anthropology of religious belief

Upload: garrison-doreck

Post on 02-Jun-2018

218 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/10/2019 Anthropology of Religious Belief

    1/18

    Religious Belief

    Author(s): Martin SouthwoldSource: Man, New Series, Vol. 14, No. 4 (Dec., 1979), pp. 628-644Published by: Royal Anthropological Institute of Great Britain and IrelandStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2802151.

    Accessed: 19/05/2013 13:38

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at.http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

    .JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of

    content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new formsof scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    .

    Royal Anthropological Institute of Great Britain and Irelandis collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve

    and extend access toMan.

    http://www.jstor.org

    This content downloaded from 169.234.126.240 on Sun, 19 May 2013 13:38:31 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=raihttp://www.jstor.org/stable/2802151?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/2802151?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=rai
  • 8/10/2019 Anthropology of Religious Belief

    2/18

    RELIGIOUS BELIEF

    MARTIN OUTHWOLD

    Universityf

    Manchester

    Those who loyally

    ubscribe o a

    religionnormally

    do believe at

    least tsbasic

    tenets.

    uch

    believing

    s an

    important art

    of

    religiousbehaviour,

    nd we should

    understand

    nd describe

    it more exactly.

    To

    dismissbelief as a matter

    for

    psychology

    s

    an

    error,

    which rests n

    a

    fallacy. hough Leach

    has

    fallen

    nto this rror

    he has also

    pointed

    o

    a fruitful

    pproach.

    The

    truth f at leastbasicreligious enets s differentromfactual ruth: tmaybe calledsymbolic

    truth.

    t is

    argued

    that basic

    religious

    tenets are

    empirically indeterminate, xiomatic,

    symbolic,

    nd

    collective.

    From

    this

    the

    mostappropriate ognitive

    attitude o

    them

    can be

    inferred: t

    is

    suggested

    hat

    religious

    belief

    may commonly approximate

    o this.

    Religious

    believersdo not ack

    rationality

    n

    believing

    enets

    which have the

    four

    haracteristicsoted:

    it would

    be less

    rational o prefer rticles f

    faithwhich did not have

    them.

    I

    Justwhat does belief' mean n

    a

    religious

    ontext?

    Of all the

    problems urrounding ttempts

    to conduct anthropological nalysisof religionthis s theone thathas perhapsbeen most

    troublesome

    and

    therefore

    he most often

    voided, usually by relegating

    t

    to psychology,

    that

    raffish utcast

    discipline

    to which social

    anthropologists

    re forever

    consigning

    phenomena they

    are unable to deal with

    within

    the

    framework

    of a

    denatured

    Durkheimianism. ut theproblem

    will

    not go away,

    t

    s not merely' psychological nothing

    social is),

    and no

    anthropological heory f religion which fails o attack t is worthyof the

    name

    (Geertz I966: 24-5).

    Shortly

    fterwards each

    produced

    n

    apt llustration

    f this vasion when

    he wrote,

    n

    his paper Virgin birth':

    When an

    ethnographer eports

    hat

    members of the X

    tribe believe

    that.

    .

    .' he is

    giving

    a

    description f anorthodoxy, dogma, somethingwhich strueof the culture s a whole. But

    Professor

    piro (and all theneo-Tylorianswho think ike him) desperatelywants to believe

    that the

    evidence

    can tell us

    much more

    than that-that dogma and ritual must somehow

    correspond to the

    inner

    psychological attitudesof the actors concerned. We need only

    consider he customs f

    our

    own

    society

    o

    see

    that his s not

    so

    (Leach I967: 40).

    II

    By

    these remarks each

    appears

    to be

    saying

    that

    an ethnographic eport

    that

    people

    believe a certain

    roposition eports

    heir dherence o a

    dogma

    andonly hat: tdoesnottell us that hepeoplebelieve-in theordinary ense

    of

    'hold as

    true' -the proposition.Put like this, the contention ppears

    implausible,not

    to

    say perverse.2 each's reference o 'inner psychological

    attitudes',

    n

    place

    of the second believe',

    serves o obscure this fact. t also

    provides

    an

    argument, lbeit fallacious,

    n

    support f the contention.And it

    Man

    (N.S.) 4, 628-44.

    This content downloaded from 169.234.126.240 on Sun, 19 May 2013 13:38:31 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Anthropology of Religious Belief

    3/18

    MARTIN SOUTHWOLD 629

    also

    has the effect

    f

    confounding

    wo contentions:

    he one

    we have

    noticed,

    which s

    wrong,

    nd

    anotherwhich s

    right

    nd fruitful.

    Let us firstustify ur interpretationf inner psychological ttitudes' s a

    paraphrase or believe'.

    i) Immediately

    fter he

    passage ited,

    each writes f

    women

    going through

    the Englishmarriage ervice,which

    he

    briefly

    utlines.He

    comments:

    But

    all

    this tells me absolutely nothing

    about the inner

    psychological

    state of the

    lady

    in

    question: I cannot nfer rom he ritual itherwhat

    she feels r what

    she

    knows. She

    may

    be

    an outright theist.Alternatively

    he

    may

    believe

    that

    church

    marriage

    s essential

    or

    the

    well-beingof her future hildren I967: 40).

    2) Leach explainswhat he is trying o say.

    ... partly I am interested n the problem of method .. how should we interpret

    ethnographical tatementsbout palpable untruth?

    . .

    Why

    do all

    thesepeople believe

    in

    somethingwhich is untrue? I967: 44).

    Intermittentlyt least,Leach supposes hatwe have to understand eports

    that

    people

    believe

    what s

    palpably

    untruefor

    hem:

    hat,

    hat

    s,they

    do not

    believe,

    .e.

    hold as true.

    3) Spiro interpreted

    each's words

    as I have: thus he

    summarises

    each's

    argument

    s

    containing:

    ... two main theses: the culturalbelief

    concerning onception

    does not

    mean what it

    says,

    and,even if tdoes,the nativesdo notbelievewhat itsays

    I968:

    243).

    4)

    So too did Needham

    (I972: 5-7);

    thus

    n

    repudiating

    each's

    approach

    he

    states

    luntly:

    Something

    that

    s

    believed

    by nobody

    is not a

    belief...

    (I972: 6).

    Now

    there

    s

    a

    grain

    of truth n this ontentionwhich we

    have understood

    fromLeach's

    words. t does

    happen

    that

    ndividuals

    who

    publicly dhere

    o a

    dogma nevertheless,

    ore or less

    privately,

    isbelieve t:

    certainly

    found

    his

    among my

    Sinhalese

    nformants. here can be situationsn

    which

    a

    dogma

    is

    maintained

    n

    a

    society

    ven

    though most,conceivablyall,

    members f the

    societydisbelieve t. But it is mostunlikely hat a competent thnographer

    reporting

    n such a situationwould

    barelyreport

    hat

    he

    people

    believe the

    dogma:

    he

    would

    surely realise,

    nd

    report,

    hat the

    people

    maintain the

    dogma

    but

    do

    not

    believe it.

    If

    a

    competent thnographer eports

    hat

    his

    people

    believe

    something,

    e

    surely

    means hat

    hey

    do

    believe

    t,

    .e. hold it as

    true

    n

    some

    sense.

    Leach

    was misled

    by

    the few

    obscure

    reports

    which

    appear

    to

    say

    that

    certain

    peoples

    maintain

    dogma

    that

    opulation

    does not

    cause

    conception:

    which,

    as

    he

    argues,

    mustbe

    palpably

    untrue orthem. do

    not

    wish to take

    space

    to

    re-open

    his

    hoary ontroversy;

    ut t

    shouldbe

    remarked hat

    Leach,

    like many otheranthropologists, isreadthe evidence.The principal

    ocus

    disputandi

    as

    a

    passage by

    W. E. Roth

    describing group

    of

    Australian

    Aborigines;

    t

    may conveniently

    e consulted n

    Spiro I968: 242, citingRoth

    I903:

    22. Leach seems to

    have

    supposed

    that Roth

    reported that these

    Aborigines

    maintained

    hat

    opulation

    s not a

    cause of

    conception.But Roth

    This content downloaded from 169.234.126.240 on Sun, 19 May 2013 13:38:31 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Anthropology of Religious Belief

    4/18

    630

    MARTIN

    SOUTHWOLD

    did not. What he wrote was that heydo not recognise' his onnexion.There

    is a subtle distinction etween not recognising fact n certain ontexts

    f

    discourse, nd denying hat t s a fact. his is similar o the distinction hich

    Spiro (I968: 256)

    draws between

    gnoring

    known fact nd

    being gnorant

    that t

    s a

    fact.

    Malinowski

    was indeed more

    positive

    bout the

    Trobrianders,

    oth

    n his

    early eportI9I6) and n hismore onsideredater ccountI932: I53-78).

    He reports ategorically

    hat heTrobrianders

    eniedthat

    onception

    s

    caused

    by copulation.

