atkinson - martyn hammersley web viewowes something to a variety of sources, from simmel and goffman...

45
1 Martyn Hammersley SOME REFLECTIONS ON PAUL ATKINSON’S FOR ETHNOGRAPHY 1 As its title makes clear, one of the purposes of this book is to present a manifesto for ethnography. Its other main aim is to offer guidance about ethnographic analysis: Atkinson suggests that many of those starting out on ethnographic work do not know ‘what to look for, how to organize their thoughts and reflections and how to structure their ethnographic work’ (p9). He is particularly keen to emphasise the distinctiveness of ethnography, and this derives in part from his critical attitude towards much qualitative work today, specifically where interviews or focus groups are relied on as the main or exclusive method, and where the primary aim is to document people’s personal experiences or perspectives. He describes the orientation behind this trend as Romantic, or sentimental, since it fails to recognise that expressions of personal experience and viewpoint are always constituted in and through interactional and discursive forms, rather than being reflections of ‘authentic’ individual selves or transparent representations of the world. In large part, his objection to this kind of work may be that it is unsociological. Much autoethnography comes in for criticism on the same grounds. What Atkinson advocates is a more formalist approach to understanding the social world, for which he sees ethnographic investigation – indeed ‘micro-ethnography’ (p121) – as essential. There is much of value here. It is undoubtedly true that there is a great deal of apparently unthinking reliance on interviews and focus groups, and frequently a misplaced preoccupation with ‘giving voice’ to people, as well as a tendency to neglect the situated and constructed character of all accounts. Atkinson also usefully emphasises the interactive character of qualitative analysis, countering both those who seem to think that analytic ideas emerge from data on their own, or can be generated by following some procedure, 1 Paul Atkinson For Ethnography, London, Sage, 2015.

Upload: dodung

Post on 30-Jan-2018

219 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Atkinson - Martyn Hammersley Web viewowes something to a variety of sources, from Simmel and Goffman to ethnomethodology, but he does not address here the important differences among

1

Martyn Hammersley

SOME REFLECTIONS ON PAUL ATKINSON’S FOR ETHNOGRAPHY1

As its title makes clear, one of the purposes of this book is to present a manifesto for ethnography. Its other main aim is to offer guidance about ethnographic analysis: Atkinson suggests that many of those starting out on ethnographic work do not know ‘what to look for, how to organize their thoughts and reflections and how to structure their ethnographic work’ (p9). He is particularly keen to emphasise the distinctiveness of ethnography, and this derives in part from his critical attitude towards much qualitative work today, specifically where interviews or focus groups are relied on as the main or exclusive method, and where the primary aim is to document people’s personal experiences or perspectives. He describes the orientation behind this trend as Romantic, or sentimental, since it fails to recognise that expressions of personal experience and viewpoint are always constituted in and through interactional and discursive forms, rather than being reflections of ‘authentic’ individual selves or transparent representations of the world. In large part, his objection to this kind of work may be that it is unsociological. Much autoethnography comes in for criticism on the same grounds. What Atkinson advocates is a more formalist approach to understanding the social world, for which he sees ethnographic investigation – indeed ‘micro-ethnography’ (p121) – as essential.

There is much of value here. It is undoubtedly true that there is a great deal of apparently unthinking reliance on interviews and focus groups, and frequently a misplaced preoccupation with ‘giving voice’ to people, as well as a tendency to neglect the situated and constructed character of all accounts. Atkinson also usefully emphasises the interactive character of qualitative analysis, countering both those who seem to think that analytic ideas emerge from data on their own, or can be generated by following some procedure, and those who wish simply to ‘apply’ pre-existing theories. And he resists the current emphasis on methodological innovation for its own sake, and the associated neglect of past work. In this connection he writes: ‘We overlook our origins at our peril, and too many contemporary commentators find novelty where there is none, revealing nothing new but a collective ignorance of the past’ (p4). That there is considerable ignorance of this kind is manifest. Furthermore, his discussion of the need to integrate analysis of different types of data (aural, visual, and material), and to take account of the dimensions that structure social interaction, especially time and space, provides very valuable guidance. In support of all this he presents many illuminating examples, covering diverse types of context, both from his own work and that of others.

At the same time, there are some important methodological and theoretical questions raised by this book, not all of which are addressed directly by the author, and it seems fruitful to focus on these here. One set relates to the particular version of ethnography that is put forward and how it is presented. Closely associated with this is the way in which Atkinson’s position seems to combine constructionism with a commitment to faithful representation of ‘the intrinsic, indigenous modes of social organisation’ (p74). His adherence to formalism owes something to a variety of sources, from Simmel and Goffman to ethnomethodology, but 1Paul Atkinson For Ethnography, London, Sage, 2015.

Page 2: Atkinson - Martyn Hammersley Web viewowes something to a variety of sources, from Simmel and Goffman to ethnomethodology, but he does not address here the important differences among

2

he does not address here the important differences among these, and between them and his own approach. There are also a few more specific issues: relating to his reliance on the pragmatist tradition, notably his appeal to the concept of abduction; his recommendation that ethnographers attend to both micro and macro aspects of context; and his insistence that ethnography is intrinsically ethical.

The status and character of ethnography

Atkinson treats ethnography as superior to other approaches, in effect as the gold standard. For example, he writes that ‘‘Ethnographic fieldwork is not just a way to conduct social research. It is a very special way. It is, if not the way, a distinctive way of knowing and being as a social scientist [...]’ (p3). And, a little later on the same page, he describes it as the ‘most rewarding and faithful way of understanding the social world’. These are bold and contentious claims, but he offers very little direct argument in support of them.

While he locates ethnography in relation to some other approaches that he regards as problematic – notably, as already mentioned, interview studies, the use of focus groups, and autoethnography – he does not discuss its relationship to the broad range of competing methodological stances that now exist in social science. Indeed, he displays a distinct lack of interest in, or even opposition to, doing this. At one point he complains that ‘too often’ ethnography ‘is overlaid with all sorts of epistemological and theoretical “positions” and disputes’ (p5).2 Although I sympathise – there is indeed a great deal of spurious philosophising in the field of qualitative research – in my view he underplays the fundamental differences in orientation now to be found in that field, a point I will illustrate. Furthermore, given that we live at a time when, in powerful quarters, there is strong emphasis on the value of ‘big data’, randomised controlled trials, and ‘mixed methods’, it is surely necessary in any ‘manifesto’ to address the question of the distinctive value of ethnographic accounts in comparison with the products of these other sorts of social research. Against this background, the superiority of ethnography cannot be treated as a foregone conclusion.

This links to another issue that Atkinson does not address, but which is relevant to his discussion: the relationship of ethnography to the demand, backed by enormous pressure today, that social research must serve public policymaking, or at least have practical payoff in other ways. Instead, he locates ethnography within a traditional academic conception of research, treating what it produces as having intrinsic worth. For example, he claims that ‘well-crafted monographs’ have ‘enduring value’ (p195). I have no quarrel with this, even if the nature of the value being assumed here needs clarification.3 However, such appeals to the 2 He adds that ‘To some degree, of course, academic debate and intellectual justifications are unavoidable, but too much is made of them’.3 Atkinson draws a parallel between the crafts he has studied and ethnography as a craft. However, while there is much to be said for this – and the notion of social research as a craft is a longstanding one – the metaphor fails to apply in some important respects. In particular, crafts generally produce objects that lay audiences value, and indeed, not to put too fine a point on it, for which they are prepared to pay. But I do not believe that ethnographic monographs have value in that sense on sufficient scale to finance the enterprise. Of course, appeal could be made to some transcendent notion of value, in the way that art has often been justified, but that idea has been subjected to considerable criticism, and it is unclear how it could apply to ethnography. While some knowledge can be of value irrespective of whether or not it is actually valued, not just any knowledge has this status: it must have relevance to human concerns. Ethnography of the kind advocated by Atkinson seems to

Page 3: Atkinson - Martyn Hammersley Web viewowes something to a variety of sources, from Simmel and Goffman to ethnomethodology, but he does not address here the important differences among

3

intrinsic value of knowledge are now widely regarded as insufficient, at best, so that this position requires defence. Research posts and funds are increasingly tied to applied forms of inquiry and to ‘public engagement’, and even academics’ use of research leave often now requires them to make commitments to produce specific ‘outputs’ addressing current ‘priorities’ that will have specifiable ‘impact’ via ‘knowledge transfer’. One wonders how the kind of ethnographic work that Atkinson favours – involving lengthy fieldwork that is exploratory in nature, and not directed at practical payoffs – can survive in this environment. Moreover, the challenge to this academic orientation comes from within the research community as well as from outside. At one point Atkinson mentions the commitment of many qualitative researchers today to pursuing social justice through their work (p186). While not espousing this, he does not explicitly reject it either. Some clarification of his stance here would have been welcome, since the use of social science to pursue any political goal, however benign, also surely represents a threat to the sort of ethnographic work he is advocating.

