a materialist theory of the mind by d. m. armstrong

Upload: don-arthur

Post on 01-Jun-2018

255 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/9/2019 A Materialist Theory of the Mind by D. M. Armstrong

    1/8

    Journal of Philosophy Inc.

    A Materialist Theory of the Mind by D. M. ArmstrongReview by: Alvin I. GoldmanThe Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 66, No. 22 (Nov. 20, 1969), pp. 812-818Published by: Journal of Philosophy, Inc.Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2024373.

    Accessed: 16/01/2015 13:06

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at.http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

    .JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range ofcontent in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms

    of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    .

    Journal of Philosophy, Inc.is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Journal

    of Philosophy.

    http://www.jstor.org

    This content downloaded from 197.255.75.83 on Fri, 16 Jan 2015 13:06:02 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=jphilhttp://www.jstor.org/stable/2024373?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/2024373?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=jphil
  • 8/9/2019 A Materialist Theory of the Mind by D. M. Armstrong

    2/8

    812

    THE

    JOURNAL

    OF

    PHILOSOPHY

    Step

    1.

    Inflationary ontological

    reduction:

    We replace

    R

    by

    R'

    and

    D

    by

    D

    u

    N; the proxy function

    is

    identity.

    Step 2. Ontological reduction without change of domain: We replace R'

    by (3 z)

    -

    (Nz

    &

    R'xy)

    V

    (z) (Nz

    &

    RN'XY).

    This reinterpretation pre-

    serves truth,

    since

    in

    the

    domain D

    v

    N the interpretation coincides

    with

    R'; the proxy function

    is

    identity.

    Step

    3.

    Ontological

    destruction: Eliminate

    D

    from the domain.

    This

    reduces the interpretation of R in effect to

    RN

    and, hence, preserves

    truth.

    Thus it appears that, if Pythagoreanism is to be resisted, either

    some

    further condition

    must be

    added

    or a further explication of the pres-

    ent conditions must be given. A more drastic alternative would be

    to seek

    a

    less

    model-theoretic approach to ontological questions.

    R.

    E. G.

    BOOK REVIEWS

    A Materialist Theory of the Mind. D. M. ARMSTRONG.

    New York:

    Hu-

    manities Press, 1968. xii, 372 p. $8.50.

    This book is a stimulating defense of the

    thesis

    that the

    mind is

    identical with the brain (or central nervous system) and that men-

    tal states are physicochemical states of the brain. Armstrong fits

    the

    identity thesis into the framework of a general theory of the mind,

    and provides one of the most

    comprehensive and clearly structured

    discussions of the subject in the recent

    literature.

    The

    book begins with a threefold

    classification

    of theories of

    mind:

    (1) Dualism, (2) The Attribute

    Theory,

    and

    (3) Materialism.

    The author's own theory is a species of

    materialism,

    which he

    calls

    Central-state Materialism. Armstrong then sets out to criticize

    the rival theories. He charges that

    dualism is unable to capture

    the

    unity of mind and body, that it fails to give a satisfactory account

    of

    the

    interaction

    of

    mind

    and body, and that it cannot

    explain

    the

    emergence

    and

    growth

    of

    the

    mind

    over time.

    The

    attribute

    theory

    differs from Cartesian dualism

    in

    positing only

    one

    substance,

    but

    contrasts with materialism in claiming that mental states are

    non-

    material attributes of the substance. Though it escapes some of the

    difficulties confronting dualism, Armstrong thinks that other objec-

    tions raised against

    dualism

    also

    hold for

    it.

    Moreover,

    he finds it

    just mysterious

    that there should

    be

    properties

    of

    the

    brain that

    are not reducible to material properties.

    The advance

    of science,

    he

    feels, renders implausible

    the

    hypothesis

    of

    any entity

    or attribute

    that is not reducible to

    the entities and attributes of

    physical

    science.

