a social practice

17
Knowledge and Organization: A Social-Practice Perspective John Seely Brown; Paul Duguid Organization Science, Vol. 12, No. 2. (Mar. - Apr., 2001), pp. 198-213. Stable URL: http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=1047-7039%28200103%2F04%2912%3A2%3C198%3AKAOASP%3E2.0.CO%3B2-Y Organization Science is currently published by INFORMS. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/about/terms.html. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/journals/informs.html. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is an independent not-for-profit organization dedicated to and preserving a digital archive of scholarly journals. For more information regarding JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. http://www.jstor.org Tue Apr 10 06:42:53 2007

Upload: imran-shaheen

Post on 17-Sep-2015

8 views

Category:

Documents


3 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • Knowledge and Organization: A Social-Practice Perspective

    John Seely Brown; Paul Duguid

    Organization Science, Vol. 12, No. 2. (Mar. - Apr., 2001), pp. 198-213.

    Stable URL:http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=1047-7039%28200103%2F04%2912%3A2%3C198%3AKAOASP%3E2.0.CO%3B2-Y

    Organization Science is currently published by INFORMS.

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available athttp://www.jstor.org/about/terms.html. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtainedprior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content inthe JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.

    Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained athttp://www.jstor.org/journals/informs.html.Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printedpage of such transmission.

    JSTOR is an independent not-for-profit organization dedicated to and preserving a digital archive of scholarly journals. Formore information regarding JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    http://www.jstor.orgTue Apr 10 06:42:53 2007

  • PERSPECTIVE

    Knowledge and Organization: A Social-Practice Perspective

    John Seely Brown Paul Duguid Xerox Palo Alto Research Center, 3333 Coyote Hill Road, Palo Alto, California 94304

    [email protected] [email protected]

    Abstract While the recent focus on knowledge has undoubtedly benefited organizational studies, the literature still presents a sharply con-trasting and even contradictory view of knowledge, which at times is described as "sticky" and at other times "leaky." This paper is written on the premise that there is more than a problem- -

    with metaphors at issue here, and more than accounts of dif-ferent types of knowledge (such as "tacit" and "explicit") can readily explain. Rather, these contrary descriptions of knowl-edge reflect different, partial, and sometimes "balkanized" per-spectives from which knowledge and organization are viewed. Taking the community of practice as a unifying unit of analysis for understanding knowledge in the firm, the paper suggests that often too much attention is paid to the idea of community, too little to the implications of practice. Practice, we suggest, cre-ates epistemic differences among the communities within a firm, and the firm's advantage over the market lies in dynami-cally coordinating the knowledge produced by these commu-nities despite such differences. In making this argument, we argue that analyses of systemic innovation should be extended to embrace all firms in a knowledge economy, not just the clas-sically innovative. This extension will call for a transformation of conventional ideas coordination and of the trade-off between exploration and exploitation. (Knowledge;Learning; Identity; Practice;Networks; Com-munities)

    Introduction While the recent focus on knowledge has undoubtedly benefited organizational studies, the literature still pres-ents sharply contrasting and at times even contradictory views of knowledge, which is variously described, openly or implicitly, as something "sticky" or "leaky." This paper is written on the premise that there is more than a problem with metaphors at issue here, and more than ac-counts of different types of knowledge (such as "tacit" and "explicit) can readily explain. Rather, these quite dif-ferent descriptions of knowledge reflect two different and partial perspectives from which knowledge and organi-zation are viewed. Finding a perspective that can account for both, the task this paper sets itself, thus seems a worth-while theoretical endeavor. To this end, we give examples of the contrasting views

    of knowledge and suggest why research often seems to evade this contrast rather than confront it. We then con-tend that the divergence is best resolved from the per-spective of practice, which can embrace in a single frame-work the sticky and leaky manifestations of knowledge. We lay out this framework and then explore what it re-veals about the external and internal relations of organi-zations. Externally, practice helps reveal the "embed-ding" conditions of organizations (Granovetter 1985,

    ORGANIZATIONSCIENCE,02001 INFORMS Vol. 12, No. 2, March-April 2001, pp. 198-213

    1047-7039/01/1202/0198/$05.00 1526-5455electronic ISSN

  • JOHN SEELY BROWN AND PAUL DUGUID Knowledge and Organization

    1999). Internally, we argue, practice creates epistemic barriers among the different communities that make up a complex organization. The formal organization's advan- tage over the market lies in dynamically coordinating the knowledge produced by these communities despite such differences. Thus, we conclude, analyses of systemic in- novation (Rosenberg 1994, Teece et al. 1994) should be extended to embrace all firms in a knowledge economy, not just the classically innovative. However, to extend the analysis this way calls for a transformation of conven- tional ideas of coordination and of the trade-off between exploration and exploitation (March 1991). Throughout this argument, our approach is deliberately informal. In this we hope to follow Winter's (1987, p. 180) intuition that, "without denying the possible usefulness of a formal modeling approach," it is sometimes useful to pursue "informal, looser, and more flexible" investigation.

    Conflicting Views and Alternating Approaches The literature overtly marks the conflict we hope to clar- ify in descriptions of knowledge as, on the one hand, "sticky" (von Hippel 1994, 1999; Szulanski 1996) and as, on the other, "leaky" (Liebeskind 1996, Wernerfelt 1984) or "mobile" (Hoopes and Postrel 1999). While some argue that there are two types of knowledge at issue here (arguments that we return to below), these contrary accounts of knowledge are nonetheless generally dis- cussed apart. Sticky discussions focus primarily on the challenge of moving knowledge inside organizations. For example, von Hippel (1994) discusses the well-known path of resistance between a firm's research labs and en- gineering, while Szulanski (1996) examines the stickiness evident in attempts to move the knowledge inherent in "best practice" from one part of an organization to an- other. In general, then, such discussions focus on the movement of knowledge within the borders of the firm. Discussions of "leakiness" and the like, by contrast, gen- erally focus on the external and (as the term suggests) undesirable flow of knowledge, in particular the loss of knowledge across the boundaries of the firm to compet- itors. Thus, Liebeskind (1996) sees a firm's competitive advantage as lying in its ability to prevent knowledge from leaking across potentially porous boundaries. We might expect these distinct analyses of knowledge

    to converge in studies that try to follow knowledge both within a firm and across substantial borders, yet here too we detect a certain de facto separation. Research into knowledge in multinationals, joint ventures, strategic al- liances, and foreign direct investment (for example Gupta and Govindarajan 2000, Hennart and Park 1993, Lyles

    ORGANIZATION 2001SCIENCE NO^. 12, NO. 2, March-April

    and Salk 1996, Simonin 1999) often focuses primarily on the "sticky" problem of coordinating knowledge among parts or partners of such extended organizations, leaving aside for the most part "leaky" worries about the poten- tial loss of proprietary knowledge as a result. These wor- ries are taken up in more theoretical accounts of how the rents accruing from its knowledge can be kept within a firm's boundaries (Williamson 198 1, 1991; Teece 1986). One perspective, then, helps to explain integration in terms of improving the reluctant flow of knowledge so that it reaches as far as the enterprise's boundaries (Kreiner and Schultz 1993, Kreiner and Lee 1999, Lee 1999); the other, in terms of creating boundaries-"pro- tective governance structures" (Williamson 1981) or "regimes of appropriability" (Teece 1986)-to prevent knowledge from spontaneously overflowing. To the ex- tent that they are thus balkanized, such discussions make it understandably hard to tackle the important task of ex- plaining the boundaries of the firm in terms of knowledge (Kogut 2000). Nevertheless, the literature does occasionally acknowl-

    edge that knowledge can appear to be both sticky and leaky. Two explanations generally follow. The first sug- gests that there are two kinds of knowledge; one kind is sticky and the other leaky. Thus, for example, Winter (1987) in his discussion of knowledge as an asset argues that "some [knowledge] assets are subject to major haz- ards of involuntary transfer; others may prove highly re- sistant to affirmative efforts to transfer them." This ty- pology is often supported by the well-known distinction between performative (and generally nonmarketable, hence sticky) knowledge and declarative (and in principle marketable and potentially leaky) knowledge. The dis- tinction often leads to distinctions of "know how" versus "know that" (for example, Garud 1997), for which the philosophical locus classicus is Gilbert Ryle's The Con- cept of Mind (1949) or "tacit" and "explicit" (for ex- ample, Nonaka and Takeuchi 1995), for which the locus classicus is Michael Polanyi's The Tacit Dimension (1966). The difficulty for this argument is that, rather than

    sticking or leaking according to type, exactly the same knowledge can prove both sticky and leaky. Ideas, in- sights, inventions, and practices that are unable to travel within the organization can prove to be quite capable of travelling to competitors. Such sticky-yet-leaky knowl- edge helps explain what Zeigler (1985) calls "fission- ingW-the process through which people who find their ideas blocked inside one organization form another to give the ideas a more sympathetic treatment. The succes- sive generations that led from the transistor to the modern microchip and, in the process, from Bell Labs through