    But

    he

    also makes

    it obvious

    why they

    did. Christian

    missionaries

    ad

    preached

    the doctrine nd ideal

    of

    Paternity' gainst

    the

    Trobriandethos:

    Only during my third xpeditionto New Guinea did I discoverthatthenativeshad been

    somewhat exasperatedby having an 'absurdity' preached

    at

    them,

    and

    by findingme,

    so

    unmissionary' s

    a

    rule, ngaged

    n the same futile

    rgument I932:

    I

    59).

    What

    people say

    n

    understandable

    xasperation ught

    not

    be

    interpreted,

    or

    reported, s their stablished ogma,

    still ess s what

    they

    believe.

    When ethnographerseport

    hat heir

    eople

    believe

    something, hey

    mean

    what

    their words

    would

    naturally

    be understood o mean.

    They may

    be

    mistaken

    r

    confused bout the

    facts,

    s Malinowski

    was, ust

    as

    theymay

    be

    wrong

    about facts f other

    kinds.But

    it

    does

    not

    appear

    that our

    fallibility

    concerningbelieving

    s of such

    an

    exceptional

    order that

    all

    ascriptions

    f

    believing must be discounted.Leach does, however, seem to imply that,

    whatever

    thnographersmean,

    we cannottake

    their

    reports

    s

    evidence

    that

    dogmas

    are

    believed,

    in

    the

    ordinary

    sense

    of

    the term.

    By referring

    o

    believing

    s inner

    psychological

    ttitudes'

    each

    suggests

    hat t

    is,

    normally

    at

    least,

    unknowable

    because

    naccessible.

    e

    confirmed hatthiswas

    indeed

    his

    mplication

    when he

    wrote,

    n

    a

    letter eplying

    o his

    critics:

    I claim that he

    anthropologist

    as

    absolutely

    no information bout what

    is

    inwardlyfeltby

    any professed

    eliever

    I 968:

    65

    5).

    On

    a

    simple nterpretation

    his s

    plainlyuntrue;

    n a

    subtler

    nterpretation,

    whichLeachsurely ntended,trests n a confusion.Whatevermaybe thecase

    regarding

    vowals of

    believing

    n

    the

    first

    erson 'I

    believe

    .

    .'),

    t s

    fallacious

    to

    supposethatascriptions

    f

    believingto

    a

    thirdparty 'he believes . .' or

    indeed they believe.. .') necessarily escribe

    his inner tate

    f

    mind, nd are

    thereforenwarranted

    o

    the extent

    hathis nner tate

    f

    mind s

    unknown.

    I

    explain below (p. 633) why this s a fallacy, howing that ascriptions f

    believing

    to others

    re

    statements

    bout theirobservable

    behaviour,

    which

    ethnographers

    an

    make,

    hould

    make,

    nd do

    make,

    for hemost

    partreliably

    and

    informatively.

    s

    Geertz

    said,

    to

    categorise uestions

    bout

    believing

    as

    psychological,

    nd thus

    beyond

    our

    competence,

    s to shirk

    ssues

    of

    major

    anthropological oncern n which we can,andshould,bringourcompetence

    to bear.

    III

    Leach's

    unsatisfactory

    ormulation

    istracts he reader from another, nd

    valuable,

    contention

    hat

    an be understood rom

    ater

    parts

    f

    his paper. He

    This content downloaded from 169.234.126.240 on Sun, 19 May 2013 13:38:31 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Anthropology of Religious Belief

    5/18

    MARTIN SOUTHWOLD

    63I

    comes to concede

    that n ethnographic eport hat people

    believesomething

    does imply

    that

    hey

    hold

    it

    to be true

    n

    some sense:

    the mportant uestion

    then s, nwhat sense?

    If we are

    not

    Tylorians

    we can

    say

    what Powell's Trobriand

    informants aid.

    There are

    different indsof truth.Which

    is also what good Catholics say

    .. (I967: 44).

    An alternative

    way ofexplaining

    beliefwhich isfactually

    ntrue

    s

    to

    say

    that

    t s a

    species

    of religious

    dogma; thetruthwhich it expresses

    oes not relate o

    the

    ordinary

    matter-of-fact

    world of everyday hingsbut

    to metaphysicsI967: 45).

    This takes

    us right away from the obscurantism

    f 'inner psychological

    attitudes'.

    t

    directs

    ur

    attention

    o

    the cognitive ttitudes-which,

    though

    inferential,

    re inferable

    from

    overt

    behaviour-appropriate

    to truthsof

    differentinds. t invites sto examinewhether elieving-holding astrue-

    is a more complex and subtle

    matter hanwe have sometimes

    upposed.

    In English

    heword true'has

    a

    wide span

    of meaning.Much the ame seems

    to

    apply

    to

    parallel

    terms

    n other

    anguages

    e.g.

    Dinka: Lienhardt

    96I:

    I

    39):

    and thismight

    ause

    an

    ethnographer

    o

    misinterpret

    hat

    an informant

    is sayingwhenhe employs

    uch a term.But it is more

    important o consider

    the

    meaning

    f our

    English

    word:

    chiefly

    ecause his ffects

    ow we use true'

    and

    hence

    hold astrue', .e. believe';

    and

    perhaps

    lso because

    similar

    attern

    may

    be

    present

    n

    other

    anguages.

    The

    ShorterOxford

    EnglishDictionary

    lists ixteen

    enses nd sub-senses

    or

    theadjective

    true'.

    Only one

    of these

    s

    specified s of a statementr belief', nd this s:

    'Consistentwith

    fact; greeing

    with reality;representing

    he thing s it s'.

    This is

    of course

    heordinary,r unmarked,

    ense f true' n modernEnglish;

    I

    shall refer o it henceforth

    s 'factual truth'.Some of

    the other senses, r

    something ikethem,might

    be applied topropositions,nd

    notablyreligious

    tenets. nspection uggests

    hat themewhichunderlies

    most, f not all, senses

    is the notion

    of

    fitting',

    whether

    n

    the direct ense

    of

    taking

    ts

    place

    in

    a

    structure, hysical,

    ocial,

    or

    conceptual,

    or

    in

    the derived sense

    of

    being

    'proper', appropriate',

    seemly'. Indeed we

    say that factuallyrue tatement

    'fits hefacts'.)

    It is conceivable, hen, hat personwho

    describes dogma

    as true' might

    mean that

    t

    is

    seemly: presumably

    most adherentswould

    consentto that.

    There

    are

    in

    our own society, nd presumably

    n others,

    ersonswho regard

    religious enets

    s eyewash,but appropriate

    or keeping

    the lower orders n

    their

    properplace.

    But

    I

    assume that

    such attitudes, eld exclusively,

    re

    exceptional;

    mostof

    thosewho believe

    a

    tenethold it

    to

    be true

    n

    a

    stronger

    sense

    than this.

    This was

    my experience

    n fieldwork

    mong

    two notably

    sophisticated

    nd

    rational

    peoples,

    he

    Ganda and the

    Sinhalese;

    nd it is what

    I

    understand rom

    monographs

    n

    otherpeoples. have

    the mpression hat

    manySinhaleseheld their enets s true withoutqualification,.e. in a sense

    including

    factual

    truth.This

    is

    hardly surprising

    when one considers

    hat

    fundamentalistsre common enough

    n our own highly ritical ulture.

    But

    I

    also had the

    mpression hat

    ome peoplewere not fundamentalists,

    utheld

    their enets s

    true

    n

    a subtler,

    more discriminating

    ense.

    I

    regret

    hat can report nly mpressions;

    did not get

    harder acts ecause

    This content downloaded from 169.234.126.240 on Sun, 19 May 2013 13:38:31 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Anthropology of Religious Belief

    6/18

    632

    MARTIN

    SOUTHWOLD

    I did not at the time grasp

    these

    ssues.

    explore

    them now with a view

    to

    better

    research n the

    future, y

    others nd

    by

    me. It should

    be

    possible

    to

    determine, or representativeampleofpeople,what thecognitive ttitudes

    to religious enets eally re;

    and it shouldbe done.

    Cognitive

    attitudes re not

    wholly

    inner

    and

    psychological:

    we do have information bout

    them,

    nd

    could and

    should have

    more. There is not a

    dichotomy

    between mere

    adherence

    nd fundamentalism:hemost

    mportant

    ttitudesie between hese

    two.

    Not

    to

    get

    this

    lear s both to demean those

    people

    whose

    believing

    we

    write

    about,

    and

    also to fail

    to

    understand

    fundamental

    spect

    of

    religious

    behaviour.

    Just

    what does belief mean n a

    religious

    ontext?'

    IV

    As I have

    indicated,

    within

    one community

    different

    ersonsmay

    have

    different

    ognitive

    attitudes owards

    religious

    enets. he

    same

    person may

    have differentttitudes n differentituations

    nd contexts

    see,

    e.g.,

    Powell

    I956: 277-8 quoted

    n

    Leach I967: 48 (note

    5),

    and

    of courseEvans-Pritchard

    I937 passim).

    And there may be differentttitudes

    o

    different

    enets:

    hus

    among

    the Sinhalese found

    t

    not uncommon

    for

    people

    to

    express

    dissent

    from ome tenets,whereas here

    were other enetswhich no one

    told me, or

    even

    showed me,

    that

    he doubted.