    This content downloaded from 197.255.75.83 on Fri, 16 Jan 2015 13:06:02 PMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/9/2019 A Materialist Theory of the Mind by D. M. Armstrong

    3/8

    BOOK REVIEWS

    8I3

    Behaviorism is

    classed as a species

    of materialism, or physicalism,

    since it tries to

    reduce the mind to physical behavior and

    to tenden-

    cies to behave physically in certain ways. Armstrong's main criti-

    cism of behaviorism is precisely its emphasis

    on outer behavior

    and

    its consequent failure to account for

    the inner nature

    of mental

    states. According

    to behaviorism, says

    Armstrong, the mind is just

    the body in action

    (56). Central-state materialism, on

    the other

    hand, sees the

    mind as an inner arena

    identified by its causal rela-

    tions to outward

    act (129). Nevertheless, Armstrong's

    own theory

    closely resembles

    behaviorism; for, like the behaviorist,

    he thinks

    our concepts of mental states are dispositional concepts. Unlike the

    behaviorist, however, he contends

    that dispositional

    states must

    have a categorical

    basis. Thus, although we may think

    of a men-

    tal state as a state apt for producing

    certain behavior,

    such a state

    must also have an intrinsic nature.

    Question then arises

    concerning

    this intrinsic nature,

    and central-state materialism asserts

    that it is

    a

    physicochemical state. Armstrong

    compares the process

    of identi-

    fying the mind with the brain to the

    process of identifying

    the gene

    with the DNA molecule.

    The concept of a gene is a causal-disposi-

    tional concept: that of a factor apt for producing hereditary charac-

    teristics. Biological

    evidence suggests that the production

    of such

    characteristics is

    attributable to DNA.

    Hence, the gene is identified

    with the

    DNA

    molecule.

    Similarly, the

    concept of the mind is the

    concept

    of

    a

    factor apt for producing

    certain behavior. Hence, since

    scientific evidence

    suggests that the

    thing apt for producing this

    behavior is the

    brain, the mind is identified

    with the brain.

    The

    defense of

    the

    mind-brain

    identity

    thesis is

    hereby

    divided

    into two stages. The first stage, a purely conceptual one, consists in

    an analysis of the concept of

    a

    mental state

    as a state

    apt for bring-

    ing about a certain

    sort

    of

    behavior

    (82).

    The

    second

    stage argues

    the

    contingent hypothesis

    that these

    behavior-causing

    states are

    physicochemical

    states

    of

    the brain.

    Actually very

    little

    space

    is

    de-

    voted to

    the second

    stage,

    whereas

    the first

    occupies

    the bulk

    of

    the

    book. In a wide-ranging survey,

    Armstrong

    seeks to

    analyze

    numer-

    ous mental-state

    concepts

    in terms

    of

    their

    dispositions

    to

    cause

    behavior (and,

    in

    some

    cases,

    to

    be caused

    by

    certain

    stimuli).

    Among

    the

    concepts analyzed

    are those of

    desire, deliberation, plea-

    sure and

    pain,

    emotion, inference,

    perception, belief,

    mental im-

    agery,

    and

    bodily

    sensation.

    The two

    most

    important

    mental

    concepts

    in

    Armstrong's theory

    are desire

    and

    perception,

    which

    play

    an

    important part

    in the

    analysis

    of

    various other mental

    concepts. Armstrong begins

    with

    This content downloaded from 197.255.75.83 on Fri, 16 Jan 2015 13:06:02 PMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/9/2019 A Materialist Theory of the Mind by D. M. Armstrong

    4/8

    8I4

    THE

    JOURNAL

    OF PHILOSOPHY

    the concept

    of desire,

    which is the clearest case

    of

    a mental

    state that

    tends to produce

    behavior.

    Problems

    arise

    immediately, however.

    Some desires do not really tend to cause behavior; for example, an

    agent does

    not

    act upon

    a desire that he

    knows

    he

    cannot

    fulfill.

    Armstrong tries to handle such cases by suitable counterfactuals,

    saying

    what behavior

    would

    result

    from

    these desires

    if

    the

    agent

    had certain beliefs. Secondly, desires

    are not the

    only mental states

    that produce behavior; so distinguishing features of desires must

    be introduced. Armstrong tries

    to do

    this by defining a purpose (or

    desire) as a state whose behavioral effects depend on perceptual

    feedback:

    Purposive activity .