    199

  • JOHN SEELY BROWN AND PAUL DUGUID Knowledge and 0rgani;ation

    Shockley and Fairchild to Intel and beyond are examples of knowledge (and knowers) stuck within one company fissioning out to another (Lecuyer 2000). A similar process between established firms can be

    seen in what might be thought of as "second mover" advantage, where ideas that failed to find a suitable re- ception in the first mover spread to another company that then makes them profitable. In a discussion of this prob- lem, Teece (1986) offers the example of EM1 and the CAT Scanner. More famous, if more anecdotal, is the example of the "Graphical User Interface" (GUI) devel- oped at Xerox PARC, but profitable primarily for Apple (with the Macintosh interface) and later Microsoft (with Windows). Here again, ideas that stuck within the origi- nating corporation leaked out and onto competitors' pro- duction lines with apparent ease (Hiltzik 1998, Smith and Alexander 1988). So, in all, those who argue that there are two types of knowledge, while addressing some stickylleaky issues succinctly but separately, are less helpful in accounting for knowledge which manifests both stickiness and leakiness simultaneously and accord- ing to circumstance. As that last phrase suggests, instead of addressing the

    inertia of knowledge in terms of inherent properties of knowledge itself, it seems more fruitful td lobk to the context or environment in which knowledge sticks or leaks. This is the second aDDr0ach to the stickvlleakv

    '1

    problem, and it generally leads to or 'ccu'ltural:' explanations of why and where knowledge sticks or flows. In such explanations, the firm usually emerges as an especially propitious place. Accounts describe it as a "social" (Kogut and Zander 1996) or "discursive"

    ~ .a

    (Tsoukas 1996) community or a single "community of practice" (Constant 1987, Kreiner and Lee 1999). Simi- larly, others have suggested it is a unitary "knowledge" (Grant 1996) or "interpretive" (Daft and Weick 1984) system. Allowing questions of collective meaning (Wenger 1998), sensemaking (Weick 1995), trust (Powell et al. 1996), motivation (Kogut and Zander 1992), and related issues that clearly bear on knowledge to enter the discussion, these sociocultural accounts offer much richer explanations than those that treat stickiness and leakiness as properties of knowledge itself. Therefore, they help to explain why the same knowledge may appear sticky and leaky. Nonetheless, sociocultural accounts face difficul- ties of their own. First, they can suggest a culturalist equivalent of the old economistic "black box" model of organizations, where the inside is somehow free of all the forces at work on the outside. Second, while helping to account for (perhaps without explaining) internal flow, they leave internal stickiness unexplained. Yet as the sticky literature would suggest, it is exactly within the

    firm that evidence of stickiness seems most perplexing. And third, despite culturalist assurances of cultural dis- continuity, knowledge does leak between firms, as the leaky literature confirms. Given these failings, we suggest there is a need not only to look beyond explanations that take knowledge as a well-defined substance, but also to look beyond explanations that take the cultural unity of the firm for granted. To do this, we propose looking at knowledge and or-

    ganization through the prism of practice-the way in which work gets done and, we would argue, knowledge is created. Such an approach, we must acknowledge in advance, raises problems of its own. In particular, instead of the balkanization of research, the perspective we pres- ent here tends to emphasize (and even exaggerate) the balkanization of the internal units of the firm, for it is, we suggest, at divisions created in practice that knowledge sticks, for these divisions (which inevitably occur within organizations that form around the division of labor) are epistemic in character. In dealing with these divisions, organizations find themselves dealing simultaneously with internal stickiness and external leaks.

    Divisions of Practice, Divisions of Knowledge ~ocioculturai accounts of knowledge and the firm gen- erally turn on the relationship between individual learning and social identity. Learning is inevitably implicated in the acquisition of knowledge, but it is also implicated in the acquisition of identity. People do not simply learn about; they also learn, as the psychologist ~ e r o k e Bruner (1996) suggests, to be. Learning, that is, doesn't just in- volve the acquisition of facts about the world, it also in- volves acquiring the ability to act in the world in socially recognized ways. This last qualification, "in socially rec- ognized ways," acknowledges that it is not enough to claim to be a physicist or a carpenter; people, particularly other physicists or carpenters, have to recognize you as such. People become managers or engineers not only by modeling themselves on managers or engineers (Ibarra 1999), but also by gaining the acceptance and recognition of managers or engineers. Learning, in all, involves ac- quiring identities that reflect both how a learner sees the world and how the world sees the learner. Learning any but the most simple job, then, is a complex social process, one that cannot simply be captured in the notion that "all learning takes place inside individual human heads" (Simon 1991, p. 125). Rather, as Teece et al. (1994) sug- gest, "learning processes are intrinsically social and col- lective phenomena" (p. 15).

    ORGANIZATION 12, NO. 2, March-April 2001SCIENCENOI. 200

  • JOHN SEELY BROWN AND PAUL DUGUID Knowledge and Organization

    Such a claim does not deny the integrity of the indi- vidual. It accepts, however, that what individuals learn always and inevitably reflects the social context in which they learn it and in which they put it into practice. When learning a job is at issue, this context usually includes the firm as a whole, immediate colleagues, and the relevant discipline or profession (as well as idiosyncratic external social forces bearing on each individual). To different degrees, these shape how individuals come to interpret the world (Daft and Weick 1984) and learn from it. Thus, "absorptive capacity" (Cohen and Levinthal 1990) is more than a function of the intelligence of the individual members of an organization. It is also reflects the way in which organizational context shapes the outlook of those individuals. "Absorptive" explanations of the flow and acquisition of knowledge both within and between firms need, then, to look beyond individuals to the milieu in which they work. Also, they must take into account the relationship between the two, a relationship in which nei- ther one (the individual or the milieu) can simply be re- duced to the other. From this perspective, the critical question becomes at

    what level to analyze the milieu. In their exploration of the same question, Kogut and Zander (1992) contrast the sociological units of the great nineteenth-century trio Marx, Durkheim, and Weber. Marx gave primacy to class (Marx 1967), Durkheim to the "organic" community (Durkheim 1984), and Weber to the bureaucratic orga- nization (Weber 1978). Kogut and Zander, in step with much organizational and business research, favor the last. Business organizations are undoubtedly a critical source of identity in modern society (Zunz 1990), but accounts can easily exaggerate and homogenize their contribu- tion. As O'Connor (1999) shows, in the thirties, Chester Barnard (1938) saw the business organization as a mech- anism for producing cultural homogeneity out of diversity (in short, the firm for Barnard was the engine of the na- tional melting pot). By the fifties, Whyte (1956) and oth- ers were denouncing the homogenizing role of the firm, yet in doing so, they nonetheless accepted and even am- plified the idea that firms are able to impose a uniform identity on their members. In the seventies, Arrow (1974) in his seminal analysis of the role of the firm in coordi- nating people and knowledge recapitulates Barnard (and a good deal of American sociology) by introducing the firm as a critical mediator between individuals and soci- ety. In the last couple of decades, as we have seen, re- search has reaffirmed the idea of organizations as cultural units. However, while accepting that firms may provide some

    degree of common culture for their members, it seems important to consider, for example, how much a CEO and

    ORGANIZATIONSCIENCENOI.12, NO. 2, March-April 200 1

    a technician in a large Fortune 500 company really have in common. As accounts of social networks and occu- pational communities indicate, both are likely to have more in common with their peers in other organizations than with many of the other employees in their own. Fo- cus on the organization as a cultural unit thus tends to overdetermine the contribution of often quite distant structures to groups of people with quite distinct prac- tices. Certainly, Kogut and Zander (1996) like Tsoukas (1996), Martin (1992), Schoenberger (1997) and, indeed, Barnard (1938) all provide accounts rich enough to ac- knowledge other "outside" forces bearing on the identity of an organization's members, and in the process resisting and refracting for each individual the pressures towards uniformity coming from the organization as a cultural force. Yet collectively such qualifications still seem caught in the familiar bind laid out by Orton and Weick (1990): "When researchers define organizations as mon- olithic corporate actors, they overemphasize order and underemphasize elements; when they define them as mere aggregates, they overemphasize elements and underem- phasize order" (p. 216). In this case, when they focus on the identity conferred by organizations, claims may over- emphasize homogeneity; when they focus on external identity-forming influences, they risk overemphasizing the autonomous and unconnected identity formation of each of an organization's members. The bind that Daft and Weick (1984) point to suggests

    a need to consider less distant social forces that, while not bearing on all members of large and diverse organi- zations equally, nonetheless bear on more than just in- dividual members separately. The choice researchers face, we want to suggest, is not simply between "indi- vidual belief and an organizational code" (March 1991) or between individual alienation and organizational man. Indeed, the cultural forces most salient for the members of an organization are probably not those "determined by leaders" (Schein 1985, p. 2) nor even necessarily those espoused by their members. Rather, they are those arising through and at the point of an individual's engagement in the organization and its work. Setting aside, as we do throughout this paper, very small organizations built around a single practice, these forces obviously do not bear on all in an organization, but they do to some degree bear on all engaged in similar jobs, and in particular on those engaged over time and collectively on particular tasks. The identity and knowledge that people acquire when joining an organization, then, while they might ap- pear to be those of an organization as a whole, are more likely to be those of the particular practice through which the individual joins the organization. The technicians Orr

    201

  • JOHN SEELY BROWN AND PAUL DUGUID Knowledge and Organization

    (1996) studied, this reminds us, become Xerox members by becoming technicians. Work practice, then, seems critical to understanding the

    acquisition of identity and knowledge at work. Looking at learning and identity through the lens of practice shifts attention from production or delivery-from structural or organizational perspectives-to include consumption and the perspectives of participation.' Turning things around this way helps to reveal that the identities developed through participation will be social if the work is social. They will be dynamic, changing as practice and the com- munity changes. They will be cumulative, as over time the community develops a history of practice, and they will be at least as varied as the distinct practices within an organization. Taking such things into account, practice-focused analysis brings investigations of knowl- edge and identity in organizations closer to the point at which working life is lived, work done, and so working identities created, than analysis focused either on auton- omous self-interest, on the one hand, or on what some cultural theorists recognized as the more abstract and dis- tant sociological "slabs" such as class or organization (Johnson 1983) on the other. The identities visible in this way will reflect the organization's de facto division of labor more than its espoused culture or autonomous in- terests (and self-interest) of its members. In all, work identities, the perspective suggests, are less something mandated by structure or dictated through culture, and more something that participation actually helps to create. In this regard, "communities of practice" as set out in