    These unquestioned rticles f faithwere,

    unsurprisingly,hosewhichare ogicallybasictopractical uddhism:those o

    deny

    which

    would

    carry

    away

    a

    large part

    of

    what is

    characteristically

    Buddhist.

    Thus religious

    belief s not

    one thing:

    t

    is a

    complex

    of

    cognitive

    ttitudes

    which,

    am

    arguing,

    we

    should

    describe

    more

    exactly hanwe usuallydo. My

    immediatepurpose s to define

    cognitive ttitudewhich s mostappropriate

    towards at least basic

    religious

    tenets, nd which

    I

    sensedwas actually the

    attitude

    f at

    least

    my

    more sensitive nd thoughtful

    nformants.ecause we

    anthropologists urselves

    are

    either unbelievers

    or at

    best

    rather crude

    believers,

    we find t difficulto

    identify his ttitude nd to distinguish

    t from

    others. ut ifwe cansee whatto look for,we may n fact ind t s as common

    as

    what

    we should

    recognise

    s

    intelligentttitudes o othermatters.

    o do so

    should lead

    to

    considerable

    evisionof our udgementsof the

    rationality f

    religiousbelievers:

    t

    might

    even enhance our understandingf the place of

    religion

    n

    our

    culture-which,

    as Durkheimremarked n the

    first age of his

    Elementary

    orms

    f

    the

    religious

    ife,

    s an objective of the anthropology f

    religion 9 I 5: I-2).

    The

    tenets

    f

    Buddhism

    an

    be broadly rdered long a continuum

    anging

    from

    the most

    basic and indispensable

    o the most accessory nd optional; as

    I have

    remarked,

    uch

    distinctionsre reflected

    n

    the cognitive

    ttitudes f at

    least ome Buddhists. or example, tis basicto hold thatrebirth, etermined

    by Karma,

    s

    real;

    thatNirvana

    s a real

    state

    ttainable

    y

    humanbeings;that

    the

    Buddha and

    othershave

    attained t; thatthe Buddha's teachingprovides

    efficacious

    irections

    for

    attaining t. But it is optional to

    hold, e.g., that

    participationn rites

    s conducive to attainment; hat he services f Buddhist

    clergy

    re essential t

    funeralsnd mortuary eremonies; hat

    godlike beings

    This content downloaded from 169.234.126.240 on Sun, 19 May 2013 13:38:31 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Anthropology of Religious Belief

    7/18

    MARTIN

    SOUTHWOLD

    633

    exist.Similardistinctions

    may

    be made

    among

    the tenets f

    any

    religion

    hat

    have been subjected o rational nalysis.What I have to say applies

    primarily

    to more basic tenets,nd may be lesstrueof more accessory enets. seek to

    show

    that t

    leastbasicreligious

    enets

    re

    i)

    empiricallyndeterminate, 2) axiomatic,

    3) symbolic,

    nd 4)

    collective.

    From these characteristics

    e can inferthe appropriate ognitive attitude

    towards

    them;

    and

    I

    suggest

    hat

    his

    ppropriate

    ttitude

    ctually

    ccurs nd

    could

    be

    identifiedfwe looked for t.

    Leach suggested hat

    he

    truthwhich a

    religious ogma expresses

    does

    not

    relate to the ordinary

    matter-of-fact orld of

    everyday things

    but

    to

    metaphysics'

    I967:

    45). Let us start from this appropriately ndefinite

    characterisation.

    ven in that

    mode

    of

    discourse

    which s concerned

    o describe

    and

    analyse

    the

    objective

    physical world-i.e.,

    in

    physics-metaphysical

    propositionshave a place.

    Here,

    a

    metaphysical roposition

    does not serve

    directly

    o

    describe

    he world-rather

    it serves o establish framework or

    mode of

    discoursewithinwhich the world can be

    described. ince

    it does not

    directly escribe heworld

    t s not

    directly alsifiable;

    nd

    if

    t s not falsifiable

    it

    is not verifiable

    either (i.e.

    it cannot

    be

    sufficiently

    onfirmed or

    corroborated).

    But

    if

    the

    physical

    statementsmade within the

    mode

    of

    discourse t founds re

    directly alsified,

    hen

    t

    may

    be

    indirectly

    alsified.

    Religious tenetsmay be used to founda mode of physicaldiscourse, s

    Horton

    has

    argued (i967; I973, etc.).

    But sometimes

    t least

    they

    are so

    formulated

    hat

    hey

    annot

    be falsifiedven

    indirectly:

    husfor

    xample

    the

    proposition hatGod exists

    eems o be undecidable, irectly

    r

    indirectly, y

    referenceo empirical

    vidence. Propositions doctrines, enets, otions, tc.)

    which

    are so

    formulated

    hat

    they are inherently mmune to

    empirical

    falsification

    r

    verification have termed

    'empirically indeterminate'

    (Southwold I978: 374).

    As

    theterm indeterminate'

    as

    been used of

    mystical

    propositions

    n a

    slightly ifferentenseby Cooper

    (I97 5)

    and Salmon

    I978),

    I

    must

    clarify. do not use the term indeterminate' n precisely

    he senseof

    Reichenbach

    I944),

    which Cooper claims to have taken over. I am not

    suggesting,

    s

    Cooper does,

    that

    religious

    believers

    ctually mploy

    a

    three-

    valued logic.

    I

    do not know of

    any language

    which

    admitsto the

    true/false

    paradigm third ermof equal weight.Referringo Putnam

    I957), Salmon

    writes: To

    say

    a

    sentence

    s

    indeterminatentails hat

    he sentence

    will never

    be

    verified

    or

    falsified'

    I978:

    448).

    I

    say

    that

    basic

    religious

    tenets

    are

    objectively

    ndeterminate

    n this

    ense. neither ssert or

    deny

    that

    believers

    themselves

    recognise

    precisely his;

    I

    find

    it '. . .

    difficult

    r

    impossible

    to

    distinguish

    n attitude

    f

    doubt

    or

    suspended elief,

    .e.

    no

    assignment

    f

    truth-

    value,

    from an

    assignment

    f the

    value indeterminate'

    Salmon I978).

    This

    uncertaintyan bebridgedby saying hatbelievers o nottreat eligious enets

    as

    factually rue

    nor as

    factually alse. uch non-assignment

    f

    true/falsealue

    seemsto be described or

    the Azande

    by

    Evans-Pritchard

    I937: 8i).

    I

    argue

    that it is

    appropriate

    for doctrines which

    objectively

    are

    empirically

    indeterminate,

    nd

    maybe

    common, ven normal.

    This content downloaded from 169.234.126.240 on Sun, 19 May 2013 13:38:31 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Anthropology of Religious Belief

    8/18

    634 MARTIN SOUTHWOLD

    Now

    although

    basic

    religious enetsmay

    serve o found mode of

    physical

    discourse, his s not their ole nor even theirprincipalfunction.Religious

    discourse ervesrather o interpret,nd shape, ur experience f reality, han

    directly

    o

    describe

    reality cf.

    Lienhardt 96I:

    I48).

    It

    includes

    myths nd

    similar imaginative

    and evocative forms. It

    normally

    includes ethical

    propositions, hich are of course prescriptive ather han descriptive.ndeed

    religious

    enets oundmore

    than an

    reasonably

    e includedunder 'mode of

    discourse':

    theyfound,

    for

    example,

    ethical

    conduct,

    nd

    ritual.

    They

    found

    not ust

    a

    mode

    of discoursebut a

    way

    of

    life, nd one which is socially

    established. ince neither rescriptions

    or

    conduct,

    neither

    way

    of lifenor

    a

    society,

    ave

    factual

    ruth-value,

    t

    s

    obvious

    why religiouslymetaphysical

    propositions annotevenindirectly e falsified.ontrary

    o the conventional

    wisdomconcerning ur own religioushistory, religion omesto be rejected

    not as simplyfalsebutrather s inappropriate r unfitting.

    V

    The relation between a basic tenet and the religion it serves to found

    resembles that between an axiom and a theory based on it. Boudon's

    observation

    s

    illuminating:

    The epistemologicaldifficulties

    aised

    by the concept of axiom

    did not vanish

    until

    t was

    understood

    that

    an axiom was not

    a

    proposition placed

    at

    the

    beginning

    of

    a

    deductive

    argumentbecause t

    was

    untestable-but

    rather

    proposition

    made

    untestable

    y

    its

    ocation

    at the

    beginning

    of

    the

    argument I97I: IO).

    We

    have

    often

    sked ourselves

    why religionspropound mystical' or,

    as

    I

    prefer o say, mpirically ndeterminate) octrines,

    nd

    have tended o answer

    by disparaging

    he

    rationality

    f

    believers.

    t

    should be evident

    hat

    religious

    tenets

    re,

    like

    axioms, necessarily

    ntestablebecause

    of

    their

    place

    at the

    beginning,

    he

    foundation,

    ot ust of a

    deductive

    rgument

    ut of a

    way

    of

    life.

    f

    they

    were

    cast

    n

    falsifiable

    orm

    hey

    would

    be

    falsified,

    nd

    could then

    serve heir urposewithgreatdifficultyfatall: what s to serve ffectivelys

    an

    axiom

    for collective

    way

    of

    ifemustbe immune

    to

    falsification.

    e

    are

    grosslymistaken

    when we criticise

    therpeoples

    s not rational or

    holding s

    true

    tenetswhich

    are

    mystical,

    on-demonstrable:

    heir

    rationality

    would

    rather

    ail f

    they

    based their ives

    on

    tenetswhich

    were

    not

    so.