    ..

    is a train of activities initiated

    and sustained by

    a mental 'thrust' or causal state. At the beginning of

    the

    activity,

    and

    as the activity develops, perceptions of the current

    state of

    the

    agent

    and

    his

    environment occur.

    Where the information

    .

    .

    .

    contained

    in

    the perceptions is relevant, it feeds back to the causal

    state, modifying

    the latter in a way suitable (or believed to be suitable) for the achieve-

    ment of the 'end' of the activity.

    The 'end'

    is simply

    the state of affairs

    such that perception that

    it

    has

    been reached

    feeds back to

    the

    sus-

    taining causal state and stops the causal state operating. Purposive ac-

    tivity is a train of activities, initiated

    and sustained

    by

    a mental

    state,

    and

    controlled

    from

    beginning to

    end

    by perception

    acting

    as

    a

    feed-

    back cause on the mental state.

    To

    put

    forward

    a slogan:

    a

    purpose

    is

    an

    information-sensitive mental cause (139).

    Having explained

    desire in

    part

    in

    terms of perception, Armstrong

    turns to

    the latter

    concept.

    Here

    again

    he

    employs

    the formula char-

    acterizing mental states as states apt

    for

    producing

    certain

    sorts

    of

    behavior, though

    he

    admits that

    perception

    does

    not

    have

    the

    same

    sort

    of

    causal

    role as desires or

    purposes.

    Now,

    in

    the case of perception, there is no question of the inner event

    actually tending to bring

    about

    behavior.

    What we must say, rather,

    is

    that perception supplies a necessary

    preconditionfor appropriate be-

    havior. If a baby can perceive a difference between a green and a blue

    block,

    then it is

    in

    a

    position

    to

    discriminate between

    them

    in

    its be-

    havior if it should want

    to. . .

    . Perception enables

    discriminating be-

    havior, but does not impel towards that behavior (249).

    The

    behavioral

    effects

    of

    perception

    tell

    only part

    of the story, how-

    ever.

    Armstrong says

    that

    certain

    mental-state concepts must be ana-

    lyzed partly

    in

    terms

    of

    the propensity to be

    caused by certain stim-

    uli, and perception is the main example of this. To perceive an ob-

    ject

    or

    situation

    in the

    environment,

    he

    says,

    is

    to

    acquire

    a belief

    about the

    environment.

    (This thesis was espoused

    in

    his

    earlier

    This content downloaded from 197.255.75.83 on Fri, 16 Jan 2015 13:06:02 PMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/9/2019 A Materialist Theory of the Mind by D. M. Armstrong

    5/8

    BOOK REVIEWS

    8i5

    book,

    Perception

    and the

    Physical

    World.')

    Such

    belief-acquirings

    are apt

    for

    being brought

    about

    by

    the

    corresponding

    objects or

    situations in the environment, which is what occurs in veridical per-

    ception.

    Thus,

    perception

    is to

    be

    understood

    in

    terms

    of

    the

    stimuli

    that

    characteristically cause

    it,

    as

    well

    as the

    behavioral differences

    it

    is apt

    to

    produce.

    Armstrong's

    analysis of mental-state

    concepts

    turns out to be far

    less

    simple

    and straightforward

    than the

    original

    billing suggests.

    As

    we have seen,

    he not

    only appeals to

    behavioral

    consequences

    in

    analyzing

    mental

    concepts,

    but

    also to

    stimulus causes.

    Moreover,

    in many cases mental states are characterized in terms of their causal

    relations

    to other

    mental

    states,

    rather than their

    direct

    ties to be-

    havior or

    stimuli.

    Emotions

    are

    analyzed

    in

    terms

    of

    propensities

    to cause

    certain

    desires

    and

    to be caused

    by certain

    beliefs,

    and de-

    liberation

    is analyzed as a

    process apt for

    causing a

    decision.