    Lave and Wenger (1991) and developed in an organiza- tional context in Brown and Duguid (1991) offer a par- ticularly helpful level of analysis for looking at work, learning, knowledge, and work identity formation. These groups of interdependent participants provide the work context within which members construct both shared identities and the social context that helps those identities to be shared. Members of such groups collectively de- velop an outlook on work and the world that may reflect the organization as a whole, but will most intensely reflect the local community. Within this, because of the shared perspective, knowledge can be readily shared. In propos- ing the community of practice, then, Lave and Wenger actually come closer to the sociology of Tonneis (1971) than to Marx, Durkheim, or Weber. Tonneis emphasized the importance of the local community (gemeinschafr) in relation to the larger abstractions of Marx, Durkheim, or Weber.2 At the same time, they suggest a solution to Winter's (1987) quest for a midlevel unit of analysis for looking at knowledge. This unit of analysis helps to amplify underexplored

    hints within some organizational literature that culture

    and identity are indeed shared most densely not at the level of the organization (unless the organization is itself little more than a community of practice), but at the level of what Schein (1985) acknowledges are its "subcul- tures." Though Schein talks little about these subcultures and does not draw on the wide literature on the topic (see Lave et al. 1992), the groups he has in mind are, we sus- pect, generally more autonomous (and often more sub- versive) than the espoused cultures he discusses in greater detail. Similarly, the community of practice highlights Cohen and Levinthal's (1990) brief suggestion that ab- sorptive capacity is not simply a function of an organi- zation as a whole, but of its internal "units." The notion also intimates, as intuitively seems more reasonable, that cultural forces might well bind groups of technicians (Barley 1996) or of senior managers (Spender 1989, Lyles and Schwenk 1992, Schoenberger 1997) quite tightly, but probably not both technicians and senior man- agers together. To the extent that there is an overall cul- ture embracing both, it is likely to be relatively ineffectual compared to the community of practice of each. The gen- eral ability to share participants' knowledge between these two practices is correspondingly limited. The per- spective of practice thus embraces recognizable divisions of identity within organizations: not only such things as "R&D culture," but also the distinct culture of, for ex- ample, technicians (Orr 1996, Barley 1996), engineers (Constant 1987, Almeida and Kogut 1999), or claims pro- cessors (Wenger 1998). It also helps to explain the mark- edly different outlooks of people within an organization with apparently quite similar jobs, such as sales and mar- keting, accounting and budget forecasting (Arrow 1974), or nurses and doctors (Leonard and Sensiper 1998). Here distinct practices make the communities, and so identities and knowledge, distinct. Therefore, communication be- tween the two can be more problematic than might at first appear. For a variety of reasons, then, communities of practice

    seem a useful organizational subset for examining orga- nizational knowledge as well as identity. First, they are privileged sites for a tight, effective loop of insight, prob- lem identification, learning, and knowledge production. As von Hippel (1999) suggests, useful knowledge in or- ganizations is often best developed not by "specialists" detached from a problem, but by those "who directly benefit from a solution," who, we contend, are likely to be the members of a community of practice in which the problem to be solved arises. Second, communities of practice are also significant repositories for the develop- ment, maintenance, and reproduction of knowledge. A community's knowledge is not held equally by all, but shared differentially across the community as a whole,

    ORGANIZATIONSCIENCENOI.12, NO. 2, March-April 2001 202

  • JOHN SEELY BROWN AND PAUL DUGUID Knowledge and Organization

    though it is made available to all. Joining such a com- munity (in the process Lave and Wenger 1991 call "le- gitimate peripheral participation") gives access to that community's identity and through that its collective knowledge. Third, community knowledge is more than the sum of its parts. Community members provide for one another social "affordances" (Cook and Brown 1999) that scaffold knowledge creation in practice. Fourth, or- ganizational adaptability (Stark 2000)-the ability to adapt continuously and respond proactively to environ- mental change-is to a significant degree determined by communities of practice. Members of a community of practice are often simultaneously members of that orga- nization and members of a larger, dispersed occupational group (van Maanen and Barley 1984). Thus, as well as providing a source of locally produced knowledge, the community of practice, as Constant (1987) suggests, also creates a vital link between organizational strategy and changes emerging outside the organization-a point we shall expand on in a m ~m e n t . ~ The idea of communities of practice has been taken up

    with a remarkable amount of enthusiasm. It nonetheless (or perhaps, for this very reason) needs handling with care, much like the notion of "culture" over which we hesitated above. On the one hand, much of the enthusiasm turns on the appeal of the word community, which Williams (1976) suggests can be a deceptive but "warmly persuasive word." (It is worth contemplating how wide the notion would have spread had Lave and Wenger de- cided to talk about a cadre or commune of practice.) Com- munities of practice are, in fact, as likely to be cold as warm, may sometimes be coercive rather than persuasive, and are occasionally explosive. Nevertheless, mediating as they do between individuals and large formal and in- formal social structures, and between organizations and their environment, they are where a good deal of the work involved in knowledge creation and organizational learn- ing gets done. The appeal of community has tended to obscure the

    importance of practice, hence our desire to redirect atten- tion here. This notion, however, brings its own problems. In the first place, the ambiguity of the term allows prac- tice to signify both work itself (the practice of a medical practitioner, for example), and rote tasks or exercises de- signed to help learn to work (as in piano practice). Let us simply assert that by practice we mean, as most theorists of practice mean, undertaking or engaging fully in a task, job, or profession. Second, and more problematically for those trying to build an organizational account, practice theory, whether from the right (in the hands of, for ex- ample, Hegel, Hayek, or Oakeshott) or from the left (in the hands of Marx, Bourdieu, or de Certeau), tends to

    ORGANIZATION 2001SCIENCE NO^. 12, NO.2, March-April

    remain at best neutral and at worst hostile to institutional and organizational theories. Consequently, in theory, the community of practice sometimes appears indifferent to other forms of social alignment, resembling a sort of so- cial monad-a fundamental building block whose artic- ulation with other better-known structures is hard to see. Finally, while the idea of community may comfortingly suggest that organizations are significantly culturally ho- mogeneous, practice, as we have noted, uncomfortingly suggests they are to a significant degree divided, riven by practice even as that practice provides participants with their particular kind of organizational identity. Indeed, if regarded as a community at all, any but the smallest or- ganization should probably be regarded as a "community of communities of practice" (Brown and Duguid 1991, Tuomi 1999).

    Practice and Knowledge So far we have made several claims about practice, knowledge, and communities, but done little to yoke them together theoretically, and we must acknowledge that the three make uneasy companions. Lying in many accounts on opposite sides of the standard division between theory and practice or mental and manual labor, knowledge and practice make something of an odd couple. Similarly, knowledge and community seem to violate the conven- tional idea noted already that knowledge belongs just to individuals. Let us begin, then, with the issue of knowledge and

    practice. The distinctions of Ryle (1949) and Polanyi (1966), being widely cited in the literature, offer a good place to start and allow us to again take up the issue of sticky and leaky knowledge as two types of kn~wledge .~ Polanyi's most quoted line is probably "We know more than we can tell" (Polanyi 1966, p. 4). This unspeakable knowing is what Polanyi deems tacit as distinct from ex- plicit. His distinction is thus often used to justify the idea that there are two kinds of knowledge, one tacit and one explicit, hence one that sticks and one that leaks. The distinction also suggests that translating the inarticulate form into the explicit form, turning sticky knowledge fluid, would be a way to promote required fluidity (Nonaka and Takeuchi 1995). Yet, while many discussions of Polanyi end with this

    point about knowing more than we can tell, for Polanyi it was only a beginning. "I shall consider human knowl- edge," he writes, "by starting from [this] fact" (Polanyi 1966, p. 4). He spends the rest of the first Terry lecture contemplating the relation of this inarticulate knowledge to what can be articulated, and he concludes that knowl- edge always has an inarticulate component. This com- ponent Polanyi calls the tacit dimension-a point suffi- ciently important that he made it the title of the published

    203

  • JOHN SEELY BROWN AND PAUL DUGUID Knowledge and Organization

    lectures. He is not, then, arguing for two types of knowl- edge, merely for two dimensions-two interdependent di- mensions, it turns out, for the explicit dimension of knowledge relies on previously "interiorized" (in Polanyi's terms) implicit or tacit dimension. Attempts to shake off this tacit dimension, buried as it is in personal identity. are in Polanyi's view at best futile, at worst c~unter~roduct ive .~Though knowledge undoubtedly can be usefully articulated and explicated, in use the explicit nonetheless always possesses this other, implicit dimen- sion. Polanyi's tacitJexplicit distinction echoes Ryle's fa-

    mous contrast between know how and know that. Like Polanyi, Ryle insists that these are not independent types of knowledge. They are interdependent and cannot be re- duced to one another. Knowing how Ryle insists "cannot be defined in terms of knowing that'' (Ryle 1949, p. 32). Acquiring know that does not lead to being able to use it. Knowing the rules of chess, in Ryle's running example, does not tell you how to play chess. Know that may be both explicit and free flowing, but from Ryle's perspec- tive it is neither actionable nor useful on its own. To make know that useful requires appropriate know how, some-thing thus very similar to Polanyi's tacit dimension. Know how, moreover, is not acquired like know that, which may circulate as precepts and rules. It is, Ryle in- sists, quite different. "We learn how," he argues signifi- cantly. "by practiceN-by, in Ryle's example, playing chess. Polanyi makes a similar claim when he argues that "comprehension," which is for Polanyi the acquisition of knowledge from another, is "both intellectual and practical" (Polanyi 1966, p. 48). In both of these well- known arguments, then, knowledge is two-dimensional and practice underpins its successful circulation. Examples of butchers and midwives (Lave and Wenger