    If we have often

    assumed

    the

    religious

    tenetsof othersto

    be false-an

    assumption

    which Evans-Pritchard

    mistakenly

    uilt into his definition f

    mystical

    otions

    I937:

    I

    2;

    see Southwold

    978: 375)-this

    has

    usually

    been

    because

    we

    did not

    share,

    r

    greatly espect,

    he

    ways

    of

    ifewhich

    they ound;

    religious

    tenets

    n

    fact are

    normally

    not false but

    unfalsifiable,mpirically

    indeterminate.

    By

    similar

    measure,

    the tenets not

    only

    are

    objectively

    axiomatic,

    n

    the senseof

    serving

    s axioms:

    they

    lso seem to

    believers o be

    axiomatic

    n the ense f

    unquestionable see, .g.,

    Evans-Pritchard

    956:

    9

    for

    the

    way

    in

    which the

    existence f God is taken for

    grantedby Nuer).

    This

    must

    be

    so:

    if the truth f

    a

    basic tenet s seen

    as

    a

    necessary recondition or

    This content downloaded from 169.234.126.240 on Sun, 19 May 2013 13:38:31 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Anthropology of Religious Belief

    9/18

    MARTIN SOUTHWOLD

    635

    the religion

    for

    which

    it

    is

    axiomatic,

    hen o consider t

    might

    not be true

    s

    to impugnthereligion, he culture

    t

    orders,

    nd hence

    the

    self hat

    s

    shaped

    by the culture.To doubt is not only to think thatone's thought s wrong

    (Evans-Pritchard937: I95),

    it

    is

    to

    suppose

    hat ne's

    elf s

    invalid. hose

    who can

    sincerely

    onsideror discuss

    he

    truth

    f basic tenetshave

    already

    ceased to be

    believers,

    n the sense f

    fully articipating

    n the

    religious

    ife.

    VI

    I have

    suggested

    hat

    believers, r at leastthemoresensitive

    mong them,

    show

    signs

    f

    recognising

    hat

    eligious

    enets re neither rue

    nor

    false;

    have

    now arguedthatneverthelesshese enets reregarded sunquestionablyrue.

    These two positions re consistent

    f

    we

    recognise

    hat

    the

    truth

    f

    religious

    tenets

    s

    not factual ruth ut

    another

    kind:

    I

    shall

    call it

    symbolic ruth.

    Something

    like this

    was

    recognised by

    Leach when

    he

    wrote,

    in

    the

    Introductiono hisPolitical

    ystems

    f

    highlandurma:

    In

    sum

    hen,myviewhere s that itual ction ndbelief re like o be understoods

    forms

    of

    ymbolic

    tatementbout he

    ocial rder

    I954:

    I4).

    That

    formulation equires orrection.

    eligiousbeliefs,

    r

    tenets,

    re

    certainly

    symbolic

    of much

    more than the social

    order.And

    symbols ommunicate

    n

    a way that s much less ike thatoflanguagethanLeach assumed cf Langer

    I95

    I:

    74-7).

    But withthese orrections

    made,

    Leach'sview

    is sound.

    Religious

    tenets

    re indeed

    symbols,functioning

    n

    very

    much the same

    ways

    as the

    concrete bjects

    or actions hat

    re

    more readily ecognised

    s ritual

    ymbols;

    and

    the cts

    of

    affirming,

    ssenting o,

    or

    even adhering o, uchtenetsreritual

    acts, ikeimmolation,

    enuflexion,

    nd so

    forth.

    I

    offerno exact definition

    f ritual symbols or symbolism: ndeed the

    category ppears

    to be

    far from

    homogeneous.

    But

    I

    do

    outline some basic

    distinctions,

    ased

    argely

    n

    Langer

    95

    I

    .

    In

    the mostgeneral ense

    Symbols

    re

    not

    proxy

    or heir

    bjects,

    ut

    re

    vehiclesor

    he

    onception

    f

    objectsI95:

    I

    60: I).

    This

    formulationwas adopted

    by Geertz I966:

    5);

    and it doubtless nderlies

    Barth's characterisation

    f ritual acts and

    objects

    as

    'vehicles for

    concepts,

    understandings,

    nd

    emotions'

    I975:

    i

    i).

    If

    we allow

    symbols o include

    linguistic orms,

    n

    the

    everyday sage of anguage, hen t s essential

    hatwe

    make

    a

    distinction f thekind thatLangerterms hatbetween

    discursive' nd

    'non-discursive'

    r

    presentational'

    ymbolismI95

    I:

    94-7,

    and

    passim).

    he

    former overs the

    manner

    n which

    language

    n its

    everydayusagesignifies;

    the

    atter he

    different

    inds f

    meaning

    o

    be found n

    art,music,

    itual,myth,

    and of coursereligiousbelief. At leastpartofthe distinctions that which

    Barth

    raws

    etween

    digital'

    nd

    analogic'

    odes

    I975:

    ch.

    5).

    There

    eems

    too to be a

    striking arallel

    with the

    differentmodes

    of

    thinking

    which

    psychologists

    nd

    neurophysiologistseport

    o be

    specialised

    n the eft nd

    the

    righthemispheres

    f

    the

    cerebral

    ortex

    see Sagan

    I977:

    ch.

    7).

    Presentational

    ymbolismdoes

    convey conceptionswhich are, at

    one or

    This content downloaded from 169.234.126.240 on Sun, 19 May 2013 13:38:31 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Anthropology of Religious Belief

    10/18

    636

    MARTIN

    SOUTHWOLD

    more removes, bout

    reality. ust ow

    it does so isnot easy o

    grasp, ut at

    east

    it

    is

    clear that tnormally

    differs romdiscursive

    ymbolism. ome

    thingswe

    call symbolsseem to signifymuch as metaphors;forotherswe need a less

    familiar

    model.

    Sperberrightly

    draws

    our

    attention o the

    term that

    the

    Ndembu use

    to

    designate

    ymbols:

    ... theword

    chijikijilu,

    hichmeansa landmark'. landmarks

    not

    sign

    but an

    index

    which erves

    ognitivelyoorganise

    ur

    xperience

    f

    pace.

    his

    Ndembu

    metaphor

    eems

    muchmore

    pposite nd ubtleomethan

    he

    Western

    metaphor

    hich

    omparesymbols

    to words I 975:

    3 3)3.

    It is

    certainly majortaskfor he

    anthropology

    f

    religion

    o

    describe

    nd

    analyse

    more

    fully

    and

    precisely ust

    how

    presentational

    ymbolism

    does

    convey conceptions boutreality; nd it sonewhich swell in hand. Formy

    present urpose

    t

    s

    necessary either

    o

    reviewtheresults e

    already

    have nor

    to

    anticipate hosewe

    may

    hope

    to

    get.

    t s

    enough,first,

    o

    acknowledge

    hat

    ritual

    symbols-including

    tenets, eliefs,dogmas-do

    convey conceptions

    about

    reality,

    nd

    hence

    may

    be

    regarded

    s true r false.

    And

    second,

    hat

    ince

    the relationof such a

    symbol

    to

    reality

    s

    different rom

    that

    of

    discursive

    symbolism

    everyday

    or

    scientific

    anguage),

    this kind of truth s different

    fromfactual ruth s we

    normally

    understandt.

    If

    people regard a presentational

    ymbol-more

    especially

    a

    tenet-as

    having

    a

    'fitting'

    r

    'appropriate'

    relation

    o

    reality, say

    they regard

    t

    as

    'symbolically rue'. Hence there s a senseof believe' which means hold as

    symbolically

    rue',

    nd this

    may

    be

    marked s

    believehts'.

    t is distinct

    rom

    'hold as

    factually rue',

    which

    may

    be written

    s

    'believehtF'4-though

    the

    two

    are easily

    nd often onfused. seekto

    explore

    ome

    of the

    differencesnd

    similarities

    etweenthese wo

    kinds

    f

    believing.

    Cooper

    (I975: 252-3)

    suggests hat t may

    be

    unjustified

    o

    say

    that

    people

    'believe'

    magico-religious ropositions

    which

    theyregard

    s

    untestable,

    nd

    which have

    some

    similarity

    with

    metaphysical

    ropositions.

    n

    view

    of the

    wide

    variety

    f

    senses f theword believe', and the

    difficulty

    f

    distinguishing

    and

    controlling

    hem,

    think

    t

    is

    prudent

    o

    try

    to avoid

    using

    the word

    altogethern scientificontextscf.Needham

    972: I92-3).

    But

    t

    is quite

    impractical otry orestrict

    he ense fbelief-terms

    i.e. theverb believe' and

    the noun

    belief)

    to hold as

    factually

    rue',

    nd

    to ruleout their

    pplication

    o

    religious belief.

    The

    latter

    pplication

    s a

    salient nd

    ineradicable

    eature

    f

    English

    usage;

    what

    we have

    to

    do

    is

    to

    make

    sure

    hatwe

    understand hefacts

    that

    have

    been,

    nd

    may be,

    reported

    hrough

    he

    usage.

    VII

    The

    way

    in

    which

    believehts'

    iffers rom

    believehtF'

    an

    bestbe brought

    out

    by considering

    arefullyust what

    the attermeans.To

    say that person

    holds

    a proposition s

    factually rue s to say

    that he

    regards t as correctly

    describing

    ome

    part r

    aspect f

    reality; r thatheholdsthat

    he tate faffairs

    it

    describes

    xists

    n

    reality.Or, better

    till, t is to

    say that his

    proposition s

    This content downloaded from 169.234.126.240 on Sun, 19 May 2013 13:38:31 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Anthropology of Religious Belief

    11/18

    MARTIN

    SOUTHWOLD

    637

    an

    element n his nternalmodel

    of

    reality y

    reference

    o

    which

    he assesses nd

    guides

    his

    transactions ith

    reality.

    Hence there re four onditionswhichmustbe satisfiedfwe are to sayof

    a person,

    with sufficient

    arrant,

    hathe

    believeshtF

    certain roposition:

    i)

    There

    mustbe some

    situationsn which some

    sets f acts re consistent ith

    (or better,

    f

    possible, rationally

    entailed

    by) the

    proposition's

    being

    factually rue,

    nd a differentet

    of acts re

    consistent ith or entailedby)

    itsbeingfalse; nd he must ncounter

    uch ituations

    ufficientlyrequently

    to allow us

    to

    make sufficient

    bservations.-Under

    acts'

    I

    include

    verbal

    acts,

    and

    notably

    those

    of

    asserting

    or

    unequivocally

    implying the

    proposition, nd of avowing

    it

    as

    true/false.

    2)

    In such

    situations

    e must

    predominantly

    o those cts that re consistent

    with tstruth ather han hose hat re consistent ith tsfalsity.

    a)

    To

    requireperfect onsistency

    f

    conduct

    with

    belief

    would

    deprive

    he

    concept

    of

    use:

    normal

    people

    are not

    perfectlyonsistent. ut there s

    often nougha clear distinction

    etween onductwhich

    s

    as consistent

    with a belief as it is reasonable to

    expect,

    and that which

    is

    grossly

    inconsistent

    ith t.

    b) Though

    the

    relevant cts

    ncludeverbal

    cts,

    hey

    hould

    f

    possible

    lso

    includenon-verbal cts.As Gombrich I 97I: 4-5) rightly emarks, e

    say

    a

    person

    does not

    really

    believe what he

    professes

    f

    his

    non-verbal

    acts are seriously nconsistent ith it. There are two good reasons or

    this:

    i)

    If

    to

    believehtF

    proposition s

    to

    have it

    as an element n one's

    internalmodel

    of

    reality, hen all one's reality-oriented

    onduct s

    potentially elevant n decidingwhether tactually s an element n

    thatmodel.

    ii) If person s deceiving thers, nd perhaps lso

    himself, y simulating

    a beliefhe does not

    reallyhold,

    t s normally asier, nd cheaper, o

    do

    so

    by

    verbal

    falsehoods han

    by

    non-verbal retences.

    3)

    There must be evidence that he

    entertains

    his

    proposition

    n association

    with theseacts.Philosophers re agreedthata personcannot be held to

    believe a

    proposition

    hat

    he has never entertained'

    r

    considered;

    nd as

    we have

    known inceEvans-Pritchard

    I 937)

    that

    eoplepractise

    ituational

    selection

    of their

    beliefs,

    we have to establish

    that

    the

    proposition

    s

    entertained

    n

    the context

    of

    the acts

    relevant o

    believing

    t.

    One

    cannot

    infer that a certain

    proposition

    s believed

    merely

    from

    the fact that

    observed conduct

    is

    consistent

    with

    it,

    since

    any

    course

    of

    conduct is

    consistent

    with

    more

    than one

    proposition Gombrich

    I97I)

    overlooks

    this-see

    my

    comments

    n

    Southwold

    I978: 366).

    Entertainment

    f a

    propositions mostplainlyestablished

    f

    the person

    expressest n or withhis act: this swhyverbal ssertions r endorsements,

    though

    unreliable vidence

    of

    holding

    s

    true,

    re mportant s evidenceof

    believing.

    t

    may

    be lessobvious that

    ntertainment

    s also

    established

    f

    the

    actor

    denies heproposition s he acts-provided hedoes so spontaneously,

    and not

    merely

    n

    replyto a leading question.

    f

    this

    were all, we should

    have

    the

    frustrating

    esult hat t

    is hardest

    o

    establish hat

    people

    believe

    This content downloaded from 169.234.126.240 on Sun, 19 May 2013 13:38:31 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Anthropology of Religious Belief

    12/18

    638

    MARTIN

    SOUTHWOLD

    just whatthey

    do

    most

    firmly

    elieve: forf

    a

    tenet saxiomatic t tends

    o

    be

    taken

    for

    granted

    rather

    han stated

    xplicitly.

    Hence we must

    allow

    that f n act scustomary n theculturen question, ndifwe can establish

    that t is also

    customary o entertain

    particular

    roposition

    n

    association

    with such acts,then any member

    of

    the culturedoing that act

    may

    be

    assumed o

    entertain hatproposition.

    4)

    His conduct cannot with

    comparable

    plausibility

    be

    explained by

    an

    alternative ypothesis.

    a)

    It

    may happen

    that heevidence

    givesequal

    support

    o

    the

    ascription

    f

    several different

    eliefs.This is no

    problem: people

    do

    operate

    with

    alternativechemes f

    nterpretation,

    nd so to

    say

    that

    person

    believes

    one

    thingneed

    not be understood s

    precluding

    is

    believing

    omething

    else-not even when, abstracted romcontexts, he two beliefs re

    logically

    nconsistent.

    b)

    A

    person's

    onduct

    may

    be

    fully

    ccounted

    orwithout eferenceo the

    belief

    by

    which he

    explains

    t.

    This does

    not n itself how thathe

    does

    not believe what

    he

    professes:

    t most t

    may

    show

    thathis belief s

    not

    the cause,

    or

    theonly

    cause,

    of his conduct.

    c)

    The kind of alternative

    ypothesis

    which

    really

    calls

    in

    question

    an

    ascription

    f belief s one that he actor s

    deceiving thers,

    nd

    perhaps

    himself.

    We can neverbe

    certain

    hat his

    s

    not

    so;

    but we can

    often

    e

    sufficiently

    onfident.

    ertainty

    s

    unattainablenempirical cience, nd

    especially

    n that

    concerning

    human

    behaviour;

    the

    uncertainty

    hat

    attends

    scriptions

    f

    belief s not

    so

    special

    s to

    place

    them

    outside

    he

    normal area of scientificikelihood.

    This

    analysis erves o make

    plain whyit is that

    scriptions fbelieving-

    statementshat

    omeone

    other

    han neself

    elieves omething-do

    not require

    special

    knowledge

    of

    the nner

    mental tate

    orpsychological

    ttitudes) f the

    believer.

    t

    should

    be

    evident

    hat he

    verb believe'

    designates relation ather

    than a

    state:

    a

    relation, irstly etween

    the believerand a

    proposition, nd

    secondly

    from

    the

    believer

    through the

    proposition to reality.What is

    purported o occur s doubtlessmental n largepart, nd specialpsychological

    knowledge

    would

    doubtless

    elp us to assess

    ndunderstandt

    better. ut such

    specialknowledge s not

    necessary,ince n

    factwe use

    believe' in away which

    enablesus to

    regard

    he

    mind of

    the

    believer s a 'black box' (see,

    .g.,Ashby

    i964:

    86sqq.).

    The factswe

    refer o are

    the

    nputs

    nd

    outputs

    f

    the black

    box',

    and the relationsbetween

    them: we are not

    committed o

    giving

    an

    account

    ofjust

    what goes on within he

    black box'.5

    VIII

    Now since we use believe' for hold as symbolically rue' as well as for

    'hold as

    factuallyrue',

    t

    s

    implied

    that his ame

    schema

    hould be

    applicable

    to

    ascriptions

    f

    believinghtS.

    n

    largepart t

    s. But

    the rucial

    difference

    s that

    the

    first

    ondition,

    nd

    consequently

    he

    second,

    annot

    be satisfied,

    tically t

    least.

    Cooper

    (I975:

    253) points

    out that f a

    proposition s untestable in my

    This content downloaded from 169.234.126.240 on Sun, 19 May 2013 13:38:31 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Anthropology of Religious Belief

    13/18

    MARTIN SOUTHWOLD

    639

    terms, mpirically ndeterminate)

    t

    is hard to see

    how behaviour could be

    distinguished s consistent ith its truth ather han ts falsity. proposition

    is empirically ndeterminatef and only if every state f affairs hich can be

    determined s

    holding

    n

    the real

    world is

    as consistent

    ith ts truth s with

    itsfalsity.

    f

    ome

    courseof actionwere

    objectively

    emonstrable s consistent

    with

    ts

    truth,

    nd a different

    ourse

    of

    action

    demonstrable s consistent

    ith

    its falsity, hen the differentonsequences f these coursesof action would

    provideevidence of thetruth-valuef theproposition, ontrary

    o

    definition.

    This

    would

    not be so only

    if

    the two coursesof action had no

    discernibly

    different

    onsequences;

    which s

    perhaps ommon,

    s the ncient

    lea, why

    do

    sinners

    prosper...?', bears

    witness.

    Empirically

    we do in

    fact

    find

    that

    a

    remarkably

    wide

    range

    of kindsof conduct s held to be consistent

    ith,

    nd

    indeed egitimated y,a given religious enet.

    Yet it is also clear,and important,

    hat

    the range

    is

    usually

    not infinite:

    within

    particular eligious

    radition ome kinds

    of

    conduct

    re difficult nd

    some

    virtually mpossible,

    o

    legitimate y accepted

    enets.

    n

    Buddhism,

    or

    example,

    it

    is difficult

    o

    legitimate

    he

    participation

    f Buddhist

    clergy

    n

    war:

    though

    tradition

    does,

    albeit

    reluctantly,

    llow the factthat Buddhist

    clergy, temporarilydisrobed,

    served

    in the

    army

    of

    King Dutthagamani

    (Gombrich I97I: 29).

    It would be

    virtually mpossible

    to

    legitimate

    he

    service

    of a

    Buddhist cleric as

    general

    or

    war-leader,

    nd

    history, think,

    records

    no instance f this.

    This is plainly

    an

    important

    ifference etween

    Buddhist nd slamic ocieties-with Christendomallingomewhere etween

    thesepoles.

    There are certainly mic, hough

    not

    etic,

    riteriawhich

    distinguish

    arious

    kindsof

    conduct

    as

    consistent,

    nd

    others

    s

    inconsistent,

    ith

    believinghts

    particular eligioustruth.

    n

    Sri Lanka, for example, t is maintained hat a

    Buddhist ayman

    who

    believes the Dhamma (the Buddhist doctrines)will

    endeavour to

    observe

    the Five

    Precepts.

    Hence a man who

    regularly

    nd

    wantonly kills iving beings in breach of the FirstPrecept), r is regularly

    drunk

    (in

    breach

    of

    the

    Fifth),

    s

    shown

    thereby

    not

    really

    to believe the

    Dhamma.

    But the criteria re characteristicallymprecise.Most Buddhist

    laymendeliberatelyake ife:e.g. theyuse nsecticides,nd will killat east he

    most dangerous

    kind

    of

    snake

    (the

    Russell's

    Viper);

    and in

    their

    own

    judgements,

    nd those

    of most of their

    fellows,

    this does not make them

    unbelievers.

    And

    many men,

    at

    least,

    onsider t allowable

    to

    drink

    iquor

    in

    moderation.

    The standards

    re not

    precisian

    but

    customary:

    those of the

    reasonable ather

    han he

    upright

    man

    (Gluckman 955: I25-6).

    Not

    only

    s

    it

    emicallydetermined

    what kinds

    of

    conduct

    shall

    be held consistent

    r

    inconsistent ith

    religious

    elief: t s also

    emically

    etermined hat

    behaviour

    is or is not

    to be classified s

    falling

    within hosekinds

    of

    conduct.

    This makes it difficult o argue (as Spiro

    I

    97

    I

    does) that customary

    behaviour

    itself s inconsistent ith

    accepted religious enets, hus showing

    that hetenets re not

    really

    believed.When we

    perceive

    uch

    nconsistency

    t

    is between the

    behaviour and what we take to be the meaningof the tenets;

    but t

    may

    be thatwe have

    misinterpreted

    hat

    meaning,

    nd

    the behaviour s

    consistent ith their

    propermeaning.Now

    if

    we take eriously he view that

    This content downloaded from 169.234.126.240 on Sun, 19 May 2013 13:38:31 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Anthropology of Religious Belief

    14/18

    640

    MARTIN SOUTHWOLD

    religious

    enets

    re ritual

    r

    presentational'

    ymbols,

    heirmeaning

    annot

    be

    discovered y

    translating

    hewords

    n which

    they

    re

    expressed,

    s ifwe

    were

    dealing with the ordinarydiscursiveuse of language.The meaning of a

    religious enet,

    s of

    any

    other

    kind of ritual ymbol,

    s theway it

    functions

    n

    shaping,

    rdering,

    nterpretingxperience;

    tsfunctions a landmark'

    perhaps:

    This can

    be discovered nly by

    determining

    ow it

    s n fact elated otheway

    of ife

    for

    which

    t serves

    ymbolically.

    he

    significance

    f a

    symbol,

    ike

    the

    meaning

    faword, ies

    n

    tsuse:

    it

    can

    be determined

    nly

    byanalysis

    f

    what

    people actually

    do,

    and cannot

    then

    be turned

    to

    udge

    what

    they

    do.

    The

    anthropologist

    must

    determine

    ow a tenet s

    actually mployed

    n theway

    of

    life

    n which

    it functions:

    nd he must

    report

    his s the

    symbolic

    meaning

    t

    actually

    bears.

    f,

    for

    example,

    he

    finds,

    s he

    will,

    thatmost Buddhists

    peak

    of nirvanaas the summumonum, etso far from activelyendeavouring o

    attain hat tate

    s

    soon

    as

    possible

    hey

    ctually ursuegoals

    they

    cknowledge

    as

    inconsistent

    ith

    t,

    while

    postponing

    heir ventual ttainment

    f

    nirvana

    into

    the

    remote

    future:

    henthe

    conclusion

    mustbe

    that he doctrines

    bout

    nirvana

    do not

    signify

    o

    them

    a

    prescription

    or

    attaining

    n immediate

    personalgoal,

    but

    ratherhave

    some transformed

    eaning

    which we

    have to

    discover.

    As Tambiah (I970:

    4I-2)

    suggests,

    piro's rror

    erives

    rom ssuming hat

    the meaning

    of

    Buddhisttenets an be

    known

    by

    reading

    them as

    they

    are

    presented

    n the Scriptures.

    ven ifwe

    allow the rather

    argeassumptions

    hat

    we can know whata tenetmeant nthecontext f the criptural ritings,nd

    that his an be

    taken n some

    defensible ense

    shaving

    once been

    ts tandard

    meaning,

    t

    still

    does not

    follow that

    this s

    its

    meaning

    in

    contemporary

    practical

    Buddhism:

    f

    practice

    s inconsistent

    iththatmeaning,

    we have to

    register

    he fact hatpractice

    eveals

    different eaning,

    no doubt

    as a result

    of

    symbolic

    ransformation.

    It

    must,

    however,be

    said that t

    is not only Spiro and

    otheroutsiders

    who

    give

    Buddhist enets

    meaning

    which s inconsistent

    ithpractice

    n practical

    Buddhism:

    so,

    n

    Sri Lanka at east, o many

    Buddhists ven

    n the

    mallworld

    of

    the villages,

    nd theyuse

    this nconsistency

    o

    point

    to theunworthiness

    f

    practice.We should not be surprised hatreligioustenets,ike otherritual

    symbols,

    ustain

    variety

    f

    meanings.

    And we

    may

    remark hat twould be

    a

    poor

    sort

    of

    religion

    that could only

    validate the actual,

    without

    also

    proclaiming

    n ideal matched gainst

    which

    the ctual

    canbe seen

    to fall hort.

    The tension etween

    the normative

    nterpretations

    f Buddhist

    doctrines

    nd

    the

    symbolic

    meanings hey

    bear n the

    context f actual ife s

    an aspect

    f

    an

    important

    ynamic

    n

    Buddhist ocieties.

    utneither his

    nor

    other eaturesf

    Buddhistreligious

    ifecan be

    correctly

    rasped

    withoutrecognising

    hat

    the

    doctrines

    o have

    symbolic

    meanings

    n actual

    ife.

    It follows

    that assessment f a symbolic

    proposition

    must be radically

    different

    rom hatof a

    factual

    roposition.With a factual roposition,f t is

    properly

    formulated,

    t is relatively

    imple

    to know

    what it means:

    the

    important

    uestion s

    whether

    t

    is true.6

    But a symbolic

    proposition-and

    especially

    basic

    religious

    enet-is,

    forthosewho maintain t,

    axiomatically

    true: the

    important

    uestion

    s,

    whatdoes it mean?

    For the anthropologist,

    This content downloaded from 169.234.126.240 on Sun, 19 May 2013 13:38:31 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Anthropology of Religious Belief

    15/18

    MARTIN SOUTHWOLD

    64I

    then, he question s not whetherheybelieve t but how.This throws ight

    on

    a notable oddity in Christian heology. n the Bible-as among the Nuer

    (Evans-Pritchard

    956:

    9)-the existence f God is taken for granted: t is

    axiomatically rue, nd the focus

    of

    concern s

    with

    thereligious ignificance

    of thisdatum.But formanymodernChristians,s

    for

    vowed unbelievers, he

    significance

    s

    taken

    for

    granted,

    ut the truth

    s

    considered

    o

    be at ssue.