    Again,

    even the

    primary

    mental

    concepts,

    desire and

    perception,

    are

    not

    independently

    analyzed. As we

    have

    seen,

    Armstrong's

    analysis of

    desire

    or

    purpose

    makes use of the

    concept

    of

    perception,

    and

    his

    analysis

    of

    perception

    presupposes the

    concept

    of

    desire; hence,

    he

    calls them package-deal concepts (253). But a full analysis re-

    quires him

    to

    distinguish

    the

    joint

    operation of

    purpose

    and per-

    ception

    from that

    of

    other

    mechanisms, e.g., automatic

    self-regulat-

    ing

    mechanisms in the

    body.

    In

    his

    attempt to do

    this,

    Armstrong

    is

    eventually

    forced to

    appeal to the

    enormously greater

    complex-

    ity

    of purpose

    and

    perception (252).

    In

    addition

    to

    the

    analysis

    of

    particular

    mental

    concepts, a com-

    plete

    theory of the mind

    must

    also give an

    account

    of

    self-knowledge

    and of consciousness in general. Here seem to lurk large obstacles to

    a

    causal-materialist

    account of the mind.

    For example,

    if a

    mental

    state

    is a

    disposition

    to

    produce

    behavior, how

    is

    noninferential

    knowledge

    of it

    possible? And

    if a

    mental state is a

    physicochemical

    state of the

    brain, why should a

    statement

    concerning such

    a state

    have

    a different

    epistemic

    status from, say, a

    statement about

    the

    state

    of

    one's

    liver? Yet it

    is

    widely

    claimed that

    first-person mental

    statements

    do

    have

    a

    unique

    epistemic status:

    they

    are

    incorrigible

    and

    self-intimating.

    Armstrong

    confronts these

    challenges

    head on. He

    argues

    that

    noninferential

    knowledge

    of

    dispositions

    is

    perfectly possible

    and,

    hence,

    that noninferential

    knowledge

    of one's mental

    states

    is

    also

    possible. On

    the

    other

    hand,

    he

    emphatically

    denies

    the

    incorrigi-

    ' New York: Humanities,

    1961; reviewed

    in this JOURNAL,

    LIX, 14

    (July

    5,

    1962):

    384-388.

    This content downloaded from 197.255.75.83 on Fri, 16 Jan 2015 13:06:02 PMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/9/2019 A Materialist Theory of the Mind by D. M. Armstrong

    6/8

    8i6

    THE

    JOURNAL

    OF PHILOSOPHY

    bility and self-intimatingness of first-person

    mental statements.

    That

    I believe I am in mental state

    M,

    he says, does not entail that

    I

    am

    in

    M; and that

    I

    am in

    M

    does not entail that

    I

    believe,

    or

    am

    aware, that

    I

    am.

    Armstrong's position

    is that

    . . . our cognitive relation to

    our mind ...

    is like our cognitive

    rela-

    tion to anything else

    in

    nature. We know in part, guess in part, in

    part we are mistakenand

    in

    large part

    we

    are

    simply ignorant.Being

    in a mental state entails nothing about our awarenessof that state

    (115).

    If mental states are physicochemical states of the brain, indubitable

    knowledge of them should not be expected. Consciousness of one's

    mental states

    is a

    self-scanning process. One is conscious of a men-

    tal state when it is scanned by a further mental state. Although

    successful

    scanning

    is

    possible,

    there is no reason to

    expect every

    mental

    state

    to be

    scanned or

    every putative scanning to

    be correct.

    Thus, Armstrong's position squares well with his materialism.

    On the

    whole,

    this

    is a valuable book

    that

    deserves, and will

    receive, considerable attention. It presents a coherent and systematic

    theory of the mind, with reasonably clear-cut proposals for the solu-

    tion of

    many

    traditional

    problems

    in

    this domain.

    It

    certainly

    con-

    stitutes

    the most detailed

    defense

    of the

    contingent identity

    thesis

    yet to appear.

    In

    addition, Armstrong writes lucidly

    and

    engagingly;

    he

    puts

    all his cards face

    up

    on the

    table,

    both

    in

    criticism of others

    and in

    defense

    of

    his

    own

    views.

