it would be

    highly misleading

    to

    say

    that

    the

    will's freedom

    is

    the

    source

    of irrational

    behavior. There

    fore,

    the

    free

    will

    never

    resists the

    rational

    judgments

    of

    the

    intellect.62

    We

    already

    saw

    that Peter Abelard

    and Albert the

    Great

    regarded

    the

    will's

    consent to not

    doing

    anything

    as

    useful

    in

    some

    situations.

    Buridan

    cultivates

    this view and

    makes it

    a

    cornerstone

    of

    his action

    theory.63

    He does

    not

    consider the

    will's

    decision

    to

    remain

    passive

    as

    an

    irrational

    liberty,

    but

    argues

    that

    in

    cases

    of double

    inclination

    it

    is

    often

    the

    most

    rational choice.

    This

    rationality

    is founded

    in the

    nature

    This content downloaded from 130.251.200.3 on Sun, 22 Dec 2013 08:35:30 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Buridan Davidson Akrasia

    11/22

    142

    RISTO SAARINEN

    of

    practical

    decision-making:

    Buridan

    says

    that it is

    often better

    not to

    choose

    to act

    too

    rapidly,

    because

    what

    seems

    good

    prima

    facie

    might

    prove

    to

    be

    wrong

    after

    thorough

    consideration.

    It

    is

    difficult

    to

    see

    the latent

    consequences

    of

    practical

    decisions;

    therefore it is

    useful

    to

    possess

    the

    capacity

    of

    delaying

    the actual decision for

    a

    while.64

    Impor

    tant

    decisions, however,

    should

    not

    be

    delayed

    too

    long.65

    The

    capacity

    to

    postpone

    the will-act is thus for Buridan

    an

    aspect

    of

    prudential66

    behavior. Because

    our

    estimations

    of moral

    situations

    remain

    incomplete

    and

    our

    practical

    judgments

    weak,

    it is

    often

    pruden

    tial to postpone a decision. Moreover, in his discussion of prima facie

    willing something

    Buridan

    seems

    to

    adopt

    the above-mentioned view

    of Peter of

    Poitiers,

    according

    to

    which

    we

    often will

    something

    without

    necessarily willing

    all

    of the

    consequences.

    For

    Buridan,

    the

    pruden

    tiality

    of

    withdrawing

    the will-act derives from

    the fact that it offers

    the

    possibility

    of

    investigating

    whether the

    agent

    in

    fact

    wants

    all

    the

    implied

    consequences.

    We

    have

    already

    seen

    that the akratic man's

    judgment

    is weak

    and

    uncertain

    (debile, dubium).

    Buridan

    adheres

    to

    the Aristotelian view

    that the

    akratic

    intellect

    is somehow

    captured

    by

    the

    passions.

    But,

    in

    addition to that, with the

    help

    of his idea that the freedom of the will

    consists

    in

    its

    possibility

    to

    defer

    its

    own

    act,

    he also

    develops

    another

    way

    of

    understanding

    akratic action.

    If

    the

    agent

    in

    the

    case

    of conflict

    ing

    alternatives and weak

    judgment postpones

    his

    decision for the sake

    of

    reflection,

    the

    judgment

    attains

    greater

    certainty,

    until

    most

    doubts

    have been

    extinguished,

    at

    which

    time

    it

    has become

    as

    certain

    as

    possible.

    Only

    then is it

    prudential

    to

    act

    in accordance

    with

    it.67

    Buridan

    seems

    to

    think that

    passion

    causes

    the

    agent

    to

    act

    hastily,

    that

    is,

    without

    paying

    enough

    respect

    to

    the eventual

    consequences

    of

    the action.

    The

    weak

    judgment

    would have

    gained

    more

    certainty,

    if

    passion

    had

    given

    the

    agent

    enough

    time

    to

    weigh

    the

    evidence

    pro

    perly.

    This

    is also the

    reason

    why

    the akratic

    man

    later

    repents:

    after

    the

    passion

    has

    extinguished

    itself,

    the

    consequences

    become

    evident,

    which

    affords

    rational

    consideration.68

    Buridan

    certainly

    does

    not

    mean

    that all

    ambiguities

    can

    be

    removed

    by

    proper

    consideration

    of

    a

    moral situation. On the

    contrary,

    he

    is

    likely

    to

    think that

    in

    most

    cases

    we

    do

    not

    reach absolute

    certainty

    and often

    simply

    have

    to

    make

    judgments

    in

    the

    context

    of

    ambiguous

    situations. But false

    judgments

    in

    totally ambiguous

    situations,

    if

    made

    after

    proper

    moral

    consideration,

    are

    not

    instances of

    akrasia.69

    This content downloaded from 130.251.200.3 on Sun, 22 Dec 2013 08:35:30 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Buridan Davidson Akrasia

    12/22

    JOHN BURIDAN AND DONALD DAVIDSON ON AKRASIA

    143

    In

    sum,

    we

    can

    say

    that Buridan

    employs

    Aristotle's

    concept

    of

    akrasia

    as a

    framework for

    analyzing

    what

    happens

    in

    uncertain moral

    situations.

    He

    defends

    Aristotelian

    intellectualism

    by

    claiming

    that free

    dom of the will

    as

    such

    does

    not

    imply

    that

    free action

    is

    irrational

    behavior.

    But

    Buridan's

    discussion is non-Aristotelian

    in

    the

    sense

    that the

    gradation

    of moral

    certainty

    is

    not

    relevant for the Greek

    philosopher.