    This

    is, n effect,o mistake symbolicproposition

    s a factual

    roposition:

    which

    may be why the religious esult ends

    o

    be somewhatprosthetic.

    Ix

    Sometimes

    hings

    ecome

    symbolic

    for

    particular

    ndividualbut

    not for

    his fellowsgenerally:we may speak of these as privateand idiosyncratic

    symbols. imilarly ropositionsmay acquire diosyncraticymbolic

    ruth

    or

    particularndividuals.

    uch

    private ymbolisms

    hould

    not have

    a

    large place

    in

    ethnographic eports,

    he

    primary

    oncern

    of

    which is

    to

    report

    what is

    common to

    members

    of

    a

    society,

    what constitutes

    heir culture.

    t

    seems

    likely,moreover,

    hat the

    greater art

    of

    the

    symbolic

    truths hat

    a normal

    personholds are collective,

    n a number f senses nd forvariousreasons.

    i)

    Most

    people

    do in fact earn

    most of their deas

    and

    attitudes

    rom

    thers,

    and are

    not much nclined

    o

    be

    original

    nd

    creative.

    A

    person's ymbolic

    truths re therefore,or he mostpart, ikely o be collective

    n

    the obvious

    senseof

    having

    been

    acquired

    fromhis culture.

    2) They

    will therefore e

    collective

    n a

    second obvious

    sense,

    hatof

    being

    common to

    and

    shared

    by

    the

    members f a

    community.

    Much

    of

    their

    power

    as

    symbols

    derives

    from hisfact.

    3) Through being

    shared

    hey cquire

    a

    kind

    of

    verisimilitude hich,while

    not

    being

    thetruth f matters

    f

    fact,

    as that aura of

    factuality'

    hat

    Geertz

    (I966)

    sees

    s

    fundamental

    o

    religion

    s

    a

    cultural

    ystem.

    ur warrant or

    saying

    hat

    omething

    xists

    s

    simply

    hat he

    hypothesis

    hat t does

    is

    the

    most

    satisfactory ay

    of

    accounting

    for

    a

    set of

    given experiences.

    he

    claimthat, .g.,God exists s warranted o the extent hatobserved vents

    are bestfitted o that upposition: nd this eems obe so ofsocial events f

    members f

    society

    re

    ndeed

    acting

    on that

    upposition. We may prefer

    to account

    for

    theseeventsby thehypothesishatthe actorsbelieve that

    God

    exists;

    but believers annotbe

    expected

    o

    recognise his s a distinct

    hypothesiswithout llowing that he beliefmightbe false, nd this, s we

    argued

    above

    (p. 635), is hardlypossiblefor hem.)

    4)

    It is

    not only that, hrough eing shared, eligious enets cquire that ura

    of

    factuality hich makes

    hem

    ppear

    to

    be simply rue: nasmuch s they

    are

    empirically ndeterminate

    his s the

    only way they an come to seem

    factually rue. As I remarkedn an earlierpaper, The apparent ruth r

    falsity

    of such

    doctrines seems

    to

    depend wholly

    on social factors'

    (Southwold I978: 374).

    5)

    Further, s we have seen, he criteria or reallybelieving ymbolic ruths

    are

    emic, customary,

    nd hence

    collective: e.g.

    a

    man

    really

    believes the

    Dhamma

    only

    f

    he sufficientlyefrains rom aking ife.

    This content downloaded from 169.234.126.240 on Sun, 19 May 2013 13:38:31 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Anthropology of Religious Belief

    16/18

    642

    MARTIN

    SOUTHWOLD

    6) Thus symbolic ruths ecome representative

    f

    membership

    f a

    group,

    community, Church. Not to overload the term symbolic' stillfurther,

    I would follow a hint f Nadel's and saythat hey re emblematic'of such

    membershipNadel 95

    I:

    262,

    cited

    n

    Firth

    973:

    I

    74). Theyrepresent

    such membership

    oth

    internally,s expressing

    ttachment o the

    group

    and solidaritywith

    fellow

    members,

    nd

    externally

    s

    identifying

    ne

    as a

    member

    of

    this group

    in

    contrast

    with outsiders nd with other

    groups.

    This emblematic unction

    s

    prominent

    n credalaffirmationsn

    liturgical

    and

    other formal

    occasions,

    nd is

    perhaps lways present

    n avowals of

    believing

    a

    religious

    enet.

    We should ask ourselves

    how

    far

    nformants'

    avowals of belief o

    an

    ethnographer

    an

    safely

    e

    interpreted

    s

    conveying

    cognitive ttitudes

    ather han s

    simply sserting roup dentity.

    7) Ifthe ymbols re andmarks or rdering world, t s mportanthat hey

    be shared

    mong

    thosewhose nteraction

    onstitutes

    person's

    ocialworld.

    8) When symbolic

    truths re held

    in common

    they

    can be

    acted

    upon

    collectively hrough ritual; they

    serve thus

    to alter

    as

    well as to order

    experiencecf.

    ienhardt96I:

    250, 291).

    9)

    The awareness

    that

    symbolic

    truths

    are

    held

    in

    common,

    and their

    activation

    n

    collective itual, vokes,

    nd

    charges

    he

    ymbolic

    ruths

    ith,

    the sense

    of

    strength

    hatmen feel

    n

    the

    support

    f

    their ellows:

    Individualsre

    weak,

    ut ocial

    roups

    re

    trong,

    oth n the

    rdinary

    ecular

    ffairs

    f

    life nd ndealingwith hePowersLienhardt

    96I:

    247).

    i

    o) It would seem

    that

    ymbolic ruths

    re

    usually,

    fnot

    nvariably,

    ollective

    in yet another ense: theirprincipal

    references

    to collective ffairs nd

    concerns,

    whether t

    be morality

    n

    the most general sense,

    or more

    specific ocial orjural values such

    as

    matrilineal escent.

    Thus

    it

    would seem

    that

    ymbolicpropositions,

    nd the

    holding

    of

    them s

    true,

    re

    eminently

    ollective. t

    is

    of

    course ndividuals

    who

    believehts

    hem:

    but

    they

    do so

    primarily

    n their

    apacity

    not as individuals

    ut as

    members

    f

    a

    collectivity.

    Because

    this s

    so,

    the fact of

    such

    believing

    s

    most

    exactly

    reported y saying, fthebelievers,theybelieve . . .' inthecollective ather

    than the

    distributive7

    ense.This

    is the

    germ

    of truth n Leach's contention

    which

    we

    began by considering.

    As we

    have

    argued, however, 'they

    believe

    . . .'

    is

    normally

    lso true

    n thedistributive

    ensewhich sums

    set,of

    'he believes

    .

    . .'

    ascriptions;

    his s

    not,

    as

    Leach

    supposed, xcluded,

    but it

    would seem to be

    secondary

    nd derivative.

    When,

    as

    is

    all

    too

    easy,we

    interpretthey believe . . .' reports imply in the distributive ense, this

    conduces

    o

    understanding

    believe' in the

    ense f'hold as factually rue'.This

    in

    turn eads to those misconceiveddebates about rationalitywhich Leach

    (I

    954:

    I

    3) dismissed s mostly scholasticnonsense'.

    x

    I

    have attributed

    our

    characteristicso

    basic religious tenets: they are

    empirically ndeterminate,xiomatic, ymbolic, nd collective.These charac-

    teristics re

    closely

    connected.

    t is because they are axiomatic that they are

    This content downloaded from 169.234.126.240 on Sun, 19 May 2013 13:38:31 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Anthropology of Religious Belief

    17/18

    MARTIN SOUTHWOLD 643

    collective, nd because hey re collective hat hey re axiomatic.Their power

    as symbols argely erives rom heir eing collective: heir bility s symbols

    to sustain variety

    of

    meaningshelps

    to

    make them

    commonly and

    hence

    collectively cceptable.

    heir

    place

    as axioms

    makes

    t

    natural hat hey hould

    be

    empirically ndeterminate; nd,

    as we

    argued,

    t is functional hat

    they

    should

    be,

    since f

    falsifiable

    hey

    would be falsified.

    heir function s

    symbolic

    truths lso makes

    t

    desirable hatthey hould

    be

    empirically ndeterminate,

    lest

    question

    and

    doubts about their

    factual ruth onfuse

    or

    confute heir

    symbolicrole.

    The logically proper

    attitude owards such

    propositions,

    f

    one

    maintains

    them,

    s

    that

    hey

    re

    symbolically

    ruebut not

    factually

    rue.This

    s

    a

    difficult

    position o maintain xplicitly, hen one's anguage ndconceptual ystem o

    notclearlydistinguishetween hese

    wo kinds f

    truth,

    nd do

    assume two-

    valued logic by

    which 'not

    factually

    rue' is

    equivalent

    to

    'factually

    alse'.

    Despite this difficulty, do see signs that the cognitive attitudeof more

    sensitive elievers s

    at

    least

    mplicitly

    lose

    to what s

    logicallyproper:

    and I

    urge

    that

    we

    should ook forfirmer

    vidence

    of this.

    I

    have

    little oubt that

    many,

    f

    not

    most, eligious

    elievers ake

    he

    impler

    and more robust

    iew

    that heir enets

    re

    factually

    rue s well as

    symbolically

    true.This is but

    subtly

    different

    rom

    the

    appropriate iew,

    and

    we should

    hardly

    describe

    people

    as irrational ecause

    they

    fail to mark such a difficult

    distinction:hemore so since, y definition,nassumptionhat nempirically

    indeterminate roposition s factually ruecan never conflictwith empirical

    evidence.

    They

    are

    no

    more mistaken

    r

    irrational

    n

    taking heir enets

    o

    be

    factually rue hanwe are, s we often ave been, n assuming hem o be false;

    and

    theyhave

    far

    better xcuse.

    NOTES

    Shorter

    Oxford

    English

    Dictionary,

    under

    believe':

    '3.

    With clause or

    infinitive

    hrase:

    To hold

    it as

    true that . .,

    to think'.

    -Leach

    actually

    llustrates

    hissense n

    the

    same

    sentencewhen

    he writes,

    But

    Professor

    Spiro .

    .

    . desperatelywants to believe that

    2

    As Needhamn

    rgues

    I972:

    5-7).

    3

    Sperber

    cites

    Turner

    I969:

    I

    5

    as his

    source;

    Turner

    reports

    here

    further

    ubtleties f

    the

    Ndembu idiom.-As

    Firth

    I973: i68)

    has

    reminded

    us,

    the

    notion

    of

    a

    symbol

    as a

    landmark

    had

    earlier

    been

    employed

    byFortes:

    Totemic and

    other

    ymbols re

    the

    deological

    andmarks

    that

    eep

    he

    ndividual

    n

    his ourse'

    I945:

    I44).

    4

    I

    have made

    myself rule

    that when

    using

    subscripts

    o

    distinguish

    ifferentensesof a

    word,

    a

    change to

    differentevel

    of

    distinction

    houldbe

    marked

    by

    a

    changeof

    fount lower

    case,

    capitals,

    numerals,

    tc.). Thus

    the two

    lower-case ettersht'

    can

    be

    understood s

    making

    one

    distinction: he

    change to

    capitals,S' and

    'F',

    indicates hatthese

    erve

    further o

    segment

    the

    sensemarked

    by

    ht'.

    5

    It is not

    only

    Leach who

    fails o see

    this: the error

    s

    very

    common. Most of

    the

    problems

    with which

    Needham

    (I972) wrestles rise from

    the

    fallacious

    ssumption hat

    belief

    must

    be

    regarded s an innermental tate; nd, sheshows, hefallacyswidespread mongphilosophers.

    It

    seems to

    arise from wo

    basic

    errors f method:

    i) If

    one

    analyses

    sageofthe

    noun belief

    rather han he

    verb

    believe' it s far

    ess

    vident hat

    a

    relationrather

    hana

    state s

    designated.

    2)

    Again concentration n

    usage

    of the noun

    obscures he crucial

    fact hat

    he

    semantics f'he

    believes' are

    significantly

    ifferentrom

    hoseof

    I

    believe'. If

    the atter s

    erroneously

    aken

    to

    be

    paradigmatic

    for

    both,

    then

    the

    way

    is

    opened

    for

    indulging

    the

    favourite

    philosophical

    This content downloaded from 169.234.126.240 on Sun, 19 May 2013 13:38:31 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Anthropology of Religious Belief

    18/18

    644 MARTIN SOUTHWOLD

    techniqueof

    introspection. he results re irrelevant

    nd confusing

    or

    nalysing

    scriptions

    f

    believing to third

    parties-i.e.

    statements

    f the form he believes' or

    they

    believe'.

    These points refarfromobvious,and to that xtentdeserveto be proved. am assuming hat

    anthropologists re too little

    committed

    to

    the

    philosophical

    errorsto

    care to see

    them

    extensively

    efuted.

    6 And

    the

    harder t is to get itproperly

    ormulated o

    as

    to make thequestionof its

    factual

    truth t

    least

    n

    principle

    decidable,

    he more

    ikely

    t s to

    be

    functioning

    ot as a factual

    ut as

    a

    symbolicproposition.

    'Distributive: referring o

    each

    individual of

    a

    class

    separately;opposed

    to collective '

    (Shorter

    Oxford

    EnglishDictionary).

    REFERENCES

    Ashby,

    W.

    Ross I964.

    An introduction

    o

    ybernetics.

    ondon: Methuen.

    Barth,

    Fredrik

    975.

    Ritual nd

    knowledgemong

    heBaktaman

    f

    New

    Guinea.

    New

    Haven:

    Yale Univ. Press.

    Boudon, Raymond I97

    I. Theuses

    f

    tructuralism

    trans.)

    M.

    Vaughan.

    London:

    Heinemann.

    Cooper,

    D.

    E.

    I975.

    Alternative

    ogic

    in

    primitive hought'.

    Man

    N.S.) IO, 238-56.

    Durkheim,

    E. I

    9

    I

    5.

    The

    lementaryormsf

    he

    eligiousifetrans.)

    .

    W. Swain.

    London:

    Allen

    &

    Unwin.

    Evans-Pritchard,

    .

    E.

    I937.

    Witchcraft,

    raclesnd

    magicmong

    he

    zande. xford: Clarendon.

    I956.

    Nuer eligion.xford:

    Clarendon.

    Firth,Raymond I973.

    Symbols,ublic

    nd

    rivate.

    ondon: Allen & Unwin.

    Fortes,Meyer

    I945. Dynamics

    f lanshipmong

    he

    allensi.xford: Clarendon.

    Geertz,

    Clifford

    966. Religion

    as a

    cultural

    ystem.

    n

    Anthropologicalpproaches

    o he

    tudyf

    religion

    ed.)

    M. Banton

    (Ass.

    social

    Anthrop.Monogr. 3).

    London: Tavistock.

    Gluckman,

    Max

    I

    955.

    The

    udicial

    rocessmong

    he

    arotse.

    anchester:Univ.

    Press.

    Gombrich,

    Richard

    F.

    I97

    I.

    Precept

    nd

    practice:

    raditionaluddism

    n the

    ighlands

    fCeylon.

    Oxford: Clarendon.

    Horton,

    Robin

    i967.

    African raditional

    hought

    nd Western

    cience.

    Africa

    7,

    50-7I, I55-

    87.

    I973. Levy-Bruhl,Durkheimand

    thescientific evolution. n

    Modes f houghteds)

    Robin Horton &

    Ruth

    Finnegan.London:

    Faber.

    Langer,

    Susanne K.

    i95i.

    Philosophyna new ey

    2nd edn).

    London: Oxford Univ. Press.

    Leach, E. R. I954. Political

    ystemsfhighlandurma.ondon: G.

    Bell.

    i967. Virgin

    birth.

    Proc. .

    anthrop.nst.

    966,

    39-50.

    i968. Virgin

    birth

    letter).

    Man

    N.S.) 3,

    655-6.

    Lienhardt,

    Godfrey

    196I.

    Divinitynd xperience:

    he eligionf he inka.Oxford:

    Clarendon.

    Malinowski,

    B.

    I9I6. Baloma.J.R. anthrop.nst.

    6, 353-430.

    I932.

    The

    exual

    ife f avages3rd edn).

    London:

    Routledge.

    Nadel,

    S. F. I

    95

    i.

    Foundationsf ocial

    nthropology.ondon: Cohen & West.

    Needham,Rodney

    I972.

    Belief,

    anguagend xperience.

    xford: Blackwell.

    Powell,

    H. A.

    I956.

    An

    analysis

    of

    present

    day social structure

    n

    the Trobriands. Thesis,

    University

    f

    London.

    Putnam,H.

    I957. Three-valued

    ogic.Phil. tud. .

    Reichenbach,

    H.

    I944.

    Philosophicaloundationsf quantum

    mechanics.erkeley: Univ. of

    California

    Press.

    Roth, Walter

    E. I903. Superstition,agicnd

    medicineN.

    Queensl.

    ethnogr.Bull. 5).

    Brisbane:

    Vaughan.

    Sagan,

    Carl

    I977. The

    dragonsf den. ondon: Hodder &

    Stoughton.

    Salmon,

    M. H.

    I978.

    Do

    Azande and

    Nuer use a non-standard

    ogic?Man N.S.) 13, 444-54.

    ShorterOxford

    English

    Dictionary,3rd edition, 944. London:

    Oxford Univ. Press.

    Southwold,

    M.

    I978.

    Buddhism and the

    definition

    f

    religion.

    Man

    N.S.)

    I3,

    362-79.

    Sperber,

    Dan

    I975. Rethinkingymbolismtrans.)

    Alice

    L.

    Morton.Cambridge:

    Univ. Press.

    Spiro,M. E.

    I

    968. Virgin birth, arthenogenesisndphysiological aternity: n essay n cultural

    interpretation. an

    N.S.) 3, 242-6I.

    I97I. Buddhism

    nd

    ociety.ondon: Allen &

    Unwin.

    Tambiah, S.J.

    I970

    Buddhismnd

    hepiritultsn

    north-east

    hailand.ambridge: Univ. Press.

    Turner,

    V.

    W.

    I

    969.

    The

    ritual

    rocess.ondon:

    Routledge.