    Though

    the

    book is

    long,

    it is

    emi-

    nently readable.

    Of

    special

    use to

    students

    is

    Armstrong's classification

    of theories

    of mind and his critique of theories that rival his own. His criticisms

    of

    rivals

    are often

    imaginative.

    I

    was

    disappointed, however, by

    in-

    sufficient discussion

    of

    the

    concept of

    reduction. In

    criticizing

    the

    attribute

    theory, Armstrong claims

    that mental

    attributes, or prop-

    erties, must be

    reducible to

    physical ones, but he never explains

    what this means.

    Presumably, reducibility requires some sort of reg-

    ularities

    holding between the

    incidence of mental

    properties

    and

    of

    physical properties.

    But

    the nature of these regularities goes com-

    pletely unexplored.

    In

    the

    same

    vein, one

    wishes

    Armstrong

    had

    said

    more

    about criteria

    of

    identity

    for states or

    events. In

    the

    early

    part

    of the book he talks almost

    exclusively

    of the

    identification of

    mind

    and brain. But since

    the mind

    is

    just shorthand,

    I

    think,

    for

    a certain

    class

    of states and

    events,

    one wishes there

    were

    some

    elaboration

    of the

    problem

    of

    when

    two

    states

    can be

    considered

    identical.

    This content downloaded from 197.255.75.83 on Fri, 16 Jan 2015 13:06:02 PMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/9/2019 A Materialist Theory of the Mind by D. M. Armstrong

    7/8

    BOOK REVIEWS

    8I7

    Armstrong's causal

    analysis of mental

    concepts is a

    salutary

    devel-

    opment

    in the

    philosophy

    of mind. Its

    main

    importance,

    I think,

    lies in its refutation of the oft-repeated dogma that logical connec-

    tions and

    causal

    connections are

    incompatible.

    Armstrong is

    quite

    right to point

    to

    concepts, such as

    the

    gene, whose

    analysis

    includes

    a

    propensity

    to

    cause

    certain

    effects. He

    is also

    right,

    I

    think,

    in

    sug-

    gesting

    that the

    concept of

    desire or

    purpose

    is the

    concept of

    a

    state

    whose

    analysis

    includes

    the propensity

    to

    cause

    behavior.

    There is

    a sense,

    then, in

    which there is

    a

    conceptual, or

    logical,

    tie

    between

    desire and

    action.

    Yet this

    logical tie

    is perfectly

    compati-

    ble with the fact that actions are caused by desires.

    More

    dubious, however,

    is

    Armstrong's

    extension

    of this

    logical

    connection

    thesis to

    all

    mental states.

    First,

    even where we

    can

    agree

    that

    a certain kind

    of mental

    state

    characteristically

    produces cer-

    tain

    behavior,

    it may

    not be

    evident

    that this is a

    logical truth.

    Sec-

    ondly, there

    are

    many kinds of

    mental

    states that do

    not

    seem to be

    associated with

    specific

    kinds of

    physical

    behavior.

    What sorts

    of

    overt

    behavior

    are

    typically

    associated

    with

    entertaining a

    hypothe-

    sis,

    doubting a

    proposition, or

    daydreaming? The

    conceptual rela-

    tionship between such states and overt behavior-even an

    indirect

    relationship via other

    mental states-is,

    at

    best, extremely

    tenuous.

    Armstrong's willingness

    to

    come

    to

    grips

    with

    the

    consequences

    of

    his

    view

    is

    most

    in evidence in

    his

    treatment

    of

    noninferential

    knowledge of mental states

    and

    his

    treatment

    of consciousness. He

    clearly

    recognizes

    the

    implications

    of his

    causal-materialist

    position

    on

    these

    issues,

    and his

    positions

    on

    them are

    original

    and

    refresh-

    ing.

    I

    remain

    unconvinced,

    however, by

    his

    support

    for

    noninferen-

    tial knowledge of dispositions. He claims that pressure is a state apt

    for

    producing

    movement in

    a

    body,

    so that

    noninferential

    knowl-

    edge

    of

    pressure

    on one's

    body

    is

    noninferential

    knowledge

    of a dis-

    position.