Turning to what Atkinson says about ethnography, it is important to recognise that while he claims that ‘an old-fashioned approach to ethnographic fieldwork lies at the heart of’ his book (p4), there are features of what he recommends that are not characteristic of a considerable amount of past work coming under this heading. For example, though he largely rejects the use of interview data as a source of information about people’s lives and perspectives, much work categorised as ethnography has used this as a key complement to participant observation, and sometimes such data have been treated as central. Secondly, his formalist interpretation of the goal of inquiry is rather different from the more substantive foci common in a great deal of ethnographic work, where the aim for instance is to describe and explain some problem in the lives of a group or type of people, the strategies they use to deal with it, the consequences of these, etc. Third, he rejects the idea that ethnography is concerned with discovering what people actually do as against what they say they do, or what is really going on as against what is portrayed in official or other accounts (pp99-101). Yet much work that would often be included under the heading of ethnography has been committed to such concerns.4 While debating what sorts of work are ‘truly’ ethnographic (p121) is fruitless, it is important to recognise that what is being presented here is a distinctive version, indeed in many ways it is an explication of Atkinson’s own recent ethnographic work: it does not represent the full range of ethnography, as conventionally understood.5

claim this via the notion that it documents social forms, or more generally how social order is achieved. I will examine this idea later.4 To take just one example, picked more or less at random, my old PhD supervisor Isabel Emmett described her aim in studying a North Wales village as ‘to observe, understand and record what people actually did, rather than what they said they did’ (Emmett 1964:ix).5 In one place Atkinson recognises this: he says he is calling for ‘a re-specification of the basic aims of social research, and of course of ethnographic research in particular’. And he continues: ‘It is important to insist that the main thrust of good ethnographic research is to understand how social action is accomplished, how orderly, co-ordinated activity is undertaken, how knowledgeable and skilful techniques are employed, how material goods and artefacts are made, used and circulated’ (p18). It is perhaps of significance that the term ‘re-specification’ has frequently been used by ethnomethodologists to designate the radical shift in the focus of social inquiry that their work exemplifies (Button 1991).The change that Atkinson is proposing may be less radical, but it is still quite a significant departure from much ethnography, and from much social science more

Page 4: Atkinson - Martyn Hammersley Web viewowes something to a variety of sources, from Simmel and Goffman to ethnomethodology, but he does not address here the important differences among

4

One way of describing the distinctive kind of ethnography being promoted here would be to say that it is ethnography in the service of a ‘sociology of everyday life’. Atkinson frequently refers to ‘everyday life’ or ‘mundane reality’ as the focus of inquiry, and it is certainly accurate to describe much of the work of Simmel, Goffman, and ethnomethodologists as concerned with this. For example, Garfinkel (1967:1) declares that ethnomethodology involves ‘paying to the most commonplace activities of daily life the attention usually accorded extraordinary events, to learn about them as phenomena in their own right’. Moreover, this was a focus that was given considerable emphasis in the late 1960s and early 70s, the formative period of Atkinson’s career (see Adler et al 1987). Interestingly, it is a theme that has been returned to quite recently, albeit sometimes approached from very different angles (Sztompka 2008; Pink 2012; Kalekin-Fishman 2013; see also Human Studies, 3, 1, 1980 and Sociology 49, 5, 2015).6

Rather like the flowering of social history in the middle of the twentieth century, this concern with everyday life amounts to a reaction against an exclusive focus on events, actions, structures, etc. that are deemed to be of great social, political or economic significance. Within sociology this focus on the mundane was perhaps, above all, a reaction against a ‘social problems’ perspective, or to various forms of ‘grand theory’. In some versions, and this is true of Atkinson’s book, the emphasis is on how particular kinds of social order are established and sustained in and through everyday patterns of social interaction.

There are at least three rather different arguments that could be put forward in support of this focus. One is that everyday life is a worthwhile but neglected topic in its own right. In these terms it complements other kinds of sociological and anthropological investigation. Alternatively, it may be argued that it is not possible to understand the issues and problems with which other sorts of social science are concerned without taking account of the mundane social processes that these inevitably involve. From this point of view the study of these processes provides a foundation for any sociological investigation. The third position is that studying everyday social processes is the only rigorous or worthwhile form of social science. Atkinson seems to adopt the second of these positions, though he does not offer much explicit argument in support of it. This is an issue I will examine later.7

The critique of interview studies

generally. This is a point that is highlighted if we compare Atkinson’s account with another recent defence of ‘traditional’ ethnography, against some of the same trends: see Walford 2009.6 There is also a French tradition – artistic and philosophical – concerned with everyday life: see Sheringham 2006.7A further sort of rationale would be via the idea that ‘the personal is political’. However, while there are many aspects of everyday life that have social, economic, or political significance, not every aspect of it does. And significance is, of course, a matter of degree and perspective. Aside from this, Atkinson would, one presumes, reject this rationale because the term ‘personal’ relates to the experience of individuals, rather than to the social forms that he sees as constituting everyday life.

Page 5: Atkinson - Martyn Hammersley Web viewowes something to a variety of sources, from Simmel and Goffman to ethnomethodology, but he does not address here the important differences among

5

As already indicated, one of the central themes of Atkinson’s book is a critique of the common tendency for many qualitative researchers today to rely primarily on interview data. At one point he suggests that interviews are ‘essentially a lazy way of undertaking social research’ (p8). However, his criticism of interview studies goes beyond the complaint that there is too much unthinking use of this method. For example, he argues that interviews:

Provide little or no opportunity to investigate the multiple forms of social organisation and action that are the stuff of everyday life. They yield information (of sorts) in a vacuum, bereft of the sensory and material means of mundane reality. They furnish no opportunity to study the techniques and skills that social actors deploy in the course of their daily lives, or in accomplishing specialised tasks. (p92)

The argument here is a methodological one: that crucial data about behaviour in other settings will not be available via interview accounts of it, so that direct observation is required if this behaviour is to be understood. He writes:

We need participant observation if we are to develop a strong, practical sense of encounters and performances. We need visual data in order to capture matters of posture and embodiment. Likewise we need to be able to record matters of appearance – clothing, hair, body-modification. We need, of course, permanent recordings of spoken activity too. (p86)8

It should be noted that while this may be true for the kind of micro-ethnography of patterns of social interaction that Atkinson focuses on in his book, it is not obviously true in some other kinds of ethnographic work; for example, say, in research concerned with what sorts of people use a particular type of drug, how they obtain supply of it, why they use it; or in researching how children become involved in prostitution and the effects on their lives. In these cases, it seems to me that a great deal of useful information could be obtained via interviews, some of it relating to matters that may not be open to direct observation. Atkinson’s argument is not, then, a basis for a blanket rejection of conventional uses of interview data by ethnographers, in the way that – in places – he seems to suggest.

There is another argument that is often used to question the use of interview data as a source of information both about other situations and about the beliefs and attitudes of informants. This concerns reactivity: the suggestion is that these data are unreliable in representational terms because they are co-constructed by interviewer (generally the researcher) and interviewee, rather than simply being an expression of what the latter knows, believes, feels, etc.9 However, it is important to recognise that what is involved here is a claim about the degree of reactivity in interviews, as compared with observation of ‘naturally occurring’ behaviour. After all, observation will often involve reactive effects too: the argument is presumably that these will be at a lower level. Furthermore, to some extent at

8 Later he reduces the requirements slightly: ‘a minimum requirement is close in situ observation and careful recording in the form of detailed fieldnotes, perhaps accompanied by sketches of embodied activities’ (p86).9 For an example of the use of this argument about reactivity to question reliance on interview data, see Potter and Hepburn 2005 (for a commentary see Hammersley 2013:ch4) – though they use other arguments as well, including some that Atkinson also employs.

Page 6: Atkinson - Martyn Hammersley Web viewowes something to a variety of sources, from Simmel and Goffman to ethnomethodology, but he does not address here the important differences among

6

least, it is possible to allow for reactivity in the course of data analysis; indeed reactivity can even be illuminating – for example showing how informants respond to types of people from outside their normal range of contacts. Moreover, it is misleading to conceptualise reactivity in terms of a dichotomy between naturalness and artificiality, as if interviews, and indeed the ethnographer, were not part of the world being studied. While Atkinson questions that dichotomy at one point (p99), in other places he seems to rely on it: for instance, he writes that ‘research interviews are deliberately designed occasions on which such performances are enacted, and to that extent there is no question: they do not constitute “naturally occurring” sources of data’ (p95).

Rather than treating reactivity as a basis for rejecting conventional uses of interview data, it could simply be argued that we must be cautious in how we handle all data, recognising that they may have been shaped by the research process in ways that could lead us astray. This requires us to take account of reactive effects, but only to the extent that they are a potential source of error in our interpretations and conclusions. In the case of interviews, much depends upon the conditions under which they were carried out, what was said and what inferences are being drawn from this. In places, this seems to be Atkinson’s position, as for example when he rightly complains that ‘we too often find informants’ accounts of events, or memories, or descriptions of social action, reproduced as if they were transparent representations’ (p93). However, generally speaking, he seems to adopt the more radical conclusion that interview data should not be used as a source of information about what the informant has witnessed or about her or his beliefs and attitudes. In my view this is not warranted, and it restricts the evidence available to ethnographers, thereby narrowing the range of topics they can address.

Later, Atkinson employs a further argument, one which is the central theme in what has been referred to as the ‘radical critique of interviews’ (Murphy et al 1998:120-3; Dingwall 1997; Hammersley and Gomm 2008). This emphasises that interview accounts are governed by discursive conventions, and are forms of action, rather than serving as windows on the world or into the minds of informants. Following Silverman (1993), he writes that:

we cannot approach interview data simply from the point of view of ‘truth’ or ‘distortion’, and we cannot use such data with a view to remedying the incompleteness of observations. By the same token, we cannot rely on our observations in order to correct presumed inaccuracies in interview accounts. On the contrary, interviews generate data that have intrinsic properties of their own. In essence, we need to treat interviews as generating accounts and performances that have their own properties, and ought to be analysed in accordance with such characteristics. (p95-6).10

Silverman’s position in the work cited is that interview data can tell us little more than what goes on in interviews, and, for the most part, it seems that Atkinson agrees with this. He writes that ‘a recognition of the performative action of interview talk removes the temptation

10 However, at one point he does recognise that interview accounts ‘may help to illuminate aspects of [...] observed activities’ (p75).

Page 7: Atkinson - Martyn Hammersley Web viewowes something to a variety of sources, from Simmel and Goffman to ethnomethodology, but he does not address here the important differences among

7

to deal with such data as if they gave us access to personal or private “experiences”’ (pp99-100). He suggests that, instead of being concerned with whether informants’ accounts provide reliable information, we should focus on credibility as a property of those accounts themselves, addressing the question: ‘How does the informant construct a plausible account?’ (p101). And as illustration he cites his own treatment of reports of alien abduction.