    1991), photocopier repair technicians (Brown and Duguid 1991), or flute-makers (Cook and Yannow 1993) may make it seem that these strictures apply only to a special kind of knowledge-to "practical knowledge," knowl-edge that is distinct and separable from the more refined, cerebral knowledge, and so to manual labor but not to mental, to use a conventional workplace distinction. Ryle categorically refutes the notion. "Theorizing," he argues, is simply "one practice amongst others" (Ryle 1949, p. 26). Schon's (1983) work on professional practice also suggests that a practice perspective undermines conven- tional assumptions about the mental-manual divide, while Barley (1996) also rejects such a d i ~ i d e . ~ So, Polanyi's and Ryle's arguments militate against the

    idea that knowledge circulation involves explicit knowl- edge alone. From the idea that tacit knowledge is "non- tradable" and needs to be converted into explicit form to

    circulate, we come instead to the idea not only that con- version (if it involves uprooting knowledge from the tacit) is problematic, but also that tacit knowledge is required to make explicit knowledge usefully tradable or mobile. Only by first spreading the practice in relation to which the explicit makes sense is the circulation of explicit knowledge worthwhile (Cook and Brown 1999). Knowl- edge, in short, runs on rails laid by practice. This is not such a fragmentary conclusion as it may seem. Simply by being human, we all engage in a great deal of similar practice, and hence share a great deal of tacit understand- ing. People do share knowledge and insight by virtue of their membership in those overarching sociocultural "slabs." Nonetheless, much of the practice that forms identity and gets work done is more local and more dy- namic. The need to share some practice to be able to share

    new ideas reveals the challenge of workplace communi- cation and coordination. Anthony Giddens (1990) ad- dresses this point in terms of "disembedding" and "reembedding" knowledge. He suggests that as technol- ogies increasingly allow people to communicate across space and time, as knowledge is disembedded in one place to be reembedded in another, the critical question concerns the degree to which the embedding conditions at both ends of the communication are similar. To the extent that they are, then communication and coordina- tion are likely to be successful. To the extent that they differ, communication and coordination are likely to break down, and we are suggesting that the same chal- lenge presents itself in attempts to communicate not across distance, but across different communities devel- oped around different practices. Distinct practices create distinct embedding circumstances. Therefore, to under- stand where knowledge flows and where it sticks we need to ask where and why practices (and so embedding cir- cumstances) are common, and where and why they are not.

    Practice, Community, and Networks First, however we need to address the question, if, as Polanyi and Ryle argue, there is a practice component in all knowledge, is there necessarily a social component'? Certainly, Polanyi and Ryle establish no explicitly social connections. Spender (1996), however, uses Vygotsky to reveal the social entailments of Polanyi's argument. Moreover, it seems reasonable to argue that if people share a practice, then they will share know how, or tacit knowledge. So, as communities of practice are defined by their communal practice, they are likely to have com-munal know how developed from that practice. If shared

    ORGANIZATION 12, NO. 2, March-April 2001 SCIENCENOI. 204

  • JOHN SEELY BROWN AND PAUL DUGUID Knowledge and Organization

    know how or tacit knowledge make it possible to share know that or explicit knowledge effectively, then such communities, sharing common embedding circum-stances, will also be effective at circulating explicit knowledge. Empirical studies (Barley 1996, Hutchins 1991, Orr 1996) suggest that communities of practice do indeed work this way, holding and sharing knowledge collectively because of their shared practice. Orr's ex- ample is particularly interesting because the technicians he discusses are presumed to work alone. In fact, they rely heavily on the collective knowledge of the group. While this knowledge is distributed unevenly across the group, members can share it because of their common base of tacit knowledge, or know how.7 The practice- based, tacit dimension of knowledge, then, is clearly im- plicated in the stickiness and leakiness of knowledge, for shared practice demarcates the extent to which knowl- edge can spread. Its role is not, we should emphasize again, confined to less cerebral kinds of knowledge. It would seem both to underpin and (where absent) to un- dermine the circulation of apparently self-sufficient and replicable scientific knowledge in scientific communities (Ziman 1967). Work on such communities also helps to add an extra

    dimension to understanding the social reach of knowl- edge. Strauss's (1978, 1982, 1984) sociology of academic practice indicates that practice does not only bind small, tight communities together. It also allows extensive aca- demic disciplines, most of whose members will never know one another, to form and communicate. Strauss re- fers to these as "social worlds," but their relation to knowledge is perhaps better understood through Knorr Cetina's (1 999) term "epistemic cultures." Knorr Cetina's ethnography-based analysis is particularly valu- able because it explores the extensive flow of knowledge across such communities that "create and warrant knowl- edge.'' Knorr Cetina's two examples, microbiologists and high-energy physicists, reveal how, where practice is common, communication can be global. Scientists within each of these disciplines can communicate and collabo- rate with colleagues around the world, for as a result of the practice common to all members of the group, the core of their embedding circumstances is widely shared. Of course, communication is not uniform across these global cultures. Small subsets of disciplines, worlung closely together and so within what Knorr Cetina calls the "hum" of "continuous reporting among partici-pantsw-in short, communities of practice--develop dis-tinct ways of working that may simultaneously create conditions for effective local communication but barriers to global communication. Consequently, new practices and the knowledge emerging from them will not spread

    as readily or as widely as insights built on settled knowl- edge. In his analysis of communities of physicists, Collins (1975) notes the sorts of barriers new practice can make to the spread of apparently replicable scientific knowl- edge:

    It's very difficult to make a carbon copy [of someone else's gravity wave detector]. You can make a near one, but if it turns out that what's critical is the way he glued the transducers, and he forgets to tell you that the technician always puts a copy of Physical Review on top of them for a weight, well, it could make all the difference. (Collins, 1975, quoted in von Hippel 1994p. 43 1).

    In recognition of the difference between local and global scientific practice, the physicist Ziman (1967) regards making the emerging local knowledge of particular groups accessible to others within the broader epistemic culture a critical and challenging part of doing science. Ziman calls the knowledge thus produced "public knowl- edge'' (as distinct from more local knowledge), but he is clear that this "public" involves the particular scientific community at issue, and not the public at large. Ziman's public is essentially Knorr Cetina's epistemic

    culture. As Knorr Cetina shows, different scientific prac- tices produce quite distinct epistemic cultures, and hence the sort of knowledge that might flow readily within one culture will not flow uninhibitedly between two. The dis- tinctive practices that internally bind the epistemic cul- tures of microbiologists and the physicists externally di- vide them from one another simultaneously. The two together do not form an epistemically homogeneous "sci- entific community" any more than, as we noted earlier, technicians and senior management within an organiza- tion form a single culture. To return to Giddens's terms, the embedding circumstances of each community are quite distinct, making the process of disembedding and reembedding problematic. There is no transparent language in social theory, but

    given the problematic ambiguity of Strauss's world, Knorr Cetina's culture, and Ziman's public, we prefer to think of these loose epistemic groups as "networks," while acknowledging that that term brings its own diffi- c ~ l t i e s . ~Reflecting what binds these networks together and enables knowledge to flow within them, we call these extended epistemic networks "networks of practice." Practice creates the common substrate. With the term net-work, we also want to suggest that relations among net- work members are significantly looser than those within a community of practice. As Strauss indicates, and unlike in communities of practice, most of the people within such a network will never know, know of, or come across one another. And yet they are capable of sharing a great deal of knowledge.

    ORGANIZATION 2001SCIENCE NO^. 12, NO. 2, March-April 205

  • JOHN SEELY BROWN AND PAUL DUGUID Knowledge and Organization

    Within the class of network of practice, we would in- clude such things as the 24,000 technical representatives working for Xerox. It is hard to conceive of this as a single community of practice, though the much smaller subset which Orr (1996) studied clearly is one. To gen- eralize, the people in a particular job category within a large organization do not necessarily make a single com- munity of practice. The category may comprise several communities of practice which together form part of a larger network, which may extend not only across the company, but beyond it. The network of Xerox reps is itself only a subset of a larger network of photocopier repair technicians in general, many of whom work for other companies. Similarly, as we have indicated, we in- clude under the rubric academic disciplines which, as Alpert (1985) and Strauss have argued, join departments from universities around the world to make up groups whose members, to the extent that they have common practices, are able to read and understand one another's work. Disciplinary networks of practice cut across het- erogeneous organizations, including, for example, uni- versities, think tanks, or research labs.9 Professions make up still other such networks of practice, where again simi- lar practitioners, by virtue of their practice, are able to share professional knowledge through conferences, work- shops, newsletters, listserves, Web pages, and the like. And as Spender (1989) suggests, managers form net- works that extend well beyond their own organizations to include similar managers in other organizations. Despite being competitors, managers, as members of a network of practice, have extensive shared practice leading to ex- tensive shared know how, which in turn allows extensive circulation of managerial knowledge. Using conventional spatial images, this argument suggests that different net- works of practice cut horizontally across vertically inte- grated organizations and extend far beyond the bound- aries of the latter. Along these networks, knowledge can flow. Spender's notion of "industry recipes," ideas about

    management practices that networks of managers share and circulate, helps to emphasize the process of com- munication within these networks. As his analysis sug- gests, these "recipes" must first be disembedded from the local. This is not an easy task, as those who try to turn their local management practice into a general manage- ment guide know.'' Knowledge thus disembedded must also be reembedded in the local conditions of those hop- ing to use it, as everyone who uses a management guide wisely realizes. Whatever the recipe, as Spender's work suggests, you need first to be part of the practice-to ex-tend Spender's metaphor, to be a cook-to understand it