    Like Socrates and

    Aristotle,

    Buridan

    denies

    the

    possibility

    of

    'clear-eyed'

    akrasia,

    but

    he

    is

    in

    fact

    more

    interested

    in

    the akratic

    behavior that

    occurs

    in

    situations

    of

    conflicting

    alternatives.

    In

    these

    situations, akrasia is due to weak judgment influenced by passion.

    4.

    'medieval'

    elements

    in

    Davidson's

    explanation

    of

    akrasia

    4.1.

    The Distinction between

    Prima

    Facie and Unconditional

    Judgments

    It is

    not

    my

    aim here

    to

    outline

    wholly

    Donald Davidson's

    argument

    in

    How is

    Weakness

    of

    the

    Will

    Possible?,

    nor

    will I

    go

    into

    the details

    of

    the

    far-reaching

    recent

    discussion of Davidson's

    ideas.70

    I

    will

    simply

    list some of the ideas that to my view have their obvious counterparts

    in

    the medieval discussion.

    Donald

    Davidson

    argues

    that

    it

    is

    possible

    to

    perform

    an

    akratic

    action while

    judging

    that,

    all

    things

    considered,

    it would be

    better

    not

    to

    do it than

    to

    do

    it.

    Moreover,

    Davidson holds that the existence of

    such akrasia

    is

    compatible

    with the

    principle

    (which

    he calls

    P2)

    that

    [i]f

    an

    agent

    judges

    that

    it would

    be

    better

    to

    do

    x

    than

    to

    do

    y,

    then

    he

    wants to

    do

    x

    more

    than he

    wants to

    do

    y .71

    Davidson makes the existence of akrasia

    compatible

    with P2

    by

    distinguishing

    between

    prima

    facie (conditional,

    'all-things-considered')

    judgments

    and unconditional

    (sans

    phrase,

    absolute)

    judgments.72

    He

    argues

    that the

    akrates

    operates

    with

    prima facie

    judgments

    in

    the

    sense

    that both the

    reasons

    for and

    against

    an

    action in

    question

    and the

    resulting

    decision

    are

    not

    unconditional

    and

    absolute,

    but

    only

    'all

    things-considered'

    (prima facie)

    judgments.

    But

    the

    judgment

    pre

    supposed

    in

    P2

    is

    absolute.73

    He further holds that

    reasoning

    that

    stops

    at

    conditional

    judg

    ments

    ...

    is

    practical

    only

    in its

    subject,

    not

    in

    its

    issue .74

    By

    this

    he

    means

    that

    the

    agent's

    prima

    facie thoughts

    concerning

    an

    action do

    not

    necessarily

    materialize

    as

    actions. As such

    they

    differ

    from absolute

    This content downloaded from 130.251.200.3 on Sun, 22 Dec 2013 08:35:30 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Buridan Davidson Akrasia

    13/22

    144

    RISTO

    SAARINEN

    judgments,

    which,

    if

    used

    in

    practical

    syllogisms,

    have the

    proposed

    action

    as

    their

    conclusion.75

    Of

    course

    there

    is

    something

    irrational

    in

    akratic

    behavior,

    since it

    is

    nevertheless odd

    to act

    against

    one's best

    all-things-considered

    judgment.76

    But

    akratic actions

    are

    not

    logically

    impossible,

    because

    a

    prima

    facie

    judgment

    does

    not

    compel

    the action

    to

    materialize. Therefore Davidson

    can

    conclude that

    there is

    no

    (logical)

    difficulty

    in the fact of

    incontinence,

    for the

    akrates is characterized

    as

    holding

    that,

    all

    things

    considered,

    it

    would be

    better

    to

    do b than

    to

    do

    a,

    even

    though

    he

    does

    a

    rather

    than

    b

    and with

    a reason.

    The logical difficulty

    has

    vanished

    because

    the

    judgement

    that

    a

    is better than

    b,

    all

    things

    considered,

    is

    a

    relational,

    or

    pf

    [prima facie], judgement,

    and

    so

    cannot

    conflict

    logically

    with

    any

    unconditional

    judgement.77

    We have

    seen

    that

    Buridan,

    too,

    uses78

    the

    expression

    prima

    facie

    in

    describing

    the moral situation that arises after the first

    act

    of

    the

    will

    has

    produced

    some

    interior

    motion,

    that

    is,

    when

    some

    desires have

    emerged.

    It would be

    highly

    anachronistic,

    of

    course,

    to

    maintain

    that

    Buridan's

    use

    of the

    term

    prima

    facie

    is

    synonymous

    with that of

    Davidson.

    But

    the

    interesting

    thing

    to

    notice here

    is

    that Buridan

    also

    makes a clear distinction between

    imperfect

    (iudicium

    debile, iudicium

    incertum)

    and

    perfect

    judgments

    (iudicium

    completum,

    certum),

    and

    holds that

    akrasia

    only

    occurs

    in

    situations

    in

    which the

    judgment

    is

    imperfect.

    With

    the

    help

    of this distinction Buridan extends

    Aristotle's

    discussion

    to

    moral situations

    in

    which

    reaching

    perfect

    judgment

    is

    difficult.

    This

    'extended'

    view of

    akrasia,

    which

    is

    already

    present

    in

    Albert

    the

    Great,

    has

    many

    affinities

    with

    Davidson's discussion of

    prima

    facie

    judgments.

    In

    the

    eighth question

    of Book

    VII

    Buridan

    asks,

    e.g.,

    whether the

    will

    necessarily

    follows the

    practical

    intellect. He ascribes different

    degrees

    of

    certainty

    to

    different

    judgments,

    and

    concludes that the

    will

    necessarily

    follows

    only

    the

    most

    certain

    ones.79

    We

    have

    already

    no

    ticed that Buridan

    does

    not

    say very

    clearly

    whether

    we ever

    in

    fact

    attain

    judgments

    possessing

    absolute

    certainty

    (iudicium certum).

    And

    the

    same

    problem

    pertains

    to

    the work

    of

    Davidson;

    it is evident

    that

    in

    inductive

    reasoning

    even

    the best

    judgments

    remain

    'all-things

    considered'

    judgments.80

    Buridan

    and Davidson

    differ,

    of

    course,

    in

    how

    they

    employ

    the

    distinction

    between

    perfect

    and

    imperfect judgments.

    Whereas

    David

    son

    describes

    akratic behavior

    as

    an

    irrational

    course

    of action left

    open

    This content downloaded from 130.251.200.3 on Sun, 22 Dec 2013 08:35:30 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Buridan Davidson Akrasia

    14/22

    JOHN

    BURIDAN

    AND DONALD

    DAVIDSON

    ON

    AKRASIA

    145

    because of the

    uncompelling

    nature

    of

    prima

    facie

    judgments,

    Buridan

    elaborates

    a

    peculiar

    dynamics

    of the will.

    According

    to

    him,

    in

    situ

    ations

    lacking

    certainty

    the

    will

    can

    be

    directed

    to

    various alternatives

    because

    the

    intellect has

    not

    excluded

    them;

    therefore

    a

    type

    of

    akrasia

    (though

    not

    'clear-eyed'

    akrasia)

    is

    possible.

    But

    although

    these

    expla

    nations

    differ,

    they

    both

    presuppose

    a

    distinction

    between

    prima

    facie

    and

    definitive

    practical

    judgments.

    Moreover,

    Davidson remarks that it is

    not

    enough

    to

    know the

    reasons

    on

    each

    side:

    he

    [the

    agent]

    must

    know how

    they

    add

    up .

    And he claims that this cannot be done in

    a

    syllogistic way.81 Thus, he

    stresses

    the

    prima

    facie

    character of

    even

    the

    best

    'all-things-considered'

    judgments.

    In

    holding

    that

    no

    logical

    calculus

    can

    determine

    the

    out

    come

    of moral

    reasoning

    in

    complex

    situations,

    Davidson

    approaches

    Buridan's view that the

    so-called 'weak

    judgment'

    does

    not

    guarantee

    the

    Tightness

    of the

    outcome

    of the action.

    4.2.

    Prima Facie

    Judgments

    as

    Conditional

    Judgments

    We have

    seen

    that

    Davidson also calls his

    prima

    facie

    judgments

    'con

    ditional'. In his article

    'Intending'

    Davidson concludes that

    [w]ants,

    desires,

    principles, prejudices,

    felt

    duties,

    and

    obligations

    provide

    reasons

    for

    actions and

    intentions,

    and

    are

    expressed

    by

    prima

    facie

    judgements;

    intentions and the

    judgements

    that

    go

    with

    intentional actions

    are

    distinguished

    by

    their all-out

    or

    uncon

    ditional

    form.82

    From

    this it

    again

    becomes clear that

    an

    unconditional

    judgment

    is

    a

    final

    statement

    concerning

    the

    whole of the situation

    under consider

    ation.

    It

    yields

    intentional

    actions,

    whereas

    prima

    facie

    judgments

    are

    valid

    only

    relative

    to

    their

    reasons.

    The

    suggested

    unconditional

    con

    clusion of the practical syllogism, i.e. the action, is not 'detachable'

    from the

    prima

    facie

    reasons

    supporting

    and

    opposing

    it. Davidson

    wants to

    point

    out

    that

    [w]e

    can

    hardly expect

    to

    learn

    whether

    an

    action

    ought

    to

    be

    performed simply

    from

    the

    fact

    that

    it

    is both

    prima

    facie

    right

    and

    prima

    facie

    wrong

    ....

    ...

    if

    we

    are

    to

    have

    a

    coherent

    theory

    of

    practical

    reason,

    we

    must

    give

    up

    the idea

    that

    we

    can

    detach

    conclusions about what

    is

    desirable

    (or better)

    or

    obligatory

    from

    the

    principles

    that

    lend those

    conclusions

    colour.83

    This line

    of

    thought

    has

    similarities with

    the

    action-theoretical

    role

    of

    the

    counterfactual,

    or

    conditional, willing

    as

    developed by

    Peter

    of

    This content downloaded from 130.251.200.3 on Sun, 22 Dec 2013 08:35:30 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Buridan Davidson Akrasia

    15/22

    146

    RISTO SAARINEN

    Poitiers

    and used

    by

    Buridan. The

    wants

    and desires that

    are

    recognized

    but

    not

    carried forward

    can

    be

    explained

    as

    counterfactual,

    or con

    ditional,

    judgments.

    In this

    sense

    Peter

    of

    Poitiers's

    example

    of the

    sinner who

    says

    that he

    counterfactually

    wishes

    (vellet)

    to

    abstain

    from

    sin

    would

    be

    an

    instance of

    Davidson's

    prima

    facie

    judgment.84

    Simi

    larly,

    in

    Buridan's

    example

    a

    continent

    man

    is asked

    whether he

    wants

    to

    fornicate.

    He

    answers

    that he

    wants

    it

    only conditionally (non

    respon

    debit

    vol? ,

    sed dicet

    vellem ),

    namely,

    only

    under the

    counterfactual

    pre-condition

    that

    it

    were

    not

    sinful. In Buridan's

    analysis

    this

    answer

    means that there exists a first act of the will supporting the fornication.

    However,

    no

    conclusion

    is detached from that

    conditional

    judgment,

    and

    the

    second

    act

    of the will

    refutes

    it.85

    It

    looks

    as

    though

    both Davidson

    and

    Buridan

    in

    fact

    operate

    accord

    ing

    to

    a

    kind

    of

    distinction between desire

    and

    assent,

    in which

    the

    desires

    are

    prima

    facie

    evaluations

    conditioned

    by

    the

    respective

    rea

    sons.

    This conditional

    (prima facie)

    evaluation does

    not

    lead

    to

    action;

    the actual

    assent

    can

    be

    described

    as

    the 'second act' of the

    agent's

    mind,

    emerging

    as

    the result of

    an

    unconditional

    judgment.

    4.3.

    Reasoning

    from

    Prima

    Facie

    Judgment

    as an

    Instance

    of

    Reasoning from

    Probabilistic

    Evidence

    Davidson also remarks

    that moral

    reasoning

    on

    the

    basis

    o?

    prima

    facie

    judgments

    has

    an

    analogy

    with

    reasoning

    from

    probabilistic

    evi

    dence.86

    Without

    entering

    the fallacies shown and re-formulations

    undertaken

    by

    Davidson

    here,87

    we

    note

    that

    his

    understanding

    is

    not

    far

    from how

    Albert the Great and Buridan

    also

    understood the

    nature

    of moral

    reasoning.

    In

    ethics

    we

    proceed

    ex

    probabilibus

    (Aristotle's

    reputable

    opinions ),

    and

    although

    this

    expression

    does

    not

    yet pre

    suppose

    any

    elaborate

    theory

    concerning

    probabilities,

    it

    is

    already

    evident that for Albert

    and Buridan it

    implies

    that

    our

    moral

    judgments

    are

    conditioned

    by

    finite

    reasons

    and,

    therefore,

    lack absolute

    certainty.

    The

    same

    analogy

    is

    also

    visible in Davidson's

    principle of

    continence,

    which

    asserts

    that

    we

    should

    perform

    the

    action

    judged

    best

    on

    the

    basis

    of all available relevant

    reasons.88

    For

    Davidson,

    this

    directive

    is

    analogous

    to

    the so-called

    requirement

    of total evidence for inductive

    reasoning,

    which

    states

    that

    we

    should

    give

    our

    credence

    to

    the

    hypo

    thesis

    supported

    by

    all available relevant

    evidence. Just

    as

    this latter

    maxim is

    not

    part of the logic of inductive reasoning but

    a

    directive the

    This content downloaded from 130.251.200.3 on Sun, 22 Dec 2013 08:35:30 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Buridan Davidson Akrasia

    16/22

    JOHN

    BURIDAN

    AND DONALD DAVIDSON ON AKRASIA

    147

    rational

    man

    will

    accept,

    so

    the

    principle

    of continence

    has

    no

    compel

    ling logical

    force,

    though

    it

    is

    nevertheless

    a

    guideline

    of rational be

    havior.

    When the akratic

    person

    acts

    against

    his

    own

    'all-things-con

    sidered'

    best

    judgment,

    he is

    not

    breaking

    any

    syllogistic

    structure

    but

    only

    this directive

    principle.89

    Davidson's

    principle

    of continence has

    some

    resemblance

    to

    what

    we

    might

    call Buridan's directive

    of

    prudentiality,

    which

    asserts

    that

    a

    pru

    dent

    man

    should

    postpone

    his

    decision

    until

    all

    relevant

    considerations

    have

    been

    completed.90

    As

    we

    have

    seen,

    Buridan considers the will's

    postponement of its will-act

    as

    prudential just because it gives

    an

    oppor

    tunity

    to

    collect

    and

    to

    weigh

    properly

    more

    evidence.

    Davidson's

    principle

    of continence and Buridan's directive of

    pruden

    tiality

    are

    meaningful only

    if

    we

    consider

    the

    ethical

    decision-making

    process

    as

    analogical

    with

    reasoning

    from

    probabilistic

    evidence. David

    son's

    important point

    in

    stressing

    this

    analogy

    is that

    we

    need

    to

    know

    in ethics

    as

    well

    how the

    different

    reasons

    'add

    up'.

    In

    other

    words,

    besides Aristotle's deductive model

    of

    the

    practical syllogism,

    ethical

    thinking

    needs

    to

    be

    supported

    by

    some

    kind

    of

    inductive

    logic

    of

    decision-making.

    When

    Albert the

    Great

    and

    Buridan consider ethics

    as proceeding ex probabilibus, they are recognizing that inductive think

    ing

    is

    necessary

    in

    situations

    permeated

    with

    a

    plurality

    of,

    more or

    less,

    probable

    prima facie

    reasons.

    NOTES

    1

    First

    published

    1970.

    We

    use

    the

    1980

    edition,

    as

    reprinted

    with

    corrections

    (1982).

    2

    Recent

    bibliographies

    of

    the

    modern historical and

    philosophical

    discussion

    of Aristot

    le's akrasia

    are

    Mele

    (1987,

    pp.

    172-80),

    Charlton

    (1988,

    pp.

    185-91),

    and

    Gosling

    (1990,

    pp.

    210-12).

    These

    three

    monographs

    also offer

    a

    general

    survey

    on

    the

    most

    important

    studies.

    3

    For

    Socrates'

    position,

    see,

    e.g.,

    Charlton

    (1988,

    pp.

    13-33).

    For

    Aristotle's

    view,

    cf.

    Charles

    (1984).

    4

    Cf.

    Mortimore

    (1971);

    Vermazen

    and Hintikka

    (1985);

    Mele

    (1987).

    5

    See

    Broadie

    and

    Pybus (1982);

    Hintikka

    (1988);

    Gosling (1990).

    6

    We will

    use

    the

    expressions

    akrasia ,

    incontinence ,

    and

    weakness

    of the will

    as

    synonymous.

    7

    Perhaps

    the

    most

    interesting

    medieval discussions

    on

    akrasia

    are

    found

    in

    the

    two

    commentaries of Albert the Great

    (1891;

    1987),

    as

    well

    as

    inWalter

    Burley's

    (1521)

    and

    John Buridan's

    (1968)

    commentaries. In

    my

    forthcoming study,

    Weakness

    of

    the Will

    in

    Medieval

    Thought,

    these

    commentaries

    will be

    analyzed.

    8

    Gosling (1990, p. 3).

    This content downloaded from 130.251.200.3 on Sun, 22 Dec 2013 08:35:30 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Buridan Davidson Akrasia

    17/22

    148

    RISTO

    SAARINEN

    9

    See Kent

    (1984,

    pp.

    269-331;

    1989),

    Krieger

    (1986,

    pp.

    184-92),

    and Saarinen

    (1986).

    10

    Gosling

    (1990,

    pp.

    69-86).

    11

    For

    Aquinas,

    see

    Kent

    (1989).

    In

    my

    opinion,

    the relevant

    problem

    for Anselm

    and

    Scotus

    was

    not

    the 'fall of the devil' described

    by

    Gosling

    (1990,

    pp.

    74-86),

    but

    rather

    the

    problem

    of

    doing

    something only reluctantly,

    or

    with the

    help

    of

    some

    'probable'

    reasons.

    For

    this,

    see

    below and Scotus

    (1968:

    Opus

    oxon.

    Ill,

    d.

    36,

    q.

    1).

    12

    This

    line

    of

    thought

    is

    consequently

    followed

    by

    Charlton

    (1988,

    e.g.,

    pp.

    5-7,

    177).

    13

    This

    is

    contrary

    to

    Charlton

    (1988,

    p.

    7),

    who

    claims that

    Western

    European

    Philos

    ophy

    has little

    to

    show

    on

    the

    subject

    of

    weakness

    of will

    before

    the

    present

    century .

    According

    to

    Kent

    (1984,

    p.

    295),

    even

    the medieval Franciscan literature

    on

    inconti

    nence can

    only

    be described

    as

    voluminous .

    14

    Cf.

    Wieland

    (1982).

    15

    Cf. Zumkeller

    (1986,

    p.

    35).

    As

    Zumkeller

    points

    out,

    Augustine

    got

    the notion

    of

    continentia

    from

    Cicero.

    16

    De

    spiritu

    et

    litera,

    8.13

    and 31.53.56. See

    Augustine

    (1844-: Patrolog?a

    latina,

    Vol.

    44,

    pp.

    207-08,

    234,

    236-37).

    17

    Cf.,

    e.g.,

    De

    sermone

    Domini

    in

    monte,

    11.17.54-55

    (Patrolog?a

    latina,

    Vol.

    34,

    p.

    1294).

    18

    Cf.

    Confessiones,

    VIII.5.11-12. For

    an

    English

    translation,

    cf.

    Bourke

    (1966).

    19

    E.g.,

    Charlton

    (1988,

    pp.

    5-6)

    and

    Gosling (1990,

    p.

    70).

    20

    Cf.,

    e.g.,

    Confessiones,

    VIII. 5.11-12.

    Augustine

    is

    not

    influenced

    by

    Aristotle's

    prohairesis

    (choice),

    but

    by

    the

    Stoic distinction between

    (animal)

    desire and

    (rational)

    assent/consent.

    For this

    distinction

    and its

    later

    Christian

    use

    see,

    e.g.,

    Lapidge

    (1988,

    pp.

    90-98).

    For

    Augustine's

    Stoicism, cf. Colish

    (1985,

    II, pp.

    142-218).

    21

    Cf. Bourke

    (1966,

    p.

    207).

    22

    Confessiones,

    VIII. 10.24.

    23

    A

    paradigmatic

    case

    is

    Augustine's

    exposition

    of the Sermon

    on

    the

    Mount,

    where

    the

    church

    father concludes

    that the

    temporal things

    are

    to

    be

    willed

    only

    for the sake

    of the eternal

    goal (De

    sermone

    Domini

    in

    monte,

    11.17.56:

    Patrolog?a

    latina,

    Vol.

    34,

    p.

    1294).

    24

    Confessiones,

    VII.4.6.

    25

    Scivi

    quoniam

    aliter

    non

    possem

    esse

    continens

    nisi

    Deus

    det . The

    translation

    is

    from

    Wolfson

    (1965,

    p.

    167),

    who

    counts

    over

    twenty

    references

    to

    this

    verse

    in

    Augustine.

    See

    also Zumkeller

    (1986,

    pp.

    35,

    39).

    26

    Anselm

    (1938,

    pp. 213-14).

    Cf.

    also

    p.

    207.3:

    Potestas

    peccandi

    non

    pertineat

    ad

    libertatem

    arbitrii .

    27

    Anselm

    (1938,

    p.

    217.26-32).

    28

    Peter

    Abelard

    (1971,

    pp.

    24-25).

    In

    another

    example (pp.

    24-25),

    a man

    who

    kills

    his

    master

    in self-defense has

    an

    evil

    consent

    without evil will.

    29

    Ibid.

    (pp.

    8.26-10.21).

    30

    In

    medieval

    Latin,

    non

    vol?

    refers

    to

    a

    passive

    state,

    whereas nolo denotes

    a

    case

    of

    active resistance.

    31

    See

    Knuuttila and

    Holopainen

    (1993).

    32

    Sent.

    11.14.

    Peter

    of

    Poitiers

    (1950-61,

    p.

    98.256-64).

    For

    synteresis ,

    see,

    e.g.,

    Baylor (1977).

    This content downloaded from 130.251.200.3 on Sun, 22 Dec 2013 08:35:30 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Buridan Davidson Akrasia

    18/22

    JOHN

    BURIDAN

    AND DONALD

    DAVIDSON

    ON

    AKRASIA

    149

    33

    Sent. 11.14. Peter of Poitiers

    (1950-61,

    p.

    98.271-84).

    34

    Sent. 11.17. Peter of Poitiers

    (1950-61,

    p.

    124.84-91).

    See also

    Sent.

    IV.16 for

    the

    example

    of

    wanting

    the

    death of Christ: Peter of Poitiers

    (1855,

    pp.

    1200-02).

    35

    Sent. 1.9. Peter of Poitiers

    (1950-61,

    p.

    83.141-44):

    Solvunt dicentes

    non

    accidere

    quod

    si

    aliquid

    antecedat

    ad

    aliud,

    et

    aliquis

    vult vel

    potest

    antecedens,

    quod

    ideo velit

    vel

    possit

    consequens.

    .

    . .

    Here the

    view is

    presented

    as mere

    opinion

    ( dicunt

    quid

    am ),

    but in

    his

    discussion of the

    two

    wills in

    Christ

    (Sent.

    IV.16:

    1855,

    pp.

    1199-1202),

    Peter

    adopts

    this

    view.

    36

    Sent. IV.16. Peter of Poitiers

    (1855,

    p.

    1199).

    37

    E.g.,

    inWilliam

    of

    Auxerre's

    Summa

    ?urea,

    I,

    XII,

    4,

    q.

    3

    (1980-86,

    pp.

    235-36).

    38

    Cf.,

    e.g.,

    McCormick

    and

    Ramsey

    (1978).

    39

    Albert

    (first commentary: 1987, pp. 532-36;

    second

    commentary: 1891, pp. 474-76).40

    Albert

    (1891,

    pp.

    206-07;

    1987,

    pp.

    523-24).

    He

    here

    (1987,

    p.

    523.45-47)

    considers

    this view

    as

    wholly

    in

    keeping

    with

    Augustine.

    Cf.

    Augustine's

    De

    duabus

    animabus,

    6.6

    (Patrolog?a

    latina,

    Vol.

    42,

    p.

    98).

    41

    Albert

    (1891,

    pp.

    214-19).

    42

    Ibid.

    (pp.

    53-54).

    43

    For

    example,

    Albert

    (1891,

    p.

    54)

    compares

    the

    certainty

    of rhetorics with that of

    ethics.

    Later,

    Albert

    (p.

    176)

    concludes

    that

    the

    knowledge

    of the

    virtues

    is

    less certain

    than

    the

    knowledge

    of

    nature,

    but

    more

    certain

    than

    knowledge pertaining

    to

    the technical

    artes.

    44

    Albert

    (1987,

    p.

    523.48-59).

    45

    Ibid.

    (p.

    523.61-73).

    Aristotle,

    Rhetorics

    I.

    2,

    14

    (1357a-b).

    46

    Albert

    (1987,

    p.

    530.21-22):

    Tertio videtur,

    quod

    contra

    ambiguum

    facer? non sit

    incontinentiae .

    47

    This

    expression

    is

    adopted

    from

    Charlton

    (1988,

    p.

    58).

    48

    Albert

    (1987,

    p.

    530.40-49).

    In medieval

    Latin,

    firmitas

    has

    also the connotations

    authority

    and truth .

    49

    It

    ought

    to

    be noted here that

    Albert in his

    second

    commentary

    (1891,

    p.

    467)

    is

    unwilling

    to

    speak

    of

    akrasia in decisions

    concerning ambiguous

    situations.

    50

    On

    the

    influence

    of

    Buridan's

    commentary,

    cf.

    Michael

    (1985).

    Walsh

    (1966,

    pp.

    24

    25)

    concludes: Whatever

    we

    find in this

    commentary

    we

    may

    be

    sure

    was

    available

    to

    thousands of students

    over

    hundreds of

    years.

    .

    . .

    Buridan's

    practical

    philosophy

    is

    analyzed

    by

    Krieger (1986).

    See

    also Saarinen

    (1986).

    51

    The

    most

    often

    quoted

    scholastic

    authors

    in

    Buridan's

    commentary

    are

    Albert

    the

    Great and

    the

    Augustinian-minded

    Franciscan Gerald

    Odonis

    (1290-1349).

    See

    Walsh

    (1975,

    p.

    258).

    52

    This

    view

    is

    presented

    in

    Book

    III,

    q.

    3

    (Buridan

    1968,

    pp.

    41va-43rb).

    53

    Buridan

    (1968,

    p.

    43ra-rb).

    54

    Ibid.

    (p.

    142ra):

    Continentia

    . . .

    capitur

    pro

    habitu,

    quo

    insistentes rectitudini rationis

    resistimus

    passionibus

    in nobis

    vehementibus existentibus

    non

    auferentes

    totum tractum

    ipsarum,

    propter

    quod

    operi

    nostro

    contradicentia

    quaedam

    vel

    displicentia

    annexa

    est .

    55

    Ibid.

    (p.

    143va).

    56

    Ibid.

    (p.

    141rb-va: Book

    VII,

    q.

    3).

    57

    Cf.,

    e.g.,

    Buridan

    (1968, 143rb):

    Quoniam

    sepe,

    ut

    mihi

    videtur,

    expertus

    sum,

    quod

    This content downloaded from 130.251.200.3 on Sun, 22 Dec 2013 08:35:30 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Buridan Davidson Akrasia

    19/22

    150

    RISTO

    SAARINEN

    cum

    rationes

    viderem ad

    utramque

    partem

    probabiles,

    tarnen

    ad

    neutram

    partem

    iudicii

    determinabam

    me

    . . .

    sed

    in

    suspenso

    tenebam

    me

    ... .

    Imo

    prudentis

    est

    prius

    examin

    are

    consilia . Cf. also

    p.

    42va

    (cited below).

    58

    Ibid.

    (p.

    143va:

    Book

    VII,

    q.

    6).

    59

    Ibid.

    (pp.

    142va,

    143va).

    60

    Ibid.

    (p.

    143ra).

    61

    Ibid.

    (p.

    145rb).

    Here

    Buridan

    also concludes

    that

    the certum iudicium need

    not

    be

    scientia ',

    it

    can as

    well

    be

    an

    opinion

    that

    the

    agent

    adopts

    because

    he has

    no

    reason

    whatsoever

    to

    think otherwise.

    62

    This

    point

    is

    made

    with

    great

    clarity by Krieger (1986). Only

    the

    most

    radical

    non

    Aristotelian

    Franciscans,

    such

    as

    Walter of

    Bruges

    (around 1270),

    claimed that

    the

    will

    could be the

    source

    of irrational behavior. See St?dter (1971).

    63

    For

    this,

    cf.

    Krieger (1986,

    pp.

    146-208).

    64

    Buridan

    (1968,

    p.

    42va: Book

    III,

    q.

    3):

    Ad cuius evidentiam

    est

    sciendum

    quod

    libertas secundum

    quam

    voluntas

    potest

    non

    acceptare

    quod

    sibi

    presentatum

    fuerit sub

    ratione boni

    vel

    non

    refutare

    quod

    presentatum

    est

    sub

    ratione

    mali,

    prodest

    valde nobis

    ad vite directionem

    pro

    tanto,

    quia

    in

    multis,

    in

    quibus

    prima

    facie

    sunt

    alique

    rationes

    bonitatis

    apparentes,

    latent

    sepe

    mille

    malicie,

    vel

    annexe

    vel

    cons?quentes, propter

    quod

    acceptare

    illud

    quod apparebat

    bonum

    esset

    nobis

    inconveniens

    et

    damnosum. Et

    sic

    etiam,

    quod

    prima

    facie videtur

    esse

    malum,

    habet

    aliquando

    bonitatem latentem

    propter

    quam

    r?futasse illud

    esset

    nobis malum .

    65

    Ibid.

    (p.

    42va-vb).

    66

    Cf.

    again

    Buridan

    (1968,

    p.

    143rb,

    cited

    above).

    For Buridan's notion of

    prudentia,

    see

    Krieger (1986,

    pp.

    15-145).

    67

    Buridan

    (1968,

    p.

    145rb-va).

    68

    Cf.

    again

    Buridan

    (1968,

    pp.

    142va;

    143va:

    Book

    VII,

    q.

    6).

    69

    This

    point

    was

    explicitly

    made

    by

    Albert the Great

    (1987,

    p.

    530,

    see

    above).

    Buridan

    also

    concludes

    (1968,

    p.

    145rb,

    see

    above)

    that

    even

    the

    opinio

    falsa

    may

    be

    certain,

    if

    no

    available

    reason

    opposes

    the

    opinion

    and if

    it is

    considered

    long

    enough.

    70

    For

    these,

    see

    Vermazen

    and Hintikka

    (1985),

    Charlton

    (1988,

    pp.

    114-34),

    Gosling

    (1990,

    pp.

    103-18),

    and

    Hurley

    (1992).

    71

    Davidson

    (1982a,

    pp.

    22-23).

    72

    All

    these

    expressions

    are

    used

    in Davidson's article. It

    is

    problematic

    whether

    they

    can

    in

    the last

    analysis

    be

    divided

    into

    two

    synonymous groups,

    but this is

    normally

    presupposed

    in

    discussion

    around

    Davidson's

    point.

    See Charlton

    (1988,

    p.

    115)

    and

    Gosling (1990,

    pp.

    104-05).

    73

    Davidson

    (1982a,

    p.

    39).

    74

    Ibid.

    75

    E.g.,

    Davidson

    (1982a,

    p.

    26;

    1982b,

    p.

    98).

    76

    Davidson

    (1982a,

    p.

    41).

    77

    Ibid.

    (p.

    39).

    78

    Buridan

    (1968,

    p.

    42va,

    cited

    above).

    79

    Ibid.

    (pp.

    144vb-145va).

    See above.

    80

    Davidson

    (1982a,

    pp.

    40-41).

    Cf.

    also

    Gosling

    (1990,

    p.

    105).

    81

    Davidson

    (1982a,

    p.

    36).