Atkinson highlights the positive as well as the negative aspects of this argument, insisting that:

The interview is itself a social encounter. Interview-derived narratives and accounts are performances in their own right. They are, or contain embedded within them, speech events. They contain stories that reflect common genres. They construct biographies and identities. They deserve attention from those analytic perspectives. They do not deserve merely to be chopped up and coded thematically without proper regard for their forms and functions as narratives and accounts (p60).

Here the suggestion seems to be that interviews should be treated as sites in which social interaction takes place, of particular kinds, and that attention should be given to the discursive practices and interactional strategies displayed there. Moreover, this requires paying close attention to how the interview unfolds, rather than coding segments of data in terms of their relationship to various emergent themes that concern matters external to it: the social situations in which informants participate and/or their feelings, beliefs, and attitudes.

It is worth noting an apparent contradiction in Atkinson’s position here. Some of the arguments on which he relies in dismissing the standard uses of interviews – arguments concerned with reactivity, informants’ reliance on discursive conventions, and the fact that talk is action – apply to observational data as well. As already noted, the latter often involve reactive effects: people may behave differently because they know they are being observed. Furthermore, participant observation involves informal conversations that rely on discourse conventions and consist of talk as action. And any fieldnotes that the researcher writes, and transcriptions of recordings, also have these characteristics. Given this, why is the use of observational data not ruled out as a means of documenting ‘the intrinsic indigenous modes of social organisation’ (p73).The answer from Atkinson’s point of view is, I suspect, that if we focus on investigating the forms of social interaction we can turn what are methodological problems in studying substantive topics into theoretical resources. In other words, by refusing to treat those forms simply as a resource in investigating substantive topics, our analysis thereby becomes more rigorous: we are focusing on the constitutive processes that shape social life, including research itself. This is a kind of argument sometimes used by ethnomethodologists. However, both Atkinson’s critique of the use of interview data and the formalist approach he puts forward appear to depend on a version of constructionism that is open to serious question.

Constructionism

We can think of ‘constructionism’ (or sometimes ‘constructivism’ – the phrasing Atkinson uses) as starting from a rejection of naive realism: the idea that the accounts people produce

Page 8: Atkinson - Martyn Hammersley Web viewowes something to a variety of sources, from Simmel and Goffman to ethnomethodology, but he does not address here the important differences among

8

(including those of researchers) are generated by the world impressing its character upon their senses, this ‘impression’ then being ‘expressed’ in a manner that simply corresponds to or captures that world. This, I suspect, is what Atkinson is opposing when he insists that ‘language-in-use is never a neutral medium of representation’ (p93). The implication is that processes of perception and cognition necessarily shape what we experience, and what we take to be true, that these are dependent upon the role of language, and that language must be seen not as some fixed, internal, generative structure but rather as a diverse collection of social practices. Thus, what is taken to be real or true is necessarily a socio-cultural product, and will vary accordingly: in short, reality is socially constructed. From this it may be further concluded that, since we do not have unmediated contact with reality, the validity of any judgment about what is real, or true, is relative to the socio-cultural framework within which it is formulated, or is conditional upon the discursive resources employed, and/or is dependent upon whether the action in which it is embedded was successful in performative terms.

However, while much of this argument is sound, the relativist or sceptical conclusion drawn from it is fallacious. This is because it relies implicitly upon the empiricist epistemology that has been rejected: in other words, it is assumed that for knowledge to be possible (in other words, for there to be statements about the world whose truth status is independent of any particular framework, set of resources, or successful form of action) we must be able to register direct sense impressions and translate these into transparent representations. And it is concluded that, since we are not able to do this, no knowledge (in that sense of the word) is possible, that the meaning of this term, along with that of ‘truth’ and ‘reality’, must be redefined if they are to be used at all, so as to take account of their relativity.11 Yet there is no reason to assume that in order to produce knowledge, in the usual sense of the word, we must have unmediated contact with reality; or, indeed, that such contact would produce knowledge. These conclusions would only be true if knowledge were a copy of reality. Once we recognise that, instead, all knowledge consists of answers to particular questions about the world, the assumptions on which any inquiry relies, and the sociocultural resources it deploys, no longer need to be seen as necessarily distorting what is produced; indeed, some assumptions and resources are essential to the production of knowledge. While particular assumptions may lead us into error, others will take us towards the truth.12

Atkinson appears to suggest that we can avoid the problem of treating data as representing features of a world that exists beyond it by focusing on the forms through which it is presented to us. Thus, we can use interview data to study the forms displayed in and by it, and similarly when we are using observational data our focus should be on how the performances observed are constructed – and, in particular, on the forms, methods, principles of organisation, etc. by means of which this is achieved. However, my point is that this remedy is unnecessary because the problem has been falsely diagnosed. While I agree that our goal should be to document and explain facts – rather than to evaluate people’s actions or

11 It is striking that, like many other writers, Atkinson tends to put scare quote marks around ‘truth’ and ‘reality’.12 For some of the epistemological background to my argument here see, for example, Williams 2001.

Page 9: Atkinson - Martyn Hammersley Web viewowes something to a variety of sources, from Simmel and Goffman to ethnomethodology, but he does not address here the important differences among

9

the institutions in which they participate – this does not rule out assessing the likely validity of people’s accounts as sources of information, in pursuit of factual knowledge. In other words, if we reject the false sceptical conclusion drawn from constructionism, while we can certainly decide to investigate social forms, this type of investigation is not privileged over other more substantive foci, and we can use interview accounts as a means of gaining information about the world along with observation.

Even aside from the fact that the sceptical constructionist argument is erroneous, we should also note that it would work against Atkinson’s commitment to ethnography as rigorous exploration of the social world. On the basis of epistemological scepticism or relativism, ethnography itself can amount to no more than a performance to be assessed in aesthetic, moral or political terms, rather than according to the likely validity of its findings. It could only produce illuminating fictions, since the ‘knowledge’ it produces is socially constructed just as much as the accounts of informants. By contrast, in places, Atkinson appears to believe that we can have direct access through observation to social forms: that these are simply there for us to see and to reproduce in our ethnographic accounts.13 He writes, for example, that

we can examine the means and methods employed by parties to the encounter to display mutual attention. The intersubjectivity of the encounter is not, therefore, merely a vague (if productive) idea, but subject to empirical investigation and analysis. Enactments of mutual attentiveness, for example, can be explored, identifying mutual gaze, attentiveness, body posture and proxemics (Kendon 1990). (p79)

Here his emphasis is on rigorous attention to and documentation of data concerned with the enactment of social forms, and he treats these as immediately available to empirical analysis.14

Along the same lines, Atkinson declares that the aim of ethnography is faithfully to represent ‘the complexity of everyday life’ (p38), claiming that it ‘preserves’ this complexity (p5), and even that it is ‘coterminous with’ ‘the social world under investigation’ (p173).15 Yet, while it is undoubtedly true that one of the contributions that ethnography, and other kinds of research, can make is to expose relevant social complexities (as compared with commonsense or theoretical understandings that gloss over these), recognising and revealing complexity is not a good in itself: it is of value only insofar as it facilitates understanding, in the form of an answer to some question. Moreover, understanding requires at least some simplification of the phenomena being studied (Hammersley 2008:ch2). Indeed, the idea of capturing complexity is at odds with Atkinson’s commitment to formal analysis, since studying social forms must surely involve reducing complex particularities to standard 13 This is an assumption that can also be found in ethnomethodology, and in phenomenology; though in the latter case, at least in its Husserlian form, what is given and its mode of givenness are rather differently conceived from what Atkinson has in mind.14By contrast, later, in outlining what is involved in ethnographic analysis he clearly recognises the need for imagination and theory, rather than treating these as necessarily distorting the account produced.15 Use of the word ‘coterminous’ reminds me of Lewis Carroll’s (2001:204) joke about the uselessness of a map of scale one-to-one.

Page 10: Atkinson - Martyn Hammersley Web viewowes something to a variety of sources, from Simmel and Goffman to ethnomethodology, but he does not address here the important differences among

10

patterns; looking for ‘generic social processes’ (p2) requires us to determine what is generic and what is situationally variable. In this connection, Simmel (1950:16) refers to ‘the one-sided abstraction that no science can get rid of’. The issue that must be addressed, therefore, is: what is productive simplification and what is misleading simplification? Or, to put it the other way round, which complexities must be preserved in an analysis and which can be omitted, for the purposes of gaining the sort of understanding desired?

Of course, the term ‘complexity’ can have different meanings. In my discussion above I have interpreted it as referring to the fact that, at best, social phenomena only approximate to any given set of types, and that they are often subject to change over relatively short periods, because they are produced by multiple causal factors. The contrast assumed here is with physical phenomena, conceived as reducible to standard types among which there are stable – perhaps even eternal – relationships.16 However, it seems that Atkinson is using the word ‘complexity’ in a special sense, to refer to the fact that everyday social interaction is generated by several ‘principles of orderliness’ (p19) rather than just one. He writes that since ‘‘Everyday performances are quintessentially complex and multi-modal enactments [...] they need to be matched by ethnographies of equal complexity’ (p86). We should note that this conception of complexity relies on a prior theory about the ‘principles’ (‘modalities’, ‘codes’, or ‘forms’ are other words he uses) in terms of which social reality is organised or ordered. And we might reasonably ask where this theory has come from, why we should assume that it is valid, and why it should be treated as an essential framework for sociological analysis. The first two questions could be answered by claiming that it has been developed out of previous ethnographic work, assuming that this has displayed cumulative theoretical development – a claim that is open to challenge. But the third question cannot be answered in this way, and I will address it in the next section.

Formalism

Atkinson cites Simmel and Goffman in support of his commitment to a formalist approach.17 He criticises the failure to adopt such an approach in much qualitative research today: ‘We have lost sight of the multiple ways in which social conduct is patterned through routine and ritualized methods of conduct. We forget that cultural domains display codes of organization and of signification’ (p13).

Simmel is, of course, renowned for his promotion of a formal sociology, and Goffman follows in this tradition in many respects, even though he goes his own way. Involved in their work is a contrast between form and content – between some structure or framework and what fills, or is generated by, it – and perhaps also between the social, on the one hand, and the personal, psychological, or individual, on the other. It should be said, though, that neither

16 This may, of course, be an inaccurate picture of physical reality, as indicated by the development of ‘complexity theory’ (see Nicolis and Prigogine 1989). In Contours of Culture, Atkinson and his co-authors (2008:207) suggest that their approach ‘complements the perspectives of complexity theory’.17 Interestingly, what he has in mind here also seems to share something in common with Russian Formalism in literary studies – in particular, a commitment to rigorous analysis of the structural organisation to be found within ‘social texts’, rather than a concern with authorial intention and motive.

Page 11: Atkinson - Martyn Hammersley Web viewowes something to a variety of sources, from Simmel and Goffman to ethnomethodology, but he does not address here the important differences among

11

Simmel nor Goffman are very clear about what is meant by ‘form’, and much the same is true of Atkinson’s usage of the term.18

There seem to be several different meanings of ‘form’ that he has in mind. First, there is the sense that is central to literary or textual analysis, where for example narrative is treated as a language form that has specifiable constituents which must occur in some particular order (as identified, for example, by Labov 2013: p102). What we have here is something like the constitutive rules that define particular types of game, though of course the rules can change over time, or develop differently in different contexts; and one game can morph into another. A second, slightly different kind of ‘form’, consists of patterns of social action or interaction that have the character of rituals, routines or skilful collective practices. One example is the ‘interaction ritual’ studied by Goffman in the context of what he calls focused gatherings or encounters. An example from Atkinson’s (2013) own research is the opera ‘master-class’ as a distinct type of pedagogical interaction. In these examples, much of the emphasis is on regulative rules that guide behaviour, partly because of a commitment to preserving ‘face’.19 A rather different example of the same type of form, despite overlap with what is displayed in opera master-classes, would be certain sorts of occupational skill, such as those deployed by the artists engaged in glass-blowing that Atkinson has also studied. In investigating such social forms the concern seems to be with how they are established and sustained, both as recognisable phenomena and as of value.20

Atkinson also identifies a more general type of social form: ‘modalities’, ‘orders’, or ‘codes’ that represent whole fields of social phenomena. Following Goffman, he refers to the ‘interaction order’, distinguishing this from the ‘political’ and ‘economic’ orders (p73). But he also adds: the ‘semiotic order’, the ‘spatio-temporal order’, the ‘material order’, and the ‘aesthetic order’. One possible parallel here is with the different systems that operate within the human body, such as the nervous system, the digestive system, and so on. However, whereas these are relatively well-defined, despite the fact that they are interrelated, this is not true in the case of Atkinson’s typology of orders. It is not entirely clear what each ‘order’ refers to and how this is separable from what the others denote, even in analytic terms. For example, there are questions about how the ‘interaction order’ can be separated from those practices that make up the ‘semiotic order’. And how are we to distinguish between the semiotic and material orders when the latter is described as involved in ‘cultural codes’ and as providing ‘semiotic resources’ (p21)? Furthermore, do not all of these necessarily operate within spatio-temporal frameworks – indeed Atkinson emphasises that perceptions of time and space are constituted interactionally and/or semiotically. And it is not clear whether he sees these orders as overarching forms that contain, or frame, other more specific ones, or whether they serve as a series of laminations (perhaps in line with the metaphor of ‘contours’ used in an earlier book: Atkinson et al 2008). There are also questions about the meaning he is giving to the term ‘order’: this is presumably closer to the sense assigned to that word by

18 This was a criticism made of Simmel by Durkheim in an early commentary, see Durkheim 1965:47-8.19 On the distinction between constitutive and regulative rules, see Searle 1995:27.20 It is important to note that these forms are experienced by individuals as objective structures to be responded to as facts, employed as tools, or adapted to in the course of interaction. They are not simply created by individuals on the basis of personal preferences.

Page 12: Atkinson - Martyn Hammersley Web viewowes something to a variety of sources, from Simmel and Goffman to ethnomethodology, but he does not address here the important differences among

12

Garfinkel than that intended by Hobbes and Parsons; yet, as we shall see, Atkinson’s position diverges in some significant respects from ethnomethodology.

Aside from this, though, it is clear that what Atkinson means by ‘order’, ‘code’, or ‘modality’ here is rather different from the more specific textual and interactional forms mentioned earlier. In part, at least, these orders comprise what we might call constitutive frameworks of interpretation. Atkinson states that ‘experience itself is constructed by and through socially shared, culturally prescribed forms’ (p13). Simmel has provided the most developed account of this kind of form. He starts from Kant’s notion of the categories of understanding that structure our experience of the physical world, notably space, time and causation.21 Kant famously argued that these are not present in the ‘things-in-themselves’, only in ‘the-world-as-it-appears’. For Simmel, though, rather than being intrinsic to the transcendental subjectivity through which we apprehend the world, they operate immanently within that world, generated by the multifarious processes he refers to as Life. Furthermore, he extends this approach beyond the frameworks of scientific understanding of the physical world, of morality, and of aesthetics, the three fields on which Kant focused, to include history and sociology as distinctive interpretive frameworks. Goffman pursues a similar approach, albeit examining more mundane frameworks in Frame Analysis.22

There is, however, a significant difference between what Atkinson has in mind here and the arguments of Simmel and Goffman, in that he stresses the need for ethnographers to attend to all of the modalities he lists in examining any particular social situation.23 In Contours of Culture, he and his co-authors write that we should not:

seek to render social life in terms of just one analytic strategy or one cultural form. The forms of analysis should reflect the forms of social life: their diversity should reflect the diversity of cultural forms; their significance should be in accordance with the significance of their social and cultural functions. (Atkinson et al 2008:34)

Yet, from Simmel’s and perhaps Goffman’s point of view, forms as interpretive frameworks involve discrepant ways of ordering reality and are therefore effectively incommensurable. This implies that in any particular study the focus would need to be on one or other of them: they cannot all be given the same weight. Thus, while the materials that make up other ‘orders’ may come within focus, they would only be taken into account selectively and would be constituted in the terms of the order that is the main concern. Given this, there is an area of uncertainty about the character of this third type of social form in Atkinson’s discussion.

On the basis of his formalist approach to the social world, Atkinson emphasises the need to draw on multiple types of data: visual material and material artefacts as well as audio-recordings. This is integral to taking account of multiple orders or ordering principles. In his

21 Interestingly while, as we have seen, Atkinson treats the first two of these as important ordering principles shaping social interaction, he rather ignores the third.22 We should note that treating forms as immanent in the social world may seem to imply that human society is a kind of collective mind. For Simmel’s account of the presuppositions of history, see his 1977 and 1980. For his account of sociology as a distinctive perspective, see ‘The field of sociology’ in Wolff 1950. 23 It is possible that what he means is that ethnographers should give attention to the potential relevance of these modalities in any particular case, but the problem I am outlining here persists.

Page 13: Atkinson - Martyn Hammersley Web viewowes something to a variety of sources, from Simmel and Goffman to ethnomethodology, but he does not address here the important differences among

13

analysis of opera master classes, for example, he emphasises the way in which the realisation of this social form articulates space and time, and involves the deployment of speech, gesture, and other non-verbal expressions, in a complex process of orchestration. And he is surely right to resist both the temptation to focus entirely on audio data, as a result of the easy availability of recordings, and the way in which a concern with visual data and with material artefacts have come to be separated off from mainstream ethnographic work. Good research must take account of any kinds of data that are relevant to the inquiry, and it is worth noting that before the emergence of audio- and video-recording technology, ethnographers probably tended to operate in a more multi-modal fashion than many have done subsequently.

What must also be resisted, however, is any tendency to subordinate ethnography to the technologies now available for collecting data about human social life: these are no more than means, and they can distort as well as enable – because it is possible to collect video data, this may be judged to be essential, and because audio or video recordings allow fine-grained, or frame-by-frame, analysis of action, it may be assumed that this is always necessary. These are carts driving horses. Atkinson may agree with this, but there are places in his discussion where he appears to make these forms of data and analysis a requirement. This emphasis on detailed analysis amounts to micro-ethnography (p121). And I suggest that this commitment stems from another important influence on his thinking: ethnomethodology and conversation analysis.24

Ethnomethodology and conversation analysis as models

Built into ethnomethodology is the idea that if we are to understand the way in which social life is organised we must approach it in a significantly different manner from that in which natural scientists are generally seen as studying physical objects. Rather than treating social phenomena as operating within a realm of causal processes that can be used to explain their character and behaviour, we must focus instead on the methods by which people produce and recognise instances of particular kinds of phenomena, in and through their actions. I suggest that this is a fundamental difference in approach from much social science, and indeed from much ethnography; I will characterise it as representing a constructionist rather than a naturalistic stance.25

One formulation of the task of ethnomethodologists is to explicate the, largely taken for granted, cultural competence through which people act so as collectively and ongoingly to construct the social world. The focus is on the how of actions and institutions rather than on questions of why (i.e. of causality). This is analogous to the manner in which Husserlian phenomenology sought to study the ways in which physical and other phenomena are constituted in our experience of them. The argument, sometimes, is that social phenomena are more various and variable than much social science assumes, and less standard in form than

24 Of course, ethnomethodologists typically reject the micro-macro distinction, see for example Schegloff 1988:100. For Atkinson’s earlier ‘sympathetic but critical’ discussion of ethnomethodology, see Atkinson 1988.25 I am aware that ethnomethodologists often deny any commitment to constructionism, and indeed criticise it –see Button and Sharrock 1993. In fact, confusingly, they use the term ‘constructive sociology’ to refer to mainstream forms of sociological work. However, the word ‘constructionism’ is used in a variety of ways, and in the manner in which I have defined it here ethnomethodology would belong in this category.

Page 14: Atkinson - Martyn Hammersley Web viewowes something to a variety of sources, from Simmel and Goffman to ethnomethodology, but he does not address here the important differences among

14

is required for them to be studied scientifically, but that the methods through which they are constituted are sufficiently stable and general to be studied rigorously. Conversation analysis has been most successful in documenting these methods, for instance those involved in turn-taking, in correcting oneself and others, in managing topical continuity and change, etc (see Schegloff 2007). At the same time, questions have been raised about whether it adheres to the ethnomethodological programme (see Lynch 1993).

In his book, Atkinson’s attitude towards ethnomethodology and conversation analysis is generally positive (pp122-3). He rightly believes that they are important sources on which ethnographers can draw. More than this, though, at one point he suggests that ‘the inspiration of ethnomethodology could and should be pervasive’ (p121), in its concern with the ‘“methods” through which social actors accomplish their ordinary and their expert everyday accomplishments’ (p121). Furthermore, there is an interesting parallel between his own account of the value of studying how complex knowledge and skills are deployed by people in situationally appropriate ways – for example in the context of producing an operatic performance or generating artworks – and ethnomethodological studies of work; though he does not emphasise the parallel.26 He also argues that ‘the distinctions between ethnography and ethnomethodology are becoming harder to sustain’ (p123).

Another sign of the influence of ethnomethodology on Atkinson’s work, besides his concern with detailed analysis of how social activities are performed, is his handling of the concept of motive. He argues that motives must be treated as rhetorical products rather than as causal factors operating on people’s behaviour. Here he is following Mills’ (1940) early account of vocabularies of motive as well as later ethnomethodological arguments along similar lines (pp97-8). Yet, it seems to me that Bruce and Wallis (1983) have conclusively demonstrated that it is impossible to avoid the attribution of intentions and motives, even for ethnomethodologists; and, indeed, that such attribution is central to most forms of sociological analysis.27

At the same time, there are important respects in which Atkinson deviates from ethnomethodology. One of these relates to the key ethnographic issue of context. For conversation analysts, the only context the researcher can legitimately take into account is that which is displayed as an oriented-to matter by participants within the processes of social interaction being studied. According to this constructionist approach, all social phenomena – whether in the background or the foreground – must be treated as constituted in and through

26Atkinson discussed these studies in his 1988 article. Also relevant, perhaps, is Collins’ (1981:373-4) argument that sociologists of science need to be competent members of the research community they are studying.27 See also Hammersley and Treseder 2007. For the debate on this see Sharrock and Watson 1984, Bruce and Wallis 1985 and Sharrock and Watson 1986. See also Housley 2008. It is even more obvious in the case of Mills that he does not avoid the attribution of motives, and apparently does not wish to: witness his claim that ‘The differing reasons men give for their actions are not themselves without reasons’ (p904). That studying motive ascription is worthwhile and important is not at issue, but sociologists also treat motives as mainsprings of action and cannot avoid doing so, in one way or another, and in my view there is nothing wrong with that. In his earlier discussion of ethnomethodology Atkinson (1988:449) complained that in ethnomethodology ‘motive is not addressed in understanding social action. Language is not treated here as a medium for intentional, motivated social action’, and in the course of this he appeals to Bruce and Wallis’s arguments. His complaint on that occasion seems to me to be well-grounded, but it looks as if he may have changed his mind about this.

Page 15: Atkinson - Martyn Hammersley Web viewowes something to a variety of sources, from Simmel and Goffman to ethnomethodology, but he does not address here the important differences among

15

processes of social interaction (or discourse), rather than as existing prior to or outside of those processes. However, while, as we have seen, Atkinson emphasises the need for detailed study of social interaction, and thereby of how people context their behaviour, his prior identification of different modalities or orders that structure interaction is at odds with the constructionist conception of context on which Conversation Analysis relies. Furthermore, he also suggests that the study of ‘the local production of social order’ needs to be ‘embedded in more general accounts of social worlds’ (p76). Taking the example of Heath’s (2013) ethnomethodological study of fine-art auctions, Atkinson insists that this should be complemented by ‘a thoroughgoing ethnography of market-making in fine art and antiques’ encompassing ‘a variety of settings and encounters’ such as ‘valuations, expert evaluation of art works and attributions of authorship, and evaluations of provenance’ (p123). Indeed, he goes beyond this to require that an ethnographic study of any group or setting should take in the broader society and its history. He writes: ‘Our ethnographic emphasis on real-time observation and recording should not blind us to the broader cultural, social and historical contexts in which ceremonial and discursive orders are created and sustained’ (p87).

This would be rejected by most ethnomethodologists, on the grounds that it involves a spurious and arbitrary imposition of an external notion of context. Atkinson declares at one point that ‘conversation analysts have sometimes been unwarrantably reluctant to engage with broader ethnographic forms of inquiry’ (p80). But he does not tell us why he believes that they have no warrant for this. While they have put forward arguments justifying their stance (see, for example, Maynard 2006), he gives no attention to these. I agree with him that their arguments are not convincing, but once this is recognised many of the reasons are removed for believing that interview data cannot be used as a source of information about the world, that social forms are the only legitimate topic for ethnography, that ethnographic documentation must always be at the level of detailed analysis of interactional materials, and that motives must be viewed solely as a matter of rhetoric.

Atkinson apparently sees no conflict between what I have referred to as naturalistic and constructionist stances. He writes: ‘the social construction of reality does not mean, and has never meant, that there is no material reality, or that phenomena are conjured up out of thin air, by whimsical acts of will or imagination’ (p21). But, in fact, constructionists do effectively deny the existence of a ‘material reality’ that shapes our behaviour, for example discourse analysts of some stripes have denied that there is anything ‘outside the text’, and as we have seen conversation analysts deny that there is anything beyond the context constituted in and through interactional processes. Moreover, it is hard to see how a consistent constructionism could avoid this.

Atkinson seeks to support his argument here by appeal to the Thomases’ dictum: ‘if men define situations as real, they are real in their consequences’ (Thomas and Thomas 1928:572).28 But he reformulates it as follows: ‘situations are real insofar as they are defined as real and are real in their consequences’ (pp21). It is important to note that Thomas and Thomas rely on a distinction between the objective character of a situation and people’s subjective perceptions of it. Their point is that even if those perceptions are erroneous they 28Goffman (1975:1) has commented that this dictum is true as stated but false as it is frequently interpreted.

Page 16: Atkinson - Martyn Hammersley Web viewowes something to a variety of sources, from Simmel and Goffman to ethnomethodology, but he does not address here the important differences among

16

can have real consequences. By contrast, Atkinson’s formulation seems to imply that situations are not real if they are not defined as real by participants. This points towards a constructionist rather than a naturalistic conception of context. Yet, later, Atkinson uses the same reformulation of the Thomases’ maxim but draws the conclusion that ‘situations, events and encounters have a reality that is relatively independent of the individual participants’, and he goes on to note that:

some constructivist approaches to sociological analysis have led to an undue emphasis on the “definition” aspect of Thomas’s dictum, as if situations could be endlessly defined and redefined indefinitely, with no regard to their conventional forms or actual participants. We need, perhaps, to remind ourselves of the social reality of the situation itself, which displays cultural regularities and social practices. (pp74-5)

There is an important ambiguity here, it seems to me, one that reflects the tension between naturalistic and constructionist stances.29

Atkinson could perhaps argue that his position is a productive eclecticism, and that what matters is the value of what is produced, rather than the internal consistency of the position in philosophical terms.30 However, as I have already noted, he has not addressed the issue of value in any sustained fashion, and assessing the value of what ethnography produces immediately raises questions about the criteria to be relied on, with naturalism and constructionism taking very different approaches. The former necessarily adopts some sort of correspondence conception of truth, as Atkinson does when he claims that ethnography can document ‘generic social processes’ or ‘indigenous forms of social organisation’. However, most constructionists cannot adopt this notion of truth consistently, since they treat accounts as constituting the reality documented, as Atkinson seems to do in his critique of interviews.

There is also the much more practical question of whether it is possible for ethnographers to cover the extent of relevant context that Atkinson envisages. As already noted, he emphasises the need for detailed analysis of talk along the lines of conversation analysis, accompanied by the study of non-verbal behaviour and immediate material context. He writes that ‘technologies now mean that the ethnographer can [...] complement general participant observation with participant recordings of encounters. [...] That is, we can examine the means and methods employed by parties to the encounter to display mutual attention. [...] Enactments of mutual attentiveness, for example, can be explored, identifying mutual gaze, attentiveness, body posture and proxemics (cf. Kendon 1990). Likewise, the relationship between speech and gesture is available for close analysis’. Doing this kind of analysis is a very tall order in itself, but combining it with careful attention to the wider societal and historical context in the way that he also recommends would be near impossible. A counsel of perfection seems to be involved here.

29There may be ways in which this ambiguity or uncertainty could be resolved, but Atkinson does not seem to recognise that there is a problem here. 30 At one point he describes ethnography as a form of bricolage (p160), and this notion could be applied to his use of methodological and theoretical ideas in this book. But, in my view, this is a problematic concept: see Hammersley 1999. It is important to remember that Lévi-Strauss drew a sharp contrast between science and bricolage, with art lying somewhere between the two.

Page 17: Atkinson - Martyn Hammersley Web viewowes something to a variety of sources, from Simmel and Goffman to ethnomethodology, but he does not address here the important differences among

17

A kind of foundationalism?

There is a further ambiguity in Atkinson’s work, this time derived from ethnomethodology itself, rather than arising from combining it with ethnographic naturalism. This concerns whether the kind of research he recommends is to be treated as a supplement to more traditional sorts of social science, as a replacement for these, or as a foundation for them. Sometimes, a commitment to ‘ethnomethodological indifference’ is expressed by ethnomethodologists, whereby social research is treated simply as one among many other members’ practices, and perhaps even analysed in these terms (see, for example, Greiffenhagen et al 2011). However, ethnomethodologists have also criticised traditional forms of sociology for adopting a false ideal, derived from taking natural science as a methodological model, in terms of which the task is seen as causal analysis. Garfinkel’s (2002) later argument that ethnomethodology is an ‘alternate’ to sociology encapsulates this ambiguity rather than resolving it.

In parallel with this, it is not clear whether Atkinson regards the kind of ethnography he practises, and recommends in this book, as the only legitimate form of social research or as providing a more solid foundation on which traditional kinds of social science could rely, in line with Schutz’s claims for his own more philosophical work on the phenomenology of the social world (Schutz 1967) or Simmel’s (1950:9) argument that ‘the study of less conspicuous forms of relationship and kinds of interaction’ is essential if we are to understand ‘the major social formations – the traditional subject matter of social science’.31 What is certainly true is that Atkinson sees the kind of ethnography he is promoting in his book as privileged over other kinds of social scientific work. But can this be justified?

Sociolinguistic studies of discourse forms and Goffman’s documentation of interactional forms clearly provide important resources that researchers can use in studying a wide range of substantive topics, in particular facilitating methodological assessments of likely threats to the validity of data and inferences from them, but it is less obvious that the other types of form that Atkinson refers to could serve this purpose. Moreover, his work offers not so much a foundation as a source of reminders and cautions. It certainly does not establish that all social research, or even all ethnography, should study discursive or interactional forms in detail, nor that social science requires such a foundation. At most, research on the organisation of social interaction, semiotic processes, and so on, can serve to complement and modify our experiential knowledge of social life, thereby improving the assumptions on which other sorts of analysis rely. This is to give the study of social forms 31Simmel seems to take the study of such behaviours as the distinctive focus of sociology, though he defines it as a ‘method’, or a form, rather than as being tied to any particular content, perhaps on the grounds that ‘sociation’ makes up human social life in all of the areas covered by other social sciences. See Simmel 1950:13-14. In these terms, sociology provides a foundation for these other sciences. Cicourel 1964 and 1968 also appears to put forward a foundationalist position, in the form of the idea that research cannot be rigorous unless it is based upon a full understanding of the means by which it is accomplished (on Cicourel’s position, see Smith and Atkinson 2015). So, for example, if researchers are to use interviews as a source of data they must gain a detailed understanding of the interview process that generated the data, and transparently document this process for readers. It seems to me that this is an echo of an argument to be found both in Cartesian rationalism and in positivism, and one that is false, since it would never be possible to produce a fully explicit account of any knowledge production process, any more than a formal demonstration of the validity of the knowledge concerned.

Page 18: Atkinson - Martyn Hammersley Web viewowes something to a variety of sources, from Simmel and Goffman to ethnomethodology, but he does not address here the important differences among

18

rather less importance than Atkinson seems to assign it; on the grounds of a constructionist formalism that, I have suggested, is not convincing.

Generating theory through abduction

Ethnomethodologists typically reject the idea that they are aiming to produce theories or explanations (concerned with why), instead they insist that their aim is description of social processes (in other words, a concern with how); more specifically, description of the methods by which people constitute the social world.32 Atkinson also emphasises description but he does not display the same aversion to theory. While he rejects the metaphor of theory-building (pp61-2), he argues that ‘we can and should move between different versions of local reality, in order to move our analysis to the generic level, developing concepts – even models – that capture recurrent features of social life across a range of social situations or cultural domains’ (p14), and he claims that ethnography has generated cumulative knowledge of this kind in some fields (pp36-7). So, he insists that, while ethnography requires ‘the methodical exploration, analysis, and re-construction of a given social world’ (p6), it also goes beyond this to produce ‘generic concepts and formal analyses that transcend the local and the particular’ (p14). In this sense he claims that ‘ethnography is generalisable’ (p34), this residing in our ‘capacity to generate reconstructions of social processes and social actors, in such a way as to remain faithful to the complexities of the particular setting, while drawing out the generic links and comparisons’ (p66).

Here Atkinson’s position is perhaps closer to that of Geertz than to ethnomethodology. Neither he nor Geertz seems to see any conflict between the production of idiographic description and of theoretical or explanatory understanding. Indeed, the latter is to be achieved through the former. But how? Do these not involve incompatible orientations (Gomm et al 2000; Hammersley 2008:ch3)?33 The problem involved here has already been mentioned: identifying recurrent, generic features in particular cases surely requires abstraction from some of the detail of those cases, that which is deemed irrelevant to the particular knowledge being pursued.

Atkinson’s proposed solution to this problem is abductive inference, a concept which he draws from the pragmatist tradition, and specifically from the work of Charles Peirce (Fann 1970). He writes that much of what passes for qualitative data analysis ‘is unhelpfully flat, reducing the complexity of everyday life to a set of themes that remain otherwise under-developed’, and suggests that:

an implicit emphasis on inductive logic, rather than the abductive logic in the original pragmatist tradition, can easily have a deadening effect on the conceptual complexity of the analysis. An adequate and sensitive understanding of a given cultural system or social setting may emerge from the ethnographer’s thorough knowledge of it, but it

32 I will leave on one side the question of how sustainable the distinction they make here is and whether in practice ethnomethodologists, for example conversation analysts, produce theoretical accounts. Much hinges on what the term ‘theory’ is being taken to mean: for an outline of the senses in current use, see Hammersley 2012.33 A similar problem arises with Simmel: see Tenbruck’s 1965 attempt to clarify what is involved in abstracting forms from contents in his work.

Page 19: Atkinson - Martyn Hammersley Web viewowes something to a variety of sources, from Simmel and Goffman to ethnomethodology, but he does not address here the important differences among

19

will not emerge from peering at ‘the data’. So we really must free notions of analysis from a close dependency on ‘data’. (p61)34

Later, he comments that: ‘we are in danger of losing sight of the role of imagination in the ethnographic enterprise. In contrast, we need collectively to encourage the sort of extrapolation and speculation that a thoroughly abductive logic implies’, suggesting that ‘our analysis therefore resides in the skill with which we interrogate simultaneously the local and the generic’ (pp66-7).

Atkinson’s conception of what abduction involves is similar in some respects to that of Peirce, for whom it involves the development of a potential explanation for some puzzling phenomenon not just through examining the phenomenon itself but also by drawing on experience of other similar and different cases, as well as by deploying both existing scientific knowledge and, as just noted, imagination.35 However, in many ways Peirce’s model of scientific inquiry is very different from what Atkinson seems to have in mind. Peirce treats abduction as aimed at developing a causal theory to explain some type of phenomenon, whereas Atkinson interprets it as addressing the question: ‘what is this a case of?’ (p65 and elsewhere) – a rather broader question, not specifically causal or explanatory in character. And this raises a more general issue about the character of the ethnographic product. I have already noted a tension between the declared goals of describing particular social worlds and documenting ‘generic processes’. But, aside from this, Atkinson seems to see the latter task as a form of description rather than of causal explanation. This contrasts with Peirce’s concern with developing scientific theories that capture causal relations.

For this reason, Peirce saw abduction as one among several modes of reasoning (including deduction and induction) that all play a crucial role in scientific inquiry, he did not treat it as standing alone. For him, abduction led to theoretical ideas from which implications must be deduced, and these hypotheses were then to be tested in order to assess the likely validity of the theory, a process he sometimes referred to as retroduction. As with most other qualitative researchers who have appealed to the concept of abduction (for example, Tavory and Timmermans 2014), Atkinson neglects these complementary forms of reasoning, and thereby apparently the need for testing the accounts generated through abduction. Perhaps he regards it as simultaneously generating and testing the ethnographic account produced, but as we have seen he emphasises the role of imagination in abduction and the need to gain distance from the data, thereby minimising any empirical constraint on the accounts produced.36

34 It seems to me that there is a puzzle here, given that Atkinson also places such great emphasis on collecting very detailed data about the processes of social interaction being studied, not just talk but also non-verbal behaviour, spatial arrangements, material artefacts, etc. The apparent contradiction may perhaps be explained in terms of commitment to an iterative phase model: that ‘peering’ at the data is essential but that it must alternate with periods when a more distanced approach is adopted that allows for creative imagination in developing or refining concepts.35 In fact, Peirce emphasises the role of intuition as much as creative imagination, regarding intuition as an evolutionary product.36 This neglect of the testing of hypotheses is perhaps encouraged or at least facilitated by the oscillation between realism and constructionism.

Page 20: Atkinson - Martyn Hammersley Web viewowes something to a variety of sources, from Simmel and Goffman to ethnomethodology, but he does not address here the important differences among

20

Atkinson writes: ‘the ideal-typical concepts and models feed directly into the analysis of the local case, while the particularities of the local setting(s) contribute to an elaboration of the general model’ (p70). At the same time, he declares that these ideal typical concepts are metaphors which ‘have to be “found” through the imaginative work of abduction, whereby general categories are drawn out from the particularities of local situations, and settings, events and activities’ (p71). This illustrates the lack of emphasis on the need to test interpretations, and the quote marks around ‘found’ underline this. Furthermore, as already noted, it is not clear how a ‘general model’ is to be produced in the way described, given that any such model always selects and simplifies, rather than simply reproducing complexity.37

So, while for Peirce abduction is concerned with developing a theory that identifies a scientific law specifying the causal relationships operating among particular types of phenomena under specifiable conditions, it is fairly clear that this is not what Atkinson envisages, even when he refers to understanding generic social processes.38 Atkinson’s use of the term ‘ideal type’ (pp36-7) perhaps signals this. Yet at the same time his usage does not follow the model of Max Weber, for whom the focus of social science was on producing singular causal explanations for value-relevant phenomena (ideal types being the means of achieving this).39 Here, an examination of the differences between Simmel and Weber may be fruitful. By contrast with Weber, Simmel is concerned with providing general understanding of how particular social forms emerge via processes of social interaction, and how they gain independent force so as to act back on those processes.40 /.However, he is vague about the nature of this understanding and how it can be achieved. Nor does Goffman provide much clarification of these matters as regards his own work. And Atkinson, like Goffman, shows a decided reluctance to engage with such philosophical issues. Here a non-philosophical pragmatism may be in operation, but this is very much at odds with the spirit of Peirce, or even for that matter of James, Dewey, and Mead. Moreover, for the reasons I outlined at the start, I believe that the need for epistemological justification is unavoidable, albeit tailored to the context of social science and its publics rather than to the discipline of philosophy.41

37 Atkinson uses Oscar Lewis’s concept of the ‘culture of poverty’ as an example of a concept produced through abduction. It is worth noting, though, that Lewis’s (1959, 1968, 1972) research practice was significantly different from what is recommended by Atkinson, involving reportage of a single day in the life of five families, and reliance on in-depth interviews with family members. Moreover, his research was concerned with the substantive issue of poverty, rather than with social forms in the manner of Simmel or Goffman.38 There are serious doubts about whether the kind of theory assumed by Peirce is achievable in social science. My own view is that theorising in social science necessarily takes the form of the clarification and elaboration of plausible ideas about motivation, unintended consequences, etc., these coming from experience and commonsense as well as from research evidence, so as to produce rational models or other sorts of ideal type. Interestingly, much of Goffman’s work can be interpreted in this way, as producing concepts that are focused on people’s social identities and sense of personal worth, along with the effect of actions, personal characteristics, and institutional arrangements on these, and how people work to preserve their sense of self in the face of potential and actual challenges.39Atkinson is, perhaps, picking up on Goffman’s use of this concept in Asylums (Goffman 1968:17).40Tenbruck (1965:84-9) emphasises the similarities between Simmel’s notion of ‘pure forms’ and Weber’s concept of ‘ideal type’, but it seems to me that the differences between their approaches are greater than his discussion suggests. For the background to my interpretation of Weber here, see Hammersley 2015.41 We should also note that in producing his illuminating account of various social forms Simmel did not employ the kind of intensive ethnography that Atkinson recommends. And much the same is true of Goffman’s work as well, even the early books on The Presentation of Self in Everyday Life (1959) and Asylums (1968) are only partial exceptions. See Manning’s (1992:ch7) useful discussion of his methods. This perhaps raises the question:

Page 21: Atkinson - Martyn Hammersley Web viewowes something to a variety of sources, from Simmel and Goffman to ethnomethodology, but he does not address here the important differences among

21

Research ethics

I will end by discussing a theme that is largely separate from those I have mentioned up to now: Atkinson’s treatment of research ethics, to which he devotes his final chapter. While I agree with much of what he says there, once again there are a few disagreements and doubts. Some of these concern ethical regulation: while he is critical of this, I think he underplays what is wrong with it. The problem is not simply that it is based on false, indeed unsociological, assumptions about the nature of the social world, or that it frequently relies on a defective understanding of social inquiry, but also that it is unethical in significant respects and ineffective in its own terms. What is required is not its improvement but its abolition (Hammersley 2009).

A second point is that Atkinson’s criticisms of randomised controlled trials (RCTs) on ethical grounds are excessive. While the notion of ethical equipoise is by no means unproblematic, I am not convinced that ‘the very principle of the RCT is ethically flawed’ (p173). To his question ‘what could be less ethical than determining a person’s medical treatment not on need but on the basis of a random-number generator?’, advocates of RCTs would reply, with some justification: ‘administering medical treatments whose effectiveness is unknown, that may have no value, or even be damaging’. Both sides of this argument have force, and they encapsulate a very difficult dilemma.

By contrast, Atkinson argues that ethnography is intrinsically ethical. Presumably this means that he believes that if it is done well it will be ethical, that it can only be unethical if done badly. However, in my view, ethical concerns are never intrinsic to the process of inquiry, even though they are an essential external constraint (Hammersley and Traianou 2012). Atkinson puts forward several rationales for his position. He writes that ethnography is ‘a profoundly ethical form of enterprise, based as it is on a commitment to other people’s everyday lives’ (p5). But this statement is misleading: ethnography is certainly committed to understanding aspects of people’s lives, but that is different from being committed to those lives, which would imply a concern with protecting, or even serving, people’s interests. And, in fact, these two commitments will often diverge.

Another formulation that Atkinson uses is that by its very nature ethnography respects the people being studied. This presumably arises from the fact that, from his point of view, the ethnographer is concerned with explicating and documenting the knowledge and skills involved in human activities. However, as I explained earlier, I regard this as an overly restrictive conception of the task of ethnography, and one that does not match much that has previously gone under this name, in both sociology and anthropology. Aside from this, a great deal depends upon what is meant by ‘respect’. This word’s usual reference surely extends beyond recognising that people deploy diverse and sophisticated cultural resources in what they do. In the context of research ethics, it would usually mean taking account of their right not to be subject to unwarranted harm, deception, or invasion of privacy. But there is nothing intrinsic to good ethnography that will ensure this, it seems to me – unless these

is it necessary to do ethnography in order to document social forms? Atkinson seems to assume that it is, but his appeal to the work of Simmel and Goffman is at odds with this.

Page 22: Atkinson - Martyn Hammersley Web viewowes something to a variety of sources, from Simmel and Goffman to ethnomethodology, but he does not address here the important differences among

22

considerations are being built into what counts as ‘good’, in which case the formulation is circular. Indeed, there is a tension between the demands of effective research and those of research ethics. For example, ethnographers often spend a great deal of effort on self-presentation and building trust with people so as to gain access to the data they need. Also involved here is a concern with minimising reactivity, which in effect means encouraging people to forget that they are being researched. Both these aspects of ethnographic work could be, and indeed have been, criticised as showing a lack of respect, or more broadly as unethical.42 Finally, sometimes ‘respect’ can even mean thinking highly of people or approving of them. But ethnographers will not always respect the people they study in these terms, nor should they do so; and there would be little justification for restricting the focus to people who can be respected in this sense.43

Atkinson offers a further justification for the intrinsically ethical character of ethnography. He declares that ‘‘the highest ethical imperative is, from my own point of view, fidelity to everyday life and its complex, detailed processes’. But while it is true that, like other kinds of social research, ethnography is committed to epistemic values, above all truth, these are not what is usually treated as central to research ethics. Moreover, I have already raised questions about the notion of fidelity to everyday life as a characterisation of the task of ethnography. While Atkinson is certainly right about the importance of commitment to epistemic values, and that these are frequently neglected in discussions of research ethics, it should be clear that researchers can pursue truth while being unethical in the manner in which they do this. Many of the Nazi medical researchers put on trial at Nuremberg were not, as far as one can tell, primarily concerned with inflicting pain on their victims but rather with finding out, for example, what the human body could survive. They were committed to epistemic values but their practices were grossly unethical. Much the same would have been true of an ethnographic study of their work, however soundly carried out in methodological terms.

Conclusion

In discussing Atkinson’s book, I have concentrated on problems and disagreements. These reflect fundamental antinomies that underlie the field of social research methodology today. They are important but also difficult to resolve, and they should not obscure the fact that this is an extremely valuable book, especially for the guidance it provides about doing ethnography, as regards generating fruitful analytic perspectives and taking seriously formal aspects of social life. While in my view the book is much less successful in promoting ethnography as an approach within social science, it nevertheless sets out a particular position with clarity and force. More than this, it serves as an important and necessary challenge to much current practice in qualitative research. Atkinson may not regard the issues I have raised as needing resolution for sound ethnographic work to be done, but in my view they

42 See MacIntyre 1993, Homan 2001, and Hammersley 2014.43 Perhaps Atkinson takes ‘respecting people’ to mean not criticising them? As I noted earlier, his position appears to rule out questioning whether they are telling the truth, and in particular scrutinising whether they actually do what they say they do. However, I suggested that there are no grounds for this, and indeed that these concerns are central to much ethnographic work. There are also questions about whether refusing to evaluate the truth of what people say constitutes showing respect.

Page 23: Atkinson - Martyn Hammersley Web viewowes something to a variety of sources, from Simmel and Goffman to ethnomethodology, but he does not address here the important differences among

23

must to be tackled if social inquiry, including ethnography, is to flourish, and perhaps even to survive, in what is an extremely challenging present and likely future. While I certainly agree that there is a great deal of misleading and often inept methodological philosophising about qualitative research, there are nevertheless fundamental issues that require attention, as Atkinson (1988) himself emphasised in his discussion of ethnomethodology some years ago. They may not be resolvable in any straightforward sense, and total agreement about them is unlikely, but they must be faced. By providing a distinctive account of the task and requirements of ethnography, Atkinson’s book is an excellent stimulus to reflection about them.

References

Adler, P., Adler, P., and Fontana, A. (1987) ‘Everyday life sociology’, Annual Review of Sociology, 13, pp217-35.

Atkinson, P. (1988) ‘Ethnomethodology’, Annual Review of Sociology, 14, pp441-65.

Atkinson, P. (2013) ‘The mastersingers: Language and practice in an operatic master class‘, Ethnography and Education, 8, 3, pp355-70.

Atkinson, P., Delamont, S., and Housley, W. (2008) Contours of Culture: Complex ethnography and the ethnography of complexity, Walnut Creek CA, Altamira.

Bruce, S. and Wallis, R. (1983) ‘Rescuing motives’, British Journal of Sociology, 34, 1, pp61-71.

Bruce, S. and Wallis, R. (1985) ‘“Rescuing Motives” Rescued: A Reply to Sharrock and Watson’, British Journal of Sociology, 36, 3, pp467-470.

Button, G. (ed.) (1991) Ethnomethodology and the Human Sciences, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.

Button, G. and Sharrock, W. (1993) ‘A disagreement over agreement and consensus in constructionist sociology’, Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 23, pp1-25.

Carroll, L. (2001) ‘Sylvie and Bruno Concluded’, in The Complete Stories and Poems of Lewis Carroll, New Lanark, Midpoint Press. (First published in 1893.)

Cicourel, A. (1964) Method and Measurement in Sociology, New York, Free Press.

Cicourel, A. (1968) The Social Organization of Juvenile Justice, New York, Wiley.

Collins, H. M., (1981) `Understanding Science', Fundamenta Scientiae, 2, pp367-80.

Dingwall, R. (1997) ‘Accounts, interviews and observations’, in Miller, G. and Dingwall, R. (eds) Context and Method in Qualitative Research, London, Sage.

Durkheim, E. (1965) ‘Sociology and its scientific field’, in Coser, L. (ed.) Georg Simmel, Englewood Cliffs NJ, Prentice-Hall. (Translation first published in K. Wolff (ed.) Emile

Page 24: Atkinson - Martyn Hammersley Web viewowes something to a variety of sources, from Simmel and Goffman to ethnomethodology, but he does not address here the important differences among

24

Durkheim, 1859-1917: A collection of essays, with translations and a bibliography, Columbus Ohio, Ohio State University Press, 1960, pp335-59.)

Emmett, I. (1964) A North Wales Village: a social anthropological study, London, Routledge and Kegan Paul.

Fann, K. T. (1970) Peirce’s Theory of Induction, The Hague, Martinus Nijhof

Garfinkel, H. (1967) Studies in Ethnomethodology, Englewood Cliffs NJ, Prentice-Hall.

Garfinkel, H. (2002) Ethnomethodology’s Program, Lanham MD, Rowman and Littlefield.

Goffman, E. (1975) Frame Analysis, Harmondsworth, Penguin.

Gomm, R., Hammersley, M., and Foster, P. (eds) (2000) Case Study Method, London, Sage.

Greiffenhagen, C., Mair, M. and Sharrock, W. (2011) ‘From methodology to methodography: a study of qualitative and quantitative reasoning in practice’, Methodological Innovations Online, 6, 3, pp93 – 107.

Hammersley, M. (1992)What’s Wrong with Ethnography?, London, Routledge.

Hammersley, M. (1999) ‘Not bricolage but boat-building: exploring two metaphors for thinking about ethnography’, Journal of Contemporary Ethnography, 28, 6, pp574-85.

Hammersley, M. (2006) ‘Ethnography: problems and prospects’, Ethnography and Education, 1, 1, pp3-14.

Hammersley, M. (2008) Questioning Qualitative Inquiry, London, Sage.

Hammersley, M. (2009) ‘Against the ethicists: on the evils of ethical regulation’, International Journal of Social Research Methodology, 12, 3, pp211–225.

Hammersley, M. (2012) ‘Troubling theory in case study research’, Higher Education Research and Development, 31, 3, pp393-405.

Hammersley, M. (2013) What is Qualitative Research?, London, Bloomsbury Academic.

Hammersley, M. (2014) ‘On the ethics of interviewing for discourse analysis’, Qualitative Research, 14, 5, pp529-41.

Hammersley, M. (2015) The Limits of Social Science, London, Sage.

Hammersley, M. and Gomm, R. (2008) ‘Assessing the radical critique of interviews’, in Hammersley, M. Questioning Qualitative Inquiry, London, Sage.

Hammersley, M. and Traianou, A. (2012) Ethics in Qualitative Research, London, Sage.

Hammersley, M. and Treseder, P. (2007) ‘Identity as an analytic problem: who’s who in “pro-ana” websites?’, Qualitative Research, 7, 3, pp283-300.

Page 25: Atkinson - Martyn Hammersley Web viewowes something to a variety of sources, from Simmel and Goffman to ethnomethodology, but he does not address here the important differences among

25

Heath, C. (2013) The Dynamics of Auction: Social interaction and the sale of fine art and antiques, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.

Homan, R. (2001) ‘The principle of assumed consent: the ethics of gatekeeping’, Journal of the Philosophy of Education, 35, 3, pp329-43.

Housley, W. (2008) ‘Motives and social organization: sociological amnesia, psychological description and the analysis of accounts’, Qualitative Research, 8, 2, pp237-56.

Kalekin-Fishman, D. (2013) ‘Review article: Sociology of everyday life’, Current Sociology, 61, 5-6, pp714–732.

Kendon, A. (1990) Conducting Interaction: Patterns of behaviour in focused encounters, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.

Labov, W. (2013) The Language of Life and Death: the transformation of experience in oral narrative, New York, Cambridge University Press.

Lewis, O. (1959) Five Families: Mexican case studies in the culture of poverty, New York, Basic Books.

Lewis, O. (1968) La Vida, London, Panther.

Lewis, O. (1972) A Death in the Sanchez Family, Harmondsworth, Penguin.

Lynch, M. (1991) Scientific Practice and Ordinary Action, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.

MacIntyre, A. (1993) ‘Ethical dilemmas: notes from outside the field’, American Anthropological Association Newsletter, October.

Manning, P. (1992) Erving Goffman and Modern Sociology, Cambridge, Polity.

Maynard, D. (2006) ‘Ethnography and conversation analysis: what is the context of an utterance?’ in Hesse-Biber, S. and Leavy, P. L. (eds) Emergent Methods in Social Research, London, Sage.

Mills, C. W. (1940) ‘Situated actions and vocabularies of motive’, American Sociological Review, 5, pp904-13.

Murphy, E., Dingwall, R., Greatbatch, D. Parker, S., and Watson, P. (1998) ‘Qualitative research methods in health technology assessment: a review of the literature’, Health Technology Assessment, 2 (16), pp1-260.

Nicolis, G. and Prigogine, I. (1989) Exploring Complexity, New York, W.H. Freeman.

Oakes, G. (1980) ‘Introduction’, in Simmel, G. Essays on Interpretation in Social Science, Manchester, Manchester University Press.

Pink, S. (2012) Situating Everyday Life, London, Sage.

Page 26: Atkinson - Martyn Hammersley Web viewowes something to a variety of sources, from Simmel and Goffman to ethnomethodology, but he does not address here the important differences among

26

Potter, J. and Hepburn, A. (2005) ‘Qualitative interviews in psychology: problems and possibilities’, Qualitative Research in Psychology, 2, 4, pp281-307.

Radcliffe-Brown, A. R. (1923) ‘The methods of ethnology and social anthropology’, South African Journal of Science, 20, pp124-47.

Schegloff, E. (1988) ‘Goffman and the analysis of conversation’, in Drew, P. and Wootton, A. (eds) Erving Goffman: Exploring the Interaction Order, Cambridge, Polity.

Schegloff, E. (2007) Sequence Organization in Interaction, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.

Schutz, A. (1967) The Phenomenology of the Social World, Evanston ILL, Northwestern University Press. (First published in German in 1932.)

Searle, J. (1995) The Construction of Social Reality, London, Penguin.

Sharrock, W. and Watson, R. (1984) ‘What's the Point of 'Rescuing Motives'?, British Journal of Sociology, 35, 3, pp435-451.

Sharrock, W. and Watson, R. (1986) ‘Re-Locating Motives’, British Journal of Sociology, 37, 4, pp 581-583.

Silverman, D. (1993) Interpreting Qualitative Data, London, Sage.

Simmel, G. (1950) ‘The field of sociology’, in Wolff (ed.)

Simmel, G. (1977) The Problems of the Philosophy of History, New York, Free Press.

Simmel, G. (1980) Essays on Interpretation in Social Science, Manchester, Manchester University Press.

Sztompka, P. (2008) ‘The focus on everyday life: A new turn in sociology’, European Review, 16, 1, pp1–15.

Tavory, I. and Timmermans, S. (2014) Abductive Analysis: Theorizing qualitative research, Chicago, University of Chicago Press.

Tenbruck, F. (1965) ‘Formal sociology’, in Coser, L. (ed.) Georg Simmel, Englewood Cliffs NJ, Prentice-Hall. (Translation first published in K. Wolff (ed.) Georg Simmel, 1858-1918: A collection of essays, with translations and a bibliography, Columbus Ohio, Ohio State University Press, 1959.)

Thomas, W. I. and Thomas, D. S. (1928) The Child in America, New York, A. A. Knopf.

Walford, G. (2009) ‘For ethnography’, Ethnography and Education, 4, 3, pp271-82.

Watson, D. R. (1992) ‘The understanding of language use in everyday life: Is there common ground?, in Watson, G. and Seiler, R. (eds) Text and Context, Newbury Park CA, Sage.

Page 27: Atkinson - Martyn Hammersley Web viewowes something to a variety of sources, from Simmel and Goffman to ethnomethodology, but he does not address here the important differences among

27

Watson, D. R. (1999) ‘Reading Goffman on interaction’, (pp138-55) in Smith, G. (ed.) Goffman and Social Organisation, London, Routledge.

Williams, M. (2001) Problems of Knowledge, Oxford, Oxford University Press.

Wolff, K. (ed.) (1950) The Sociology of Georg Simmel, New York, Free Press.