    (as any novice who tries to use a cookbook quickly dis- covers). Such networks then spread knowledge among practi-

    tioners, crossing the boundaries of particular organiza- tions and following routes prepared by practice. Along these, knowledge will often leak to the extent that com- mon practice has prepared the way (Powell et al. 1996, Kreiner and Schultz 1993, von Hippel 1999). To return to the example of the Xerox GUI, the knowledge devel- oped at PARC leaked to Apple, where similar researchers were engaged in similar pursuits (Smith and Alexander 1988). As Walker et al. (1997) argue, the structure of these types of network is more than a description of the "flow of information" (as Casson 1997 would suggest), but rather "an expression of social knowledge." Consequently, while these networks are, as Knorr

    Cetina argues, potentially global, they will tend to have a local character. While similar communities in different firms will take different approaches to common problems (Constant 1987), where such firms are close, the contacts among people in the network dense, and the movement of individuals (as bearers of practice, rather than as bear- ers of knowledge) from one firm to another (Almeida and Kogut 1999) frequent, practice is likely to be sufficiently shared to let specialized knowledge flow. Hence, areas of local network density help to explain "regional advan-tage" (Marshall 1890, Saxenian 1996) and the sort of institutional framework that supports such advantage (Lynn et al. 1996).

    Stickiness, Leakiness, and Practice From the perspective of practice, then, it is possible to understand the flow of new knowledge into and out of organizations. A community of practice and its members stand at the intersection of the organization and the net- work. As such, they lie within two dominant strands of social relations. One strand, bound together by organi- zational membership, extends along the value chain of the firm, but crosses its divisions of labor (and practice). The other, bound together by practice, orthogonally crosses the value chain but extends beyond the organi- zation along the network of practice. We can enumerate several implications of this argument. First, as knowledge will travel along the networks built

    by practice, it will quite understandably leak between the firms along these conduits. Second, as a result, a firm's boundaries are unlikely to encompass all its knowledge and, when informal links are taken into account, distinc- tions between "stocks" and "flows" of knowledge (Decarolis and Leeds 1999) may be hard to draw. Co- location of organizations from a particular industry gives

    ORGANIZATION 200 1SCIENCE NO^. 12, NO. 2, March-April 206

  • JOHN SEELY BROWN AND PAUL DUGUID Knowledge and Organization

    rise to fine differentiation of practice (Porter 1998, Kenney and Von Burg 1999) creating complex "ecolo- gies" of knowledge (Brown and Duguid 2000). Third, given the role of networks, trying to stop knowledge at organizational boundaries can be a very difficult task. Moreover, aggressive attempts to prevent leaking may be counterproductive. As a result of the two strands of iden- tification-one in the organization, one in the network- members of a particular community are likely to have divided loyalties as Arrow (1974), Alpert (1985), Constant (1987), Knorr Cetina (1999), and Saxenian (1996) have all noticed in their different ways. Which strand communities favor or disfavor will have a signifi- cant effect on the direction in which knowledge flows. Aggressive organizational attempts to inhibit network re- lations are paradoxically likely to reinforce network iden- tification, which may grow at the expense of loyalties to the organization. Fourth, moreover, trying to stop knowl- edge at these boundaries may be strategically counterpro- ductive too. The lines that let knowledge leak out, also let it flow in. Firms trying to block leaks risk cutting themselves off from essential knowledge (Saxenian 1996, Mounier-Kuhn 1994). In all, strategic decisions about knowledge need to take into account the firm's degree of embeddedness (Granovetter 1985). In this regard, how- ever, it is important to note that networks of practice may also inhibit the flow of knowledge. As Lynn et al. (1996) show, professional networks will occasionally work to resist the spread of ideas felt to be inimical to the interests of the network's members.

    Organizing Communities, Overcoming Stickiness We have used the notion of networks of practice to ex- plain leakiness. This is not, we have suggested, simply an inherent property of some kinds of knowledge. It does not result from making knowledge explicit and, so, trad- able. It is rather a function of the common underlying practice, which creates social-epistemic bonds. Where practice doesn't prepare the ground, knowledge is un- likely to flow. As the CEO of Chapparal Steel told Leonard-Barton (1995), he can tour people through the plant, show them almost "everything and we will be giv- ing away nothing because they can't take it home with them." So stickiness, rather than being the property of a dif-

    ferent kind of knowledge and subject to different expla- nations, can now be explained in the same terms. If knowledge leaks in the direction of shared practice, it sticks where practice is not shared. People with different practices have different assumptions, different outlooks,

    ORGANIZATION 2001SCIENCE NO^. 12, NO. 2, March-April

    different interpretations of the world around them, and different ways of making sense of their encounters. Such differences challenge the fluidity of networks, where as we have shown newly emerging knowledge is hard to circulate until the practice underlying it becomes com- mon beyond its originating community. Inevitably, these epistemic differences present an even greater challenge to organizations. As we have noted, while networks em- brace people with a core of common practices, organi- zations, by contrast, deliberately embrace communities with fundamentally different practices, presiding as most do over a particular division of labor, and hence of prac- tice and knowledge. Ultimately, an organization's competitive edge, and

    hence survival, depends on its unique ability to coordinate knowledge across these divisions (Hoopes and Postrel 1999) better than both its competitors and the market- place. However, the tendency to understand coordination principally in terms of individuals and organizations and not, as we are contending here, from a perspective that embraces the practice and communities, makes the chal- lenge of coordinating knowledge more difficult. Ignoring practice, we suspect, is likely to exacerbate the internal stickiness that inevitably arises from the internal division of labor, to promote counterproductive outward leakiness, and above all to contribute to core rigidity (Leonard- Barton 1995). The complementary character of the divisions in a firm

    has been well explained in the context of invention and systemic innovation (Schumpeter 1947, Rosenberg 1994, and Teece et al. 1994). Rosenberg and Teece et al. argue that innovation-making inventions marketable-often involves building coherent systems of complementary knowledges. In addition, they suggest that formal orga- nization is often uniquely well adapted to this sort of dy- namic coordination of complementary, inchoate knowl- edge. As outsourcing, technology, and the falling transaction costs that technology produces strip away those aspects of knowledge and routine that are better dealt with elsewhere, knowledge production and coordi- nation will increasingly dominate the critical assets of firms. As a result, the charge of building and continuously developing such knowledge complementarity will fall to all firms, whether canonically "innovatory" or not." The knowledge arising from all of its different communities- as they interact with their part of the firm's environment, develop local solutions to their problems, and draw in knowledge from their network connections-will become increasingly important and firms will have to engage in a dynamic balancing act. Consequently, conventional ways of dealing with the potential autonomy inherent in each community of practice in a firm as it follows its

    207

  • JOHN SEELY BROWN AND PAUL DUGUID Knowledge and Organization

    particular practice will become increasingly inappropri- ate. The conventional approach has been, in essence, to use

    the firm's hierarchical control to limit disruptive local change and so ensure coordination. Certain communities or areas within the firm receive the right to search for new knowledge (Nelson and Winter 1982). The others are strictly regimented and expected to follow routine. This strategic distinction (which in many ways follows the old mentallmanual division we mentioned above) can be seen in Lecuyer's (2000) description of Fairchild. That com- pany's founders ranged wide in their own intellectual ex- ploration of the integrated circuit, but they specified in extraordinary detail the activities of all other employees and acted aggressively against anyone who did not follow specifications minutely. Routines inevitably shift work- place activity from practice as preeminently an adaptive, improvisational, knowledge-producing propensity of the sort we have been describing to practice as principally repetitive rote behavior of the sort to which the same term can also refer. However, as Stinchcombe (1990) suggests, there is always a little of the first kind of practice in rou- tines, however regimented. Whatever insights or inven- tions such practice may generate will almost inevitably be lost to the organization. The organizational choice at issue here has been characterized by March (1991) as a trade-off between exploration and exploitation, by Demsetz (1988) as between specialization and coordina- tion, and by Sorensen and Stuart (2000) who sum it up as innovative processes versus organizational learning. The former in each pair represents the search for new knowledge, the latter the increasing refinement of existing knowledge, with significant sunk costs (Arrow 1962) that make change costly. In effect, these arguments suggest, organizations conventionally seek a static balance be- tween these antinomies by suppressing organizationwide ramifications of the sort of spontaneity important to knowledge work through most of the organization. Of course, to survive, even hierarchical control must

    be adaptable and often is. Adler et al. (1999) give a de- scription of organizational flexibility at Toyota's NUUMI plant which shows how effective it can be. Effective hi- erarchical control is also evident in Microsoft's extraor- dinary achievement of turning the entire organization to- wards the Internet in the mid-1990s (Cusumano and Yoffie 1998). But, as the latter case reminds us, this rad- ical adaptation decreed from above was necessary be- cause noises from below, from those in the firm who "got" the Internet much earlier, could not be heard for what they were-signs of profound environmental change. As organizations shift away from routine coor- dination and towards innovative, continuously develop- ing practice, such local insight into the environment will

    be too valuable for firms to ignore or to stifle. Instead, it must be able, at least potentially, to effect "from below" not just the practice of specific communities, but the or- ganization's overall processes and strategies. As structur-ation theory (Giddens 1984) applied to the firm (Yates and Orlikowski 1992, Barley and Tolbert 1997) might suggest, communities of practice will become ubiquitous sources of knowledge driving organizational change. In such circumstances, there will no longer be a simple choice or static balance between exploration and exploi- tation, or spontaneity and structure, but a constant and pervasive need to dynamically balance and coordinate the two throughout the organization. Ubiquitous pressure for change presents a profound challenge to coordination and structure. Thus coordination is likely to be highly unsta- ble, the structure always under construction and always under threat. Consequently, strategic coordination is likely to appear

    rather different from heretofore. In the first place, as we have stressed, the elements to be coordinated are not just individuals, but communities and the practices they fos- ter. Second, as a result, focus on trust (Kramer and Tyler 1996) or individual motivation (Kogut and Zander 1992) is unlikely to achieve organizational coordination on its own. Both of these are undoubtedly important to orga- nizational stability and success, but alone they suggest that the critical divisions in an organization lie between the individual and the organization and come down to matters of individual alienation or self-interest versus the collective culture and interests of the organization. In- evitably these contrasts, important though they are, gloss over the epistemic differences that we argue are inherent in the organizational division of labor, and present quite a different challenge. Certainly, trust and motivation might help overcome epistemic differences. However, as Sitkin and Stickel (1996) suggest in their analysis of the "quality movement," ignoring epistemic differences that distinguish different communities within a firm can ac- tually serve to damage trust quite significantly. On this interplay of epistemic differences and issues of

    trust and coordination, we would also cite an example from our own experience at Xerox. The Xerox research center developed a novel imaging technology and sought to move it out of the labs and into production. However, the technology found no sympathy with the engineers, who compared results of tests on key parts to the critical parameters for apparently similar parts on other print technologies and found the new device wanting. Nego- tiations between the two groups were all but abandoned as trust collapsed. The problem, it eventually emerged, was that the critical parameters for the new parts actually

    ORGANIZATION 2001SCIENCE NO^. 12, NO. 2, March-April 208

  • JOHN SEELY BROWN AND PAUL DUGUID Knowledge and Organization

    bore little relation to those for their equivalents on con- ventional print technologies. Though the result of tests on both might have looked much the same, simple compar- ison of a set of parameters did not produce a coherent set of results. Some measures essential to the engineers' un- derstanding of the existing technology and manufacturing process just did not apply to the new technology. The example fits nicely with Constant's (1987) argument that communities of practice are keepers of a particular tra- dition and for engineers in particular a "tradition of test- ability sustains and defines, almost tautologically, the specific tradition" (p. 226). To generalize, while two communities may and often do acknowledge a single set of measures as a common boundary object (Star and Grie- semer 1989), one, as this example suggests, may unilat- erally change its own "tradition of testability" or com- parable orientation to a boundary object in the process of developing new ideas, but in so doing may unwittingly disrupt communication, coordination, and even trust be- tween itself and other communities hitherto managed through that boundary object. In all, the example suggests to us that for organizations

    to take the evolution of knowledge and practice seriously, to gain the advantages that accrue from overcoming in- ternal stickiness while simultaneously preventing disaf- fection from promoting external leakiness, it is important to address the epistemic-social issues of different kinds of knowledge as well as the psychosocial ones of different levels of trust and motivation. Of course, epistemic rifts within organizations are rarely Kuhnian gulfs with wholly incommensurable practices on either side. Usually, com- munities that work together share some common prac- tices. Loss of synchronization may be common. Complete breakdown because of mutual incomprehension is rare. (As we noted at the outset, while bringing intercommunal differences helpfully to light, the practice perspective tends to exaggerate the internal balkanization of organi- zations.) For example, in almost all organizations, career changes of one sort or another will often take people out of one community and into another, leaving them with an understanding of both. Such people are then in a position to become translators or boundary spanners between the two. These sorts of connections often make the informal networks within a firm (like those without) much more important for spreading practice than the formal ones to which so much time and attention is given. Moreover, between such communities there are usually

    many boundary objects. Such things as shared docu- ments, tools, business processes, objectives, schedules, and the like not only serve to coordinate, but to record and signal changes in one community's practice. In so doing, they can make explicit the need for negotiation

    between the two over their diverging practices and prompt both sides to reconsider their practices and pre- suppositions. This way, coordinated communities can ac- tually transform the notion of "single-" and "double- loop learning" (Argyris and Schon 1974) from "interpersonal behavior" (Schon 1987) to intercom-munal behavior, with one community pushing another to reconsider its underlying assumptions. This intercom- munal dynamic is, then, one of the advantages of the co- ordinated but adaptive division of labor. The challenge of stickiness, hitherto primarily dealt

    with through the imposition of routines, changes in or- ganizations whose primary asset is the ability to develop knowledge continuously. For such organizations, the most important relationship between quasi-autonomous communities within a dynamically structured firm must be one of negotiation-negotiation that allows change, on the one hand, to occur locally and, on the other, to affect global strategic change if necessary.12 The idea of intercommunal negotiation may seem like an anodyne or vague summation of such a lengthy analysis. Still, it is on the one hand profoundly different from conventional organizational coordination, and on the other capable of creating dynamism in the organizational structure ade- quately responsive to the dynamism within creative com- munities.

    Conclusion Starting with the paradox of sticky and leaky knowledge, we have attempted to find a perspective that allows the paradox to be resolved, and we have claimed that the perspective of practice does the task. This perspective supports a sociocultural view of learning and knowledge, but one that challenges conventional views of the internal homogeneity of the firm. In contrast, we have stressed the internal divisions and external connections highlighted by practice. These internal divisions, communal rather than individual in origin, help explain stickiness, while the ex- ternal connections help explain leakiness. Together they suggest that a firm's knowledge base is not a property that falls within its boundaries, but one that in part draws on its embeddedness in broader structures. Consequently, knowledge may more easily flow out of a firm than move productively within it. Ultimately, the greatest benefits to knowledge accrue from coordinating its development across the division of labor, coordination often better achieved within the structure of the firm than in the mar- ketplace. We conclude that coordinating a firm around knowledge and practice, a dynamically demanding stra- tegic task, is quite different from coordinating it around more conventional routines, and helps to uncover the in- novative potential and challenge in all firms.

    ORGANIZATION 2001SCIENCE NO^. 12, NO. 2, March-April 209

  • JOHN SEELY BROWN AND PAUL DUGUID Kno~,ledgeand Organization

    Acknowledgments The authors are grateful to Mario Bernassi, Martin Kenney, Bruce Kogut, Kirstina Lee, Sid Winter and two anonymous referees for help with drafts of this paper.

    Endnotes or accounts of practice, see Bourdieu (1977), de Certeau (1988), and Lave and Chaiklen (1993). 2 ~onn i e sresists the notion that gemeinschafr and gesellschaji were al- ternate ways (and, in particular, temporally successive ways) of orga- nizing society. For contemporary interpretations of this "community question," see Wellman (1989). jconstant, we should note, developed a notion of "community of prac- tice" before and independently of Lave and Wenger, on whose work our own has been based. We are grateful to Kristina Lee for bringing his work to our attention. We return to his approach below, but we should note that Constant explicitly uses the term communit): in at least three different ways. w h i l e focussing on Polanyi and Ryle would appear to exclude all but Anglo-Saxon philosophy from debate, Polanyi's neo-Kantian approach in fact helps build implicit bridges to more phenomenological tradi- tions. For more explicit bridge building, see Tsoukis (1996) and Tuomi (1999). 'AS Polanyi (1966) puts it: "The declared aim of modem science is to establish a strictly detached, objective knowledge. . . . [but if] tacit thought forms an indispensable part of all that knowledge, then the ideal of eliminating all personal elements of knowledge would, in ef- fect, aim at the destruction of knowledge" (p. 20). 6~necdo t a laccounts claim that Polanyi, a chemist, developed his no- tion of the tacit dimension from contemplating the highly cerebral in- tuitive scientific practice of his physicist colleague and Nobel laureate Patrick Blackett. 'we should state once again, this social perspective on knowledge is in no way a dismissal of the individual. Implicitly, Polanyi and Ryle recreate the old Kantian distinction between concepts and precepts. Toulmin uses this to embrace both the individual and the social when he argues that that "each of us thinks his own thoughts; our concepts we share" (Toulmin, 1972, p. 32). Toulmin's notion of "communities of concept users" resembles the notion of communities of practice. ' ~ m o n g the difficulties that come with using network are the two, completely orthogonal uses in organizational literature. On the one hand, social network analysis, sparked by Strauss (1977) and Granovetter (1982) discusses the sort of networks that cut across or- ganizations, tying people in one to people in similar positions in an- other. This is the sort of network we have in mind here. On the other hand, many networking discussions in organizational literature have in mind networks formed out of organizations (see for example Ebers (1997), Grabher (1993)). To extend a point we made earlier, this dif- ference has to some degree allowed proponents of institutional eco- nomics (Williamson, 1981) who look in the direction of the value chain, and their critics (Granovetter, 1984) whose focus cuts across that chain, to talk past one another. Recent work by Stark (1999) and Grabher (2000) on heterarchies may provide one way of bringing these two dimensions together. 'See Powell (1996) for the heterogeneous organizational types in- volved in biotech.

    he process of disembedding management recipes resembles Ziman's (1967) account of creating "public knowledge" within a sci- entific discipline and can be a particular challenge to communities where the act of distilling ideas for consumption beyond the immediate community of practice is unfamiliar. Bobrow et al., (in preparation) indicate the challenge this extra practice created for the Xerox reps when they sought to put their insights into a database accessible by reps throughout one country. "Some have suggested that diminishing transaction costs will make the coordination role of the firm irrelevant (Downes and Mui, 1998). This is not Coase's view: "If transaction costs were the only factor, then we would [become an economy of individual entrepreneurs]. But the fact of the matter is the cost of organizing is decreasing too. The question is whether the costs of transacting decreases as fast as the costs of organizing. My guess is that sometimes it does and sometimes it does not." [R. H. Coase, "Talking about Tomorrow," interview in The Wall Street Journal, special issue, Jan 1, 2000, quoted in Odlyzko, 2000, p. 41.1 We are grateful to Andrew Odlyzko for bringing this quotation to our attention. Implicit in our own argument (and we sus- pect those of Rosenberg and Teece et al.) is the notion that transacting costs for inchoate, complementary knowledge embedded in practice are inherently higher than the cost of organizing. I21n most organizations, the power to negotiate is not equally distrib- uted. Consequently, in Xerox, the technicians' insights failed to affect the rest of the organization (Orr, 1996). The claims processors Wenger (1998) studied negotiated practice among themselves but were pow- erless to negotiate with those to whom their work passes. And as Star and Griesemer (1989) suggest the parties negotiating around boundary objects rarely negotiate on equal terms.

    References Adler, Paul, Barbara Goldoftas, David I. Levine. 1999. Flexibility ver-

    sus Efficiency?: A case study of model changeovers in the Toyota production system. Organ. Sci. lO(1) 43-68.

    Almeida, P., B. Kogut. 1999. Localization of knowledge and the mo- bility of engineers in regional networks. Management Sci. 45(7) 905-917.

    Alpert, Dan. 1985. Performance and paralysis: The organizational con- text of the American Research University. J. Higher Ed. 56(3) 242-28 1.

    Argyris, Christopher, Donald C. Schon. 1974. Theory in Practice: In- creasing Professional Effectiveness. Jossey-Bass, San Francisco, CA.

    Arrow, Kenneth J. 1962. The economic implications of learning by doing. Rev. Econom. Stud. 28 155-173.

    -. 1974. The Limits of Organization. W. W. Norton, New York. Barley, Stephen R. 1996. Technicians in the workplace: Ethnographic

    evidence for bringing work into organization studies. Admin. Sci. Quart. 41(3) 401444 .

    Barley, Stephen R., P. Tolbert. 1997. Institutionalization and structur- ation: Studying the links between action and institution. Organ. Stud. 18(1) 93-1 17.

    Barnard, Chester I. 1938. The Functions of the Executive. Harvard Uni- versity Press, Cambridge MA.

    Bobrow, Daniel G., Robert Cheslow, Jack Whalen. Community knowl- edge sharing in practice." Forthcoming.

    210 ORGANIZATION 12, NO. 2, March-AprilSCIENCENOI. 2001

  • - - -

    JOHN SEELY BROWN AND PAUL DUGUID Knowledge and Organization

    Bourdieu, Pierre. 1977. Outline of a Theory of Practice. Cambridge University Press, New York.

    Brown, John Seely, Paul Duguid. 199 1. Organizational learning and communities-of-practice: Toward a unified view of working, learning, and innovation. Organ. Sci. 2(1) 40-57.

    --, . 2000. Mysteries of the region. William F. Millar, Chong- Moon lee, Marguerite Gong Hancock, Henry S. Rowen, eds. The Silicon Valley Advantage. Stanford University Press, Palo Alto, CA.

    Bruner, J. 1996. The Culture of Education. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA.

    Cohen, Wesley M., Daniel A. Levinthal. 1990. Absorptive capacity: New perspective on learning and innovation. Admin. Sci. Quart. 35 128-152.

    Collins, H. 1975. The seven sexes: A study in the sociology of a phe- nomenon, or the replication of experiments in physics. Sociology 9(2) 44-64.

    Constant, Edward W. 1987. The social locus of technological practice: Community, system, or organization. W. Bijker, T. Hughes, T. Pinch, eds. The Social Construction of Technological Systems: New Directions in the Sociology and History of Technology. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, 223-242.

    Cook, Scott Noam, John Seely Brown. 1999. Bridging epistemologies: The generative dance between organizational knowledge and or- ganizational knowing. Organ. Sci. lO(4) 382-400.

    -, Dvora Yanow. 1993. Culture and organizational learning. J. Management Inquiry 2(4) 373-390.

    Cusumano, Michael A., David B. Yoffie. 1998. Competing on Internet Time: Lessons from Netscape and Its Battle with Microsoft. Free Press, New York.

    Daft, R. L., Karl E. Weick. 1984. Toward a model of organizations as interpretation systems. Acad. Management Rev. 9(2) 284-295.

    de Certeau, Michel. 1988. The Practice of Everyday Life. University of California Press, Berkeley, CA.

    Decarolis, Donna Marie, David L. Leeds. 1999. The impact of stocks and flows of organizational knowledge on firm performance: An empirical investigation of the biotechnology industry. Strategic Management J. 20 953-968.

    Demsetz, Harold. 1988. The theory of the firm revisited. J. Law, Econom. Organ. 4(1) 141-161.

    Downes, Lany, Chunka Mui. 1998. Unleashing the Killer Application: Digital Strategies for Market Dominance. Harvard Business School Press, Cambridge, MA.

    Durkheim, Emile. 1984. The Division of Labor in Society. The Free Press, New York.

    Ebers, Mark. 1997. The Formation of Inter-Organizational Networks. Oxford University Press, Oxford, U.K.

    Garud, Raghu. 1997. On the distinction between know-how, know- what, and know-why. A. Huff, J. Walsh, eds. Advances in Stra- tegic Management. JAI Press, Greenwich, CT.

    Giddens, Anthony. 1984. The Constitution of Society: Outline of a Theory of Structuration. Polity Press, Cambridge, U.K.

    -. 1990. The Consequences ofModernity: The Raymond Fred West Memorial Lectures. Stanford University Press, Stanford, CA.

    Grabher, Gemot. 2000. Spaces of creativity: Heterarchies in the British advertising industry. Paper presented to the seminar Organiza- tional Innovation: Distributed Intelligence and the Organization of Diversity, Columbia, NY, March 29.

    Granovetter, Mark. 1985. Economic action and social structure: The problem of embeddedness. Amer. J. Soc. 91(3) 48 1-5 10.

    -. 1999. Coase encounters and formal models. Admin. Sci. Quart. 44 158-162.

    Grant, Robert M. 1996. Towards a knowledge-based view of the firm.

    Strategic Management J. 17 (Winter Special Issue) 109-122.

    Gupta, Anil K. Vijay Govindarajan. 2000. Knowledge flows within

    multinational corporations. Strategic Management J. 21 473496.

    Hayek, F. A. von. 1988 The Fatal Conceit: Errors of Socialism. Rout-ledge, London, U.K.

    Hegel, G. 1910. The Phenomenology ofMind. J. B. Baillie, trans. Mac- millan, New York.

    Hennart, Jean-Francois, Young-Ryeol Park. 1993. Greenfield vs ac- quisition: The strategy of Japanese investors in the United States. Management Sci. 39(9) 1054-1070.

    Hiltzik, Michael. 1999. Dealers of Lightning: Xerox PARC and the Dawn of the Computer Age. HaperBusiness, New York.

    Hoopes, David G., Steven Postrel. 1999. Shared knowledge, 'glitches,' and product development performance. Strategic Management J. 20 837-865.

    Hutchins, Edwin. 1991. Organizing work by adaptation. Organ. Sci. 2(1) 14-38.

    Ibarra, Herminia. 1999. Provisional selves: Experimenting with image and identity in professional adaptation. Admin. Sci. Quart. 44 764-79 1.

    Johnson, Richard. 1983. What Is Cultural Studies Anyway? Working paper. Centre For Contemporary Cultural Studies, University of Birmingham, Birmingham, England.

    Kenney, Martin, Urs von Burg. 1999. Technology and path depen- dence: The divergence between Silicon Valley and Route 128. Indust. Corporate Change 8(1) 67-103.

    Knorr-Cetina, Karin. 1999. Epistemic Cultures: How the Sciences Make Knowledge. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA.

    Kogut, B. 2000. The network as knowledge: Generative rules and the emergence of structure. Strategic Management J. 21 405-425.

    -, Udo Zander. 1992. Knowledge of the firm, combinative capa- bilities, and the replication of technology. Organ. Sci. 3(3) 383- 3Y7.

    --, . 1996. What do firms do?: Coordination, identity, and leam- ing. Organ. Sci. 7(5) 502-5 18.

    Kramer, Roderick M., Tom R. Tyler, eds. 1996. Trust in Organiza- tions: Frontiers of Theory and Research. Sage Publications, Thousand Oaks, CA.

    Kreiner, Kristen, Kristina Lee. 1999. Knowledge assimilation: Mobi- lizing distributed knowledge. Paper presented at the Third World Congress on the Management of Intellectual Capital, Hamilton Ontario, Canada, January 20.

    -, Majken Schultz. 1993. Informal collaboration in R-and-D: The formation of networks across organizations. Organ. Stud. 14(2) 189-209.

    Lave, Jean C., Paul Duguid, Nadine Femandez, Eric Axel. 1992. Com- ing of age in Birmingham. Ann. Rev. Anthropology 21 257-282.

    -, Etienne Wenger. 199 1. Situated Learning: Legitimate Peripheral Participation. Cambridge University Press, New York.

    -, Seth Chaiklin, eds. 1993. Understanding Practice: Perspectives on Activity and Context. Cambridge University Press, New York.

    Lecuyer, Christophe. 2000. Fairchild semiconductor. M.F. Kenney, ed.

    ORGANIZATION 12, NO. 2, March-April 21 1 SCIENCENOI. 2001

  • JOHN SEELY BROWN AND PAUL DUGUID Knowledge and Organization

    Anatomy of an Innovative Region: Understanding Silicon Valley. Stanford University Press, Palo Alto, CA.

    Lee, Kristina. 1999. Knowledge Assimilation: A Case Study of Learn- ing and Cooperation between Communities of Practice. Institute of Organization and Industrial Sociology, Copenhagen Business School, Copenhagen, Denmark.

    Leonard-Barton, Dorothy. 1995. Wellsprings of Knowledge: Building and Sustaining the Sources of Innovation. Harvard Business School Press, Cambridge, MA.

    -, Sylvia Sensiper. 1998. The role of tacit knowledge in group innovation. California Management Rev. 40(3) 1 12-1 32.

    Liebeslund, Julia P. 1996. Knowledge, strategy, and the theory of the firm. Strategic Management J. 17 (Winter Special Issue) 93-107.

    Lyles, Marjorie A,, Jane E. Salk. 1996. Knowledge acquisition from foreign parents in international joint ventures: An empirical ex- amination in the Hungarian context. J. Internat. Bus. Stud. 27(5) 877-903.

    -, Charles R. Schwenk. 1992. Top management, strategy, and or- ganizational knowledge structures. J. Management Stud. 29(2) 154-174.

    Lynn, Leonard H., N. Mohan Reddy, John D. Aram. 1996. Linking technology and institutions: The innovation community frame- work. Res. Policy 25 91-106.

    March, James G. 1991. Exploration and exploitation in organizational learning. Organ. Sci. 2(1) 71-87.

    Marshall, Alfred. 1890. Principles of Economics. Macmillan and Co., London, U.K.

    Martin, Joan. 1992. Cultures in Organizations. Oxford University Press, Oxford, NY.

    Marx, Karl. 1967. The Communist Manifesto. Penguin Books, Har- mondsworth, Middlesex, U.K.

    -. 1971. Grundrisse. D. McLellan, trans. Harper & Row, New York.

    Mounier-Kuhn, Pierre E. 1994. Product policies in two French com- puter firms: SEA and Bull (1948-64). Lisa Bud-Frierman, ed. Information Acumen: The Understanding and Use of Knowledge in Modern Business. Routledge, London, U.K. 113-135.

    Nelson, Richard R., Sidney G. Winter. 1982. An Evolutionary Theory of Economic Change. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA.

    Nonaka, Ikujiro, Hirotaka Takeuchi. 1995. The Knowledge-Creating Company: How Japanese Companies Create the Dynamics of In- novation. Oxford University Press, New York.

    Oakeshott, M. 1991. Rationalism in Politics and Other Essays. Liberty Press, Indianapolis, IN.

    O'Connor, Ellen S. 1999. The politics of management thought: A case study of the Harvard Business School and the Human Relations School. Acad. Management Rev. 24(1) 117-131.

    Odlyzko, Andrew. 2000. The history of communications and its im- plications for the Internet. Online. Available: http:// www.research.att.com/~amo/doc/networks.html(July 23, 2000).

    Om, Julian. 1996. Talking about Machines: An Ethnography of a Mod- ern Job. IRL Press, Ithaca, NY.

    Orton, J. Douglas, Karl E. Weick. 1990. Loosely coupled systems: A

    reconceptualization. Acad. Management Rev. 15(2) 203-223.

    Polanyi, Michael. 1966. The Tacit Dimension. Doubleday and Co.,

    Garden City, NY.

    Porter, Michael. 1998. On Competition. Harvard University Press, Bos- ton, MA.

    Powell, Walter W. 1996. Inter-organizational collaboration in the bio- technology industry. J. Institutional Theoret. Econom. 152(1) 197-215.

    -, Kenneth W. Koput, Laurl Smith Doerr. 1996. Interorganizational collaboration and the locus of innovation: Networks of learning in biotechnology. Admin. Sci. Quart. 41 116145.

    Rosenberg, Nathan. 1994. Exploring the Black Box: Technology, Eco- nomics, and History. Cambridge University Press, New York.

    Ryle, Gilbert. 1949. The Concept of Mind. Hutchinson, London, U.K. Saxenian, AnnaLee. 1996. Regional Advantage: Culture and Compe-

    tition in Silicon Valley and Route 128. Harvard University Press., Cambridge, MA.

    Schein, Edgar H. 1985. Organizational Culture and Leadership. Jossey-Bass, San Francisco, CA.

    Schoenberger, Erica. 1997. The Cultural Crisis of the Firm. Black-wells, Oxford, U.K.

    Schon, Donald A. 1983. The Reflective Practitioner: How Profession- als Think in Action. Basic Books, New York.

    -. 1987. Educating the Reflective Practitioner: Towards a New De- sign for Teaching and Learning in the Professions. Jossey-Bass, San Francisco, CA.

    Schumpeter, Joseph A. 1947. Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy, 3rd Ed. Harper Torchbooks, New York.

    Simon, Herbert A. 1991. Bounded rationality and organizational learn- ing. Organ. Sci. 2(1) 125-134.

    Simonin, Bernard. 1999. Ambiguity and the process of knowledge transfer in strategic alliances. Strategic Management J. 20(7): 595-623.

    Sitlun, Sim B., Danyl Stickel. 1996. The road to hell: The dynamics of distrust in an era of quality. Roderick M. Kramer, Tom R. Tyler, eds. Trust in Organizations: Frontiers of Theory and Re- search. Sage Publications, Thousand Oaks, CA.

    Smith, Douglas K., Robert C. Alexander. 1988. Fumbling the Future: How Xerox Invented, then Ignored the First Personal Computer. Morrow, New York.

    Sorensen, J. B., T. Stuart. 2000. Aging, obselescence, and organiza- tional innovation. Admin. Sci. Quart. 45(1) 81-1 12.

    Spender, J-C. 1989. Industry Recipes: The Nature and Sources of Man- agerial Judgement. Basil Blackwell, Oxford, U.K.

    -. 1996. Competitive advantage from tacit knowledge?: Unpacking the concept and its strategic implications. B. Moingeon, A. Edmondson, eds. Organisational Learning and Competitive Ad- vantage. Sage, London, U.K.

    Star, Susan Leigh, James R. Griesemer. 1989. Institutional ecology, 'translations' and boundary objects: Amateurs and professionals in Berkeley's Musuem of Vertebrate Zoology, 1907-39. Social Stud. Sci. 19 387-420.

    Stark, David. 2000. Ambiguous assets for uncertain environments: Het- erarchy in postsocialist firms. P. DiMagio, W. Powell, D. Stark, E. Westney, eds. The 2Ist Century Firm: Changing Economic Organization in International Perspective. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ.

    Stinchcombe, Arthur L. 1990. Information and Organizations. Uni-versity of California Press, Berkeley, CA.

    212 ORGANIZATION 2001SCIENCE NO^. 12, NO. 2, March-April

  • JOHN SEELY BROWN AND PAUL DUGUID Knowledge and Organization

    Strauss, Anselm. 1978. A social world perspective. Stud. Symbolic In- teraction l(1) 119-128.

    -. 1982. Social worlds and legitimation processes. Stud. Symbolic Interaction 4 17 1-1 90.

    -. 1984. Social worlds and their segmentation processes. Stud. Sym- bolic Interaction 5 123-1 39.

    Szulanski, Gabriel. 1996. Exploring internal stickiness: Impediments to the transfer of best practice within the firm. Strategic Manage- ment J. 17 (Winter Special Issue) 27-43.

    Teece, David J. 1986. Profiting from technological innovation: Impli- cations for integration, collaboration, licensing, and public policy. Res. Policy 15(6) 285-305.

    -, Richard Rumelt, Giovanni Dosi, Sidney Winter. 1994. Under- standing corporate coherence: Theory and evidence. J. Econom. Behavior Organ. 23(1) 1-30.

    Tonneis, Ferdinand. 1971. On Sociology: Pure, Applied, and Empiri- cal. University of Chicago Press, Chicago, IL.

    Toulmin, Stephen. 1972. Human Understanding: The Collective Use and Evolution of Concepts. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ.

    Tsoukas, Hardimos. 1996. The firm as a distributed knowledge system: A constructionist approach. Strategic Management J. 17 (Winter Special Issue) 1 1-25.

    Tuomi, Ilkka. 1999. Corporate Knowledge: Theoty and Practice of Intelligent Organizations. Metaxis, Helsinki, Finland.

    van Maanen, John, Stephen R. Barley. 1984. Occupational communi- ties: Culture and control in organizations. Barry M. Staw, L.L. Cummings, eds. Research in Organizational Behavior. JAI Press, Greenwich, CT.

    von Hippel, Eric. 1994. 'Sticky information' and the locus of problem solving: Implications for innovation. Management Sci. 40(4) 429- 439.

    -. 1999. Economics of product development by users: Impact of "sticky" local information. Management Sci. 44(5) 629-644.

    Walker, Gordon, Bruce Kogut, Weijian Shan. 1997. Social capital, structural holes, and the formation of an industry network. Organ. Sci. 8(2) 109-125.

    Accepted by Bruce Kogut; received July 5, 2000.

    Weber, Max. 1978. Economy and Society,