    This content downloaded from 130.251.200.3 on Sun, 22 Dec 2013 08:35:30 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Buridan Davidson Akrasia

    20/22

    JOHN

    BURIDAN

    AND DONALD

    DAVIDSON

    ON

    AKRASIA

    151

    82

    Davidson

    (1982b,

    p.

    102).

    83

    Davidson

    (1982a,

    p.

    37).

    On

    detachment ,

    see

    also

    Gosling

    (1990,

    pp.

    107-09).

    84

    Peter

    of Poitiers

    (1950-61,

    p.

    98).

    Cf. above.

    85

    Buridan

    (1968,

    p.

    43ra-rb).

    Cf.

    above.

    86

    Davidson

    (1982a,

    p.

    37).

    87

    Ibid.

    (pp.

    37-39).

    Davidson

    claims,

    as

    we

    have

    seen,

    that in

    practical reasoning

    it is

    fallacious

    to

    detach

    absolute

    judgments,

    i.e.

    conclusions that materialize

    as

    actions,

    from

    prima facie

    reasons.

    He

    compares

    practical reasoning

    with

    probabilistic

    reasoning

    of the

    type:

    (a)

    if

    the barometer

    falls,

    it

    almost

    certainly

    will

    rain;

    (b)

    the

    barometer

    is

    falling;

    and

    (c)

    it

    almost

    certainly

    will rain.

    In

    this

    example,

    (a)

    and

    (b)

    do

    not

    allow

    detachment

    of the modal conclusion

    (p.

    37).

    Davidson further

    argues

    that

    practical reasoning

    should

    not

    proceed

    in the form of universalized conditionals.

    For

    discussion, cf., e.g.,

    Charlton

    (1988,

    pp.

    118-23)

    and

    Gosling

    (1990,

    pp.

    105-07).

    88

    Davidson

    (1982a,

    p.

    41).

    89

    Ibid.

    (pp.

    41-42).

    90

    Buridan

    (1968,

    pp.

    143rb, 42va,

    cited

    above).

    REFERENCES

    Abelard,

    Peter:

    1971,

    Ethics,

    ed.

    D.

    E.

    Luscombe,

    Clarendon

    Press,

    Oxford.

    Albert the Great:

    1891,

    Ethicorum Lib.

    X,

    in

    his

    Opera omnia,

    Vol.

    VII,

    ed. A.

    Borgnet,

    Vives,

    Paris.

    Albert the Great:

    1987,

    Super

    Ethica

    commentum et

    quaestiones,

    Pars

    2,

    in his

    Opera

    omnia,

    curavit

    Institutum

    Alberti

    Magni

    Coloniense,

    Tomus

    14/2,

    ed. W.

    K?bel,

    Aschendorff,

    M?nster.

    Anselm of

    Canterbury:

    1938,

    De

    lib?rtate

    arbitrii,

    in

    his

    Opera

    omnia,

    Vol.

    1,

    ed.

    F. S.

    Schmitt,

    T.

    Nelson,

    Edinburgi.

    Augustine:

    1844-,

    Opera

    omnia,

    in

    Patrolog?a

    latina,

    Vols.

    32-47,

    ed. J.-P.

    Migne,

    Paris.

    Baylor,

    M.:

    1977,

    Action and

    Person,

    Conscience

    in

    Late

    Scholasticism

    and

    Young

    Luther,

    Brill,

    Leiden.

    Bourke,

    V.

    J.:

    1966,

    Introduction and

    Notes,

    in

    Augustinus, Confessions,

    The Fathers

    of the

    Church,

    Vol.

    21,

    trans.

    V.

    J.

    Bourke,

    Catholic

    University

    of America

    Press,

    Washington.

    Broadie,

    A. and E.

    Pybus:

    1982,

    'Kant and

    Weakness

    of

    Will',

    Kant-Studien

    73,

    406

    12.

    Buridan,

    John:

    1968,

    Quaestiones

    super

    decem libros

    Ethicorum,

    Minerva,

    Frankfurt

    (reprint

    of

    Paris 1513

    edition).

    Burley,

    Walter:

    1521,

    Expositio

    super

    decem libros Ethicorum

    Aristotelis,

    Venice.

    Charles,

    D.:

    1984,

    Aristotle's

    Philosophy of

    Action,

    Duckworth,

    London.

    Charlton,

    W.:

    1988,

    Weakness

    of

    Will,

    A

    Philosophical

    Introduction,

    Blackwell,

    Oxford.

    Colish,

    M. L.:

    1985,

    The

    Stoic

    Tradition

    from Antiquity

    to

    the

    Early

    Middle

    Ages,

    I?II,

    Brill,

    Leiden.

    This content downloaded from 130.251.200.3 on Sun, 22 Dec 2013 08:35:30 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Buridan Davidson Akrasia

    21/22

    152

    RISTO

    SAARINEN

    Davidson,

    D.:

    1982a,

    'How

    is

    Weakness

    of the Will

    Possible?',

    in

    his

    Essays

    on

    Actions

    and

    Events,

    Clarendon

    Press,

    Oxford,

    pp.

    21-42.

    Davidson,

    D.:

    1982b,

    'Intending',

    in his

    Essays

    on

    Actions and

    Events,

    Clarendon

    Press,

    Oxford,

    pp.

    83-102.

    Gosling,

    W.:

    1990,

    Weakness

    of

    the

    Will,

    Routledge,

    London.

    Hintikka,

    J.:

    1988,

    'Was

    Leibniz's

    Deity

    an

    Akrates?',

    in S. Knuuttila

    (ed.),

    Modern

    Modalities,

    Synthese

    Histo