    But this is dubious.

    His

    view of

    consciousness as a

    self-

    scanning

    process

    is

    also

    questionable.

    On his

    view,

    M

    is a

    conscious

    mental

    event

    if

    it

    is the

    object

    of

    another mental

    event

    (the

    aware-

    ness

    of

    M).

    Otherwise

    it

    is

    unconscious.

    It

    follows that an

    awareness

    is itself

    an

    unconscious mental event

    if

    it

    is not the

    object

    of a

    fur-

    ther

    awareness.

    Thus,

    an

    awareness

    of

    a

    pain

    is

    unconscious

    if

    it

    goes

    unscanned

    by

    a

    higher-level

    awareness. This

    strikes me

    as

    extremely

    counterintuitive.

    There

    are

    other

    specific points

    where

    Armstrong's

    discussion

    is

    inadequate,

    sometimes because he

    tries

    too

    hard to fit

    things into

    his

    framework without

    full

    cognizance

    of

    the

    difficulties

    involved.

    On

    the

    other

    hand,

    his

    development

    of the

    theory

    is

    always

    interest-

    This content downloaded from 197.255.75.83 on Fri, 16 Jan 2015 13:06:02 PMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/9/2019 A Materialist Theory of the Mind by D. M. Armstrong

    8/8

    8i8

    THE

    JOURNAL

    OF

    PHILOSOPHY

    ing and frequently ingenious. Bold theories, like Armstrong's,

    are

    the stuff of which

    philosophical progress is made, and so this is a

    val-

    uable contribution

    to

    the

    philosophy of mind.

    ALVIN

    I.

    GOLDMAN

    University

    of

    Michigan

    ERRATUM. The last item of the

    APA Program for Saturday,

    December 27, in

    LXVI,

    20 (Oct.

    16, 1969): 725-735,

    page 726, was omitted. This

    line

    should

    have read:

    8:00

    Smoker,

    Grand Ballroom

    The editors regret

    the

    omission,

    and trust that many

    of our readers will

    attend

    the

    Smoker.

    NOTES AND NEWS

    The editors

    report with deep

    regret

    the death of A. N. Prior, fellow

    in

    phi-

    losophy

    of Balliol College, Oxford,

    and former

    editor

    of the Journal

    of

    Symbolic

    Logic.

    Professor Prior was

    born and educated

    in New Zealand;

    he

    had taught

    at Otago University

    and

    at

    Canterbury University,

    and

    also

    at Manchester

    University,

    England. At

    the

    time

    of his death he was

    on

    sabbatical

    leave, visiting

    at the

    University

    of Oslo. He died

    in

    Trondheim,

    Norway, on October

    6, i969,

    at the age of fifty-four.

    The editors regret to learn that J. W. Swanson, Professor of Philosophy at

    the

    University

    of

    Massachusettts,

    Amherst,

    and a contributor

    to

    this

    JOURNAL,

    died on November

    6, i969.

    THE

    Undergraduate

    Journalof

    Philosophy

    Founded and

    edited by students

    at Oberlin

    College, the

    journal

    provides

    a

    forum

    for the

    presentation

    and

    criticism of philosophi-

    cal

    articles,

    discussions,

    and book reviews

    written

    by undergrad-

    uates.

    Not committed

    to

    any branch

    or school of

    philosophy,

    the

    Journal

    will

    continue

    to

    publish

    works on

    a

    wide variety of

    philo-

    sophically

    challenging

    subjects.

    MANUSCRIPTS

    should be typed and

    not

    exceed 4000

    words.

    SUBSCRIPTIONS:

    STUDENTS: $1.00

    INDIVIDUALS: $1.50

    INSTITUTIONS: $2.00

    Published

    in

    December and

    May.

    Send

    all

    correspondence

    to:

    King Building 105,

    Oberlin,

    Ohio 44074

    This content downloaded from 197 255 75 83 on Fri 16 Jan 2015 13:06:02 PM

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp